Causes of Psychiatric Illness - JAMA - 2019

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

Clinical Review & Education

JAMA Psychiatry | Special Communication

From Many to One to Many—the Search


for Causes of Psychiatric Illness
Kenneth S. Kendler, MD

Supplemental content
The search for the causes of medical and psychiatric disorders has gone through 3 historical
phases. First, up until the mid-19th century, causes of illness were anecdotally recorded from
individual cases, resulting in long and diverse lists for all disorders. Second, in the latter half of
the 19th century, with the use of microbiological methods, single causes were found for many
infectious diseases that led to specific diagnostic tests, effective preventions, and, in some
cases, treatments. Causal thinking in medicine shifted from the earlier multicausal
approaches to monocausal theories of etiology. Indeed, proving monocausal etiology became
a way to establish the legitimacy of a disorder. Through the writings of Kahlbaum and Hecker,
psychiatry was deeply influenced by this monocausal perspective, the importance of which
was substantially amplified by a twist of fate: the increasing clinical importance of general
paresis of the insane throughout the 19th century and the eventual proof that it too was a
monocausal condition. However, in the mid-20th century, the third phase began. With
decreasing deaths from infectious diseases, epidemiology and clinical medicine shifted to a
chronic disease model in which paradigmatic disorders, such as cancer and cardiovascular
Author Affiliations: Virginia Institute
disease, were shown to be highly multicausal. Biostatistics evolved from deterministic to for Psychiatric and Behavioral
probabilistic models of disease risk factors. Paradoxically, at this time, biological psychiatry, Genetics, Department of Psychiatry,
then rising to dominance in American psychiatry, vigorously pursued monocausal theories, Virginia Commonwealth University,
first of neurochemical origin and then of genetic origin. We were trying to establish the Richmond; Department of Psychiatry,
Virginia Commonwealth University
legitimacy of our field by pursuing an outmoded model—that “real” diseases are monocausal. School of Medicine, Richmond.
Despite ample evidence to the contrary, monocausal thinking continues to influence our field, Corresponding Author: Kenneth S.
for example, in the popular but improbable view that we can, with a few key advances, move Kendler, MD, Virginia Institute for
easily from descriptive to etiologically based diagnoses. Psychiatric and Behavioral Genetics,
Department of Psychiatry, Virginia
Commonwealth University,
JAMA Psychiatry. doi:10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2019.1200 PO Box 980126, Richmond, VA
Published online June 19, 2019. 23298-0126 (kenneth.kendler@
vcuhealth.org).

(aka “psychological”). The leading causes of each were, respec-


Many Causes tively, heredity and convulsions during pregnancy, and domestic
troubles and disappointed affection.
Robert Burton, an Oxford don who himself experienced depres- Such diverse lists of causes were not unique to mental illness.
sion, completed the first edition of his magnum opus The Anatomy In reviewing descriptions of scurvy in the late 18th century, 5
of Melancholy in 1621. In this encyclopedic book, he summarized the Harrison quotes the typical views of Baron van Swieten, an Aus-
extant theories of the “kinds, causes, symptoms, prognostics and trian court physician, who regarded “scurvy as a disease brought
several cures” for melancholy.1 It is his list of the causes that are of about by humours that had become putrid, acrimonious and con-
interest to the present article (Table 1). They number 44 and are di- densed…. This meant avoiding external causes such as “noisome
verse, including old age, temperament, parents, poverty, over- vapours, arising from marshy grounds and stagnating waters, inac-
much alcohol, sorrow, anger, immoderate eating, and envy. tion, scarcity of greens and vegetables, drinking of corrupted and
In 1786, at the beginning of “modern” psychiatry, the British stagnating waters, the use of salted and smoked flesh and
alienist Thomas Arnold provided a detailed list of bodily and men- fish…damp and low lodgings.” It also meant counteracting predis-
tal causes of “insanity” (Table 2 and Table 3).2 Although lacking the posing factors such as “fear and sorrow” and avoiding food which
supernatural elements of Burton’s list of causes, Arnold’s list is even had gone bad.”5(p9)
more extensive, including dryness of the brain, inflammation, con- Smith6 summarized the etiologic approach to cholera, specifi-
cussion, ambition, jealousy, and despair. cally, and fevers, more generally, in the 1830s: “The causes…were
In the opening chapter of his 1838 text, Jean Esquirol, the pre- often discussed in terms of predisposing and exciting causes. In gen-
eminent French alienist of his age, provided tables of the most com- eral, predisposing causes were factors such as inadequate diet, over-
mon causes of insanity (“La Folie”) recorded at a major Parisian pub- work, poverty, inadequate housing or ventilation, debilitation
lic asylum (Le Salpêtrière) and at his private madhouse (Table 4).3,4 through alcohol and mental exhaustion. The exciting causes were
Like Arnold, he divides the causes into 2 groups: physical and “moral” those which drove the debilitation due to predisposing causes

jamapsychiatry.com (Reprinted) JAMA Psychiatry Published online June 19, 2019 E1

© 2019 American Medical Association. All rights reserved.

