You are on page 1of 23

Book Reviews

goehr, lydia. Elective Affinities: Musical Essays on talism (and, again, Cage), connections between the
the History of Aesthetic Theory. Columbia Univer- philosophies of history and of art, the tendency of
sity Press, 2008, xviii + 386 pp., $35.00 cloth. commemorative art to mirror the violence done to
the victims we commemorate, the musicality of film
A decade ago, Lydia Goehr shared her thoughts on movement, and the problem of American opera. In
Wagner and German Romanticism in The Quest for the spirit of the book’s own methodology, my gen-
Voice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998). In the present eral response is best summarized by the observation
volume she resumes her exploration of the history that my reading was constantly accompanied by the
of aesthetic theory by interrogating modernism in thought, “These fragments she has shored against our
its German incarnation. With a title borrowed from ruins,” a variation on T. S. Eliot’s line in The Waste
Goethe, the book consists of eight long, idiosyncratic Land (1922).
essays on the aesthetics of music, all of which are Why did this line of poetry keep coming to me as
ultimately reflections on Theodor Adorno’s reflec- I read? It might be because the topic of ruins domi-
tions on music. Sympathetic readers will appreciate nates chapter five, as does fragmentation elsewhere.
her patient exploration of a cluster of reoccurring However, that is not really why. It is because, in the
themes. Detractors are likely to respond that the un- end, I felt that I’d been touring the ruins of Ger-
dertaking would be improved by aggressive editing man intellectual history. Not that the tour guide isn’t
and tightening. A Hegelian might suggest that this amazingly well informed! Yet the guide is overly di-
standoff exemplifies an inevitable dialectical tension gressive; at the end of the tour there is no sense of the
that will be resolved in her future explorations of whole. Different chapters will resonate to different
German postmodernism. degrees with each reader, but there’s no overarching
Goehr explains that she “do[es] not engage in the- thesis, no core idea to applaud or dispute. (This might
ory production,” but rather that she offers “a criti- very well be Goehr’s intended effect, if we take seri-
cal history of concepts,” mapping “a history of their ously her early remarks that her aim is to display the
reception and thereby of the complex adaptations, “movement of [her] thought” [p. xvii], sacrificing in-
appropriations, and retrievals of some of the most ternal consistency in the process [p. xii].) On another
dominant philosophical and aesthetic theses of mod- level, the whole book seems to me a working out of
ern times” (p. x). Dominant, that is, if you agree with the last chapter’s theme concerning the problem of
her assessment that “it is to Adorno to whom even American opera, to wit, that it is symptomatic of a
those most irritated [by Adorno’s difficulty and ob- (German) nostalgia for a historical moment and cul-
scurity] turn when in search of something new or tural configuration that did not, because it could not,
interesting to say” (p. xi). To further complicate the exist.
proceedings, Goehr intentionally reads Adorno and Before tackling these eight essays, readers who
other theorists “against the grain of their usual re- are not presold on the book’s appeal might prepare
ceptions” (p. xiii), and pursues concepts “at a certain themselves by self-assessing their familiarity with a
level of perpetuated and mythified abstraction, ex- wide range of cultural landmarks. (And that means
plicitly to expose assumptions that . . . remain preva- knowing them well, for Goehr is not one to pro-
lent” (p. 259). vide details, much less background exposition. Any
In order of appearance, the eight essays range over reader who needs to consult the notes or bibliogra-
the topics of affinities between music and philosophy, phy in order to understand that “Benjamin” is Wal-
the concept of musicality as it applies to Beethoven ter Benjamin is not a reader addressed by this au-
and Wagner, John Cage and birdsong, experimen- thor. In that spirit, the following list is restricted to

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 68:2 Spring 2010



c 2010 The American Society for Aesthetics
176 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

surnames.) Minimally, and in rough order of impor- tentional ruins, including the question of which par-
tance, Goehr assumes that the reader knows Adorno, ticulars fall within the scope of those remarks, in-
Danto, Hegel, Benjamin, Nietzsche, Kant, Marx, spires a comparison of Adorno and Danto on both
Hanslick, Merleau-Ponty, Dewey, Schiller, Wittgen- history and art. Another illuminating discussion ex-
stein, Proust, Twain, Yeats, and Beckett as well as plains how their shared commitments to art’s unique-
the music of Beethoven, Wagner, Schoenberg, Cage, ness and to its “posthistoricist condition” (p. 85)
Mozart, Stockhausen, Strauss, Stravinsky, Brahms, inform the thinking of both Adorno and Danto con-
Adams, Rossini, Puccini, Weill, and Tippett. With re- cerning the continuation of art relative to the ends or
spect to chapter seven, it’s imperative that one knows endings of art.
the major film theorists of the early twentieth century I wonder if other readers will experience the odd
and Hitchcock’s Lifeboat (1944). reversal that these sections inspired in me. Situat-
I admit to puzzlement in response to some of ing Adorno in a larger conversation makes his views
Goehr’s references. And I do not mean her refer- more understandable and thus a bit more plausible.
ences to Schiller and Mann. As in Adorno, references Situating Danto in the same conversation has the op-
to examples are frequently vague or obscure: her ref- posite effect, making it more difficult to appreciate
erence to Tarantino’s Death Proof (2007) seems quite The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (Harvard
gratuitous (p. 252), and despite having seen it at least University Press, 1981) as a series of independent ar-
four times, I did not initially recall the eighty sec- guments. Transfiguration contains only one passing
onds of the Marx Brothers’ The Cocoanuts (Robert reference to Hegel, so the book’s arguments formerly
Florey and Joseph Santley, 1929) that matters to her seemed to rest on Danto’s well-chosen examples. By
argument (pp. 293 and 301). (Incidentally, shouldn’t reminding us that Danto’s methodology is a critical
some credit go to Irving Berlin, who wrote this par- response to his framing Hegelianism, Goehr brings
ticular bit?) After locating and watching the scene, a out his underlying affinities with Adorno and thus
Carmen spoof, I worry that she expects it to bear too asks us to reevaluate Danto’s position as a thread
much weight. There is no particular reason to read it in a larger intellectual history. In the end, however,
as a critique of European opera, as Goehr would have Goehr’s decision to compare Adorno and Danto is
it. One might as well say that Groucho’s reference to buried in its surroundings. One cannot avoid the sus-
Winnie the Pooh in the film’s auction sequence is a picion that a shorter book, concentrating primarily on
critique of British children’s literature. Consider an- those two philosophers for a hundred pages, would
other example: Goehr discusses Mark Twain’s obser- have been a greater accomplishment.
vations, in A Tramp Abroad (1880), about applause
at a Munich concert, and then her next paragraph THEODORE GRACYK
begins, “Twain’s story recalls the king of Bavaria” Department of Philosophy
and his preference to attend opera sans audience (p. Minnesota State University Moorhead
303). Initially, there is no mention that the story about
the king is likewise from Twain’s A Tramp Abroad. fowler, sherry d. Muroji: Rearranging Art and His-
(Precisely how many readers will “recall,” with her, tory at a Japanese Buddhist Temple. University of
that the Wagner chapter ends with this story?) She Hawaii Press, 2005, xiv + 293 pp., 13 color + 79
then extracts a major conclusion from Twain’s punch b&w plates, $57.00 cloth.
line, which compares German and American “mod-
eration.” Yet how much weight should a punch line levine, gregory p. a. Daitokuji: The Visual Cultures
in Twain be asked to bear? Is a (fictional?) anecdote of a Zen Monastery. University of Washington
from 1880 really the place to look for evidence of Press, 2005, lii + 444 pp., 136 color and b&w plates,
an American predisposition to welcome the end of $60.00 cloth.
art, as Goehr supposes (p. 304)? Moving from an (al-
leged) sadistic disregard for performers to an Ameri- It is one thing to write philosophy of art and quite an-
can desire for the end of art is certainly an “elective” other to write philosophy of art that is not solely a re-
affinity on her part. I might just as well ground this flection of one’s own familiar experience and biases.
review in my own happenstance associations, such as But while many aestheticians want to incorporate
that her frequent references to nightingales reminded non-Western material, and even points of view and
me of battlefield hospitals in the Crimean War and methods, into their teaching, writing, and research,
the Derek and the Dominos song that contains the and even their own thinking, this is not always as easy
phrase “There sings no bird.” But free association is as it may seem before one begins. Even reading the
neither analysis nor argument. literature (in translation) may be more complex than
Granted, some of her examples yield interesting it first appears. Longtime foundational texts are be-
affinities, most notably when her examination of Al- ing reevaluated. Works such as D. T. Suzuki’s Zen and
bert Speer’s remarks on Nazi architecture and in- Japanese Culture (Princeton University Press, 1970)
Book Reviews 177

have come under criticism for oversimplifying sectar- away from that paradigm. They begin their books
ian differences or ignoring social and historical con- by examining issues that were long invisible to art
texts (that is, for being of their time rather than ade- historians, namely, the movements or repositioning
quately theoretically informed, as we are today); the of sculpture (and less commonly painting) from one
work of Okakura Kazuo (aka Tenshin, 1862–1913), place to another and the renaming of statues and
such as The Ideals of the East, with Special Atten- their temples. How and why (under what circum-
tion to the Art of Japan (London: John Murray, 1903) stances and auspices and with what motivations) do
and his well-known classic The Book of Tea (New works that have been known by one name and have
York: Putnam’s, 1906), is now recognized as disingen- been located in one place come to have their identi-
uously disavowing political agendas as well as foster- ties reassigned? And what do these reassignments tell
ing illusions that Japanese art, indeed all of Asia, is us about art-historical and religious practices, beliefs,
transcendent, unchanging, and timeless while also in and motivations? What roles are played by religious
some cases exacerbating ideological breaches among ritual and by politics, national or sectarian?
Japanese artists themselves. In the process of exploring these case studies,
Rushing into the breach, at least in terms of both authors undertake the debunking of century-
Japanese culture, is a series of substantial interdis- old myths of the timelessness and transcendence of
ciplinary books about temples and shrines, by schol- Japanese (and by extension other Asian) art, such as
ars of religion and art historians. (Within Japanese are perpetuated not only by writers like those men-
studies, the term ‘temple’ is restricted to Buddhist tioned in paragraph one above but also by the temple
institutions or buildings, while, with the exception of photography, often commissioned by the Japanese
a few very small tabernacle-like constructions some- government, that has made these buildings so mes-
times found within Buddhist temples that are also merizing. (Levine is by far the more overtly the-
referred to as shrines, ‘shrine’ is reserved for Shinto oretical, not to say jargon-riddled and straight-out
institutions or buildings.) Among the more helpful verbose, of the two; he is also mean-spirited in his
to aestheticians are two recent books, Sherry D. condemnations of scholars whose work predated our
Fowler’s Muroji: Rearranging Art and History at a contemporary enlightened theorizing.)
Japanese Buddhist Temple and Gregory P. A. Levine’s Both books raise a number of issues related to phi-
Daitokuji: The Visual Cultures of a Zen Monastery. losophy of art, including interrelations among paint-
The pioneers in this informal “series” are John K. ing, sculpture, and architecture; the ways in which the
Nelson’s A Year in the Life of a Shinto Shrine (Uni- identity of works of art is understood and assigned;
versity of Washington Press, 1996), which focuses the ways in which a work’s identity may change over
on Suwa Jinja, Nagasaki’s major Shinto shrine, and time (and under what circumstances, and for what the
Donald McCallum’s Zenkoji and Its Icon (Princeton reasons are); resemblance in portraiture; purposes of
University Press, 1994). The other major pieces on portraiture; relations between religious architecture
Shinto shrines are Dominic McIver Lopes’s “Shiki- and its surrounding landscape, the natural environ-
nen Sengu: The Ontology of Architecture in Japan” ment, and their aesthetics; gender and art; and more.
(The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65 [2007]: Those working in philosophy of religion and envi-
77–84) and Jonathan Reynolds’s article “Ise Shrine ronmental philosophy will also find much of interest,
and a Modernist Construction of Japanese Tradi- especially related to sacred space (indexed by Fowler
tion” (The Art Bulletin 83 [2001]: 316–341). Re- under ‘landscape’ and ‘esoteric cosmology’). Written
cent works on Buddhist temples include Andrew by art historians of specific buildings and the reli-
Watsky’s Chikubushima (aka Tsukubusuma), De- gious institutions that built and care for them, not
ploying the Sacred Arts in Momoyama Japan (Uni- all their questions are those of philosophers of art;
versity of Washington Press, 2004) and Mimi Yieng- you may encounter far more than you want to know
prukusawan’s Hiraizumi: Buddhist Art and Regional about contesting the temples’ affiliations and the in-
Politics in Twelfth-Century Japan, on Chusonji (Har- tricacies of dating works of art. Yet the information
vard University Asia Center, 1998). they provide and the questions and perspectives they
Both Daitokuji and Muroji are well-illustrated offer challenge many prevailing Western paradigms.
cross-disciplinary studies by art historians specializ- Both books situate their subjects historically
ing in Japanese art who bring considerable historical, and are diachronic, rather than synchronic, look-
cultural, photographic, and linguistic or literary ex- ing at changing beliefs and practices within the sites
pertise to bear on issues that turn out to be of philo- and communities they study, as well as across dif-
sophical interest, although the authors do not tackle ferent communities at certain historical junctures.
them philosophically themselves. Thus they are able to examine the varying senses
Having completed dissertations on these temples (within the temples’ own communities) of differ-
within more traditional art-historical paradigms (dat- ences in understanding of identity, both personal
ing and stylistic analysis and so on), both authors turn identity (for example, of abbots, the subjects of
178 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

