Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 20

Information and Economics:

A Critique of Hayek
Allin F. Cottrell and W. Paul Cockshott
October, 1994

1 introduction ning put forward by Hayek in his classic arti-


cle ‘The Use of Knowledge in Society’ (1945).
Neither the theoretical arguments put forward The relevance of such an argument to the read-
in the West, nor the fact of the collapse of ership of this journal might be questioned.
Soviet socialism, historic landmark as it un- Doesn’t Hayek lie outside of the mainstream
doubtedly is, warrant the belief that socialist of British (increasingly, Anglo-American) pro-
economic planning tout court is an untenable fessional economics, with its dual roots in Mar-
notion whose time has passed. Indeed, mod- shallian pragmatism and the formal general
ern developments in information technology equilibrium theory of the Lausanne school?
open up the possibility of a planning system Wasn’t Hayek’s defence of the market always
that could outperform the market in terms of a bit too strident and doctrinaire to suit the
efficiency (in meeting human needs) as well sensibilities of a profession that (in Britain
as equity. Such are the claims that we have at any rate) has traditionally had a broadly
defended in a number of recent publications, social-democratic outlook? Maybe so, but it is
designed to re-open a debate over socialist our impression that Hayek’s star is on the rise
economics.1 We do not expect that our ideas in the post-Communist world, and that even
will meet with immediate political success, those who baulk at his extreme enthusiasm for
but we do venture to hope that open-minded the unfettered market are often quite ready to
economists will consider our economic argu- see his arguments used to bury any form of
ments on their merits. thorough-going socialism.
We do not intend to reiterate our general And so to business. We offer below an expo-
arguments in favour of planning here. Our ob- sition and point-by-point contestation of the
ject is to refute the objections to socialist plan- ideas in Hayek (1945). We should make it clear
that some, though by no means all, of our criti-
1 Our ideas were first presented in Cockshott and cisms of Hayek are anachronistic—that is, they
Cottrell (1989), and are set out most fully in Cockshott
depend on advances in information technology
and Cottrell (1993). Cottrell and Cockshott (1993a)
re-examines the historic socialist calculation debate, that have taken place since Hayek wrote. We
with emphasis on the arguments of Mises and Lange. think this is justified for two reasons. First,
In Cottrell and Cockshott (1993b) we stress the dif- Hayek clearly thought he was putting for-
ferences between our proposals and the system that
ward a very general argument, which he did
existed in the Soviet Union. Technical details of the
algorithm we propose for short- to medium-term plan- not expect to see undermined by technological
ning are spelled out in Cockshott (1990). change. Second, Hayek’s followers (e.g. Lavoie,

1
1985) continue to support his arguments of He argues that there is an irreducible sub-
several decades ago, and to assert that devel- jective element to the subject mater of the so-
opments in information technology are largely cial sciences which was absent in the physical
beside the point. sciences.
In our exposition of Hayek we try to bal-
ance concision with the need to produce a suf- [M]ost of the objects of social or human
action are not “objective facts” in the
ficiently full and fair account to obviate the
special narrow sense in which the term
suspicion that we may be attacking a straw is used in the Sciences and contrasted
man. We begin with a brief summary of the to “opinions”, and they cannot at all be
philosophical views that inform the argument defined in physical terms. So far as hu-
of ‘The Use of Knowledge in Society’, which man actions are concerned, things are
are spelled out more fully in The Counter- what the acting people think they are.
Revolution of Science (Hayek, 1955). (Hayek, 1955, pp. 27–27)

His paradigm for the social or moral sciences


2 hayek’s argument out- is that society must be understood in terms of
men’s conscious reflected actions, it being as-
lined sumed that people are constantly consciously
choosing between different possible courses of
2.1 The philosophical action. Any collective phenomena must thus
background be conceived of as the unintended outcome of
the decisions of individual conscious actors.
In The Counter Revolution of Science Hayek This imposes a fundamental dichotomy be-
is concerned to contrast the natural and social tween the study of nature and of society, since
sciences, whose relation to their subject mat- in dealing with natural phenomena it may be
ter, he claims, is fundamentally different. In reasonable to suppose that the individual sci-
the natural sciences, advances involve recog- entist can know all the relevant information,
nising that things are not what they seem. while in the social context this condition can-
Science dissolves the immediate categories of not possibly be met.
subjective experience and replaces them with
underlying, often hidden, causes. The study of
society on the other hand has to take as its
2.2 The basic economic problem
raw material the ideas and beliefs of people in From this philosophical ground Hayek (1945)
society. The facts studied by social science poses the question: ‘What is the problem we
wish to solve when we try to construct a ra-
differ from the facts of the physical sci- tional economic order?’
ences in being beliefs or opinions held by He continues:
particular people, beliefs which as such
are our data, irrespective of whether On certain familiar assumptions the an-
they are true or false, and which, more- swer is simple enough. If we possess all
over, we cannot directly observe in the the relevant information, if we can start
minds of people but which we can recog- out from a given system of preferences
nise from what they say or do merely be- and if we command complete knowledge
cause we have ourselves a mind similar of available means, the problem which
to theirs. (Hayek, 1955, p. 28) remains is purely one of logic. That is,

2
the answer to the question of what is 2.3 Against centralisation
the best use of the available means is
implicit in our assumptions. The condi- The point at issue between Hayek and the
tions which the solution of this optimum proponents of socialist economic planning is
problem must satisfy have been fully not “whether planning is to be done or not”.
worked out and can be stated best in Rather it is “whether planning is to be done
mathematical form: put at their briefest, centrally, by one authority for the whole eco-
they are that the marginal rates of sub- nomic system, or is to be divided among many
stitution between any two commodities individuals” (Hayek, 1945, pp. 520–21). The
or factors must be the same in all their latter case is nothing other than market com-
different uses. (Hayek, 1945, p. 519) petition, which “means decentralized planning
He immediately makes it clear, however, by many separate persons” (Hayek, 1945, p.
that the ‘familiar assumptions’ upon which the 521). And the relative efficiency of the two al-
above approach is predicated are quite unreal. ternatives hinges on
This, however, is emphatically not the whether we are more likely to succeed in
economic problem which society faces putting at the disposal of a single cen-
. . . The reason for this is that the data tral authority all the knowledge which
from which the economic calculus starts ought to be used but which is initially
are never for the whole society given to dispersed . . . or in conveying to individ-
a single mind which could work out the uals such additional knowledge as they
implications, and can never be so given. need in order to fit their plans in with
(ibid .) those of others. (ibid .)