Downloaded From: https://jamanetwork.com/ by a Idaho State University User on 07/18/2019


Clinical Review & Education Special Communication From Many to One to Many—the Search for Causes of Psychiatric Illness

Table 1. Causes of Melancholia in Burton’s Table 3. Moral (aka Psychological) Causes of Insanity
The Anatomy of Melancholy, 1621a as Described by Arnold, 1786a

General Cause Individual Causes Category of Cause Individual Causes


Supernatural God, devil, witches Intense application Study; business or schemes or much exertion of genius;
of the mind employment of the mind, keeping it for a long time
Natural in an active wakeful state
General Passions of various Surprise or astonishment; joy; enthusiasm or religious
Inward Stars, old age, temperament, parents (hereditary) kinds when violent joy; pride and vanity; desire, anger, hatred or aversion,
or habitual love, ambition; avarice, distress, grief, despair, fear,
Outward Nurses, education, terrors, scoffs, imprisonment, suspicion, jealousy, anxiety, religious fear
poverty, losses Too great activity
Specific of imagination
Head Imbecility
Inward Humors, hot brain, excess venery, agues, stomach a
See Arnold.2
fumes
Outward Heat, blow to the head, overmuch alcohol, idleness
Windy Table 4. Physical and Moral (aka Psychological) Causes
Inward Default of bowel, ceased bleeding hemorrhoids of Insanity as Described by Esquirol, 1838a
Over body No. of Cases
Inward Distempered liver, bad diet Public Asylum Le Esquirol’s
Salpêtrière, Private
Diet Coarse bread, unclean water or milk, sharp sauces, Causes 1811-1812 Establishment
immoderate eating
Physical
Necessary Constipation; dark, thick air; excessive exercise;
over much or over little sleep Heredity 105 150
Passions Irascible, sorrow; fear; shame, disgrace; envy, malice; Convulsions during pregnancy 11 4
hatred, desire for revenge; anger; miseries;
concupiscible; ambition; covetousness; excess Epilepsy 11 2
of pleasures; pride, desire of praise; excess study Menstrual disorder 55 19
See Burton.1 Results of confinement 52 21
Critical period 27 11
Progress of age 60 4
Table 2. Bodily Causes of Insanity as Described by Arnold, 1786
Isolation 12 4
Category of
Cause Individual Causes Blows or falls upon the head 14 4
Internal Firmness, hardness, dryness of the brain; hard substances, Fevers 13 12
causes in tumors, excrescences; purulent mucous matter, blood, water
the brain in the ventricles; distension or enlargement; inflammation; Syphilis 8 1
indurations, adhesions; other causes of compression, irritation Mercury 14 18
External Exostosis of the skull; depression, fracture of the skull; Intestinal worms 24 4
causes on concussion; burning rays of the sun on the head; smallness
the brain of the head compressing the brain; swelling in the neck Apoplexy 60 10
Causes Phrenitis, delirious fevers, small pox; immoderate exercise; Moral
affecting profuse evacuations; excessive venery; defect of nourishment;
the body in other fevers; inactive, sedentary life Domestic troubles 105 31
general by Disappointed affection 46 25
acting
directly on Political events 14 31
the brain
Fanaticism 8 1
Causes Disease of abdominal viscera;a causing infirm state of the
acting in stomach or intestines;b active substances taken into the Fright 38 8
particular stomach: wine, opium, narcotics, or poisons; disordered Jealousy 18 14
body parts, state of womb, ovaries, or spermetic vessels; retention of
acting customary evacuation: lochia, milk, menses, piles, old ulcers; Anger 16 0
speedily or metastases to brain of gout, erysipelas, herpes, or cutaneous Misery and reverses of fortune 77 14
slowly on eruption; worms in the nostrils or frontal sinuses
the brain Wounded self-love 1 16
a 2
Arnold lists the following specific body parts: stomach, pylorus, intestines, Disappointed ambition 0 12
pancreas, mesentery, mesenteric glands, liver, spleen, hemorrhoidal vessels, Excessive study 0 13
kidneys, glandulae atrabiliariae, omentum, and peritoneum.
Misanthropy 0 2
b
Hard and indigestible aliment, immoderate use of warm diluting liquors,
a
intemperance of diet, viscous phlegm, and worms. See Esquirol.3,4

towards a particular pathological form, such as the specific atmo- posure to sudden alterations of heat and cold, indulgence in copi-
spheric factors seen as leading to cholera outbreaks.”6(p921) ous drafts of cold fluid when the system has been over-heated by
As noted by Carter,7 prior to the last half of the 19th century, labor or exercise, intemperate use of spiritous liquors, poor living,
causes of illness were anecdotally recorded by physicians from in- sleeping of the whole of the night in the open in a state of intoxica-
dividual cases, resulting in an accumulation of long and diverse lists tion, checking perspirations suddenly and mental anxiety and dis-
for each disease. He proceeds: “For example, in his account of dia- tress. Similar lists can be found for virtually any disease in most
betes, Bardsley (1845) identified the following causes: frequent ex- German, English, or French medical texts from the period.”7(p11)

E2 JAMA Psychiatry Published online June 19, 2019 (Reprinted) jamapsychiatry.com

© 2019 American Medical Association. All rights reserved.