portraiture) and identity of artworks and institutions. the task of the temple was to guarantee continued ef-
(And while acknowledging that the very notion of fectiveness of the space? The ‘landscape’ entry omits
sectarian identity is largely a modern construct, these several of her discussions. Why are the female pa-
studies are able also to help clarify the specificity of trons discussed not indexed by name or title? Why
Zen and other “sects” or schools within Buddhism are there no entries for thatch or roof repair when
that nonspecialists are liable to confuse or ignore.) her discussions of these topics are so interesting and
The two books also share some faults. Regret- informative, even enlightening, and it is a book on
tably, despite their focus on Buddhist temples (Zen architecture?)
at Daitokuji and Hosso school, Tendai and Shin- Unlike the temples of the other studies men-
gon [both esoteric] at Muroji), neither author spends tioned above, which are known (among Western-
much time on gardens, on the aesthetics of the tem- ers) primarily to Japanese art and religion special-
ples’ natural sites, or on the relations of built site ists, Daitokuji, a Zen temple in northeast Kyoto,
to natural environment, concentrating instead on is- is widely known through its enormous impact on
sues raised by architecture (primarily) and sculpture. American arts and letters. In the 1950s and 1960s,
(Painting enters in a supportive role in both, and cal- Daitokuji opened itself to foreign students of Zen
ligraphy in Daitokuji.) This is too bad, as Daitokuji’s and of Japanese literature and culture. Among the
gardens, especially those at the abbot’s quarters in most influential were poets and writers, including
the subtemple Daisen’in, are, outside, and probably Beat poet Gary Snyder and poet-filmmaker Ruth
within Japan, among the three most published, along Stephan, who lived at Daitokuji for many years; art
with Ryoanji and Kinkakuji, aka the Temple of the historians like Jon Carter Covell, who published Zen
Golden Pavilion, outside, and probably within, Japan. at Daitokuji with abbot Yamada Sobin (1974); art
Of the two, Sherry D. Fowler’s Muroji: Rearrang- historian-cum-mystery writer Janwillem van de We-
ing Art and History at a Japanese Buddhist Temple tering; and Rand and Sondra Castile, the first direc-
is the more manageable stylistically: the reader may tor of the Japan Society Gallery in New York City
bog down from time to time in lineages, sectarian and the founder of the East Asian conservation stu-
conflicts, or comparative dating of sculpture, but the dio at the Metropolitan Museum of Art, respectively.
range of information is very helpful. The narratives (The latter were among a number of American stu-
remain clear and her periodic summaries and the con- dents who were affiliated with the Sen schools of
clusions of the chapters are excellent. (Hint: feel free tea ceremony.) Scholars of religion and translators
to skip the genealogies in chapter 2, most of the dis- Philip Yampolsky and Burton Watson also studied
cussion of institutional conflicts, and minute details of and visited there. In 1958 Ruth Fuller Sasaki reno-
dating. You may want to begin with the conclusion; vated its subtemple Ryosen’an so it could house the
chapters 1 and 2 are not to be missed.) She draws First Zen Institute of America in Japan, while ab-
connections among the temple and its artworks, reli- bot Kobori Nanrei Sohaku mentored Americans and
gious beliefs and practices, the environment, and the held zazen (sitting meditation) sessions in the sub-
politics of the state (for Muroji this latter is primar- temple Ryokoin until the 1980s. (This informative
ily during its early centuries). Fowler makes all her discussion is not indexed; it is on pp. xliii–xliv of the
reasoning explicit and explains exactly where and on Prologue.)
what grounds she faults others’ theories. While her Levine begins his study of arts at Daitokuji with
focus is largely on the rearrangements and renamings abbot portraiture: specifically, a case he uncovers
of statues and the temple’s buildings, the issues raised where the accepted attribution turns out upon care-
go far beyond the particulars of one rather isolated ful examination (of a written inscription in the in-
temple. terior of the wooden sculpture) to be a seemingly
Fowler’s supporting materials are superb: infor- deliberate misidentification of the personage it pur-
mative photographs conveniently placed; a transla- ports to be. Zen abbot portraits (originally painted
tion of the main historical document, a list of illustra- but increasingly, in the seventeenth and eighteenth
tions, an excellent bibliography of English as well as centuries, wooden sculptures) have long been puz-
Japanese sources and a glossary with Japanese char- zling, because in spite of the doctrine of “emptiness”
acters (not found in Levine’s book). With a few im- derived from the Heart Sutra (among others), in-
portant exceptions, the index is useful, though per- cluding the emptiness of the self, they are treated
haps organized more for specialists in temple archi- with enormous respect and show startling degrees of
tecture than the general reader. (Why are there no resemblance; indeed they are regarded as being the
entries for ‘painting,’ ‘portrait,’ and ‘iconography’ in person himself after death.
a book on art that discusses these topics at length, Just how the portrait can be so full in the face
nor on sacred space and geography when the mo- of theoretical emptiness has bearing not only for
tivation for the placement of Muroji was based on philosophers of art and religion but also for those
space that was conceived as already sacred and when interested in personal identity and philosophy of the
Book Reviews 179

person and of the body. (Relics play a role here, aestheticians will find the information, arguments,
among other things.) Luckily the question has been and photographs in both Muroji and Daitokuji deeply
the subject of a number of fascinating studies re- informative and philosophically provocative.
cently. (Bernard Faure’s work is particularly helpful;
see “The Buddhist Icon and the Modern Gaze” [Criti- MARA MILLER
cal Inquiry 24 (1998): 768–813] and Visions of Power: Independent Scholar
Imagining Medieval Japanese Buddhism [Princeton Honolulu, Hawaii
University Press, 1996]. Richard Vinograd’s Bound-
aries of the Self: Chinese Portraits 1600–1900 [Cam- dadlez, e. m. Mirrors to One Another: Emotion and
bridge University Press, 1992] and Richard H. Davis’s Value in Jane Austen and David Hume. Chichester,
Lives of Indian Images [Princeton University Press, UK: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, xv + 234 pp., $89.95
1997] investigate issues of selfhood, social and per- cloth.
sonal identity, resemblance and portraiture in other
Asian contexts.) Vinograd’s theory is also applica- As Eva Dadlez makes clear at the outset of her
ble to Japanese portraiture; see Mara Miller’s “Iden- new book, any brave soul who attempts to deci-
tity, Identification, and Temperament in Emblematic pher some systematic philosophical content in Jane
Portraits of in Edo Japanese Literati Artists Taiga & Austen’s writing faces two considerable obstacles.
Gyokuran: A Philosophical and Theoretical Anal- Not only does Austen explicitly deny that she had
ysis of the Ming-Qing Legacy” [MingQing Yanjiu any knowledge of philosophy, but many of the fea-
(MingQing Studies)] (2007): 65–116.) tures of the complex and precisely rendered moral
Levine concludes that site setting (enshrinement) world readers confront in her novels fall neither
and ritual (including a variety of texts) may be as im- exclusively nor unambiguously under the purview
portant as resemblance and naming in the attribution of any particular philosopher. If one rejects, more-
of identity to a religious sculpture. At the same time, over (as Dadlez emphatically does) seeing Austen
there are important repercussions of the practices as egoist or deontologist, claiming her instead for
for the understanding of the personage represented, the tradition of virtue ethics, the themes that charac-
both by the original and subsequent audiences of be- terize the moral vision that approach involves can
lievers, and for us today who strive to understand art be heard plausibly as echoes not only of Aristo-
and human identity in a scholarly context; the rites, he tle, but of a host of eighteenth-century philosophers
argues, “presented, it seems two senses (two faces) of from Shaftesbury to Dugald Stewart. Refusing to
the patriarch: as a physical presence of institutional yield to such impediments, however, blessed with
and spiritual authority and charismatic sayings and a careful eye to detail and armed with an impres-
doings and as a transcendent absence, his enlightened sive command of her subject matter, Dadlez pro-
nature beyond form and representation” (p. 80). poses to defend a strikingly bold thesis: not only
The result is a case study with important impli- are we indeed able to decipher the “philosophical
cations for our understanding not only of the is- position to which [Austen’s] writing commits her”
sues mentioned but also of the range of possibil- (p. viii), but it is also possible to show that this
ity of intertextuality, of contextualized viewing and commitment finds its best expression in the work of
experience, and of the roles of personal subjective David Hume.
experience. Dadlez clearly recognizes the potential briars and
Levine’s subsequent case study in the book ex- brambles by which the traveler on this road might be
plores the famous Sanmon Gate and the portrait- snagged, and she is careful both to distance her posi-
statue of the founder of the modern tea ceremony, tion from the hardly tenable one that Austen’s preoc-
Sen no Rikyu (1522–1591), erected at Daitokuji after cupations can be tied exclusively to Hume and to dis-
Rikyu refurbished its gate, together with its infamous tinguish it from a mere Humean “reading” of Austen:
crucifixion by the newly unified nation’s warlord- while the latter might be undertaken with a variety
ruler Toyotomi Hideyoshi. He follows this with anal- of authors without any particular philosophical con-
yses of calligraphy, personal identity, and cases of tent, Dadlez contends that Austen and Hume actu-
forgery, and of the institution of mushiboshi, or an- ally share “common concerns and perspectives” and
nual airings and exhibitions of artworks. Again the have the same “insights” about moral life (p. 207).
material is inherently fascinating and also useful to Dadlez risks watering down her proposal with four
those who wish to understand the arts outside of our secondary theses, including largely undeveloped ones
familiar Western paradigms. Regrettably, Daitokuji about Austen’s “affinity for Enlightenment thought”
has neither a list of illustrations nor a list of Japanese (p. ix) and Hume’s “immediacy and relevance”
characters. (p. xiii), both of which appear in the preface but
Although their intended audiences are primar- resurface only en passant in the final chapter. As
ily art historians interested in Japanese architecture, the book proceeds, however, all of the others effec-
painting, and sculpture, philosophers of art and other tively devolve into the primary one around which the
180 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

narrative is structured and from which the metaphor does, at a sufficiently high level of generality when
that provides the title of the book is derived. Hume comparing, say, the “fit” in their aesthetic views
and Austen are “mirrors to one another,” Dadlez (pp. 114ff.) or the role they assign utility in moral
urges, because in the novels of the latter we discover a judgment (pp. 100ff.). When one descends to the par-
series of thought experiments that represent norma- ticular, however, cracks begin to show. For at bot-
tive positions that reflect, illustrate, and embody the tom, the philosopher Hume and novelist Austen are
insights of the former, including the method of moral engaged in fundamentally different tasks. As Hume
reasoning through which they are reached; similarly, himself emphasizes, philosopher and novelist view
in Hume’s Treatise and second Enquiry we find a the same landscape from radically divergent points
space where Austen’s insights “survive intact” within of view originating in the different tasks in which
a systematic philosophy that enables us to “better they are engaged: the former casts the eye of rea-
understand” her (p. xi). son over the geography of common life to reflect its
Given the difficulty of pinning the details of shapes and disparate forms in a cold, unimpassioned
Austen’s work with any specificity onto the body of way; the latter, by contrast, rises on flights of fancy
Hume’s philosophy, Dadlez opts for an approach in- to fashion an artificial world populated by creations
tended to amass such a quantity of evidence that its that deliberately distort the original, warm the imag-
“cumulative” effect will overwhelm readers and lead ination of readers, and invite them into a world that
them to accept the cogency of the proposed thesis. is a representation: enticing, seductive, but ultimately
The upside of this gambit is that Dadlez can work unreal.
at a comfortable level of generality with the famil- This observation goes to the heart of Dadlez’s
iar elements of Hume’s philosophy (inter alia plea- thesis and while the wound is not mortal, when it
sure, sympathy, the general point of view, beauty, strikes home, the force is sufficient to upset the steady
views of marital relations, and an array of virtues rhythm with which the “cumulative” evidence is sup-
and vices) paraded in consecutive chapters along- posed to mount. While Austen’s novels and plots
side judicially chosen episodes and passages from leave one in no doubt as to the moral lessons the
Austen’s novels, designed to demonstrate the connec- reader should take away (think, most obviously, of
tion in question. Some of these juxtapositions elicit the transformation of Emma Woodhouse or Eliza-
insights that are original, informative, and a joy to beth Bennet), it is not easy to find much moraliz-
read, especially the latter chapters of the book where ing in Hume, who, as Dadlez herself comments in
Dadlez tackles chastity, fidelity, pride, jealousy, mal- a rather feeble plea for her case, is on “normative
ice, indolence, and industry. On the way, the reader is territory, surely” (p. 101). The main problem is that
also treated to spirited appropriations of Austen for even if Hume does venture into recommending cer-
Hume against Kantian (pp. 37ff.) and Aristotelian tain courses of action over others, it emerges as a mild
(pp. 46ff.) interlopers, a subtle rejection of preferring reflection and affirmation of the accurate description
Smith’s account of sympathy as adequate to appreci- and explanation of moral life he has provided: appro-
ating Austen (pp. 76ff.), some nicely developed criti- bation and disapprobation of action and character
cal appreciation of Austen’s literary style and narra- based on features of our nature (our affective capac-
tive skill (pp. 20ff.), and an impassioned disdain for ity, ability to sympathize, tendency to self-interest,
film and Masterpiece Theater adaptations of Austen’s and the like) that he captures in the explanatory prin-
ouvre to which only the Austen aficionado could rise ciple of utility and agreeableness to self and others.
(pp. 210ff.). Beyond this rather safe bet of living in the house
On the other hand, the downside of Dadlez’s at- he has himself confidently and carefully constructed,
tempt to convince the readers by sheer volume of Hume is largely silent on venturing into the “oughts”
evidence has the effect of blurring the outlines of of moral life, but often vocal in expressing his suspi-
the narrative and elicits the unsettling feeling that cion that the heated brains of philosophers (let alone
one cannot, as reader, pin down exactly what has the enthusiastic visions of fiction writers!) can emit
been established. Dadlez is forced to frame her dis- much of anything useful when it comes to directing
cussion in necessarily vague terms of ‘fit,’ ‘corre- our conduct.
spondence,’ ‘commonalities,’ ‘complimentarity,’ ‘cor- One cannot fail to appreciate the labor of love
relation,’ and the like, sufficiently ambiguous that that is Dadlez’s book, but, in the end, it tends to
it is hard actually to deny that the thesis has, in confirm Hume’s own express view about the limits
some sense, been proved. Dadlez clearly demon- of the philosopher-cum-moralizer and the contrasts
strates that one can plausibly describe Austen’s nov- between philosophy and fiction: there is less a “corre-
els in a Humean idiom by finding in them characters, spondence” between the worlds of Hume and Austen
passages, plots, and dialogue illustrative of Hume’s than an incommensurability that emerges, ironically,
moral philosophy. One can, pari passu, find in Hume in the very body of evidence marshaled by Dadlez
intimations of views fictionalized by Austen. Yet this with the intention of showing the very opposite. If
succeeds only if one casts the comparison, as Dadlez there is a mirror, to return to and conclude with her
Book Reviews 181