Hayek then spells out his own perspective The next step in Hayek’s argument in-
on the nature of the problem: volves distinguishing two different kinds of
knowledge: scientific knowledge (understood
The peculiar character of the problem of as knowledge of general laws) versus “unor-
a rational economic order is determined ganized knowledge” or “knowledge of the par-
precisely by the fact that the knowledge
ticular circumstances of time and place”. The
of the circumstances of which we must
make use never exists in concentrated
former, he says, may be susceptible of central-
or integrated form, but solely as the dis- ization via a “body of suitably chosen experts”
persed bits of incomplete and frequently (Hayek, 1945, p. 521) but the latter is a differ-
contradictory knowledge which all the ent matter.
separate individuals possess. (ibid .)
[P]ractically every individual has some
The true problem is therefore “how to se- advantage over others in that he pos-
cure the best use of resources known to any sesses unique information of which ben-
of the members of society, for ends whose rel- eficial use might be made, but of which
use can be made only if the decisions
ative importance only these individuals know”
depending on it are left to him or
(Hayek, 1945, p. 520, emphasis added). That are made with his active cooperation.
this is not generally understood, Hayek claims, (Hayek, 1945, pp. 521–22)
is an effect of naturalism or scientism, that is
“the erroneous transfer to social phenomena Hayek is thinking here of “knowledge of peo-
of the habits of thought we have developed in ple, of local conditions, and special circum-
dealing with the phenomena of nature” (ibid .). stances” (Hayek, 1945, p. 522), e.g., of the fact

3
that a certain machine is not fully employed, central planning based on [aggregated]
or of a skill that could be better utilized. He statistical information by its nature can-
also cites the sort of specific, localised knowl- not take direct account of these circum-
edge relied upon by shippers and arbitrageurs. stances of time and place, and . . . the
He claims that this sort of knowledge is often central planner will have to find some
way or other in which the decisions de-
seriously undervalued by those who consider
pending upon them can be left to the
general scientific knowledge as paradigmatic. man on the spot. (ibid .)

2.4 The importance of change Rapid adaptation to chang-


ing circumstances of time and place requires
Closely related, in Hayek’s mind, to the un-
decentralisation—we can’t wait for some cen-
dervaluation of knowledge of local and specific
tral board to issue orders after integrating all
factors is underestimation of the role of change
knowledge.
in the economy. One key difference between
advocates and critics of planning concerns
2.5 Prices and information
the significance and frequency of
changes which will make substantial al- While insisting that very specific, localised
terations of production plans necessary. knowledge is essential to economic decision
Of course, if detailed economic plans making, Hayek clearly recognises that the
could be laid down for fairly long pe- “man on the spot” needs to know more than
riods in advance and then closely ad-
just his immediate circumstances before he
hered to, so that no further economic de-
cisions of importance would be required,
can act effectively. Hence there arises the prob-
the task of drawing up a comprehen- lem of “communicating to him such further
sive plan governing all economic activ- information as he needs to fit his decisions
ity would appear much less formidable. into the whole pattern of changes of the larger
(Hayek, 1945, p. 523) economic system” (Hayek, 1945, p. 525) How
much does he need to know? Fortuitously, only
Hayek ascribes to his opponents the idea that which is conveyed by prices. Hayek con-
that economically-relevant change is some- structs an example to illustrate his point:
thing that occurs at discrete intervals and on
a fairly long time-scale, and that in between Assume that somewhere in the world a
such changes the management of the produc- new opportunity for the use of some raw
tive system is a more or less mechanical task. material, say tin, has arisen, or that one
As against this, he cites, for instance, the prob- of the sources of supply of tin has been
lem of keeping cost from rising in a competi- eliminated. It does not matter for our
tive industry, which requires considerable day- purpose and it is very significant that
to-day managerial energy, and he emphasises it does not matter which of these two
causes has made tin more scarce. All
the fact that the same technical facilities may
that the users of tin need to know is
be operated at widely differing cost levels by that some of the tin they used to con-
different managements. Effective economical sume is now more profitably employed
management requires that “new dispositions elsewhere, and that in consequence they
[be] made every day in the light of circum- must economize tin. There is no need for
stances not known the day before” (Hayek, the great majority of them even to know
1945, p. 524). He therefore concludes that where the more urgent need has arisen,

4
or in favor of what other uses they ought This observation leads Hayek to a very char-
to husband the supply. (Hayek, 1945, p. acteristic statement of his general case against
526) central planning.

Despite the absence of any such overview, [T]hose who clamour for “conscious
direction”—and who cannot believe
the effects of the disturbance in the tin market
that anything which has evolved with-
will ramify throughout the economy just the
out design (and even without our
same. understanding it) should solve prob-
lems which we should not be able
The whole acts as one market, not be- to solve consciously—should remember
cause any of its members survey the this: The problem is precisely how to ex-
whole field, but because their limited in- tend the span of our utilization of re-
dividual fields of vision sufficiently over- sources beyond the span of the control
lap so that through many intermedi- of any one mind; and, therefore, how to
aries the relevant information is commu- provide inducements which will make in-
nicated to all. (ibid .) dividuals do the desirable things with-
out anyone having to tell them what to
Therefore the significant thing about the do. (Hayek, 1945, p. 527)
price system is “the economy of knowledge
with which it operates” (Hayek, 1945, pp. 526– Hayek generalises this point by reference to
7). He drives his point home thus: other “truly social phenomena” such as lan-
guage (also an undesigned system). Against
It is more than a metaphor to describe the idea that consciously designed systems
the price system as a kind of machin- have some sort of inherent superiority over
ery for registering change, or a system those that have merely evolved, he cites A.
of telecommunications which enables in- N. Whitehead to the effect that the progress
dividual producers to watch merely the of civilisation is measured by the extension of
movement of a few pointers, as an engi- “the number of important operations which
neer might watch the hands of a few di-
we can perform without thinking about them”
als, in order to adjust their activities to
changes of which they may never know
(Hayek, 1945, p. 528). He continues:
more than is reflected in the price move- The price system is just one of those for-
ments. (Hayek, 1945, p. 527) mations which man has learned to use. . .
after he had stumbled upon it without
He admits that the adjustments produced understanding it. Through it not only
via the price system are not perfect in the a division of labor but also a coordi-
sense of general equilibrium theory, but they nated utilization of resources based on
are nonetheless a “marvel” of economical co- an equally divided knowledge has be-
ordination. (ibid .) come possible. . . [N]obody has yet suc-
ceeded in designing an alternative sys-
tem in which certain features of the ex-
2.6 Evolved order isting one can be preserved which are
dear even to those who most violently
The price system has not, of course, arisen as assail it such as particularly the extent
the product of human design, and moreover to which the individual can choose his
“the people guided by it usually do not know pursuits and consequently freely use his
why they are made to do what they do” (ibid .). own knowledge and skill. (ibid .)