Downloaded From: https://jamanetwork.com/ by a Idaho State University User on 07/18/2019


From Many to One to Many—the Search for Causes of Psychiatric Illness Special Communication Clinical Review & Education

century,15 the distinctiveness of the syndrome—its specific neurologic


Toward One Cause signs and rapid deteriorative course—were well recognized by the mid-
19th century. For example, in describing his research program for turn-
All of this changed in the latter half of the 19th century. Due largely ing psychiatric syndromes in diseases, Hecker saw GPI as the paradig-
to the work of 2 men, Pasteur and Koch, the causal paradigm of medi- maticsuccessfulexample:“Theonlyrealdiseaseform,whichhasgained
cine shifted dramatically to what Dubos8 termed the doctrine of entry into psychiatry, provides the best evidence for this: the so-called
specific etiology. He writes, “There is no more spectacular phenom- progressive paralysis of the insane [AKA GPI].”12(p353) Many other de-
enon in the history of medicine than the rapidity with which the germ scriptions in the late 19th century by prominent neuropsychiatrists, in-
theory of disease became accepted by the medical profession- cludingKraepelin,documenttheparadigmaticroleplayedbyGPIinthe
.…From the haphazard accumulation of clinical facts, these clini- search for monocausal psychiatric disorders (eg, see Kahlbaum,16(p27)
cians derived generalizations that made it possible to classify dis- Behr,17(p5) Daraszkiewicz,18(p10) and Kraepelin19(p132)).
eases as if they were defined biological entities.…[C]linical analysis
and classification [were developed and]…managed to make order
of the incredibly confused field of febrile diseases…. [D]iphtheria and Histories of Epidemiology and Biostatistics—
scarlatina emerged as well-defined diseases out of the chaos of the
From One to Many
‘fevers.’”8(p325)
The distinguished epidemiologist Mervyn Susser9 suggested The histories of 2 additional fields need to be interwoven into our
that the startling developments in infectious disease in the late 19th narrative: epidemiology and statistics. Let us first examine epide-
century “led to the redefinition and reclassification of many dis- miology. Susser and Susser, using the Kuhnian concept of a dominant
ease entities by the criterion of cause…. By current definition, tu- scientific paradigm, described 3 successive eras of epidemiology.20
berculosis is caused by the tubercle bacillus.”9(p23) That is, the mono- The first focused on sanitary statistics, had as its paradigm “mi-
causal doctrine of specific etiology fundamentally changed the way asma,” and dominated the field until the mid-19th century. Miasma
medical diagnoses were conceptualized. The desired approach was frequently occurred in the long lists of causes of illnesses in pre-
no longer descriptive. Rather, the task was, whenever possible, 1850s medicine but never as the single cause. The second epide-
to define a disorder in relation to its 1 specific underlying cause. miologic phase, termed infectious disease, had as its paradigm “the
Disorders not amenable to such causal clarification were of lower germ theory,” lasted roughly from 1850 to 1950, and was domi-
status—syndromes and not real diseases. The monocausal theory— nated by monocausal etiologic theories in which the relationship be-
derived from work on bacteria and viruses—soon spread to include tween putative etiologic agents and specific diseases was one to one
parasitic and vitamin-deficiency diseases.7 (although most investigators recognized such modifying factors as
Psychiatry sought to participate in this diagnostic revolution “host resistance”). The third epidemiological phase, termed chronic
characterized by Dubois as the rise of the “doctrine of specific disease, had a dominant “black box” paradigm. It incorporated a mul-
etiology.”8,10 In the same year as his influential monograph on he- tifactorial disease model for what was termed chronic noncommu-
bephrenia (1871),11 Hecker published a detailed defense of the di- nicable diseases (eg, diabetes, heart disease, certain forms of can-
agnostic approach to psychiatric disorders of his mentor Kahlbaum: cer, and hypertension), diseases often associated with particular
“Just as in somatic pathology where prognosis and treatment be- lifestyles that could not be explained by a single salient causal fac-
came infinitely more secure after the clinical disease forms fever, tor. In this paradigm, the goal of epidemiology was to determine the
typhoid fever, etc, branched off from the general symptom constel- magnitude and causal nature of the associations between a wide
lation fever, the definition of clearly demarcated psychological dis- range of putative risk factors and these chronic noncommunicable
ease forms, established according to the principles outlined above, diseases. This phase began around 1950 and has lasted until cur-
will greatly inform our diagnosis, prognosis and therapy, and help rent times.
us to shed the current uncertainty.”12(p353) Two metaphors well capture this third phase of medical epide-
As general medicine turned from generic labels such as “fe- miology. The first of these is the “causal pie” proposed by Rothman.21
vers” to disorders with specific etiologies, courses, preventions and He writes, “The causal pie model posits that several causal compo-
cures (the latter 2 by vaccination and serum treatments, respec- nents act in concert to produce an effect…. One can view each causal
tively), so too did psychiatry, under the influence of Kahlbaum and pie as a set of interacting causal components.21(pS145)
Hecker’s teachings, later largely adopted by Kraepelin.13 This para- The second metaphor, a “web of causation,” is described by
digm sought to turn symptom-based diagnoses into distinct dis- Krieger22: “Conceptually, the metaphor evoked the powerful im-
eases discovered using an iterative clinical research paradigm of signs, age of a spider’s web, an elegantly linked network of delicate strands,
symptoms, and course of illness. Implicit in this model (as it was in the multiple intersections representing specific risk factors or out-
the advances in microbiology that it imitated) was that the resul- comes, and the strands symbolizing diverse causal pathways. It en-
tant diseases so defined would be monocausal. couraged epidemiologists to look for multiple causes and multiple
In this quest, the young field of psychiatry was greatly aided by a effects, and to identify the many—as opposed to singular—routes by
twist of fate. In the mid-to-late 19th century, the central nervous sys- which disease could be prevented.”22(p891)
tem infection by Treponema pallidum produced a syndrome, general Parallel to these changes in epidemiology, statistical and proba-
paresis of the insane (GPI), which as documented by Kraepelin ac- bilistic approaches toward diseases evolved. As argued by Gillies,23
counted for around 5% of asylum admissions in rural districts in Ger- based on a detailed study of Koch’s postulates (see also Carter7):
many and to up to 45% in urban public hospitals.14 Although the de- “19th and early 20th century scientific medicine, as it was devel-
finitive infectious etiology of GPI was not proven until early in the 20th oped by Pasteur, Koch, and others, used a deterministic notion of