metaphor, it resembles more a specimen from a fun- age of a disaster (perhaps an ongoing disaster, or one
fair hall of mirrors than one into which the heroines still pending) that “comes to life out of the picture,
of Austen’s novels might peer to find, in their faithful makes demands, activates, tries to pull strings, hovers
reflection, some truth about themselves: what we see in the air, commands, seduces, repels, troubles, and
instead is more blurry and indistinct. irritates” (p. 375), that looks forward to some future
“rebuilding” (p. 36).
TIMOTHY M. COSTELLOE If all this sounds a bit overdramatic, consider that,
Department of Philosophy for Azoulay, every photographic image “always and
The College of William and Mary inescapably involves a measure of violence” (p. 99),
due to the necessary “instrumentalization” (p. 99)
azoulay, ariella. The Civil Contract of Photogra- of what is photographed. In a way it is as if ev-
phy. Zone Books and MIT Press, 2008, 585 pp., ery photograph exists “on the verge of catastrophe”
$36.95 cloth. (p. 289), but seeing this requires “collaboration”
(p. 411) with the photograph: “Watching as a spec-
Photography is public. Indeed, photography is a tator means thoroughly investigating the visual phe-
model of publicity, in all sorts of ways. Photographs nomenon . . . the spectator . . . seeks to reconstruct
publicize: they reveal; they make photographed the situation . . . from the surface of the photograph”
things publicly available (and to an ever-widening (p. 342). After “prolonged observation” (p. 168), af-
public); they create a public record of events. Every- ter “hours of looking, possibly days, weeks, or years”
one knows this, from the producers of celebrity gossip (p. 411), the photograph becomes something more
television shows to analytic philosophers. For exam- than “a picture on a wall” (p. 448): “Watching some-
ple, when Michael Tye, in Consciousness, Color, and thing as a spectator . . . allow[s] the visible to unfold,
Content (MIT Press, 2000), needs a quick argument like a picture in motion. . . . This motion does not be-
to show that we see external objects and not private long to what is seen, as in a movie, but to the specta-
sense data, he simply notes that the visual things he tor” (p. 342). The photograph itself does not project
is discussing can be photographed. Whether the pho- a world (as movies do, on Stanley Cavell’s view, for
tographable quality of certain visual things proves example), but rather “the gap between world and
Tye’s point is a question for another day, but Ariella picture” (p. 329) calls on the spectator “to take part
Azoulay would follow Tye here, if nowhere else. In . . . to take responsibility” (p. 169), to speak for the
The Civil Contract of Photography, Azoulay too in- photograph in some way or other: “Handicapped, the
sists that photography, no matter how baffling or her- image is not sufficient in itself and requires visual and
metic any particular photographic image may seem, verbal support, a spokesperson to bring it forth and
is necessarily public. have it speak” (p. 191).
Necessarily public, but also, for Azoulay, necessar- Azoulay criticizes both Roland Barthes and Su-
ily incomplete: every photographic image is “always, san Sontag for reducing the role of the spectator to
of necessity, the product of an encounter, even if a vi- the mere making of an “aesthetic judgment” (p. 130)
olent one, between a photographer, a photographed about the photograph. According to Azoulay, this
subject, and a camera” (p. 13), an encounter that aesthetic judgment model depends upon “the notion
moreover is always mute: “This is what photogra- of a stable meaning of what is visible in the pho-
phy is like by nature—lacking a mouth, speechless, tograph” (p. 130), “as though it were a given, easily
dumb at birth” (p. 448) and always limited. “In its accessible piece of visual data that can be determined
very essence, the image is partial, obscured, fissured, without any negotiation” (p. 311). Sontag, for exam-
and questionable” (p. 191). A photograph “attests to ple, ridicules “any attempt to start speaking for the
what ‘was there’ ” (p. 126), but “what was there is photo” (p. 130) as akin to some magical “attempt
never only what is visible in a photograph” (p. 127). to revive the dead” (p. 130), but for Azoulay that is
Every photograph tells parts of various stories, but at precisely the spectator’s duty: to “speak on behalf
the same time every photograph refuses to tell only of the photograph” (p. 117). A photograph requires
one story or to tell any story completely: a photo- support; it seeks “collaboration” (p. 411): “the pho-
graph “always includes more than one wants it to tograph wants something from me” (p. 375). And
contain” (p. 355). It is impossible to say what a pho- any spectator has standing, “as a plaintiff, rather than
tograph finally means or represents, and yet, it is an owner” (p. 117), to assist in the presentation of the
something, and the world somehow is there, how- photograph’s “grievance” (p. 143).
ever partially, in the photograph: “The photograph is Azoulay’s account of photography here resem-
out there, an object in the world, and anyone, always bles the general theory of interpretation Miguel
(at least in principle), can . . . trace it in such a way as Tamen develops in his dazzling Friends of Inter-
to reopen the image and renegotiate what it shows” pretable Objects (Harvard University Press, 2004).
(p. 13). For Azoulay, a photograph is like a kind of On Tamen’s view, an interpreter speaks for an other-
urgent ruin: an “opaque, dumb, distant” (p. 375) im- wise mute interpretable entity almost in the way an
182 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

attorney speaks for, represents, a client unable to raphy not only ripens the world for surveillance but
speak directly for itself (a corporation, say). Inter- also makes possible a reconstruction of a “hypothet-
pretable objects, for Tamen, require representation ical, imagined” (p. 23) public: “an international com-
in order to speak, but such objects are hardly static: munity of the governed” (p. 45). This accounts for
they often surprise their representatives, much as Azoulay’s focus on photographic engagements with
clients often surprise their lawyers. Azoulay’s view what she calls the “impaired citizenship” (p. 15) of
is similar: a viewer has a duty to try to speak for both Palestinians and women. Azoulay’s hope is that
the photograph, but the photograph may surprise the such photographic engagements make possible a hy-
viewer. A photograph may resist or evade a viewer’s pothetical reconstruction of universal citizenship, a
attempts to represent it, just as a client may resist reconstruction that rehabilitates sorts of citizenship
or evade a lawyer’s representative efforts. This un- that are currently impaired: “Photography . . . deter-
ending possibility of resistance and surprise makes ritorializes citizenship, reaching beyond its conven-
speaking for photographs a slippery and uneasy sort tional boundaries and plotting out a political space
of collaboration. It is far less demanding to assume in which the plurality of speech and action . . . is actu-
that a photograph is simply a straightforward record alized permanently by the eventual participation of
of “what ‘was there’ ” (p. 160), and that the character all of the governed” (p. 25).
of a photograph is thus graspable “at a glance” (p. The overall project is thus Rousseauian and post-
251) (“Oh, that’s a photograph from Abu Ghraib” structuralist, and like many a Rousseauian post-
[p. 272]), but for Azoulay, such casual looking re- structuralist before her, Azoulay overplays her hand.
mains aesthetically dim and ethically costless. Such The utopian and vaguely anarchistic desire for an inti-
an approach refuses to enter what Azoulay calls, a mate community from which power and humiliation
bit hazily, the civil contract of photography. have been banished is likely unsatisfiable, even in fan-
What does Azoulay’s title mean, exactly? Some- tasy. Certainly it appears to be well beyond what any-
thing like this: photographs address everyone. Any one could reasonably expect either photography or
photograph (even a photograph taken for a very par- contractarianism to deliver. At times, Azoulay drifts
ticular purpose, a crime scene photo, for example) toward acknowledging this, as when she notes that
may be examined by anyone who sees it. Traces of her “turn to the rhetoric of the contractarian tradition
the past (of a real event, a real encounter) are present . . . may seem curious” (p. 86). Indeed, it is curious,
in the photograph: “a photograph is evidence of the and in a number of ways. To mention only two: first,
social relations that made it possible” (p. 127). The the rhetoric of contract seems oddly suited to the stri-
meaning of the crime scene photo remains to be ne- dent urgency Azoulay brings to her encounters with
gotiated, and indeed, the purpose for which the pho- photography and, second, the use of social contract
tograph was taken (police record keeping) does not terminology raises the reader’s hopes that Azoulay
and cannot exhaust the photograph’s message. On has in mind some concrete political program, a pro-
Azoulay’s view, the crime scene photo calls out in gram that moreover will be built out of an ethical,
its mute, peculiar way to all sorts of viewers, in all civic, and aesthetic engagement with photography.
sorts of voices: one thinks, for example, of Weegee’s These wild hopes (for some kind of Benjaminian re-
brutally evocative crime scene photos, but also of construction of Friedrich von Schiller’s Letters on the
the strange mesmeric power sometimes found in the Aesthetic Education of Man [1795] perhaps filtered
most ordinary mug shot. This “heterogeneity” (p. through the work of T. M. Scanlon, say) are of course
199) of address “turns the photographic sign into an soon dashed. But to say that Azoulay fails because
active statement that can never be completely and she presents no workable political program is to miss
ultimately sealed” (p. 199). the crucial point: photographs disclose traces of the
Out of this photographic “instability” (p. 199), and past, and thus the past may sort of speak (ambigu-
drawing on a hodgepodge of philosophical sources ously and equivocally to be sure) through us and
(Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Walter Benjamin, Hannah to us. But this “us” is potentially universal, and ex-
Arendt, Jean-François Lyotard, and Giorgio Agam- tends far into the future. Azoulay sketches a way in
ben, among others), Azoulay cobbles together a which unending interpretive work may serve as a ve-
utopian notion of universal citizenship ostensibly me- hicle for political continuity, albeit of a virtual and
diated and made possible by photography: “photog- utopian sort, rather than as a barrier to such con-
raphy created a new community, in part actual and tinuity. Azoulay has thus somehow managed to use
in part virtual . . . a new political community . . . not photography to reconstruct a tentative notion of po-
mediated by a sovereign ruling power” (pp. 22–23). litical agency, however elusive and unstable it may be,
Thus, for Azoulay, “a viewing of the photograph . . . in the wake of post-structuralism. This, surely, counts
becomes a civic skill, not an exercise in aesthetic ap- as some sort of success.
preciation” (p. 14). And since “[t]he world cannot The Civil Contract of Photography is a frus-
be wiped clean of photography” (p. 345), since pho- trating book, no question. It is prolix, repetitive,
tography “is present everywhere” (p. 146), photog- high-handed, and cryptic. At times riddled with
Book Reviews 183