5
The outline of Hayek’s argument is now, we aging director. In any large firm, the courses
trust, clearly in view. We are ready to pro- of action taken result from a complex set of
ceed to our criticisms, which are structured as practices, reviews, and decision-making proce-
follows. We first challenge the subjectivist phi- dures involving many people, and in which the
losophy that underpins Hayek’s conception of procedures can be as important as who fills
information. We then offer an alternative per- which particular positions. We would argue
spective on the nature of the problem faced by that the economic subject that Hayek takes
a planned economic system, and we dispute as his starting point is not empirically given
Hayek’s claims regarding the benefits of de- at all, but is rather a reification of economic
centralisation. This then leads into a critique theory. The rational economic subject makes
of the idea that the market constitutes an effi- sense only in terms of formalised calculating
cient telecommunications system. Our critique procedures, which, if they are realised in prac-
is developed by means of a formal model of the tice, are more likely to be materialised in the
information exchanges required under market accounting and management practices of firms
and plan. The penultimate section of the pa- than in the brains of individuals. Economic
per deals with the idea that change is all im- theory then projects back these practices, ra-
portant; and the concluding section takes up tional for the enterprise as a juridical subject,
the issue of the market as a ‘spontaneously onto a supposedly constitutive human subject.
evolved’ system. The historical conditions for this projection
are clear enough. In the early stages of cap-
italism the distinction between personal and
3 hayek’s subjectivism: cri- juridical subjects was as yet ill defined. The
agent of economic practice thus appeared to
tique be the person of the capitalist or entrepreneur
rather than the firm. But from the standpoint
Hayek’s radically subjectivist view of the so- of the current state of economic development,
cial sciences is open to the objection that it can be seen that the rational calculating sub-
its constitutive category, the rational subject, ject is the property-maximising juridical sub-
is by no means obviously given. As Lawson ject. To the extent that in a property system
(1992) has argued, a wealth of psychological some of the juridical subjects are individual
and sociological research has revealed that hu- human animals, the reified subject of economic
man behaviour is highly routinized, and co- theory provides an account of what would be
ordinated in the main by unconscious brain rational action on their part. But the assertion
functions. Indeed, as Dennett (1991) relates, that these animals do engage in such rational
experiments in neuropsychology indicate that action is more an act of faith than an empirical
people act first and become concious of their result of science. By starting out with this act
intention to act later. of faith Hayek aimed to mark off economics as
For the more limited domain of economics, essentially a branch of moral philosophy rather
there is the problem that the ‘subjects’ in than science.
question are more likely to be juridical than But once the category of subject is recog-
personal. In the main, the economic actors in nised for what it is, not an empirically exist-
industrial production are firms, not human in- ing property of the human animal, but some-
dividuals. Nor can the actions of a firm be re- thing ascribed to it both by the structures of
duced to the inner subjective life of its man- language and of juridical discourse (Althusser,

6
1971), then this exclusion of science from the recording ownership and tenancy contracts,
study of society becomes untenable. It be- whether as written documents or the mortgage
comes just one more of the special pleas by marker stones so hated by the peasantry of At-
morality to hold the encroachments of science tica.
at bay. The development of price relies upon the
Hayek’s subjectivist philosophical stand- technology of counting and calculation, which
point has an important bearing on his argu- can never in a commercial society be a purely
ments against socialist planning, since these mental operation. Calculation demands a ma-
arguments hinge on the notion of subjective in- terial support, whether it be the calculi or
formation. Despite the fact that The Counter- small stones of the early Romans, or the coins
Revolution of Science was published after the and reckoning tables of late Antiquity and the
establishment of a scientific information the- middle ages. Economic rationality is an al-
ory by Shannon and Weaver (1949), Hayek’s gorithmic process supported by a machinery
notion of information remains resolutely pre- for computation and information storage. The
scientific. Admittedly, it takes time for the dis- fact that until recently the machinery was sim-
coveries of one discipline to percolate through ple and hand-operated—the abacus, the coin
to others. In the mid-1950s the idea of the ob- box, or the ledger—allowed it to be ignored in
jectivity of information had not yet spread far economic theory. But the means of rationality
beyond the study of telecommunications. But are as essential to economic relations as the
now, when it has revolutionised biology, be- means of production. Trade without a technol-
come the foundation of our major industries, ogy of calculation and record is as impractical
and begun to transform our understanding of as agriculture without instruments to turn the
social ideologies (Dawkins, 1982), its absence soil. Once these aspects of information the-
vitiates Hayek’s entire argument. ory and information technology are consid-
For Hayek information is essentially subjec- ered, quite different answers can be given to
tive; it is knowledge in people’s minds. Thus Hayek’s problem of economic information.
we have the problem of how information that
is dispersed in the minds of many can, through
the operations of the market, be combined for 4 the calculation problem
the common good. By taking this subjectivist
standpoint, attention is diverted away from
and its misrepresenta-
the very practical and important question of tion
the technical supports for information. It be-
comes impossible to see the production and We have argued elsewhere (Cottrell and Cock-
manipulation of information as both a tech- shott, 1993a) that the classic ‘socialist calcu-
nology and a labour process in its own right, lation debate’ in the first part of this cen-
whose development acts as a constraint upon tury took place on the terrain of the neo-
the possibility of economic relations. classical critics of socialism rather than its
In any but the most primitive of economies, Marxian advocates. This had an effect in
economic relations have depended upon the defining the structure of the problem. In the
development of techniques for objectifying in- neoclassical variant, the problem starts with
formation. Consider the relationship between the preferences of the individual agents and
landlord and tenant, and thus rent. This can their production possibilities. This formula-
only stabilise once society has a means for tion is vulnerable to Hayek’s critique, on the

7
grounds that individuals’ preferences are in via the market)? Surely only a megalomaniac,
no sense ‘given’ to the planners. But Marxian or at any rate one blinded by scientific hubris,
economists would not accept that these indi- could propose such a thing.
vidual preferences have any meaningful pre- Of course no single individual has the brain-
existence;2 they do not, therefore, form part power to understand all of the interconnec-
of the problem. tions of an economy, but when have social-
The practical problem is to bring produc- ists ever asserted anything so foolish? Not even
tion potential into alignment with a pattern of the most avid personality cultists claimed that
social need revealed by a combination of demo- Stalin drew up the 5-year plans himself. What
cratic political decisions (as in the case of, socialists have proposed is the replacement of
say, the appropriate level of public health ser- market information processing by the process-
vice provision) and aggregate consumer pur- ing of economic information within a planning
chases. Given a reasonable data-collection sys- organisation. In the past, because of techno-
tem reporting on the rates at which consumer logical limitations, the planning organisation
goods are selling, and assuming a pricing sys- has proceeded by a division of mental labour
tem based on labour values (Cockshott and among a large number of people. In the future,
Cottrell, 1993), deriving a target net-output the information processing is likely to be done
vector demands no special telepathic powers mainly by computing machines.
on the part of the planning system. It is per- In neither case—and here our critique of
haps harder to gather the information about Hayek’s subjectivism comes into play—is the
production possibilities. It is in this practical information concentrated in one mind. In the
context that Hayek’s discussion of centralised former case it is obviously not in the mind
versus decentralised control systems must be of a single worker, but it is not even in the
placed. minds of a collection of workers. Instead, the
information is mainly in their written records,
forms, ledgers, etc. These constitute the in-
5 to centralise or not? dispensible means of administration. From the
earliest temple civilisations of Sumer and the
5.1 ‘One mind’ Nile, the development of economic adminis-
tration was predicated upon the development
Austrian opponents of socialism talk as if so-
of means of calculation and record. The hu-
cialist planning has to be carried out by one
man mind enters in as an initial recorder of
man. Mises (1949) personified him as ‘the di-
information, and then as a manipulator of the
rector’. Hayek continues the metaphor, stating
recorded information. By procedures of calcu-
that the “data from which the economic calcu-
lation strings of symbols are read and trans-
lus starts are never for the whole society given
formed ones written down. The symbols—
to a single mind”. How then, he asks, can one
whether they be arabic numerals, notches on
mind presume to improve on the combined re-
tally sticks or quipu—represent physical quan-
sult of the cogitations of millions (as achieved
tities of goods; their transformations model ac-
2 Take the homely example of Christmas shopping. tual or potential movements of these goods.
Many of us find it impossible to draw up a complete By posing the question in terms of con-
plan for such shopping in advance. We have to go to the
centrating the information in a single mind,
shops, look at the goods and their prices, and see what
strikes our fancy. Our ‘demand functions’ are revealed Hayek harks back to a pre-civilised condition,
to ourselves in the act of choosing. abstracting from the real processes that make