jamapsychiatry.com (Reprinted) JAMA Psychiatry Published online June 19, 2019 E3

© 2019 American Medical Association. All rights reserved.

Downloaded From: https://jamanetwork.com/ by a Idaho State University User on 07/18/2019


Clinical Review & Education Special Communication From Many to One to Many—the Search for Causes of Psychiatric Illness

causality. An attempt was made to show that each disease had a articles proposing these theories were couched in qualifications,
single cause which was both necessary and sufficient.”23(p2) as a psychiatry resident in the late 1970s, I was taught these theo-
However, around 1950, indeterministic causal models became in- ries as monocausal explanations. Schizophrenia was caused by
creasinglyimportant.Manyfactorsinfluencedthischange,butonewas excess dopamine transmission. Decades later, I would commonly
predominant—theintensedebateaboutandeventualresolutionofthe see patients who would say some version of “my psychiatrist said
causal association between smoking and lung cancer. This debate led I have a chemical imbalance in my brain” and then proceed to sum-
to the proposal and eventual wide acceptance of the Hill criteria24 for marize one or more of these theories. It is now widely accepted
causation. Smoking became a paradigmatic risk factor that was an im- that these theories, claiming a dominant causal pathway to illness,
portant cause of lung cancer despite unequivocal evidence that many are false although debate continues regarding the dopamine
people who were long-term smokers never developed lung cancer and hypothesis.37,38
many individuals with lung cancer never smoked. The second wave of monocausal theories in psychiatry was ge-
At this time, biostatistics was developing the statistical machin- netic. Despite much evidence from family studies that major psy-
ery to detect and further characterize a wide range of causes whose chiatric disorders did not segregate in pedigrees as expected for a
relationship with their outcome was probabilistic. Rothman and mendelian condition, the first successful linkage study of Hunting-
Greenland25 made a key point regarding the public health signifi- ton disease in 198339 elicited intense excitement in psychiatric ge-
cance of such causes: “The importance of multicausality is that most netics and launched a large number of linkage studies, especially of
identified causes are neither necessary nor sufficient to produce dis- schizophrenia and bipolar illness. These early investigations used
ease. Nevertheless, a cause need not be either necessary or suffi- small numbers of pedigrees and were only powered to detect genes
cient for its removal to result in disease prevention. If a component of a mendelian-like effect. The common parlance in those days was
cause that is neither necessary nor sufficient is blocked, a substan- that the hunt was on for “the gene for…” This led to 3 reports in 1987
tial amount of disease may be prevented.”25(p145) through 1988 in prominent journals claiming successful linkage to
genes of large effect for schizophrenia40 and bipolar illness.41,42 The
field thought that success was at hand. However, all 3 of these claims
The Anomalous History of Late 20th Century were later disproved.
Thirty years later, we have published evidence of 108
Psychiatry—Focused on Monocausal Theories
schizophrenia-associated common loci in the human genome using
During the second half of the 20th century, the approach to dis- genome-wide association studies (GWAS),43 with unpublished re-
ease causation of major parts of psychiatry was out of step with the sults more than doubling that number. For major depression, the
rest of medicine and medical epidemiology. Instead of multicausal current number is 4444 and increasing. Smaller number of loci are
models, the rising and soon to be dominant field of biological psy- identified for other disorders (eg, bipolar illness, autism, obsessive-
chiatry pursued monocausal models for their major disorders. compulsive disorder, and anorexia), but the evidence suggests that
This search has 2 prominent phases, both fueled by new scientific as sample sizes rise, the number of identified risk variants inexora-
developments. The first was neurochemical. The stage was set bly increases.45 Molecular genetics provides us with the clearest ex-
in 1957 by Montagu’s discovery of dopamine in brain tissue26 ample of the “one to many” transition in causal theories of psychi-
quickly followed, in 1960, by the dramatic finds from Ehringer atric illness in recent decades. We started by seeking the gene for
and Hornykiewicz of the decreased content of dopamine in the post- our major disorders by using linkage analysis and ended up finding,
mortem brains of patients with Parkinson disease.20 Here was a for these same conditions, many genes of small effect with GWAS.
major neurologic disorder fitting apparently into a monocausal neu-
rochemical theory. What could be more exciting for the then young
and ambitious field of biological psychiatry? Even greater excitement
Current Evidence for the Multicausal Nature
followed the impressive treatment effects obtained for L-dopa (leva-
of Psychiatric Illness
dopa)inpatientswithParkinsondisease.27 Thus,thesinglemajorcause
predicted a viable treatment. Anyone who reads leading psychiatry or clinical psychology jour-
In the early to mid-1960s, through histofluorescence nals on a regular basis will see that high-quality research on the causes
stains, the cell bodies and neuronal pathways of the 3 monoamine of psychiatric illness spans a wide array of perspectives and subdis-
neurotransmitters were identified: dopamine, norepinephrine, ciplines. In 2013, I sought to rigorously assess this informal impres-
and serotonin.28-31 This further spurred the development of 3 sion by reviewing all studies that addressed the etiology of psychi-
long-lived monocausal neurochemical theories for psychiatric ill- atric disorders in the first four 2013 issues of 12 major psychiatry and
ness. All were proposed in the mid-to-late 1960s: the “catechol- psychology journals.46 In the resulting 197 reviewed articles, I rated
amine hypothesis of affective disorders,” 32,33 the “dopamine the putative causes that were examined using 12 categories. Five
hypothesis of schizophrenia,”34,35 and the “serotonin hypothesis categories reflected various levels of biological science: molecular
of depression.”36 Although based on a range of evidence, the pri- genetics; molecular, neurochemical, or cellular neuroscience; sys-
mary support for these theories was reasoning backward from tems neuroscience; aggregate genetic effects; and miscellaneous
therapeutic mechanisms to etiology. That is, for Parkinson disease biological influences. Four categories reflected various levels of psy-
the logic was sound: clarification of cause leading to a proposed chological science: neuropsychological traits; personality and other
treatment. By contrast, psychiatry followed the more problematic trait-like measures; cognitions or attitudes; and psychiatric symp-
approach of extrapolating backward from a proposed mechanism toms or other disorders. Three categories reflected environmental
of treatment to the cause of the disease. Although the original effects: individual; family; and community, society, or culture.