jargon, at times question begging, at times self- were a matter of word of mouth; she simply met with
congratulatory, the book has a grandiose flowery es- Morton White, then the director of graduate studies
chatological tone that exhausts and exasperates the in the department, and convinced him through con-
reader over the long course of more than five hun- versation that she could do the work. And she could
dred pages. And yet, something important is going do the work. Her literary sympathies were already
on here. The project of entering into never-ending firmly entrenched in the European avant-garde, en-
negotiations with photographs does serve to estab- tailing certain philosophical interests that were, by
lish a way to connect the sufferings of the past and and large, outside the mainstream of the Harvard
present to some future, forever imaginary, horizon philosophy department, but quality will out, and she
of justice. That this collaborative project is fraught developed avidity for issues of conceptual and epis-
with bizarre risks and ironies—Azoulay, for instance, temological holism and fell in with Quine’s version
writes compellingly about ways in which photographs of it. White has written that, should she have contin-
themselves may be used “as a mode of torture” ued in her philosophical studies, she would have as-
(p. 422) through the branding of photographed per- cended in philosophy to the same intellectual promi-
sons as “collaborators” (p. 423), in turn implicating nence she enjoyed in cultural and artistic criticism
the spectator’s collaboration with the photograph in (A Philosopher’s Story [Pennsylvania State Univer-
a kind of collaboration with the torture—comes as no sity Press, 1999], pp. 148–149). As it is, she went to
surprise. What is surprising, however, is that Azoulay Oxford on a Fulbright the next year, and although
partially succeeds at the seemingly impossible task she was impressed by Hart and Austin (but not by
she sets herself: using photography to allow the dead Berlin), she decamped to Paris at the end of fall
to speak, and in surprising ways. and never looked back. She came into her own in
France, meeting public intellectuals, reading cutting-
edge philosophy and literature, obsessively attending
CHAD MCCRACKEN the cinema, and discovering her sexuality. After the
Department of Philosophy year, she returned to the States, to a divorce and cus-
Lake Forest College tody battle for her son, and plunged into the perilous
waters of the New York intellectual scene, waters she
lopate, phillip. Notes on Sontag. Princeton Univer- later would come to dominate.
sity Press, 2009, vi + 247 pp., $19.95 cloth. Reborn: Journals and Notebooks 1947–1963 is a
selection from Sontag’s journals from the age of four-
sontag, susan. Reborn: Journals and Notebooks teen to the year of the publication of her first mature
1947–1963. Edited by David Rieff. New York: Far- work, the novel The Benefactor (1963). The journal
rar, Straus and Giroux, 2008, xiv + 318 pp., $25.00 (she is very careful not to conceive of these note-
cloth. books as “diaries” [Reborn, pp. 164–165]) is divis-
ible into three main biographical periods: Sontag’s
We live in a time in which intellectual labor is teenage years up through her time in college and
treated as almost synonymous with academic labor marriage to Rieff, the period she spent in Oxford
and in which fastidious scholarship ranging over very and Paris, and her entry into New York literary life.
circumscribed areas of concern defines intellectual One gets three main impressions from the entries
worth. Judged in terms of its ultimate coherence that cover the initial period. First, she is quite gifted.
or technical accuracy, Susan Sontag’s achievement “Self-possessed” does not exactly do justice to this,
will always come up short in the academy. But that written by a fifteen-year-old girl: “What seemed once
doesn’t really matter. Her main importance (and to be a crushing weight has sharply shifted position,
surely she knew and even calculated this) rests in in a surprising tactic, swung beneath my fleeing feet,
how she presented herself in her work as a perform- become a sucking force that drags and tires me. How
ing intellect: a passionate thinker pursuing complex, I long to surrender! How easy it would be to convince
interesting, and, in some cases, novel ideas, all the myself of the plausibility of my parents’ life! . . . Does
while surrounded by the atmosphere of herself. my ‘intelligence’ need frequent rejuvenation at the
From childhood on she considered herself spe- springs of other’s [sic] dissatisfaction and die without
cial. Sontag was precocious, entering college when it?” (Reborn, p. 5). Second, she feels hemmed in by
she was fifteen, transferring to Chicago because she her home life. Her family is deeply bourgeois and
found Berkeley too mundane, and graduating at the her suburban high school is a bore. As it turns out,
top of her class. At seventeen she married the soci- they weren’t so bourgeois, and she was not quite free
ologist Philip Rieff and gave birth to a son two years from that constraint. These adolescent sentiments are
later. Then it was off to Harvard where she began in hardly new, but her expression of them (as imping-
the English department, but transferred over to phi- ing upon a developmental path she feels already her
losophy within the year. Such transfers at that time life’s task to tread, that is, to be “intellectual”) is
184 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

less common. The way she conceives of this path and which she never covers, if several basic grammati-
its relation to art, literature, music, and philosophy cal errors in the journals are any indication. There is
is, nevertheless, oddly consumerist. She treats such a rather strained relation between Sontag’s wish to
things as objects to “possess” or “own,” an attitude experience European culture at its deepest and her
quite consistent from beginning to end of these jour- lack of the discipline that would put her in the best
nals (Reborn, pp. 19, 306). List follows upon list of position to do so, for instance, learning languages
films to see, books to read, music to hear, as if having well. This tension imposed itself on Sontag’s intellec-
the experience of any one of them might amount to tual dealings throughout her career. She was taken
merely ticking a box next to its entry in the list. The to task at times for superficiality and pretension, and
young make such lists of course. I recall one having the championing of her European favorites is apt to
to do with learning all the languages and sources for seem less compelling when one suspects that either
the allusions in Pound’s Cantos. This autobiographi- she is not reading them in the original or, if she is, that
cal aside on my part points to an interesting feature of she does not have sufficient linguistic knowledge to
these notebooks. If one, in retrospect at least, views fully appreciate their literary merit. One simply can-
one’s youth as tending toward becoming intellectu- not read Lautréamont, Mallarmé, or Proust with any
ally able, one will be prompted to such thoughts (and real comprehension unless one speaks the language
asides) in reading Reborn. The sixteen-year-old Su- quite well. It seems that she was so intent on pos-
san will endear with her admonition to herself to use sessing these works, on incorporating them into her
the word ‘enormous’ correctly (and she does [Re- sense of all-things-Sontag, that she could not bear
born, p. 30]). Her chutzpah in showing up on Thomas to be slowed down by the drudgery of acquiring lin-
Mann’s southern California doorstep to “interview” guistic competence. Still, her advocacy could work in
him will delight. the face of such suspicions. I remember quite well
She is agog with Mann, although comes later to reading her endorsement of Péter Nádas’s A Book
regard this as a youthful indiscretion, demoting him of Memories (1986) and picking it up on that basis
(quite properly) below her favorite, Kafka. Another alone, never mind what I supposed was her lack of
early soul mate is Gide, but it is, tellingly, Djuna Hungarian (and what I knew to be mine).
Barnes’s Nightwood (1936) that keeps popping up The third biographical period finds Sontag in New
in the journal again and again. This leads to the third York in the midst of the Partisan Review crowd, her
point to make about the early journals: Sontag comes transformation from academic to intellectual com-
to the knowledge that she is lesbian. It is sometimes plete. She writes in 1956 that “college instruction is a
said that she was bisexual (she even said so at times), brand of popular culture; the universities are poorly
and, to be sure, she had sexual relationships with run mass media” (Reborn, p. 81). True, true, yet we
men. But these relationships were few, far between, find her in academics too, first at Sarah Lawrence
short (often ending up in a kind of domestic monasti- College and, then, at Columbia. The essayist Phillip
cism), and quite unsatisfying (for her at least). She an- Lopate, a student at Columbia at that time, knew
nounces early on and “reluctantly” in the notebooks her then and since and has written a comprehensive
that she is lesbian; but the reluctance has nothing to and judicious assessment of her achievement in his
do with possible mistake on the topic. It rather has Notes on Sontag. Lopate deems Sontag’s first three
to do with coming to state what she knows to be a collections of essays (Against Interpretation [1966],
fact. The overwhelming impression one gets here is Styles of Radical Will [1969], and Under the Sign of
of someone who embraces her sexuality realistically. Saturn [1980]) preeminent both in her corpus and in
Her loves were not easy, and this comes clear in the genre of the modern intellectual essay (Notes on
the second period covered by Reborn. Sontag writes Sontag, p. 8). He is surely right in both assessments.
of her fraught passion for “H”: Harriet Sommers, a He is also right, it seems to me, to rate her fiction in
habituée of James Baldwin’s circle in Paris, some- the main to be “poor” and “derivative” (Notes, p. 9),
time artistic model, and translator into English of although I would not make the exception that he does
Sade. This last vocation is highly relevant; for all of for the late novel The Volcano Lover (1992), which,
her self-awareness, it seems to have never dawned indeed, is not derivative but lacks artistry nonethe-
on Sontag that she was involved in a sadomasochistic less. How much does Sontag’s lack of accomplish-
relationship. The other great love of her youth was ment in art color her overall achievement? I would
the playwright Maria Irene Fornes, another relation- say: not much. The brilliance of her criticism more
ship in which Sontag played second fiddle, this time than makes up for her schematic and unconvincing
as too cerebral and withdrawn. Nonetheless, Paris is novels and films. After all, how many great critics are
a revelation. There is a seriousness of mind there that also great fiction writers, playwrights, or poets? How
makes philosophy at Harvard and Oxford seem te- many great fiction writers, playwrights, or poets are
dious and desiccated. Despite her desire to immerse great critics, for that matter? But failing to make the
herself in the scene there, her French lags, a deficit grade artistically would have mattered to her a great
Book Reviews 185

deal (for example, Reborn, p. 166). And this is part of less accepted fact by adopting a pragmatic attitude
the story that Lopate wants to tell. That is, Sontag’s of intellectual “wait and see,” one is gripped by the
writerly self-creation consists in passionate relation- thought that every form of assertion is fraught with
ships to the art of others in which she measures her unseen problems and that what freedom amounts to
competencies against theirs. This is the essence of the is the capacity to think one’s way out of any asser-
sense of judgment operative in her essays. Sontag’s tion. It is a form of irony, although it is not a very
work, at least the best of it, demands that she per- enjoyable one, and its classic text is Adorno’s Min-
form this high-wire act of putting herself on the line ima Moralia (1974) (Notes, p. 91). Any essay with
by putting others on it as well. a claim to be truly critical must set up an internal
Notes is full of perceptive criticism of Sontag, nega- tension; it arrests the reader with an insight that is
tive and positive. Perhaps most impressive is Lopate’s enough separated from the dross of ideology to pro-
assessment of the way the early essays express the vide some measure of relief without, however, taking
general scheme of Sontag writing herself into exis- itself to be so unproblematic as to hold out hope of
tence. As he puts it, the issue is “how she came to put deliverance.
forth the complicated identity of ‘Susan Sontag’ over Does Sontag intend her essays to be of this kind,
the course of her books, how she created this part- and are they? I agree with Lopate that the answer
intentional, part-inadvertent persona, and to some to the first question is affirmative. I am less sanguine
extent become a prisoner of it, while at other times about such a response to the second. That is, I am less
she was able to slip the knot of our expectations and accepting than is Lopate that she pulls it off even in
augment her worldliness” (Notes, p. 6). Lopate quite some of her most formidable early essays. It is unar-
correctly locates the literary precursor of those es- guable that Sontag remained a tourist in the land
says in a specific form of aphoristic writing that one of Kafka, Benjamin, and Adorno. This is a land she
finds in the early Frankfurt School. German letters cherished deeply, but her essays do not disassemble
borrow much in this vein from the French tradition themselves at the brink of assertion as do the best of
of La Rochefoucauld, Vauvenargues, and Chamfort, this genre. Hers are more assertive, in essence more
but put a twist on this, producing a distinctive line American, and the tensions that are constitutive of
running from Lichtenberg and the Schlegels down to even her very best essays are often more a matter of
Benjamin and Adorno that is important to Sontag. irresolution than resolve. In the early work, the com-
The use of “fragments” and the short pungent essay ponents in tension are typically fealty to some type
that Nietzsche perfected are extensions of this apho- of aesthetic formalism, on the one hand, and to the
ristic impulse. These literary forms allow thoughts quasi-moral requirements of the cultural critic, on
expressed by their means a potent indeterminacy. the other. Lopate is right to emphasize the neglected
Lopate holds that such writing involves “a statement essay “The Aesthetics of Silence” and perhaps her
that moves in two directions at once. It raises and greatest achievement, “Notes on ‘Camp,’ ” as center-
resolves a paradox; it leaves behind an after-image, pieces of her critical practice in this vein. But I remain
like an op art painting the clash of whose two colors more skeptical than Lopate that even these essays re-
produce a third on the retina. . . . Kafka’s plausible- alize what he takes to be their core intentions. I would
gnomic style . . . fascinated Benjamin and Adorno, attribute the ambivalence present in this work more
and their sentences at times seemed modeled on to the subject matter of the essays (the interrelation
his ability to achieve uncannily disillusioned effects” of the triads: high culture–low culture–gay sensibility;
(Notes, p. 92). silence–irony–popular culture) than to any formal di-
This compact and extraordinarily apt statement of mension of the pieces.
the power of the aphorism in its modernist form limns Lopate’s discussion of Sontag’s modernist creden-
an aspect of Sontag’s early essayistic practice. Disil- tials also engages. Artistic modernism is sometimes
lusion and demystification are important for Sontag, considered a progressive doctrine according to which
as they were for her predecessors; both are reactions the arts, subject perhaps to restrictions native to their
to an alleged pervasive falseness that systematically various genres, advance stepwise toward ideal ends.
dominates the standard and basic means by which But this progressive thesis does not sit well with Son-
one might reveal such falseness. In view of this pos- tag’s aestheticism or with her reliance on “negative
sibility, critical intelligence must exercise constant dialectics.” So, she replaces the concept “progres-
vigilance lest it, too, unwittingly succumb to the ef- sive” with the concept “radical” (Notes, pp. 86–88).
fects of illusion. In fact, one can never know that one One can be enjoined to “go to one’s root” without in-
has not fallen prey. This requires a radical readjust- volving progression in any standard sense. And here
ment of rationality away from explanation toward we see the other, less overtly modernist side of Son-
interpretation and away from conceptual security to- tag once more. She abjures realism as an aesthetic
ward a form of skepticism. Instead of confronting doctrine; nevertheless, she is a kind of ethical realist
uncertainty against a general background of more or for whom the imperative “get radical” is the exact
186 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