8
any form of administration possible. If instead, Further, even the sort of ‘particular’ knowl-
his objection is that no system of admin- edge which Hayek thought too localised to
istration can possibly have the information- be susceptible to centralisation is now rou-
processing capacity required for the task, then tinely centralised. Take his example of the in-
he is liable to the attack that information tech- formation possessed by shippers. In the 1970s
nology has revolutionised the amount of infor- American Airlines achieved the position of
mation that can be effectively administered. the world’s largest airline, to a great extent
on the strength of their development of the
SABRE system of computerised booking of
5.2 Forms of knowledge
flights (Gibbs, 1994). Since then we have come
The dichotomy that Hayek operates between to take it for granted that our local travel
the natural sciences and the social domain agent will be able to tap into a computer net-
also leaves its imprint on his categorisation work to determine where and when there are
of forms of knowledge. In his view, there flights available from just about any A to any
are but two such forms: knowledge of gen- B across the world. Hayek’s appeal to localised
eral scientific laws, and (subjective) knowl- knowledge in this sort of context may have
edge of ‘particular circumstances of time and been appropriate at the time of writing, but
place’. But this leaves out of account a whole it is now clearly outdated.
layer of knowledge that is crucial for eco- We would not dispute, however, that some
nomics, namely knowledge of specific technolo- localised knowledge, important for the fine-
gies. Such knowledge is not reducible to gen- grained efficiency of the system, may be too
eral scientific law (it is generally a non-trivial specific for any meaningful centralisation. Our
problem to move from a relevant scientific the- objection here is that Hayek seems to overlook
ory to a workable industrial innovation), but the possibility that this sort of knowledge may
neither is it so time- or place-specific that it is simply be used locally, without prejudice to the
non-communicable. The licensing and transfer operation of a central plan. The question here
of technologies in a capitalist context shows concerns the degree of recursiveness of plan-
this quite clearly. A central registry of avail- ning, that is, the extent to which plans can
able technologies would form as essential com- be formulated in general terms by the higher
ponent of an efficient planning system. How planning authorities, to be specified in pro-
would such information be assembled? Again, gressively fuller detail by successively lower or
Hayek’s notion of knowledge existing solely ‘in more local instances. Nove (1977, 1983) has ar-
the mind’ is an obstacle to understanding. It gued persuasively that as regards the compo-
is increasingly common—indeed, it is by now sition of output, the degree of recursiveness of
all but universal practice—for firms to keep planning is rather small. If a central authority
records of their inputs and outputs in the form sets output targets in aggregated terms, and
of some sort of computer spreadsheet. These leaves it to lower instances to specify the de-
computer files form an image of the firm’s tails, the result is bound to be incoherent. In
input–output characteristics, an image which the absence of the sort of horizontal links be-
is readily transferable.3 tween enterprises characteristic of the market
3 Admittedly, such an image does not of itself pro- system, the enterprises simply cannot know
vide any information on how, for instance, a particu-
larly favourable set of input–output relations can be ther thoughts on the transmission of such ‘know how’
achieved, only that it is possible. We offer some fur- in Section 6 below.

9
what specific sort of output will be needed, production function as alternative users of in-
unless they are told this by the planning au- puts.
thority. This may be granted.4 But low recur- It is important to distinguish the two types
siveness with respect to decisions on the com- of interaction. The first represents real flows
position of output does not imply that all de- of material and is a static property of a snap-
cisions relating to production have to be taken shot of the economy. The second, the variation
centrally. Consider the knowledge, at the level in potential uses for goods, is not a property
of the enterprise, of which particular workers of the real economy but of the phase space
are best at which tasks, who is the fastest of possible economies. The latter is part of
worker and who the most reliable and so on the economic problem insofar as this is consid-
(and similarly for the particular machines op- ered to be a search for optimal points within
erated within the enterprise). Why shouldn’t this phase space. In a market economy, the
such knowledge just be used locally in draw- evolution of the real economy—the real inter-
ing up the enterprise’s own detailed schedules dependencies between branches—provides the
for meeting an output plan given from the search procedure by which these optima are
‘centre’ ? Isn’t this precisely what happens at sought. The economy describes a trajectory
plant level in the context of planning by a large through its phase space. This trajectory is the
(multiplant) capitalist enterprise? product of the trajectories of all of the indi-
vidual economic agents, with these individual
agents deciding upon their next position on
5.3 Disadvantages of dispersal the basis of the information they get from the
Having argued that the centralisation of much price system.
economic information is feasible, we now con- Following up on Hayek’s metaphor of the
sider its desirability. When economic calcu- price system as telecoms system or machin-
lation is viewed as a computational process, ery for registering changes, the market econ-
the advantages of calculation on a distributed omy as a whole acts as a single analog pro-
or decentralised basis are far from evident; cessor. A single processor, because at any one
the question hinges on how a multiplicity of point in time it can be characterised by a sin-
facts about production possibilities in differ- gle state vector that defines its position in the
ent branches of the economy interrelate. Their phase space of the economic problem. More-
interrelation is, partially, an image in the field over, this processor operates with a very slow
of information of the real interrelation of the cycle time, since the transmission of informa-
branches of the economy. The outputs of one tion is bounded by the rate of change of prices.
activity act as inputs for another: this is the To produce an alteration in prices, there must
real interdependence. In addition, there are po- be a change in the real movement of goods (we
tential interactions where different branches of are abstracting here from the small number of
highly specialised futures markets). Thus the
4 Although Nove’s case is surely exaggerated in one
speed of information transmission is tied to
respect: if the central plan calls for enterprise A to
supply intermediate good x to enterprise B, where it the speed with which real goods can be moved
will be used in the production of some further good or new production facilities brought on line.
y, and if the planners apprise A and B of this fact, In sum, a market economy performs a single-
surely there is scope for horizontal discussion between
threaded seach through its state space, with
the two enterprises over the precise design specification
of x, even in the absence of market relations between a relatively slow set of adjustments to its po-
A and B. sition, the speed of adjustments being deter-