E4 JAMA Psychiatry Published online June 19, 2019 (Reprinted) jamapsychiatry.com

© 2019 American Medical Association. All rights reserved.

Downloaded From: https://jamanetwork.com/ by a Idaho State University User on 07/18/2019


From Many to One to Many—the Search for Causes of Psychiatric Illness Special Communication Clinical Review & Education

I identified 306 individual predictor variables from those pa- proach (molecular genetics, systems neuroscience, neuropsychol-
pers, and the variables were widely distributed across the 12 levels. ogy, environmental exposures, etc.), we have no good way to arbi-
Our discipline, which includes individuals with expertise in molecu- trate between them. So rather than having a breakthrough moment
lar biology, neuroscience, genetics, imaging, cognition, personal- when we discover the definitive etiologic measure that can replace
ity, clinical and developmental psychology, epidemiology, and soci- our signs and symptoms, we should prepare for a scenario with
ology, has provided rigorous evidence of potential and widely diverse slower, more incremental progress.
causes of psychiatric illness. Although the diversity and number of Consider how laboratory tests are used in general medicine out-
these causes resemble the lists generated by our predecessors in the side of microbiology or medical genetics. Typically, we find practi-
17th through 19th centuries, these causes are the product of scien- cal tests from different levels of explanations that help in our diag-
tific study, not anecdotal bedside observations. However, of those nostic task. We use the electrocardiogram and plasma troponin levels
197 studies, only 22 (11%), engaged in meaningful, integrative, cross- to help us diagnose myocardial infarction not because the tests di-
level research. rectly index the monocausal etiology of coronary atherosclerosis but
Seeking to close the circle that started with Burton’s list of causes because they are practical and have good sensitivity and specificity
in his The Anatomy of Melancholy,1 I set myself the task of identify- for detecting key consequences of the underlying disorder. But those
ing, either from review papers or replicated studies, risk factors that tests are not ordered unless the patient displays some features of
are associated with major depression and that could plausibly be con- the classic symptoms and signs well known by any physician who
sidered causes. I organized them in the categories used in my prior has spent time in an emergency department. Indeed, their sensi-
article. As seen in the eTable in the Supplement, while far from en- tivity and specificity make sense only when they are assessed in pa-
cyclopedic, I was able to identify 37 potential causes of depression tients with a particular clinical presentation. Laboratory tests will
distributed across 11 levels of scientific inquiry, nearly equal to evolve in a similar way in psychiatry. We will not likely be giving
Burton’s number of 44. up our long-accumulated clinical diagnostic wisdom any time soon.
While disappointing to visions of dramatic progress in psychiatry,
giving up our dreams of monocausal theories will reflect increased
scientific maturity and realism.
Implications
Psychiatry has had a long-term love affair with monocausal theories
of illness dating at least from the late 19th century, heavily influenced
Caveats
by our success at the identification and effective eradication of GPI.
In the latter half of the 20th century, with both neurochemical and mo- Acceptance of a multicausal model for psychiatric illness should be no
lecular genetic theories of illness, our enthusiasm for monocausal causeforcynicismaboutbiologicaletiologicresearch.Indeed,formany
theoriesoutranourcommonsense.Emergingfromdecadesofpsycho- highly multicausal medical disorders, effective treatments exist, some
analytic dominance, we were deeply committed to reestablishing our ofwhichweredevelopedinresponsetoclarificationofparticularcausal
medical legitimacy. What better way to show that we treated “real” dis- pathways. Equifinality is also a realistic possibility—where pathways to
eases than to show that they were monocausal? illnessfromseveralseeminglydisparateriskfactorscoalescetoacausal
This is in retrospect ironic because such an approach fitted bet- bottleneck at which interventions could be aimed.
ter into the world of medicine in the late 19th century than the late Monocausal subforms of major psychiatric disorders remain to be
20th century. In those hundred years, Western medicine and medi- identified. We have discovered rare copy number variants that carry
cal epidemiology moved from a focus on monocausal infectious dis- a substantial risk for schizophrenia, but none have close to complete
eases to the multifactorial chronic disease model. In the late 20th penetrance.48 Some de novo genetic variants strongly predispose to
century, it would have been more accurate for psychiatry to claim autism,especiallytheformwithlowIQandothersyndromalfeatures.49
that we treated “real” disorders because they were multicausal, simi- But we have ruled out single major locus genetic causes where efforts
lar to coronary artery disease, hypertension, rheumatoid arthritis, havebeenmadeinmanypartsoftheworldtolocatepedigreesinwhich
and type 2 diabetes, not that they were monocausal, such as clas- psychiatric disorders, especially schizophrenia and bipolar affective ill-
sic infectious or mendelian medical disorders. ness, segregate like a mendelian disorder. Although certainty here is
Our long yearning for monocausal theories of etiology drives, at impossible, we have extensive evidence that suggests that our major
least in part, our heartfelt calls for the abandonment of our descriptive psychiatric disorders are multicausal “all the way down.”
nosologic systems in favor of an etiologic model. Implicit in this posi-
tion is the expectation that we will have one definitive causal explana-
tion for our major disorders that operates at one scientific level, typi-
Final Thoughts
cally a biological one. That is, as a bacterial pneumonia can be shown
tobeattributabletoaspecificmicrobiologicalcauseoramendeliandis- Our journals are now filled with evidence for the multicausal nature
order a result from a definitive causal alteration in DNA sequence, so of psychiatric conditions.50 Thus, this matter should be settled. Yet
we can give up our symptoms and signs and replace them by a defini- the ghost of GPI—of monocausal psychiatric disorders—lurks in our
tive etiologic laboratory test or evidence of an aberrant brain circuit. memory. To this day, it influences our nosologic thinking. It makes
This will not happen for major psychiatric disorders because they us too willing to adopt a monocausal perspective in our clinical work
have multiple levels of etiology; thus, there is not 1 possible etio- and in our explanations of psychiatric disorders to patients. Mono-
logic model that could be used, but rather many.47 Although each causal thinking continues to support hard reductionist approaches
subdiscipline within psychiatry might favor its own particular ap- that seek the cause of our major disorders and is one of several fac-