opposite of “keep turning on the spit of critical intel- deal with such things” [tr. P. Green]). Sontag was not
ligence.” When she asks for an “erotics of art” in the so calculating. Sometimes “unpleasant medicines”
famous ultimate line of “On Interpretation,” she is were all that she was prepared to offer, rivals be
neither asking for simple rapture (erotics is a branch damned.
of knowledge after all) nor for a constant juggling of Sontag was ubiquitous in the New York that she
concepts. She wants a connection of the seriousness dearly loved, and many have stories of her. What was
of art with the seriousness of the project of becoming my Sontag moment? It came in 1990 at a party after
a person. a preopening screening of Pedro Almodóvar’s film
Sontag was a great one for pronouncements or, ¡Átame! at the old Limelight in New York. This was
one might say, renouncements. She was “against in- Almodóvar prior to his turn to melodrama, and the
terpretation,” “against metaphor,” “against photog- party was camp on stilts. The stars were abundant
raphy,” and so forth. What she was truly against, and (Pedro Almodóvar, Antonio Banderas, Penélope
what unites these cases, was psychologism. She was Cruz, and Liza Minelli were there), the music loud,
schooled in this temperament in both her studies of and strobe lights pumped in time, making it all seem
analytic and European philosophy; she understood like an outtake from 8 1/2. I believe there were peo-
Freud non-psychologistically as a “moralist” (Notes, ple in animal masks. I recall Liza sliding down a fire
pp. 73–74), and her tastes in literature, film, and mu- pole trailing a feather boa. Absolutely distinctively,
sic (in short, her love of aesthetic surfaces) bear this with her signature hair, white shock amid black, Son-
out. She was, in a way, classical in her outlook. But tag made her way through the heaving throng. It did
she leavened this with the nascent literature in erotic not part for her as would a crowd of her admirers
power and its political place. (Sontag was an early at a proper New York cocktail party. This tribe was
reader of Norman O. Brown, and Herbert Marcuse oblivious to who she was. Yet, that didn’t seem to
was her houseguest for a year in Cambridge.) A judg- matter to her. She was taking it all in: the Queen of
ment for her is precisely not a psychological report Camp, incognito in her own realm. Right by me she
of an opinion; it is rather a form of self-care and went. I didn’t dare speak.
discipline. Beyond this of course she could play the
role of the disciplinarian of others and of their tastes, FRED RUSH
and many were taken aback, and taken aback of- Department of Philosophy
ten, by her rigidity. It is undeniable that she could be University of Notre Dame
doctrinaire, but she was able to reconsider her judg-
ments, for example, her somewhat positive appraisal krausz, michael, denis dutton and karen bards-
of Riefenstahl’s films (“On Style” vs. “Fascinating ley, eds. The Idea of Creativity. Leiden, The
Fascism”). And she did modulate some of the more Netherlands: Brill Academic, 2009, 350 pp.,
apocalyptic utterances of On Photography (1977), $147.00 cloth.
where every photographer was saddled with being
“Diane Arbus” (even Diane Arbus) and in which The Idea of Creativity invites the reader to reflect on
the constant barrage of visual media was criticized as questions of creativity by presenting seventeen es-
sapping any real response to the images, the latter a says on various aspects of scholarly research on the
view straight out of Adorno. It is fair to say that she subject. All seventeen are solid and fascinating inves-
held views firmly but not with fixation. This is con- tigations into this vexing area, and each one leaves
sistent with her conception of critical judgment as a the reader, if not completely satisfied, at least bet-
species of caring for oneself. One would not be caring ter equipped to think about creativity. Like the blind
for the self very well if one were not willing to recon- men and the proverbial elephant, each writer offers
sider prior attempts to exercise that care. Self-care is his or her perspective on the subject while at the same
not self-certifying; it admits of error. time leaving the impression that no one has com-
Similarly, in her personal dealings Sontag could be pletely accounted for it. Nevertheless, one’s thinking
curt, dismissive, and even rude. Lopate recounts sev- about creativity will be enhanced by reading this vol-
eral incidents in which Sontag’s intellectualism and ume. Though most of the chapters were written at dif-
lack of social skill combine to poor effect. I suspect ferent times and do not directly address each other,
she rationalized some of this behavior as a kind of nine were written specifically for this volume and do
“tough love,” but it was measured out usually with often seem complementary. Interestingly, eight of the
at least a pinch of self-regard. In Ars Amatoria Ovid essays are reprinted from an earlier ten-essay book,
dispenses wise counsel on the subject of the proper The Concept of Creativity (Martinus Nijhoff, 1981),
solicitude of lover to beloved: “neve cibo prohibe nec edited by Dutton and Krausz. A perfectionist might
amari pocula suci/porrige; rivalis misceat illa tuus” wonder why eight-tenths of a twenty-eight-year-old
(II.335–336) (“Never restrict her diet, never make book was reprinted without comment, especially in
her drink unpleasant/Medicines: leave your rival to light of the fact that two of the three previous editors
Book Reviews 187

are the same and the book has a similar title. This is so-called creative people produce were arrived at
no objection, however; all of the exquisitely written through trial and error mediated by self-critical stan-
chapters here have something deep and interesting to dards. This point dovetails nicely into Dean Keith
say about the topic, and the added chapters of more Simonton’s chapter, where the author argues that
recent origin give the book even more breadth than Darwin’s theory is in fact a theory of creativity in-
the original. sofar as it explains how new forms arise from old.
The book has three parts, though the delineation Like Jarvie, Simonton emphasizes the creative pro-
is rough and sometimes appears downright arbitrary. cess, one that is guided by both chance and constraint.
The aim of Part One, “Explaining Creativity: Persons, Here we may find something of a formula for creativ-
Processes, and Products,” is to draw attention to one ity. One should work on several problems concur-
or another site of creativity and attempts to sepa- rently in order to take advantage of insights in one
rate what has been said of value on the topic from domain arising and thus being available to be em-
what has been simplistic and misleading in previous ployed in another. Interestingly, this setup operates
theorizing. Carl Hausman, employing a phenomeno- on another higher level insofar as creative persons
logical approach, reasons that creativity only makes tend to be those who are easily distracted and thus are
sense in light of some result, so that the product is constantly “blindly” scanning the environment for
primary over both the person and the process. He interesting associations to fit together. In addition,
further argues that the idea of “newness” is intrin- creative development appears to be enhanced when
sically important to any idea of a creative outcome. individuals are exposed to multicultural and multilin-
(This idea crops up again and again throughout the guistic influences. Moreover, Simonton argues that
book.) Certainly “newness” simpliciter won’t suffice successfully creative works tend to be produced by
for an understanding of creativity, for simply saying those people who produce the highest number of
that something is “new” would include too much, for unsuccessful works. So if you want to increase your
instance, a boy learning math tables, which is new but percentage of hits, increase your output, thus also
arguably not “creative.” Nevertheless, starting with increasing the number of misses. Berys Gaut takes
the concept “newness” allows Hausman to derive cri- up the theme of randomness within constraints by
teria from it: creative outcomes are those composed focusing on the creative process, which, he argues,
of irreducibly intelligible structures that are unpre- involves skill. Against the traditional view that holds
dictable, inherently instrumentally valuable, and with that a creative process is one that gives rise to a prod-
a component of spontaneity. Larry Briskman too uct that is innovative and valuable, Gaut maintains
maintains that the search for an explanation for cre- that a creative act is a kind of skill that is performed
ativity must be found in creative products, not pro- by one who has the courage to revise and redirect
cesses or persons. For Briskman, the creative product routine paths in new ways.
is a transcendent one, by which he means a novel so- Peter Lamarque’s chapter appears to depart some-
lution to a problem that nevertheless conflicts with what from the process–product–person debate, as he
the background constraints of a tradition but at the deals with the issue of how artworks arise in the
same time is seen as an appropriate solution, one world, arguing that an artwork is not just a rearrange-
that has internal connections to what came before. ment or revision of something already in the world;
As opposed to a mechanistic, random, or teleological rather, artworks can only come into existence against
approach, Briskman argues that a Darwinian model a background of cultural practices. And this can only
can most powerfully explain how such creative prod- occur when the artist finishes (that is, knows when to
ucts can arise. The Darwinian model gives rise to stop) fashioning a work rather than abandoning it.
plasticity on the one hand, in that the producer of In the second section of the book, “Creativity,
creative products must be willing to go against tra- Imagination, and Self,” processes are once again
dition in searching for solutions to problems, and to taken up, along with questions surrounding their ef-
control on the other, insofar as the producer must fects. Paisley Livingston, employing some ideas from
work within the constraints of the job specification Henri Poincaré, observes that creative persons are
for the discipline. those who take time to let their ideas “incubate,” but
Taking a different tack, the next two chapters em- that this is not to be confused with being completely
phasize processes over products or persons. I. C. idle. Creative persons are those who let their psy-
Jarvie proposes that only a rational process can result chological processes work on preselected elements.
in creative products. In fact, Jarvie suggests that we Michael Polanyi uses scientific advancements as ex-
might dispense with the word ‘creativity’ for words amples to argue that creativity in science stems from
like ‘simple,’ ‘unifying,’ or ‘trail-blazing,’ since what imagination guided by intuition. The kind of intu-
the word finally means is something like a successful ition Polanyi has in mind apparently involves the be-
solution to “an artistic or cognitive problem” (p. 55). lief that the scientist is one whose understanding of
For Jarvie, then, the focus is on a rational process the universe is guided by a “gradient of deepening
rather than a mysterious product, since the actions coherence.”
188 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Francis Sparshott’s chapter, one that seems a bit ing in Arthur Koestler’s chapter. Koestler envisions
out of place in the otherwise theoretical content of artistic originality, scientific discovery, and comic in-
the rest of the articles, is nevertheless a welcome re- spiration as constituting a continuum of creativity. He
lief from so much theorizing. Reflecting on his prac- coins the term ‘bisociation’ to make the point that
tice as a poet, he observes that creativity involves a creative ideas come from associations made from
special kind of attending, one whose purpose is to different contexts. The comic, for instance, is one
produce something original and unpredictable. Only who tells a story whose climax involves information
an inexperienced writer has themes “come to him.” from a different context. Similarly, where the comic
The experienced poet is one who knows how to find shows different contexts colliding, the creative sci-
themes to work with; he seeks them out. Here again, entist shows different contexts fusing together into a
routine is coupled with selection. Sparshott says that new whole and the artist juxtaposes two contexts in
the experienced poet has a kind of preset schema, an artwork.
“his own way of working,” though he does not know Rom Harrè argues that the creative scientist is
how he does it. Like Sparshott, Michael Krausz be- one who finds an icon or a model with which to make
gins from personal experience. Painting, says Krausz, sense of the world, and that the supporting evidence
is something he does because the process fosters a never justifies it but rather serves as metaphor and
“self-transformation.” In this way, art is not some- illustration in the understanding of the icon (one may
thing he does to produce artworks; rather it is a be reminded of Kuhn here). Thomas Leddy argues
“personal program.” Krausz interestingly compares that a reader helps to create a literary work by way
his own transformational experiences to “religious,” of her interpretation of that work, not as a replace-
“oceanic,” or “flow” experiences where the gap be- ment for the writer’s creativity, but as an augmen-
tween subject and object is dissolved. tation of it. Moreover, one’s interpretation is always
Citing Hegel and Heidegger as his point of de- made from a worldview, the interpretation also serv-
parture, Albert Hofstadter invites us to think about ing to partially constitute that worldview. John Car-
creativity from the perspective of “dialectical phe- valho employs the thought of Gilles Deleuze to argue
nomenology,” where the artist is one who tries to that creativity in philosophy occurs when the philoso-
find a unity between form and content in order to de- pher retrieves a concept contained in the flow of
velop a new totality. Hofstadter uses the master–slave thought that is already present in the world. Creativ-
idea from Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit (1807) to ity, then, is not so much an adding, but rather a kind of
show how the struggle between master and slave is subtracting.
analogous to the struggle between the artist and his The Idea of Creativity is certainly not a how-to
medium. Moreover, the relation is also analogous book on how to be creative, but one can learn a great
with the struggle between a child and his world and, deal about how to be creative if one reads closely.
in fact, with every creative person and the world. Though treating the subject for the most part the-
It seems to me that the chapter by David Davies oretically, embedded in the many conceptual twists
only indirectly concerns creativity, in that his main and turns are hints at how one might go about in-
focus is to maintain that some facts about the history creasing one’s creativity, or at least increasing the
of an artwork’s making are relevant to understanding likelihood of producing something new, surprising,
it. Although Davies is against aesthetic realism (the and valuable. A reviewer writing about the 1981 ver-
view that only properties experientially apparent are sion of this book implied that there was little of value
relevant to interpretation), he does hold that the rele- in it. I disagree. While certainly not for the casual
vant historical properties are those that bear on one’s reader looking for light summer reading, The Idea of
experience of a work. In addition, many times the Creativity will deeply enhance one’s thinking on the
relevant historical properties are those that reveal subject and should serve to stimulate debate about
originality and a creative process at work, which can, the essential ingredients of creative processes, prod-
in turn, only be seen against a background of cultural ucts, and persons for many years to come.
conventions.
In section three, “Forms and Domains of Creativ- PHIL JENKINS
ity,” Margaret Boden, a cognitive scientist, argues Philosophy Department
that there are three different kinds of creativity: com- Marywood University
binatorial, exploratory, and transformational. One
interesting result of Boden’s research is the insight stock, kathleen and katherine thomson-jones, eds.
that if we want our children to become more creative New Waves in Aesthetics. New York: Palgrave
we need to encourage novel experiences in their edu- Macmillan, 2008, xix + 269 pp., $95.00 cloth, $38.00
cation, and work hard to foster their self-confidence paper.
by not always punishing them for breaking the rules
and engaging in surprising and unusual behaviors. Analytic philosophy of art is alive and doing well at
Another surprising result comes from the theoriz- the start of the twenty-first century. New Waves in
Book Reviews 189

