Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

Hutcheson's Reflections upon Laughter

Author(s): Elizabeth Telfer


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 53, No. 4 (Autumn, 1995), pp.
359-369
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/430971
Accessed: 02-05-2020 14:35 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ELIZABETH TELFER

Hutcheson's Reflections Upon Laughter

Francis Hutcheson's three short essays on which show that a sudden perception of one's
laughter first appeared in The Dublin Journal in superiority is neither necessary nor sufficient
1725, the same year as the first publication of for the production of laughter. Among the kinds
the Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of of laughter which do not depend on a sudden
Beauty and Virtue. The first essay is a refutation perception of superiority he mentions a favorite
of Thomas Hobbes's account of laughter, which topic of his, laughter at burlesque or parody;
had been discussed by Joseph Addison in The among the perceptions of superiority which do
Spectator in 1711.1 The second is Hutcheson's not normally arouse laughter are the cases of
own account of the nature of laughter. The third a rich man suddenly seeing a poor man or a
is a discussion of the uses and dangers of laugh- healthy man a sick one.
ter. I will show that the limitations of Hutche-
son's account of the nature of laughter weaken II
his account of its uses and dangers. But I am
aware that it was impossible in any case for
Hutcheson's reasons for rejecting Hobbes's ac-
Hutcheson to do more than scratch the surface
count as a general account of all kinds of laugh-
of this enormous topic in the space of three very
ter are sound ones, although Hobbesian consid-
short essays. Nevertheless, they are an impor-
erations do have a place in a full account of
tant and interesting contribution to an ongoing
laughter. Hutcheson's own theory of laughter in
debate on the nature and morality of humor
the second essay is more problematic. The first
which began with Plato and Aristotle and con-
problem is to work out what the theory is a the-
tinues today.
ory of. He says that laughter is a "sensation, ac-
According to Hobbes, the "passion of laugh-
tion, passion, or affection, I know not which of
ter" is a "sudden glory" which arises when we
them a philosopher would call it."'5 This list runs
suddenly see ourselves as eminent in compari-
together laughter the observable phenomenon
son with the "infirmity" of others or with our
and what produces it; laughter itself is not a sen-
own former selves. The account is simple in
sation, passion, or affection. But neither is it
Hobbes's Human Nature,2 the version that Ad-
usually an action, something deliberately per-
dison quotes; in Leviathan Hobbes adds the ob-
formed for a reason. (Where laughter is deliber-
servation that people laugh a lot at others if
ate, it is called insincere or not genuine laugh-
conscious of many deficiencies in themselves.3
ter.) Hutcheson is really more interested in what
This kind of account of laughter has a long his-
produces laughter. In his third essay he dis-
tory: it is somewhat akin to Plato's doctrine in
tinguishes between laughter which "begins in
the Philebus4 that comedy is based on a mali-
the natural manner, from our perception in the
cious pleasure in weak characters' delusions
mind of something ludicrous"6 and laughter
about themselves or their situation.
arising "unnaturally from external motions in
Hutcheson dislikes Hobbes's account, partly
the body."7 By the latter he presumably means
because it is one manifestation of the doctrine
laughter when tickled and the like-though the
that all human behavior is self-interested. He ar-
fact that one cannot tickle oneself suggests that
gues against it by producing counterexamples
a psychological element is actually present there

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53:4 Fall 1995

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
360 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