jamapsychiatry.com (Reprinted) JAMA Psychiatry Published online June 19, 2019 E5

© 2019 American Medical Association. All rights reserved.

Downloaded From: https://jamanetwork.com/ by a Idaho State University User on 07/18/2019


Clinical Review & Education Special Communication From Many to One to Many—the Search for Causes of Psychiatric Illness

tors inhibiting collaborative psychiatric research work across can positively embrace the etiologic complexity of our disorders. After
scientific levels. all, as psychiatrists, we have chosen to study the most complex func-
Despite the wide acceptance of the chronic noncommuni- tionsofthehumanbeing’smostintricateorgan.Thehumanbrain/mind
cable disease model in modern medicine, there remains in our cul- not only self-wires—a system far more intricate than the genome can
ture a sense that disorders with many causes have reduced legiti- specify in any one-to-one relationship—but also is the great organizer
macy. Therefore, both clinicians and their patients would feel more and compiler of our own existence. It remembers and changes in ways
secure if a large indisputable cause were found for their disorders. that the liver, kidney, or heart can never do. It interfaces between our
This, however, is a social and not a scientific problem. The stigma of organism and the psychological, social, and cultural world around us
psychiatric illness and the low status of the psychiatric profession to provide the structure and meaning of our existence. We have cho-
need to be addressed at both social and political levels and will not sentostudyandtreatthemostcomplexofhumandisorders,thecauses
likely be solved through the discovery of major single causes for our of which span the many levels of our biology, our psychology, and our
illnesses. The legitimacy of the discipline of psychiatry does not rest socialexistence.Ifthecommon,morbiddysfunctionsofthehumancar-
on our ability to find single major causes of our disorders. diovascular, immune, hormonal, musculoskeletal, and gastrointesti-
Some may mourn the passing of monocausal theories for psychi- nalsystems,whichcausemostofthemorbidityinourcountry,arehighly
atric illness. I prefer to view the process more positively. Rather than multifactorial, could we realistically expect anything else from the par-
grieving for the loss of our visions of another GPI around the corner, we allel dysfunctions of our mind/brain system?

ARTICLE INFORMATION 9. Susser M. Causal Thinking in the Health Sciences. 23. Gillies D. Causality, Probability, and Medicine.
Accepted for Publication: April 7, 2019. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 1973. London: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group; 2019.