Aesthetics charts the range of topics and practices once questions of beauty and the aesthetic drop out of
that define a healthy, growing field of research that the demarcation equation as merely contingent fea-
is integrated into the mainstream of analytic philoso- tures of only some artworks. These types of questions
phy. This contrasts starkly with the mid-twentieth- can only be answered by an examination of the prac-
century conception of aesthetics as a myopic and tices associated with particular works. Therefore, the
derivative field dedicated to discussions of the na- artistic turn in analytic aesthetics leads naturally out
ture of judgments about beauty, discussions whose of the armchair and into the field. Furthermore, ana-
resolution would ultimately depend upon the out- lytic philosophers of art borrow a range of tools from
come of discussions of moral value. It also contrasts metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy
with a late twentieth-century view of aesthetics as of mind. In this regard philosophers of art treat art-
a second-order pursuit dedicated to the clarification works as instances of the ordinary categories of ob-
of concepts and distinctions borrowed from produc- jects and mental events particular to those branches
tive and critical artistic practices. These perspectives of philosophy. Investigations of artworks and associ-
identified aestheticians as second-class citizens, out- ated mental events can, as a result, contribute to re-
siders in between and alienated from the artistic lated discussions within those philosophical domains
and philosophical practices that defined their sub- (for example, discussions of the nature of metaphor
ject matter and discipline. The papers in this volume or investigations of the role imagination plays in in-
speak against this view. First, clarifications of con- terpretation). These discussions, in turn, clarify our
cepts like ‘art,’ ‘music,’ ‘beauty,’ ‘expression,’ and understanding of the differences between different
‘imagination’ involve questions about the particular art forms and the nature of our engagement with art.
objects and practices that fall within their extensions. Therefore the reciprocity between analytic aesthet-
Therefore, conceptual clarification in the philosophy ics and other domains of philosophy generalizes to
of art is in part a first-order empirical project that the first-order critical practices associated with our
includes a direct examination of particular artworks. understanding of art. The papers in this book reflect
Second, this artistic turn has enabled aestheticians this framework for analytic aesthetics.
to have a direct impact on the productive and criti- The contemporary focus within analytic aesthet-
cal practices of art, for example, the critical writing of ics on particular artworks and artistic practices is
Arthur Danto. Finally, and perhaps most importantly, a distinct virtue. A willingness to struggle through
the analytic turn in aesthetics has demonstrated that methodological challenges raised by difficult con-
the range of issues germane to our understanding temporary works guarantees that philosophy of art
of art do not lie outside the mainstream of analytic is philosophy of art and not simply philosophy for
philosophy. philosophy’s sake. This focus is most strongly illus-
The thirteen original papers collected in this vol- trated in the papers by Sherri Irvin, Dustin Stokes,
ume are arranged in a loosely topical order. They Aaron Meskin, Stacie Friend, and Jonathan Wein-
include discussions of the ontology of art, the nature berg. A recurrent theme among these papers is that
of metaphor, the nature of creativity, definitions of standard difficulties for a definition of “art” general-
art, aesthetic judgments, the nature of aesthetic prop- ize to definitions of particular artforms. Consider,
erties, imagination, the relationship between history for instance, Irvin’s discussion of Felix Gonzalez-
of aesthetics and contemporary philosophy of art, Torres’s Untitled (Portrait of Ross in L.A.) (1985),
and questions about the way artifacts can be used to a pile of hard candies to be eaten and replenished
express emotions. The diversity of topics presented throughout the duration of its installation. The strate-
reflects a central unifying goal of analytic aesthet- gic promise of a definition of particular arts strategy
ics. Questions about beauty and the aesthetic do not lies in the hope that, perhaps because they were tradi-
exhaust the range of substantive questions that one tionally defined by static media and single perceptual
can ask about art. Artworks are a diverse lot loosely modalities (for example, vision, color, and light for
divided into categories by a range of distinct media painting or hearing, sound, and tonal structure for
and practices. Once upon a time these differences music), particular art forms will yield homogenous
were thought to be subordinated to a set of common categories of objects. However, this hope is compli-
goals, the presentation of beauty and the production cated by the fact that our critical and appreciative
of aesthetic experience. However, twentieth-century practices are constrained by the range of parame-
art was indefatigably focused on driving a wedge be- ters an artist sanctions for the presentation of his or
tween art and the concepts of beauty and the aes- her work. Irvin argues that this fact renders even the
thetic (for example, Mario Mertz’s arte povera instal- canonical category of “visual artworks” problematic.
lations, John Cage’s As SLow aS Possible [1985], and Gonzalez-Torres’s piece illustrates the trouble. The
Vito Acconci’s Following Piece [1969] and Seedbed nature of this work is not transparent in its publicly
[1972]). Ontological and epistemic questions about accessible physical form, but rather emerges from the
the individuation of art forms rise to the forefront set of instructions provided for its presentation. The
190 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

intentions of the artist are the sole source of con- genuinely engaging with art when one writes about
straints on the presentation of the work in this case. it.
Why is this a difficulty? Because, generally, there A second central theme in this book is that the
are no natural medium-specific constraints on the in- field can make substantive contributions to philo-
tentions of an artist. Therefore, the probability that sophical debates in core analytic topics. This strain
there are a common set of defining features for any of argument comes through most clearly in Andrew
category of artwork grounded in publicly accessible Kania’s discussion of musical ontology, Andrew Mc-
shared aspects of a medium is negligible. Gonigal’s discussion of Davidson’s error theory of
I am sympathetic to Irvin’s point. However, I have metaphor, and Saam Trivedi’s discussion of musical
one small quibble with her arguments that illustrates metaphor and paraphrase. But it is also present in
the importance of engaging with particular artworks Dustin Stokes’s and Jonathan Weinberg’s papers on
and associated critical practices. Irvin argues that her creativity and imagination. Kania argues that musical
case study demonstrates that the category “visual art- works are deeply perplexing, temporally extended,
work” lacks clear defining parameters. This is likely abstract objects that challenge our basic metaphysi-
true. Contemporary artists (as contrasted with, say, cal notions. He argues, following Amie Thomasson,
Maine Plein Air painters) simply do not make ob- that if musical ontology doesn’t fit well to off-the-rack
jects, let alone objects whose identity is constrained categories borrowed from metaphysics, the problem
by discrete media. And this is the rub. Untitled (Por- may not lie with philosophy of art, but with meta-
trait of Ross in L.A.) is not a visual artwork. It is physics itself. Grappling with these types of thorny
a conceptual artwork. Consider Sol LeWitt’s location problems may therefore be just as good for the goose
drawings. LeWitt would fax galleries sets of scribbled as it is for the gander. Likewise, metaphor is a cen-
instructions that loosely defined the relative sizes and tral formal device used in both literature and music.
positions of the elements of the drawings. But the ex- Works of literature and music can therefore provide
ecution and final form of these works was left to the a well-articulated context in which a central aspect of
installation staff who drew them on the gallery walls. language can be studied.
Lewitt argued that the work itself was the idea in the The papers in this volume exemplify the diverse
artist’s head, and that its execution was perfunctory. range of interests of a vibrant and expanding field.
Of course, LeWitt’s drawings are rather beautiful and However, there is one new wave in analytic aesthetics
his assistants get paid quite well to carefully supervise that is underrepresented. Jonathan Weinberg, Aaron
their execution to this day. But his point can still be Meskin, and Dustin Stokes have each made signifi-
taken. The differences between particular instances cant contributions to our understanding of the rela-
of these works do not matter ontologically. What mat- tionship between cognitive science and the philoso-
ters is the idea they exhibit, an idea that includes phy of art. Their papers in this volume reflect these
within it the variability of its particular instantiation contributions. However, these papers also explic-
at any time. In this regard Gonzalez-Torres’s piece is itly downplay the importance of empirical research
not a difficult visual artwork. It is a traditional con- to philosophical questions about art. The sentiment
ceptual artwork that pays homage to and, in classic seems to be that, although we should be method-
form, pokes mischievous fun at its precursors. The ological scavengers who draw on any and all relevant
candy matters. The variability of the size of the pile interdisciplinary information in our research, some
matters. Even eating the candy matters. The mate- form of good old-fashioned conceptual analysis is the
rial embodiment of the work is therefore no more most efficient and perhaps the only appropriate way
perfunctory in this case than it is in LeWitt’s. Nor to get at genuine answers to the problems of analytic
are its aesthetic dimensions mere eye candy. They aesthetics. My concern with this sentiment is, in one
firmly ground the work within its category (as we ca- sense, a matter of taste. New Waves is a collection of
sually enjoy the sweets we symbolically eat the body papers at the metaphysicians’ end of our field. In this
of Ross, enacting a range of semantic associations re- regard, it makes sense to downplay issues in cogni-
lated to AIDS, homosexuality, and Catholicism that tive science. But there is another sense in which it is a
are salient to the content of the work). The relation- substantive question. If one interprets artworks as ar-
ship between the artist’s sanction and the ontology tifacts intentionally designed to direct consumers’ at-
of the work are therefore not problematic. They are tention to nonaesthetic features responsible for their
standard for an entrenched category of art whose his- artistically salient aesthetic and semantic effects, then
tory stretches back at least as far as the collaboration cognitive science will play a critical role in the ontol-
between Merce Cunningham and John Cage. I take ogy of art. If not, a potential role for cognitive science
it this point doesn’t detract from Irvin’s arguments. in philosophy of art is far from established. However,
Conceptual art is singularly dedicated to gumming up the claim that questions about key concepts in the
the works of traditional definitions of particular art philosophy of art are questions about the particular
forms. However, it does illustrate the importance of objects that fall within their extension is a unifying
Book Reviews 191

assumption of the papers collected in this volume. the field as well as a useful framework for the psy-
Questions about the nature of particular artworks chology of aesthetics, and the one by Chenier and
are, at least in part, questions about the nature of Winkielman, which offers a general explanation of
our engagement with them, that is, questions about aesthetic pleasure. Neuroaesthetics is in its infancy,
the way consumers acquire, represent, and use salient and we should expect that progress in this field will
information encoded in a work’s surface in order to be made in small steps. With that in mind, let us ex-
recognize and evaluate its content. Therefore, un- amine how the book performs with respect to its own
derstanding the nature of particular artworks would more modest goal.
seem to require understanding something about the The editors have selected the topics covered in
nature of our psychological engagement with them. the book according to what they consider to be the
Good philosophical theories have been proposed in “key questions of neuroaesthetics.” The key issues
this regard. But, there is a range of psychological re- are (1) to identify the main features of aesthetic pro-
search in cognitive science that bears on the validity cesses and to explain how they contribute to aesthetic
of these theories. This research plays an increasingly experience, (2) to inquire about the evolutionary sig-
important role in analytic aesthetics. Why ignore it? nificance of aesthetic experience, (3) to elucidate the
nature and the role of representation in art and aes-
W. P. SEELEY thetics in general, and (4) to explain the role of emo-
Department of Philosophy tion in aesthetic experience. The editors also wanted
Bates College to highlight the multidisciplinary nature of the field
by including contributions from (and also coauthored
skov, martin and oshin vartanian, eds. Neuroaes- by) researchers working in a wide range of disci-
thetics. Amityville, NY: Baywood, 2009, iv + 302 plines and from various theoretical and methodolog-
pp., 8 color + 47 b&w illus., $68.50 cloth. ical perspectives; the book features contributions by
psychologists, neuroscientists, anthropologists, evo-
Neuroaesthetics, as defined by the editors in their lutionary biologists, historians, artists, and indepen-
brief introductory chapter, “is the study of the neu- dent scholars (there is, however, a noticeable absence
ral processes that underlie aesthetic behavior” (p. 3). of philosophers, more on which below). These ed-
More precisely, “there are forms of interaction with itorial decisions were made with a specific aim in
objects that can be called ‘aesthetic,’ ” and “[t]he job mind, namely, to allow for genuine integration to oc-
of neuroaesthetics is to identify these aesthetic func- cur along the four areas of inquiry just outlined.
tions and to investigate their neurobiological causes” Researchers from different disciplinary back-
(p. 3). They then make two clarifying remarks con- grounds propose different, and often competing, ex-
cerning the scope of the field. First, the study of aes- planations of aesthetic response, either at the same
thetic behavior, as the term suggests, should not be level of analysis (for example, cognitive, neurobiolog-
restricted to the study of aesthetic response. It should ical) or at different levels of analysis. To be successful,
also include the study of the processes involved in neuroaesthetics must seek integration among these
the production of aesthetic objects. Second, we en- different explanations, whenever possible. Here the
gage aesthetically with objects as diverse as paintings, book delivers on its promise. There are several cases
faces, landscapes, and food, which means that the of this kind of integration throughout the book. One
study of aesthetic behavior should not be restricted example is Oshin Vartanian’s chapter on the experi-
to our interactions with artworks. ence of pleasure in art, in which he proposes a way to
These are of course the goals of neuroaesthetics, as integrate a recently proposed neurobiological model
a field, so it shouldn’t be too surprising if the contribu- of the experience of emotion with an influential cog-
tion of the book’s fourteen chapters toward fulfilling nitive model of aesthetic experience. Another exam-
these goals is rather modest. For example, despite ple is Chenier and Winkielman’s explanation of aes-
repeated mention by several contributors of the im- thetic pleasure in terms of processing fluency. They
portance of studying the production side of aesthetic argue that processing fluency, the experience of the
behavior, only the chapter by Chatterjee and the one ease with which the perceiver perceives a stimulus,
by Zaidel (which both include interesting discussions can account for the hedonic character of a broad
of the effects of brain damage on artistic production) range of previously identified aesthetic phenomena
deal directly with this topic. Similarly, even though (for example, mere exposure, symmetry, prototypi-
many of the contributors explicitly acknowledge that cality). Finally, in their chapter on the evolution of
empirical approaches to the study of aesthetics need art and aesthetic appreciation, Nadal et al. elegantly
to go beyond art, discussions of our aesthetic en- use data from comparative neurology, biological an-
gagement with objects other than artworks are few. thropology, and cognitive neuroscience to propose
Such discussions are, in fact, practically limited to the a framework for studying the evolution of aesthetic
chapter by Jacobsen, which contains a mini review of preference.
192 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