10
mined by how fast the real economy can move. (Hayek, 1955;5 see also Nove, 1983). We have
established elsewhere (Cockshott and Cottrell,
Contrast this now with what can poten-
1993; Cottrell and Cockshott, 1993b) that
tially be done if the relevant facts can be
given modern computer technology this is far
concentrated, not in one place—that would
from the case.
be impossible—but within a small volume of
space. If the information is gathered into one
or more computing machines, these can search 6 inadequacy of the price
the possible state space without any change in
the real economy. form
Here the question of whether to concentrate Prices, according to Hayek, provide the tele-
the information is very relevant. It is a basic coms system of the economy. But how ade-
property of the universe that no portion of it quate is this telecoms system and how much
can affect another in less time than it takes for information can it really transmit?
light to propagate between them. Suppose one Hayek’s example of the tin market bears
had all the relevant information spread around careful examination. Two preliminary points
a network of computers across the country. As- should be made. First, the market system does
sume any one of these could send a message manage to achieve a reasonable degree of coor-
to any other. Suppose that this network was dination of economic activities. The “anarchy
now instructed to simulate possible states of of the market” (Marx) is far from total chaos.
the economy in order to search for optima. The Second, even in a planned system there will al-
evolution from one simulated state to another ways be scope for the disappointment of expec-
could proceed as fast as the computers could tations, for projects that looked promising ex
exchange information regarding their own cur- ante to turn out to be failures and so on. Fail-
rent state. Given that electronic signals be- ures of coordination are not confined to market
tween them travel at the speed of light this will systems. That said, it is nonetheless clear that
be far faster than a real economy can evolve. Hayek grossly overstates his case. In order to
But the speed of evolution will be much make rational decisions relating to changing
faster still if we bring all of the computers into one’s usage of tin, one has to know whether a
close proximity to one another. Massively par- rise in price is likely to be permanent or tran-
allel computers attempt to place all the proces- sient, and that requires knowing why the price
sors within a small volume, thereby allowing has risen. The current price signal is never
signals moving at the speed of light to prop- enough in itself. Has tin become more expen-
agate around the machine in a few nanosec- sive temporarily, due, say, to a strike by the tin
onds, compared to the hundredths of a second miners? Or are we approaching the exhaustion
required for telecoms networks. Hence, in gen- of readily available reserves? Actions that are
eral, if one wishes to solve a problem fast, the 5 The specific reference here is to p. 43, and

information required should be placed in the more particularly to note 37 on pp. 212–213, of The
smallest possible volume. Counter-Revolution of Science. In the note, Hayek ap-
peals to the judgment of Pareto and Cournot, that
It may be objected that the sheer scale the solution of a system of equations representing the
conditions of general equilibrium would be practically
of the economic problem is such that al-
infeasible. This is perhaps worth emphasising in view
though conceivable in principle, such com- of the tendency of Hayek’s modern supporters to play
putations would be unrealisable in practice down the computational issue.

11
rational in the one case will be quite inappro- If we start from the assumption that prices
priate in the other. will almost certainly not remain unchanged in
Prices in themselves provide adequate future, how are agents supposed to form their
knowledge for rational calculation only if they expectations? One possibility is that they are
are at their long-run equilibrium levels, but able to gather sufficient relevant information
of course for Hayek they never are. On this to make a definite forecast of the changes that
point it is useful to refer back to Hayek’s own are likely to occur. This clearly requires that
theory of the trade cycle (Hayek, 1935; see they know much more than just current prices.
also Lawlor and Horn, 1992; Cottrell, 1994), They must know the process whereby prices
in which the ‘misinformation’ conveyed by dis- are formed, and form forecasts of the evolution
equilibrium prices can cause very substantial of the various factors (at any rate, the more
macroeconomic distortions. In Hayek’s cycle important of them) that bear upon price de-
theory, the disequilibrium price that can do termination. Hayek’s informational minimal-
such damage is the rate of interest, but clearly ism is then substantially breached. A second
the same sort of argument applies at the micro possibility is that described by Keynes (1936,
level too. Decentralised profit-maximising re- esp. chapter 12): agents are so much in the
sponses to unsustainable prices for tin or RAM dark on the future that, although they are
chips are equally capable of generating misin- sure that some (unspecified) change will occur,
vestment and subsequent chaos. they fall back upon the convention of assum-
At minimum, prices may be said to carry ing that tomorrow’s prices will equal today’s.
information regarding the terms on which var- This enables them to form a conventional as-
ious commodities may currently be exchanged, sessment of the profitability of producing vari-
via the mediation of money (so long as markets ous commodities, using current price informa-
markets clear, which is not always the case). It tion alone; but the cost of this approach (from
does not follow, however, that a knowledge of the standpoint of a defender of the efficiency
these exchange ratios enable agents to calcu- of the market) is the recognition that those ex
late the profitability, let alone the social use- ante assessments will be regularly and perhaps
fulness, of producing various commodities. A substantially wrong.
commodity can be produced at profit if its
price exceeds the sum of the prices of the in- 6.1 Prices, efficiency and ‘know
puts required to produce it, using the pro-
how’
duction method which yields the least such
sum, but the use of current prices in this cal- It is one of the progressive features of capi-
culation is legitimate only in a static con- talism that the process of competition forces
text: either prices are unchanging or produc- some degree of convergence upon least-cost
tion and sale take zero time. Hayek, of course, methods of production (even if the cost in
stresses constant change as the rule, so he is question is monetary cost of production, which
hardly in a position to entertain this sort of reflects social cost in a partial and distorted
assumption. Whether production of commod- manner). Hayek reminds us, and rightly so,
ity x will in fact prove profitable or not de- that this convergence may in fact be far from
pends on future prices as well as current prices. complete. Firms producing the same commod-
And whether production of x currently ap- ity (and perhaps even using the same basic
pears profitable depends on current expecta- technology) may co-exist for extended periods
tions of future prices. despite having quite divergent costs of pro-