Published Online: June 19, 2019. 10. Ross LN. The doctrine of specific etiology. Biol 24. Hill AB. The environment and disease:
doi:10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2019.1200 Philos. 2018;33(37):1-22. association or causation? Proc R Soc Med. 1965;58
11. Hecker E. Die hebephrenie: ein beitrag zur (4):295-300.
Conflict of Interest Disclosures: None reported.
klinischen psychiatrie. Virchows Archiv für 25. Rothman KJ, Greenland S. Causation and causal
Additional Contributions: Peter Zachar, PhD, pathologische Anatomie und Physiologie und für inference in epidemiology. Am J Public Health.
Department of Psychology, Auburn University at Klinische Medizin. 1871;52:394-429. doi:10.1007/ 2005;95(suppl 1):S144-S150. doi:10.2105/AJPH.
Montgomery, Alabama, and Joel Braslow, MD, BF02329963 2004.059204
Department of Psychiatry, University of California,
Los Angeles, provided helpful comments on earlier 12. Kraam A. On the origin of the clinical standpoint 26. Montagu KA. Catechol compounds in rat
versions of the manuscript. They were not in psychiatry, Dr Ewald Hecker in Görlitz. Hist tissues and in brains of different animals. Nature.
financially compensated for their contributions. Psychiatry. 2004;15(59, pt 3):345-360. doi:10.1177/ 1957;180(4579):244-245. doi:10.1038/180244a0
The manuscript was stimulated in part by reading 0957154X04044598 27. Kopin IJ. Parkinson’s disease: past, present,
the insightful essay of Ross.10 13. Kendler KS, Engstrom EJ. Kahlbaum, Hecker, and future. Neuropsychopharmacology. 1993;9(1):
and Kraepelin and the transition from psychiatric 1-12. doi:10.1038/npp.1993.39
REFERENCES symptom complexes to empirical disease forms. 28. Falck B, Hillarp NA, Thieme G, Torp A.
1. Burton R. The Anatomy of Melancholy. What it is, Am J Psychiatry. 2017;174(2):102-109. doi:10.1176/ Fluorescence of catechol amines and related
With All the Kinds, Causes, Symptomes, appi.ajp.2016.16030375 compounds condensed with formaldehyde. Brain
Prognostickes, and Seuerall Cures of it. Oxford: John 14. Kraepelin E. General Paresis. Moore JW, trans. Res Bull. 1982;9(1-6):xi-xv. doi:10.1016/0361-9230
Lichfield and James Short for Henry Cripps; 1621. New York, NY: The Journal of Nervous and Mental (82)90113-7
2. Arnold T. Observations on the Nature, Kinds, Disease Publishing Co; 1913. 29. Dahlstroem A, Fuxe K. Evidence for the
Causes, and Prevention of Insanity, Lunacy, or 15. Noguchi H, Moore JW. A demonstration of existence of monoamine-containing neurons in the
Madness. Leicester: Printed by G. Ireland, for treponema pallidum in the brain in cases of general central nervous system, I: demonstration of
G. Robinson, 1786. paralysis. J Exp Med. 1913;17(2):232-238. doi:10. monoamines in the cell bodies of brain stem
3. Esquirol E. Des Maladies Mentales. Considérées 1084/jem.17.2.232 neurons. Acta Physiol Scand Suppl. 1964;232:232,
Sous Les Rapports: Médical, Hygiénique et 16. Kahlbaum KL. Catatonia. Levij Y and Pridan T, 1-55.
Médico-Légal [in French]. Tome Premier. Bruxelles: trans. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press; 30. Fuxe K, Hökfelt T, Nilsson O, Reinius S.
Librairie Médicale et Scientifique de J.B. Tircher, 1973. A fluorescence and electron microscopic study on
1838. 17. Behr A. Die Frage der “Katatonie”, oder central monoamine nerve cells. Anat Rec. 1966;155
4. Esquirol JED. Mental Maladies: Treatise on des Irreseins mit Spannung [in German]. (1):33-40. doi:10.1002/ar.1091550105
Insanity. Hunt EK, trans. Philadelphia, PA: Lea and Univerisitas Dorpatensis: Riga: WF Häcker; 1891. 31. Dahlstroem A, Fuxe K, Olson L, Ungerstedt U.
Blanchard; 1845. 18. Daraszkiewicz L. Ueber hebephrenie, Ascending systems of catecholamine neurons from
5. Harrison M. Scurvy on sea and land: political insbesondere deren schwere form: the lower brainstem. Acta Physiol Scand. 1964;62:
economy and natural history, c. 1780-c. 1850. inaugural-dissertation. Dorpat: Laakmann's Buch 485-486. doi:10.1111/j.1748-1716.1964.tb10446.x
J Marit Res. 2013;15(1):7-25. doi:10.1080/21533369. und Steindruckerei; 1892. 32. Schildkraut JJ. The catecholamine hypothesis
2013.783167 19. Kraepelin E. Dementia Praecox and Paraphrenia. of affective disorders: a review of supporting
6. Smith GD. Commentary: behind the Broad Huntington, NY: Krieger Publishing; 1971. evidence. 1965. J Neuropsychiatry Clin Neurosci.
Street pump: aetiology, epidemiology and 1995;7(4):524-533. doi:10.1176/jnp.7.4.524
20. Hornykiewicz O. The discovery of dopamine
prevention of cholera in mid-19th century Britain. deficiency in the parkinsonian brain. J Neural 33. Hirschfeld RMA. History and evolution of the
Int J Epidemiol. 2002;31(5):920-932. doi:10.1093/ Transm Suppl. 2006;(70):9-15. doi:10.1007/978-3- monoamine hypothesis of depression. J Clin
ije/31.5.920 211-45295-0_3 Psychiatry. 2000;61(suppl 6):4-6.
7. Carter KC. The Rise of Causal Concepts of 21. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104 34. van Rossum JM. The significance of
Disease: Case Histories. Burlington, VT: Ashgate (6):587-592. doi:10.1093/oxfordjournals.aje.a112335 dopamine-receptor blockade for the mechanism of
Publishing Co; 2003. action of neuroleptic drugs. Arch Int Pharmacodyn
22. Krieger N. Epidemiology and the web of Ther. 1966;160(2):492-494.
8. Dubos RJ. Man Adapting. New Haven, CT: causation: has anyone seen the spider? Soc Sci Med.
Yale University Press; 1980. 1994;39(7):887-903. doi:10.1016/0277-9536(94) 35. Kendler KS, Schaffner KF. The dopamine
90202-X hypothesis of schizophrenia: an historical and