The field of neuroaesthetics presents another of aesthetic response and then expect scientists to do
integration challenge. There is a great deal of vari- the job of explaining how its different components
ability in (and sometimes disagreement about) what are implemented in the brain. As anyone who reads
researchers think must be explained. Indeed, differ- this book will realize, aesthetic science, by discover-
ent groups of investigators differently conceptualize ing the mechanisms behind our aesthetic responses,
aesthetic response. For example, Jacobsen notes that is telling us a great deal about the nature of this phe-
one meaning of the term ‘aesthetics’ is related to nomenon that we would have otherwise had no way
processes of sensation and that beauty is “the main of finding out. We should therefore expect that a con-
conceptualization of aesthetics in Philosophical and ception of aesthetic response that is productive for
Psychological Aesthetics,” and then concludes that research across the different scientific, philosophi-
“aesthetic processing is sensation-based evaluation cal, and humanistic disciplines involved in its study
of an entity” primarily with respect to the beauty di- will emerge as a result of integration.
mension, along with other concepts such as elegant, The book is written for the most part in non-
harmonious, shapely, big, small, and so forth (p. 29). technical language (with the exception of a small
Chenier and Winkielman take aesthetic pleasure to number of chapters in which part of the discussion
be “the sine qua non of aesthetic experience” (p. 275). requires the reader to have some background in cog-
However, others focus their discussions on emotion nitive neuroscience) and should therefore be acces-
or evaluation or a combination of both. This vari- sible to nonscientists. The book would also be well
ability in what researchers view as the focus of ex- suited for an advanced undergraduate course or a
planation suggests that it is an open question what graduate seminar.
features of aesthetic response need to be explained.
It also leaves open the list of features that should be VINCENT BERGERON
considered essential (if any) to aesthetic response, Department of Philosophy
typical to it, or simply occasional. For example, aes- University of Ottawa
thetic response and evaluation may dissociate if some
works of art have great artistic value and yet evoke chapin, keith and lawrence kramer, eds. Musical
no pleasure, and pleasure is a necessary component Meaning and Human Values. Fordham University
of aesthetic response. Press, 2009, ix + 226 pp., $65.00 cloth.
This second kind of integration, wherein re-
searchers converge on a common conception of what The book under review (henceforth MMHV) is an
they are trying to explain, is hard to find in the anthology of contributions to a conference held at
book. In this respect, it is interesting to note that the Fordham University in 2007 under the title “Mu-
book contains virtually no discussions of classical and sical Meaning and Human Values: A Symposium
contemporary philosophical theories of aesthetics. It with Lawrence Kramer.” In addition to an introduc-
would seem likely that philosophical analysis could tion by Kramer there are eight chapters, as follows:
contribute a great deal to the development of a com- “Due Rose, Due Volte: A Study of Early Modern
mon theoretical concept of aesthetic response. After Subjectivities,” by Susan McClary; “Sublime Experi-
all, neuroaesthetics, and aesthetic science in general, ence and Ironic Action: E. T. A. Hoffmann and the
can easily be conceived as branches of cognitive sci- Use of Music for Life,” by Keith Chapin; “The De-
ence, which is itself a multidisciplinary field that has voted Ear: Music as Contemplation,” by Lawrence
benefited greatly from philosophy. One of the editors Kramer; “Music and Fantasy,” by Marshall Brown;
(Martin Skov) seems to be well aware of the need for “Whose Brahms Is It Anyway? Observations on the
this kind of integration. In his chapter, in which he Recorded Legacy of the B-flat Piano Concerto,” by
sketches a framework for neuroaesthetic research, Walter Frisch; “The Civilizing Process: Music and the
he writes that “the burgeoning field of neuroaesthet- Aesthetics of Time-Space Relations in The Girl of the
ics, while primarily concerned with the question of Golden West,” by Richard Leppert; “A Farewell, a
how the brain computes art behavior, must advance Femme Fatale, and a Film: Three Awkward Moments
with an eye to discussions of what art behavior is” in Twentieth-Century Music,” by Peter Franklin; and
(p. 10). He then adds that “to a high degree, exper- “ ‘Pour Out . . . Forgiveness Like a Wine’: Can Music
imental aesthetics cannot get started without using Say ‘An Existence Is Wrong’?” by Walter Bernhart.
the insights from traditional aesthetics” (p. 11). Skov A perusal of the foregoing will quickly reveal that
is here pointing to the need to develop a common the book is largely devoted to what has come to be
conception of art appreciation, but the same point known as the “New Musicology.” In the spirit of full
could be made with respect to aesthetic response in disclosure I must state that I have little sympathy
general. for the conception either of music or of humanistic
This is not to say, however, that we should wait scholarship generally which informs New Musicol-
for philosophers to provide a satisfactory definition ogy; I will nonetheless do my best to offer a reasoned
Book Reviews 193

critique of the contents of this volume, though with ness in the idea that the late sixteenth century might
a warning to the reader that there is some polemic have been a more modern time than it is commonly
ahead. I should also make it clear that I am not a thought of as being, and that the composer who gave
musicologist (New or otherwise) and will therefore us Tosca (1900) and La Bohème (1896) might be more
limit my discussion to other matters. of a modernist than usually thought. But the book
The very title of the book is already problemati- skimps on its promises, partly because the authors
cal, or at least provocative. Whether the concept of insist, to a distressing degree, on cloaking everything
meaning in any commonly understood sense of the in an impenetrable verbal haze. Here are a few sam-
term applies to music at all is at best unsettled, and ple quotes: “Transformative reflection . . . marks the
how music might relate to questions of value out- experience of a novel form of subjectivity. It maps
side the aesthetic sphere is no less open. (Stephen the interior space of a developing historical condi-
Davies [Meaning and Expression in Music (Cornell tion. It makes self-recognition available in a new or
University Press, 1994), pp. 39ff.] presents the most evolving mode of awareness” (Kramer, p. 3); “Music
detailed and careful analysis I know of ways in which allows human beings to experience the mysteries of
the concept of meaning might be applicable to music, animation, to allow their participation in imbricating
though whatever the authors represented in MMHV orders to rise above the mechanical, and ultimately
mean by the term ‘meaning’ seems far removed from to achieve the semblance of immediacy” (Chapin,
what Davies is talking about.) But since the various p. 45); “In its compact intensity, [Beethoven’s Fifth]
contributions to the volume turn out to be largely is a triumph of form, for sure; the blending of in-
unconcerned with its two putative subjects, either in- troduction and implementation brilliantly fulfills the
dividually or in relation to each other, I cannot accuse postulates of Kantian or Schillerian organicism. Yet
the editors of anything worse than false advertising. it fulfills them only to show the impossibility of form
What exactly is the book about? This is madden- ever disentangling itself from the spooky, mysteri-
ingly hard to pin down (one of my gripes with New ous energies in which it is implicated and with which
Musicology and its siblings elsewhere in the humani- it is activated” (Brown, p. 99). Language like this
ties), but certain themes and tendencies make them- gives the entire enterprise a whiff of phoniness, ex-
selves apparent. The contributors other than Kramer acerbated by such displays of pseudo-erudition as
himself are largely in intellectual orbit around him the misuse of the word ‘parameter’ (for example, by
and thus are prone to concentrate on matters that Chapin on p. 42 and Leppert on p. 138). This ia all
he deems important, or at least to profess agreement the more dismaying given that there is some real eru-
with things that he has said. (Though there is noth- dition on display here.
ing wrong with this in itself, it troubles me somewhat That said, I’ll do my best to identify places—there
that Kramer is seldom, if ever, cited except in the are some—where something of value can be extracted
most fulsomely positive terms. It would be refresh- from the dross. In that spirit, let me first say that
ing, not to say more instructive, if someone were oc- there are a couple of chapters (the ones by Frisch and
casionally to say, “I agree up to this point but. . .” or McClary, especially Frisch) which have something of
“The premise is correct but not all the conclusions genuine interest to offer.
follow . . .”). Among his concerns, as expressed in his Frisch takes up the question of the correct tempo
introductory chapter, are the idea of modernity in for the Andante from the second piano concerto
music and a particular response to it that Kramer of Brahms (1881), providing a fascinating survey
calls transformative reflection. Given the former (in of recorded performances to show how the move-
regard to the latter I confess to not knowing, even af- ment has, over the years, gotten progressively slower,
ter reading what he says, what Kramer means), one and he supplies textual and biographical information
might expect the focus of the book to be on musical about the composer in support of the contention that
figures and works associated with such historical mo- it ought to go much faster than one tends to hear it
ments as the Counter-Reformation and the period these days. The only thing I can see to object to in this
extending from the late nineteenth century through atypically lucidly written and tightly argued piece is
the years directly preceding and following World War the unexamined presumption that one must hew ex-
I. But the contributors’ attention turns in unexpected actly to what the composer wanted in cases where
directions: we hear more about Marenzio than about this is known, of which this is one: Brahms penciled
Palestrina and more about Puccini than about Wag- metronome markings into the manuscript prior to
ner, Debussy, and Schoenberg. the work’s premiere and carried them over without
There is nothing wrong with this a priori: ‘mod- alteration into the published score. About the afore-
ern’ is a flexible term. (Descartes is considered to be- mentioned presumption I have some doubts, tending
long to the modern period of philosophy and ‘Early to side with those who maintain that if it works it
Modern’ is the label given by linguists to the En- works, whether or not it is exactly what the com-
glish of Shakespeare.) Indeed, there is a certain fresh- poser had in mind. (The pianissimo final chords in
194 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Horowitz’s performance of Chopin’s Op. 10, No. 8 ception,’ and what (if anything) is gained by replacing
at his legendary 1965 Carnegie Hall concert run di- the usual, well-understood one with another which is
rectly counter to the composer’s dynamic indication, less well understood. I’m also not sure whether the
but are pure magic to which a performance faithful values to which Frisch alludes aren’t purely artistic
to the score does not hold the proverbial candle.) ones (for example, it’s better to do what the com-
But all this prompts a larger concern and a sense poser wanted) rather than ones meriting the all-
of a significant opportunity missed. Start with the encompassing label ‘human.’ Perhaps that’s all any-
fact that our lives today, both inside the arts and out- one represented in MMHV means by ‘human values,’
side, have long been in thrall to something Benjamin but if so, then one is entitled to wonder whether the
Filene will calls the Cult of Authenticity (in Romanc- title of the volume isn’t so much hype.
ing the Folk [University of North Carolina Press, McClary compares two settings of a sonnet of
2000]). Now, if ever there was a connection to be Petrarch, one by Gabrieli and one dating from nine-
made between music and human values, here is one: teen years later by Marenzio. Anyone interested in
surely authenticity is one of the most highly valued of the music of the Renaissance and in the art of set-
virtues in today’s world, and surely the performance ting texts to music should find plenty to feast on
of classical music as we now routinely encounter it here. As I say, I’m not a musicologist and so will
has been profoundly influenced by the belief that our take as given that the musicology is sound, particu-
renderings of it must be informed by what is known larly as regards the harmonic practices of the time.
about the composer’s wishes and the practices of the Marenzio (so McClary tells us) departs from an ear-
composer’s time and place. And here, moreover, is lier norm in ways which produce some of the same
a paradox of some interest: authenticity in the con- feelings as “the lunges for tonic conclusions in so
duct of one’s personal affairs requires being true to much nineteenth-century music after the certainties
oneself, whereas authenticity in the performance of of eighteenth-century tonality had been called into
music, on one understanding, requires the suppres- question” (p. 29).
sion of one’s own instincts (bad, bad Horowitz for This is not an entirely uninteresting conclusion,
not playing those final chords as Chopin ordered!) but one might wonder why it’s treated as a matter
and being true to someone else’s. But this vexing, of so much moment. From other comments which
subtle, and compelling issue regarding art in rela- McClary makes, there would appear to be some air-
tion to values goes, as far as I can determine, un- ing of grievances and score settling involved here.
touched by any of the contributors here. (The most As she says: “[As a specialist in seventeenth-century
comprehensive exploration known to me is that of music] I quickly found that attempts at publishing my
Peter Kivy, Authenticities [Cornell University Press, analyses and interpretations ran up against the com-
1995]. See also James O. Young [“The Concept of Au- monly held belief that early music ‘does not work.’. . .
thentic Performance,” British Journal of Aesthetics Thirty years after I started, I find it possible at last
28 (1988): 228–238] for some highly perceptive com- to address sixteenth- and seventeenth-century mu-
ments, likewise Alfred Brendel, On Music [Chicago: sic with the kind of analytical depth and the sorts of
A Cappella, 1991], p. 375ff.) This strikes me as espe- questions that Kramer brings to Mozart or Strauss”
cially surprising given the preoccupation of Kramer (p. 11). And here is her parting shot: “If what I am
and others with modernity and its attendant crises: doing is [imposing my own semiotics on a tempo-
the authenticist movement in musical performance rally distant and defenseless culture], I vastly pre-
has a modernist aspect, at least insofar as it repre- fer it to accepting the notion that musicians in the
sents a counterweight to the perceived excesses of Renaissance were simple-minded and incapable of
nineteenth-century musical practice. anything we might want to acknowledge as the ar-
As a final comment about Frisch, I should add ticulation of subjectivity. We can learn a great deal
that he says what is perhaps the most comprehen- about how our predecessors experienced the self and
sible thing to be found in the book about how his interiority, but only if we take the music itself seri-
subject relates to musical meaning, or is intended to: ously as historical evidence” (p. 31). Well and good,
“[T]he horizon of meanings of the Andante of the but I find the ha-ha-on-you-guys tone a bit unseemly
[B-flat] Concerto has morphed dramatically across here, more appropriate to an interview or a memoir
almost 130 years through the mediation of per- than a scholarly communication.
formance, recording and reception by generations In an intermediate category I would place the
of listeners. . . . Musical meanings are never stable; chapters by Chapin, Leppert, and Bernhart. Chapin’s
they are continuously being reshaped by values, as contains an interesting and largely lucid discussion of
reflected by performance styles and preferences” Hoffmann’s career as a jurist in a difficult time dur-
(p. 114). But I think this entitles one to ask whether ing which his interpretation of the law led him to
the word ‘meaning’ as used above isn’t just a substi- some decisions that did not sit well with the Prussian
tute for the more familiar locution ‘interpretive con- monarchy. Human values in the broadest sense are
Book Reviews 195