12
duction. If the law of one price applies to the 7 information flows under
products in question, the less efficient produc-
ers will make lower profits and/or pay lower
market and plan
wages. This situation can persist provided the
mobility of capital and labour are less than One of Hayek’s most fundamental arguments
perfect. is that the efficient functioning of an economy
involves making use of a great deal of dis-
tributed information, and that the task of cen-
tralising this information is practically impos-
sible. In what follows we attempt to put this
The question arises whether convergence on argument to a quantitative test. We compare
best practice could be enforced more effec- the communications costs implicit in a mar-
tively in a planned system. We believe this is ket system and a planned system, and exam-
so. If all workers are paid at a uniform rate ine how the respective costs grow as a function
for work done, it will be impossible for in- of the scale of the economy. Communications
efficient producers to mask their inefficiency cost is a measure of work done to centralise or
by paying low wages. Indeed, with the sort of disseminate economic information: we will use
labour-time accounting system we have advo- the conceptual apparatus of algorithmic infor-
cated elsewhere (Cockshott and Cottrell, 1989, mation theory (Chaitin, 1982) to measure this
1993), differentials in productive efficiency will cost.
be immediately apparent. Not only that, but Our strategy is first to consider the dynamic
there should be a broader range of mecha- problem of how fast, and with what commu-
nisms for eliminating differentials once they nications overhead, an economy can converge
are spotted. A private firm may realise that on equilibrium. We will demonstrate that this
a competitor is producing at lower cost, but can be done faster and at less communications
short of industrial espionage may have no way cost by the planned system. We consider ini-
of finding out how this is achieved. Conver- tially the dynamics of convergence on a fixed
gence of efficiency, if it is attained at all, may target, since the control system with the faster
have to wait until the less efficient producer impulse response will also be faster at tracking
is driven out of business and its market share a moving target.
usurped by more efficient rivals. In the context Consider an economy E = [A, c, r, w] with
of a planned system, on the other hand, some n producers each producing distinct products
of the managers or technical experts from the under constant returns to scale using technol-
more efficient enterprises might, for instance, ogy matrix A, with a well defined vector of
be seconded as consultants to the less effi- final consumption expenditure c that is inde-
cient enterprises. One can also imagine—in the pendent of the prices of the n products, an
absence of commercial secrecy—economy-wide exogenously given wage rate w and a compati-
electronic bulletin boards on which the people ble rate of profit r. Then there exists a possible
concerned with operating particular technolo- Sraffian equilibrium e = [U, p] where U is the
gies, or producing particular products, share commodity flow matrix and p a price vector.
their tips and tricks for maximising efficiency. We will assume, as is the case in commercial
The present popularity of this sort of thing arithmetic, that all quantities are expressed to
amongst users of personal computers suggests some finite precision rather than being real
that it might easily be generalised. numbers. How much information is required

13
to specify this equilibrium point? similar argument applies to the two price vec-
Assuming that we have some efficient binary tors pk and pe . If we assume that the system
encoding method and that I(s) is a measure follows a dynamic law that causes it to con-
in bits of the information content of the data verge on equilibrium then we should have the
structure s using this method, then the equi- relation I(kt+1 |e) < I(kt |e).
librium can be specified by I(e), or, since the We now construct a model of the amount
equilibrium is in a sense given in the starting of information that has to be transmitted be-
conditions, it can be specified by I(E) + I(ps ) tween the producers of a market economy in
where ps is a program to solve an arbitrary sys- order to move it towards equilibrium. We make
tem of Sraffian equations. In general we have the simplifying assumptions that all produc-
I(e) ≤ I(E) + I(ps ). In the following we will tion process take one timestep to operate, and
assume that I(e) is specified by I(E) + I(ps ). that the whole process evolves synchronously.
Let I(x|y) be the conditional or relative in- We assume the process starts just after pro-
formation (Chaitin, 1982) of x given y. The duction has finished, with the economy in
conditional information associated with any some random non-equilibrium state. We fur-
arbitrary configuration of the economy, k = ther assume that each firm starts out with a
[Uk , pk ], may then be expressed relative to given selling price for its product. Each firm i
the equilibrium state, e, as I(k|e). If k is in carries out the following procedure.
the neighbourhood of e we should expect that 1. It writes to all its suppliers asking them their
I(k|e) ≤ I(k). For instance, suppose that we current prices.
can derive Uk from A and an intensity vec- 2. It replies to all price requests that it gets,
tor uk which specifies the rate at which each quoting its current price pi .
industry operates then 3. It opens and reads all price quotes from its
suppliers.
I(k|e) ≤ I(uk ) + I(pk ) + I(pu ) 4. It estimates its current per-unit cost of pro-
duction.
where pu is a program to compute Uk from
some A and some uk . Since Uk is a matrix 5. It calculates the anticipated profitability of
and uk a vector, each of scale n, we can assume production.
that I(Uk ) > I(uk ). 6. If this is above r it increases its target pro-
As the economy nears equilibrium the con- duction rate ui by some fraction. If profitabil-
ditional information required to specify it will ity is below r a proportionate reduction is
made.
shrink, since uk starts to approximate to ue .6
Intuitively we only have to supply the differ- 7. It now calculates how much of each input j
ence vector between the two, and this will re- is required to sustain that production.
quire less and less information to encode, the 8. It sends off to each of its suppliers j, an order
smaller the distance between uk and ue . A for amount Uij of their product.
9. It opens all orders that it has received and
6 Note that this information measure of the distance
from equilibrium, based on a sum of logarithms, differs (a) totals them up.
from a simple Euclidean measure, based on a sum of (b) If the total is greater than the avail-
squares. The information measure is more sensitive to
a multiplicity of small errors than to one large error.
able product it scales down each order
Because of the equivalence between information and proportionately to ensure that what it
entropy it also measures the conditional entropy of the can supply is fairly distributed among
system. its customers.

14
(c) It dispatches the (partially) filled orders entropy of the economy to some level . Com-
to its customers. munication takes place at steps 1, 2, 8 and
(d) If it has no remaining stocks it increases 9c of the procedure. How many messages does
its selling price by some increasing func- each supplier have to send, and how much in-
tion of the level of excess orders, while formation must they contain?
if it has stocks left over it reduces its Letters through the mail contain much re-
price by some increasing function of the dundant pro forma information: we will as-
remaining stock. sume that this is eliminated and the messages
10. It receives all deliveries of inputs and deter- reduced to their bare essentials. The whole of
mines at what scale it can actually proceed the pro forma will be treated as a single symbol
with production. in a limited alphabet of message types. A re-
11. It commences production for the next period. quest for a quote would thus be the pair [R, H]
where R is a symbol indicating that the mes-
Experience with computer models of this
sage is a quotation request, and H the home
type of system indicates that if the readiness
address of the requestor. A quote would be the
of producers to change prices is too great, the
pair [Q, P ] with Q indicating the message is a
system could be grossly unstable. We will as-
quote and P being the price. An order would
sume that the price changes are sufficiently
similarly be represented by [O, Uij ], and with
small to ensure that only damped oscillations
each delivery would go a dispatch note [N, Uij ]
occur. The condition for movement towards
indicating the actual amount delivered, where
equilibrium is then that over a sufficiently
Uij ≤ Uij .
large ensemble of points k in phase space, the
If we assume that each of n firms has on av-
mean effect of an iteration of the above proce-
erage m suppliers, the number of messages of
dure is to decrease the mean error for each eco-
each type per iteration of the procedure will
nomic variable by some factor 0 ≤ g < 1. Un-
be nm. Since we have an alphabet of message
der such circumstances, while the convergence
types (R, Q, O, N ) with cardinality 4, these
time in vector space will clearly follow a loga-
symbols can be encoded in 2 bits each. We
rithmic law—to converge by a factor of D in in
will further assume that (H, P, Uij , Uij ) can
vector space will take time of order log g1 (D)—
each be encoded in binary numbers of b bits.
in information space the convergence time will We thus obtain an expression for the commu-
be linear. Thus if at time t the distance from nications cost of an iteration of 4nm(b + 2).
equilibrium is I(kt |e), convergence to within a Taking into account the number of iterations,
distance  will take a take a time of order the cost of approaching the equilibrium will be
I(kt |e) −  4nm(b + 2)∆I(k|e).
δ log( g1 ) Let us now contrast this with what would be
required in a planned economy. Here the pro-
where δ is a constant related to the number of cedure involves two distinct procedures, that
economic variables that alter by a mean fac- followed by the (state-owned) firm and that
tor of g each step. The convergence time in followed by the planning bureau. The firms do
information space, for small , will thus ap- the following:
proximate to a linear function of I(k|e) which
1. In the first time period:
we can write as ∆I(k|e).
We are now in a position to express the com- (a) They send to the planners a message
munications costs of reducing the conditional listing their address, their technical in-