E6 JAMA Psychiatry Published online June 19, 2019 (Reprinted) jamapsychiatry.com

© 2019 American Medical Association. All rights reserved.

Downloaded From: https://jamanetwork.com/ by a Idaho State University User on 07/18/2019


From Many to One to Many—the Search for Causes of Psychiatric Illness Special Communication Clinical Review & Education

philosophical analysis. Philos Psychiatry Psychol. chromosome 11. Nature. 1987;325(6107):783-787. 47. Kendler KS. Levels of explanation in psychiatric
2011;18(1):41-63. doi:10.1353/ppp.2011.0005 doi:10.1038/325783a0 and substance use disorders: implications for the
36. Coppen A. The biochemistry of affective 42. Baron M, Risch N, Hamburger R, et al. Genetic development of an etiologically based nosology.
disorders. Br J Psychiatry. 1967;113(504):1237-1264. linkage between X-chromosome markers and Mol Psychiatry. 2012;17(1):11-21. doi:10.1038/mp.
doi:10.1192/bjp.113.504.1237 bipolar affective illness. Nature. 1987;326(6110): 2011.70

37. Edwards AC, Bacanu SA, Bigdeli TB, Moscati A, 289-292. doi:10.1038/326289a0 48. Marshall CR, Howrigan DP, Merico D, et al;
Kendler KS. Evaluating the dopamine hypothesis of 43. Schizophrenia Working Group of the Psychosis Endophenotypes International
schizophrenia in a large-scale genome-wide Psychiatric Genomics Consortium. Biological Consortium; CNV and Schizophrenia Working
association study. Schizophr Res. 2016;176(2-3): insights from 108 schizophrenia-associated genetic Groups of the Psychiatric Genomics Consortium.
136-140. doi:10.1016/j.schres.2016.06.016 loci. Nature. 2014;511(7510):421-427. doi:10.1038/ Contribution of copy number variants to
nature13595 schizophrenia from a genome-wide study of 41,321
38. Gründer G, Cumming P. The dopamine subjects. Nat Genet. 2017;49(1):27-35. doi:10.1038/
hypothesis of schizophrenia: current status. In: Abel 44. Wray NR, Ripke S, Mattheisen M, et al; ng.3725
T, Nickl-Jockschat T, eds. The Neurobiology of eQTLGen; 23andMe; Major Depressive Disorder
Schizophrenia. Cambridge, MA: Academic Press; Working Group of the Psychiatric Genomics 49. Ramaswami G, Geschwind DH. Genetics of
2016:109-124. doi:10.1016/B978-0-12-801829-3. Consortium. Genome-wide association analyses autism spectrum disorder. Handb Clin Neurol. 2018;
00015-X identify 44 risk variants and refine the genetic 147:321-329. doi:10.1016/B978-0-444-63233-3.
architecture of major depression. Nat Genet. 2018; 00021-X
39. Gusella JF, Wexler NS, Conneally PM, et al.
A polymorphic DNA marker genetically linked to 50(5):668-681. doi:10.1038/s41588-018-0090-3 50. Paulus MP, Thompson WK. The challenges and
Huntington’s disease. Nature. 1983;306(5940): 45. Sullivan PF, Agrawal A, Bulik CM, et al; opportunities of small effects: the new normal in
234-238. doi:10.1038/306234a0 Psychiatric Genomics Consortium. Psychiatric academic psychiatry [published online February 27,
genomics: an update and an agenda. Am J Psychiatry. 2019]. JAMA Psychiatry. doi:10.1001/
40. Sherrington R, Brynjolfsson J, Petursson H, jamapsychiatry.2018.4540
et al. Localization of a susceptibility locus for 2018;175(1):15-27. doi:10.1176/appi.ajp.2017.17030283
schizophrenia on chromosome 5. Nature. 1988;336 46. Kendler KS. The structure of psychiatric
(6195):164-167. doi:10.1038/336164a0 science. Am J Psychiatry. 2014;171(9):931-938.
41. Egeland JA, Gerhard DS, Pauls DL, et al. Bipolar doi:10.1176/appi.ajp.2014.13111539
affective disorders linked to DNA markers on

jamapsychiatry.com (Reprinted) JAMA Psychiatry Published online June 19, 2019 E7

© 2019 American Medical Association. All rights reserved.

Downloaded From: https://jamanetwork.com/ by a Idaho State University User on 07/18/2019

You might also like