clearly pertinent to this chapter in history; but I lost referred to by the same name as one with which I
patience trying to figure out how this pertains to mu- am. (Example: Kramer’s description of Beethoven’s
sic (Hoffmann’s or anyone else’s). What I found of Sixth Symphony as imagining “an unbroken conti-
most interest in Leppert’s chapter had less to do with nuity of tradition.” Maybe that’s an apt description,
Puccini and the music of La fanciulla del West (1910) but I’m powerless to see what motivates it or why,
than with the lengthy discussion of the David Belasco even if I shared this judgment, it would overcome
play on which the opera is based, and on Belasco’s anyone’s indifference to this or any other classical
instructions for its staging. (Disclosure: Leppert is an work.) Some of this no doubt is due to my not be-
institutional colleague of mine, but we are not well ing initiated in all the mysteries of the Kramer circle;
acquainted.) but it seems not unreasonable to wish that a book as
Bernhart takes up the matter of the evocation of portentously titled as MMHV might have something
evil in music via three case studies (all operas, all from to say to interested readers outside this coterie. I had
the modern era): Henze’s Elegy for Young Lovers a similar difficulty with Brown’s chapter (in which,
(1961), Hindemith’s Cardillac (1926), and Britten’s I might add, Kramer’s statement about Beethoven’s
The Turn of the Screw (1954). In the first two, un- Sixth is admiringly quoted). I question, for exam-
ambiguously evil acts occur without any accompa- ple, what insight is to be gained from statements like
nying music, whereas in the last, music of a specific “Musical fantasy . . . cuts into and cuts away the com-
kind is associated with moments fraught with ambi- placencies of logic” or the one I quote earlier in this
guity: evil may or may not be present, and, if it is, its review.
true perpetrator could be either of two people. The Franklin presents a different kind of difficulty. I
point appears to be that music is too beautiful, hence have no quarrel with the idea that awkward moments
too “forgiving,” to be associated with unquestionable can be of great interest on many scores. But I had
evil, whereas its two-sided nature (seductive as well much trouble discerning what is supposed to be re-
as forgiving) makes it appropriate for inclusion in the vealed by the three particular works Franklin chooses
portrayal of more ambiguous circumstances. to describe (Mahler’s Tenth Symphony (1910–11),
There might be something to this, but I wonder if the 1913 opera Das Spielwerk und Die Prinzessin
the matter is quite so simple. Consider, for example, by Franz Schrecker, and the 1946 Hollywood film
the final scene of Dialogues of the Carmelites (Francis Humoresque [Jean Negulesco]). Indeed, I had trou-
Poulenc, 1957), in which an unambiguously evil act ble figuring out why they are associated with awk-
(the guillotining of a group of French nuns for defy- ward moments (beyond the fact that at least two of
ing the revolutionary government’s edict dissolving them are bad). Here I also had a very strong sense of
religious orders) takes place as the nuns sing a Salve an opportunity missed: surely there have been awk-
Regina. Perhaps Poulenc’s intent is to indicate that ward moments more familiar to contemporary musi-
those responsible for this ghastly deed are being ab- cophiles that reveal something about the stresses and
solved, as they perform it, by their victims, but I have strains to which our musical culture is subject. (Even
my doubts. Rather, it would seem that the ethereal a cursory glance at Christopher J. Washburne and
beauty of the music serves principally to accentuate Maiken Derno’s Bad Music: The Music We Love to
the horror taking place offstage. Granted, that horror Hate [New York: Routledge, 2004] will suggest plenty
is most directly evoked not by anything musical but of possibilities.)
by the repeated sound of the falling blade (and the I have some gripes of a less substantive nature.
simultaneous stilling of a voice); but what gives such First, there is no excuse for any publisher to resort
great power to the opera’s portrayal of the monstrous to endnotes. The book is also inadequately indexed,
deed being done is the very quality of the music that to say the least: there is an index of musical and
Bernhart would presumably take as rendering it in- literary works cited, but none for authors or subjects.
appropriate to such a moment. (Inappropriateness There is also no list of references. These deficiencies,
of music to text or dramatic action is sometimes de- while unrelated to the content of the book, are quite
liberate, but in cases I can think of it’s usually for serious ones, for which the publisher owes readers an
humorous effect, as in Tom Lehrer’s Oedipus Rex apology.
theme song [1953].) In sum, my dissatisfaction notwithstanding,
The chapters by Kramer, Brown, and Franklin MMHV isn’t a total loss. But the ratio of sunlight to
were, for me, the most problematical. I had the same fog is not favorable, and readers who react with fury
difficulty with Kramer’s as I did with his book Why to the constant need to flip back and forth between
Classical Music Still Matters (University of California text and notes have my complete sympathy.
Press, 2007), rather, two difficulties. In both cases I
found the writing frustratingly opaque, and where I MICHAEL B. KAC
could make out what the author was trying to say, it Department of Philosophy and Program in
struck me as having to do with an art form with which Linguistics
I’m not familiar, though for some mysterious reason University of Minnesota
196 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

argenton, alberto. Arte e Espressione. Studi e work and the experimental phenomenology prac-
Ricerche di Psicologia Dell’arte. Padua, Italy: Il ticed in Italy, and downplaying Arnheim’s adher-
Poligrafo, 2009, 320 pp., 116 illus., €25.00 paper. ence to the gestalt brain model believed superflu-
ous by such prominent Italian psychologists as Paolo
Expression, it can be argued, is why we are interested Bozzi and Giovanni Vicario, Argenton is able to rely
in the arts in the first place. Yet there seems to be a on a large body of shared phenomenological and
long-standing reticence to deal with just how it comes introspective research. Against Gombrich’s proba-
about. We either leave expression to the neuroscien- bilistic approach, Argenton affirms the “genetic and
tists or the poets. This book does neither. It outlines phenomenal priority of expressive qualities” (p. 44).
how one may use an experimental phenomenologi- While Argenton expects that perceptual forces and
cal approach to visual phenomena in order to bet- tensions will have a physical basis, in line with Ital-
ter understand how expression arises. It is one thing ian experimental phenomenology he does not find it
to apply perceptual principles to art, discovering the necessary to defend it at length. The perceptual facts
workings of color or space perception in a painting; it are there and have to be explained.
is another to face the challenge of the full complexity In the last chapter of Art and Visual Perception
of the work of art and, as a by-product, to enlighten (University of California Press, 1954), “Expression,”
the psychologist’s knowledge of laboratory percep- Arnheim writes that if the previous chapters have
tion itself. This is the challenge accepted by Alberto done their job there will be little left to say. This
Argenton in this important book. is exactly the path pursued by Argenton, who uses
Along with Lucia Pizzo Russo, Argenton is the the second chapter to investigate how the dynamics
most prominent psychologist of art in Italy. He has of perception led to expressive qualities. Like Arn-
already written an excellent introduction to the sub- heim, Argenton does not mean movement by the use
ject, Arte e cognizione [Art and Cognition], but of dynamic, but rather “mental life and the behaviors
his works are relatively unknown in the English- which constitute it as regulated by energetic factors”
speaking world. This is unfortunate, because The (p. 64) like vectors, forces, and tensions. Briefly con-
writing of American Psychologists on art, and es- sidering the possibility that perceptual forces are the
pecially on the latest biology . . . and neuroaesthetics product of physical forces, Argenton calls dynamics
of art in which anthropomorphization of the brain natural and authentic aspects of experience. Male-
abounds (“the brain sees,” “the brain decides”), vich’s Black Circle (1913), an off-center circle on a
is extremely shoddy from a philosophical perspec- square ground, is a useful example. The circle be-
tive. (Pizzo Russo’s recent So quello che senti: Neu- comes a “protagonist” and develops a “perceptual
roni specchio, arte ed empatia [I Know What You meaning,” as a sort of “symbolic icon” or “visual
Are Feeling], on mirror neurons, is a masterly in- metaphor” (p. 76). Comparing two paintings, Titian’s
dictment of this tendency.) Argenton’s approach af- Adam and Eve (c. 1550) in the Prado with Rubens’s
firms the perceptual sphere by simply ignoring these copy of the same in the same museum, Argenton is
developments. When brain models go away, even able to show how minor differences have deep con-
as we are pursuing a methodological goal of neu- sequences for perceptual meaning and expression.
rophysiological reduction, the phenomenology will Chapter three is a discussion of what Argen-
remain. ton calls the “see-saw effect,” contour rivalry in
Argenton’s book proudly carries on the mantle of line drawings. Argenton delves into why this phe-
Rudolf Arnheim, even more so than the related Psy- nomenon only occurs when there are two separated
chology of Graphic Images (Psychology Press, 2001) objects perceived. When a dividing line is part of a
by his colleague, Manfredo Massironi. These two unified object, it is an “object line,” whereas in the
books stand well together for a similarity of method- latter case it has a “bilateral function.” The “tug of
ology as well as subject matter, moving from shape war” that results can be quite dynamic, and Argenton
and space to expression. The book is made up of two devises the two conditions for the illusion to appear
excellent introductory chapters on, respectively, “Ex- and distinguishes it from other cases of perceptual
pression and Expressive Qualities” and “Perceptual multistability. Referring to logos, symbols, geometric
Dynamics and Expressive Qualities.” The bulk of the decorations, and works of art by artists like Sano
book is three chapters exploring different perceptual di Pietro and Picasso, Argenton examines his hy-
phenomena: contour rivalry, amodal completion, and pothesis that the see-saw effect ought to be found
the perception of obliquity. Finally, Argenton and a in highest proportion in areas that search out ambi-
collaborator, Tamara Prest, put the model to work by guity and the punning that results. The simplicity of
building an iconographic analysis. logos and symbols, where two elements often occur,
In chapter one, Argenton emphasizes that expres- ensures the presence of the see-saw effect. In formal
sion is central to any science of psychology and de- painting, where clarity is sought after, it is rarer, al-
plores its neglect. Utilizing a blend of Arnheim’s though Sano di Pietro obtains an interesting, almost
Book Reviews 197

theological, point by merging the contour of the Renaissance paintings, the windmill is seen at three
Christ child’s and Virgin Mary’s faces. Indeed, in the quarters and the blades are symmetrically oblique.
final chapter, Argenton and Prest present no less than The “realistic” phase begins in the seventeenth cen-
eight works with this “cheek to cheek” (guancia a tury, when the windmill is shown at a sharper an-
guancia) configuration by this artist. They suppose gle and the blades are now obliquely asymmetrical.
that the small size of the devotional format allowed The effect is more dynamic, appropriate to the aims
Sano to experiment with this iconography in a way of the landscape painters who used the windmill to
that no one else ever did. express activity, extreme weather, or change of sea-
Argenton turns to the problem of amodal com- sons. As for clocks, Argenton again took a number
pletion in chapter four. Amodal completion, which of examples, notably from paintings but especially
has been investigated deeply by Italian psychologists, advertisements. He hypothesized that the configura-
consists of an integral percept for which some stimuli tion of ten and two o’clock would be the most popu-
are incomplete. Moreover, in the case of some figures lar because it shows active time measurement, which
like two horses or scooters over which a solid square vertical and horizontal hands would negate and a
occludes half of each, the object appears to stretch, downward dynamic (eight and four o’clock) would
overriding our knowledge. Once again, Argenton is counteract.
interested in how this phenomenon of surface infor- The studies described here raise many important
mation and “completed” object can serve expressive issues, first, regarding the usefulness of psychology
purposes. Using an example from the Giottesque mu- for the creation of conventional meaning and, sec-
ralist Giusto de’ Menabuoi, he shows how the over- ond, the possibility of using perceptual dynamics as a
lapping of halos in a Taking of Christ (fourteenth naturalistic basis for ontologically founding expres-
century) creates an intensely dynamic effect, as the sive qualities. As regards meaning, it is clear that
golden aureoles of the apostles are stacked one upon Argenton’s quasi-experimental method clarifies the
another. Again, in the last chapter, Argenton and range of meaning established by iconography but
Prest follow the iconography further and compare does not leave variation to randomness but rather
twenty-two images of this “stampede” (fuggi fuggi) can explain the popularity of solutions based on fun-
effect. In general, almost all apostles are occluded by damental perceptual facts. The method of variation
other apostles in these works (and not objects), and recalls Lucien Rudrauf’s found within these pages
most show occlusion at the border, where they are sixty years ago (vol. 7, 1949). As regards expressive
shown cut off, as they leave the scene. qualities, Argenton gives good reasons to consider
The last phenomenon Argenton investigates is the Arnheimian bridge between perceptual dynamics
oblique perception, using the examples of picto- and aesthetic expression a good candidate for cross-
rially depicted windmills and clocks to investigate ing the aesthetic and nonaesthetic divide. Frankly,
the placement of, respectively, the blades and watch in Anglo-American aesthetics this possibility has not
hands. Argenton first took a sample of numerous proved too interesting of late, but perhaps Argen-
painted depictions of windmills and then examined ton’s thorough and convincing book will allow us to
the configuration of the blades. Departing from an consider it again.
observation of Arnheim that oblique forms are per-
ceived as more dynamic, Argenton hypothesized that IAN VERSTEGEN
these would be the most numerous. In the early, Moore College of Art & Design
“symbolic” form common to manuscripts and early Philadelphia, PA

You might also like