15
put coefficients and their current out- We assume that with computer technology the
put stocks. steps b and c can be undertaken in a time
(b) They receive instructions from the plan- that is small relative to the production pe-
ners about how much of each of their riod (Cockshott 1990, Cockshott and Cottrell
output is to be sent to each of their 1993).
users. Comparing the repsective information flows,
(c) They send the goods with appropriate it is clear that the number of orders and dis-
dispatch notes to their users. patch notes sent per iteration is invariant be-
(d) They receive goods inward, read the tween the two modes of organisation of pro-
dispatch notes and calculate their new duction. The only difference is that in the
production level. planned case the orders come from the cen-
(e) They commence production. ter whereas in the market they come from the
customers. These messages will again account
2. They then repeatedly perform the same se- for a communications load of 2nm(b + 2). The
quence replacing step 1a with: difference is that in the planned system there
(a) They send to the planners a message is no exchange of price information. Instead,
giving their current output stocks. on the first iteration there is a transmission of
information about stocks and technical coeffi-
The planning bureau performs the comple-
cients. Since any coefficient takes two numbers
mentary procedure:
to specify, the communications load per firm
1. In the first period: will be: (1 + 2m)b. For n firms this approxi-
(a) They read the details of stocks and mates to the nm(b + 2) that was required to
technical coefficients from all of their communicate the price data.
producers. The difference comes on subsequent itera-
(b) They compute the equilibrium point e tions, where, assuming no technical change,
from technical coeffients and the final there is no need to update the planners’ record
demand. of the technology matrix. On i − 1 subsequent
(c) They compute a turnpike path (Dorf- iterations, the planning system has therefore
man, Samuelson and Solow, 1958) from to exchange only about half as much infor-
the current output structure to the mation as the market system. Furthermore,
equilibrium output structure. since the planned economy moves on a turn-
(d) They send out for firms to make deliv- pike path to equilibrium, its convergence time
eries consistent with moving along that will be less than that of the market econ-
path. omy. The consequent communications cost is
2nm(b + 2)(2 + (i − 1)) where i < ∆I(k|e).
2. In the second and subsequent periods:
The consequence is that, contrary to
(a) They read messages giving the extent Hayek’s claims, the amount of information
to which output targets have been met. that would have to be transmitted in a planned
(b) They compute a turnpike path from the system is substantially lower than for a market
current output structure to the equilib- system. The centralised gathering of informa-
rium output structure. tion is less onerous than the commercial corre-
(c) They send out for firms to make deliv- spondence required by the market. In addition,
eries consistent with moving along that the convergence time of the market system is
path. slower. The implication of faster convergence

16
for adaptation to changing rather than stable value of the increase, say 10 pence, the whole
conditions of production and consumption are amounts to some 12 bits. So on the day the
obvious. price changes, it conveys some 3000 times as
In addition, it should be noted that in our much information as it did every other day of
model for the market, we have ignored any in- the year.
formation that has to be sent around the sys- So it is almost certainly true that most of
tem in order to make payments. In practice, the information in a price series is encoded
with the sending of invoices, cheques, receipts, in the price changes. From the standpoint of
clearing of cheques etc., the information flow someone observing and reacting to prices, the
in the market system is likely to be twice as changes are all important. But this is a view-
high as our estimates. The higher communi- point internal to the dynamics of the market
cations overheads of market economies are re- system. One has to ask if the information thus
flected in the numbers of office workers they conveyed has a more general import. The price
employ, which in turn leaves its mark on the changes experienced by a firm in a market
architecture of cities—witness the skylines of economy can arise from many different causes,
Moscow and New York. but we have to consider which of these rep-
resent information that is independent of the
social form of production.
8 the argument from dy- We can divide the changes into those that
are direct results of events external to the price
namics system, and those which are internal to the
system. The discovery of new oil reserves or
Does Hayek’s concentration on the dynamic an increase in the birth rate would directly im-
aspect of prices, price as a means of dy- pinge upon the price of oil or of baby clothes.
namically transmitting information, make any These represent changes in the needs or pro-
sense? duction capabilities of society, and any sys-
In one way it does. Consider the price of tem of economic regulation should have means
a cup of coffee. Notionally this can be writ- of responding to them. On the other side,
ten in a couple of digits—80 pence, say— we must count a fall in the price of acrylic
which would imply that on information the- feedstocks and a fall in the price of acrylic
oretic grounds it transmits about 7 bits of sweaters, among the second- and third-order
information. But look more closely, and this internally generated changes consequent upon
is almost certainly an overestimate. Not only a fall in oil prices. In the same category would
is the price likely to be rounded up to the go the rise in house prices that follows an
nearest 5 pence, implying an information con- expansion of credit, any fluctuation in share
tent of about 5 bits, but yesterday’s price was prices, or the general fall in prices that marks
probably the same. If the price changes only the onset of a recession. These are all changes
once a year, then for 364 days the only infor- generated by the internal dynamics of a mar-
mation that it conveys is that the price has ket system, and as such irrelevant to the con-
not changed. The information content of this, sideration of non-market economies.
− log2 364
365 , is about 0.0039 of a bit. Then when Hayek is of course right that the planning
the price does change its information content problem is greatly simplified if there are no
1
is − log2 365 + b where b is the number of bits changes, but it does not follow from this that
to encode the price increase. For a reasonable all the changes of a market economy are po-

17
tential problems for a planned one. We have Hayek is to be commended on his ability to
demonstrated elsewhere that the problem of make the best of a bad case, to make virtues
computing the appropriate intensities of oper- out of necessities. The unavoidable instabili-
ation of all production processes, given a fully ties of the market are disguised as blessings.
disagregated input–output matrix and a tar- The very crudity of prices as an information
get final output vector, is well within the ca- mechanism are seen as providentially protect-
pacity of computer technology. The compute ing people from information overload.
time required is sufficiently short for a plan-
ning authority, should it so wish, to be able
to perform the operation on a daily basis. In 9 conclusion: evolution and
performing this calculation the planners arrive
at the various scales of production that the history
market economy would operate at were it able
to attain general equilibrium. Faced with an Hayek contrasts the ‘spontaneously evolved’
exogenous change, the planners can compute price system with the artificiality of conscious
the new equilibrium position and issue direc- attempts to control the economic process, a
tives to production units to move directly to contrast that he feels is to the disadvantage of
it. This direct move will involve the physical the latter. At best, this is no more than the
movement of goods, laying of foundations, fit- maxim that one is better to ‘hold tightly onto
ting out of buildings etc, and will therefore nurse for fear of meeting something worse’. At
take some considerable time. worst it degenerates into a Panglossian com-
We now have two times, the time of calcu- placency about the existing order of things.
lation and the time of physical adjustment. If Voltaire’s rejoinder on earthquakes—these too
we assume that the calculation is performed are spontaneous—is apposite. But while we
with an iterative algorithm, we find that in can hope to do no more than forecast earth-
practice it will converge acceptably within a quakes, it fallacious to think that we are forced
dozen iterations. Since each of these iterations endure their economic equivalent with the
would take a few minutes on a supercomputer same stoicism.
the overall time would probably be under an By writing of spontaneous evolution, Hayek
hour. In a market economy, even making the surreptitiously slips in connotations from biol-
most favourable assumptions about its ability ogy, with its associations of fitness of form to
to adjust stably to equilibrium, the individual function. But the analogy of a market economy
iterations will take a time proportional to the with a naturally evolved order is superficial,
physical adjustment time. The overall relax- with regard both to its operation and gene-
ation period would be around a dozen times sis. If we consider the operation of a market
as long as that in the planned system. economy as the procedural search for an opti-
But of course these assumptions are unreal- mum, it obvious that while there is a great deal
istically favourable to the market system. Long of parallelism going on—lots of people mak-
before equilibrium was reached, new external ing decisions at the same time—it remains the
shocks would have occurred. Even the assump- case that the whole search is single-threaded.
tion that the system seeks equilibrium is ques- Taken as a whole, the state space of the econ-
tionable. There is every reason to believe that omy is a Cartesian product of the state spaces
far from having stable dynamics, it is liable to of its components, and within this total state
oscillatory or chaotic behaviours. space the economy is located at a unique point

18
at every moment in time. As such, it can only tra Hayek, is to let a hundred flowers bloom.
visit a small proportion of the possible set of
solutions, and for it to progress towards any-
thing other than a local optimum presupposes References
a particular and very simple topology to the
space. Althusser, L. (1971). ‘Ideology and ideo-
In this sense, the movement of a market logical state apparatuses’. In Lenin and
economy differs from the process of biological Philosophy and Other Essays. London:
evolution. A species evolves towards increas- NLB.
ing adaptation to its environment by a highly Chaitin, G. J. (1982). ‘Algorithmic infor-
parallel process. The state space in this case mation theory’. In Encyclopedia of Sta-
consists of the genetic code. But a species is tistical Sciences, vol. 1. New York: Wiley,
not in one position in this space at any one pp. 38–41.
time: it is at as many positions as there are Cockshott, W. P. (1990). ‘Application of
individual members of the species, each with artificial intelligence techniques to eco-
a unique combination of genes. A species rep- nomic planning’. Future Computing Sys-
resents a neighbourhood in gene space. It ap- tems, vol. 2, pp. 429–43.
plies a parallel search procedure: millions of al- Cockshott, W. P. and Cottrell, A. (1989).
ternative designs are produced and compared ‘Labour value and socialist economic cal-
each generation. Although a market economy culation’. Economy and Society, vol. 18,
can to some extent emulate this in the area of pp. 71–99.
product development within individual com- Cockshott, W. P. and Cottrell, A. (1993).
petitive markets, the economy as a whole acts Towards a New Socialism. Nottingham:
as a single processor. Spokesman.
It equally invalid to treat the genesis of Cottrell, A. (1994). ‘Hayek’s early cycle
the capitalist world system as an evolution- theory re-examined’. Cambridge Journal
ary outcome. It is an historical outcome, but of Economics, vol. 18, 197–212.
history and evolution are not the same thing. Cottrell, A. and Cockshott, W. P. (1993a).
Evolutionary adaptation is impossible without ‘Calculation, complexity and planning:
variation, competition and selection. To ap- the socialist calculation debate once
ply evolutionary concepts one would have to again’. Review of Political Economy, vol.
hypothesise a substantial population of simul- 5, pp. 73–112.
taneously existing international economic sys- Cottrell, A. and Cockshott, W. P. (1993b).
tems. In fact there is only one. For a while ‘Socialist planning after the collapse of
there were two, of which only one has survived. the Soviet Union’. Revue Européene des
That is not a statistically valid sample. To Sciences Sociales, vol. 31, pp. 167–185.
say that one economic order was evolutionarily Dawkins, R. (1982). The Extended Pheno-
better adapted than another, one would need a type. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
large enough ensemble for stochastic effects to Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness Ex-
cancel out—an ensemble including instances plained . Boston: Little, Brown.
where the market system was restricted to one Dorfman, R., Samuelson, P. A., and Solow,
poor and backward economy surrounded by an R. M. (1958). Linear Programming and
industrialised socialist world. Economic Analysis. New York: McGraw
The logic of the analogy with evolution, con- Hill.

19
Gibbs, W. W. (1994). ‘Software’s chronic
crisis’. Scientific American, vol. 271, pp.
86–95.
Hayek, F. A. (1935). Prices and Produc-
tion, revised edition. London: Routledge.
Hayek, F. A. (1945). ‘The use of knowl-
edge in society’. American Economic Re-
view , vol. 35, pp. 519–30.
Hayek, F. A. (1955).
The Counter-Revolution of Science. New
York: The Free Press.
Keynes, J. M. (1936). The General The-
ory of Employment, Interest and Money.
London: Macmillan.
Lavoie, D. (1985).
Rivalry and Central Planning: The So-
cialist Calculation Debate Reconsidered .
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lawlor, M.S. and Horn, B.L. (1992).
‘Notes on the Sraffa–Hayek Exchange’,
Review of Political Economy, vol 4.
Lawson, T. (1992). ‘Realism and Hayek:
a case of continuous transformation’,
mimeo, University of Cambridge.
Mises, L. (1949). Human Action: A Trea-
tise on Economics. New Haven: Yale Uni-
versity Press.
Nove, A. (1977). The Soviet Economic Sys-
tem. London: George Allen and Unwin.
Nove, A. (1983). The Economics of Feasi-
ble Socialism. London: George Allen and
Unwin.
Shannon, C. E., and Weaver, W. (1949).
The Mathematical Theory of Communica-
tion. Urbana, Ill.: University of Illinois.

20

You might also like