too.8 He seems to think that all "mental" laugh- The theory that amusement is produced by a
ter arises from a "perception of the ludicrous." combination of incongruity and resemblance
Strictly speaking, this is false; we can laugh for certainly fits some kinds of amusement very
joy or from a sense of relief, for example. But it be- well. Hutcheson says that the same principle ap-
comes clear that Hutcheson is attempting to give plies to all kinds of amusement. But many of his
an account only of our reactions to what we see examples do not involve simile, metaphor, or
as funny: amusement, in one sense of that word. other deliberately created resemblance, and it
Hutcheson thinks amusement is based on the is not clear that resemblance must always be
perception of an incongruity between some- involved. Hutcheson says that our amusement
thing dignified and something mean. He gives at the slipping-on-a-banana-peel type of case
various examples: (i) a dignified piece of writ- arises from the incongruity between two ideas:
ing, such as a passage of the Bible, or a dignified our idea of a person as dignified and of the inci-
manner of writing, applied to a trivial or undig- dent befalling that person as undignified. Here
nified subject; (ii) an undignified event happen- the humor seems to arise only from a difference,
ing to a dignified person (or to anyone, since he rather than from a difference combined with a
says we think of humanity itself as having dig- resemblance. Hutcheson might say that we see
nity); (iii) silly mistakes, unworthy of the dig- the man's undignified fall as incongruous be-
nity of man as a rational creature (typical of us cause he partly resembles the same man walking
Irish, he says); (iv) strong emotions, which have in a dignified way. But some comic incon-
their own dignity, aroused by an object which is gruities between the dignified and the mean-
either unworthy or (as in the April-Fools'-Day for example, a dog wandering into a church ser-
type of joke) nonexistent; (v) mean manners or vice-do not seem to involve even this degree of
dress on a dignified occasion. It is clear at once resemblance. Perhaps what Hutcheson should
that Hutcheson's account of amusement can be say is that incongruity presupposes some kind
applied to a much wider range of cases than of connection, often but not necessarily resem-
Hobbes's, including the literary examples of blance, between the elements seen as incongru-
burlesque and parody with which Hobbes can- ous. In the case of the dog in church, the con-
not cope at all. nection is simply one of place. But in many
In outline, Hutcheson's theory falls into the other kinds of humor, the connection is a resem-
category of incongruity theories of humor, blance combined with incongruous elements.
which, like superiority theories, have a long his-Thus in the burlesque or satirical cartoon, re-
tory.9 But his account of the incongruity is quitesemblances which "have contrary additional ideas"
complex. He begins by considering the use of are presented to us by the writer or artist.
apt, dignified simile and metaphor in heroic po- Hutcheson does not claim that we laugh at all
etry, and moves via a consideration of "grave incongruities. His claim seems to be that when
wit"-the use of unexpected comparison or the we do laugh it is always at something we see as
extension of it to more and more points of like- in some way incongruous. This has an intuitive
ness, as perhaps in the metaphysical poets-to plausibility, but even so it is rather a strong
the cause of laughter as the "bringing together claim. What are we to say about being amused
of images which have contrary additional ideas, by someone, whether in real life or in a play,
as well as some resemblance in the principal saying or doing exactly what we expect? This
idea."10 The contrast is between "ideas of common situation seems to be a case of being
grandeur, dignity, sanctity, perfection, and ideasamused by the congruous rather than the incon-
of meanness, baseness, profanity."' 1 Thus in a gruous. I think, however, it may be possible to
burlesque, a banal incident might be compared reconcile it with the incongruity theory. We can
to a heroic one which is somewhat similar in divide such cases into two types. The first type
content but totally different in dignity. Similarly,
of case is that of stereotyped behavior. For ex-
a cartoonist of today might depict Lady ample, the person repeats a stock phrase, like a
Thatcher as a turkey, and thereby link her with schoolmistress I had who greeted every misde-
something which is or can be made like her in meanor with the words: "They would never have
appearance, but which is also banal and there- done that at St. Leonard's, St. Andrews." De-
fore incongruous with her dignity. spite its predictability, this kind of behavior

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Telfer Hutcheson's Reflections Upon Laughter 361

does have a certain incongruity, because human the dignified and the mean, perhaps the notions
beings are normally more spontaneous; it is per- of the dignified and the mean are too vague to
haps a case of the mechanicalness which Berg- tell us much. I think there is something in this
son thought of as the essence of the amusing. criticism; we feel disappointed by the dilution of
The second kind of predictability is that where the notion of dignity from the narrower, more
people amuse us because what they say or do, informative sense it carries when Hutcheson is
while not mechanical, is very much in character. talking about burlesque and the comic misappli-
This is much more difficult for an incongruity cation of sacred texts. On the other hand, if an
theory to accommodate. But I think we tend to account of humor is to have any hope of apply-
be amused only where what is predictably said ing to all varieties of it, its basic ideas will need
or done betrays a foible or weakness (or some- to be very broad. Perhaps the basic idea which
thing which we see as such) such as meanness, Hutcheson requires is that of incongruity as im-
vanity, or an inability to say no to anyone. In- propriety, the failure (deliberate or accidental)
deed, we can be amused by a single incident to conform to some norm or canon of appropri-
which clearly reveals a weakness in an other- ateness. Since there are many different kinds of
wise respectable person. We might therefore con- norms, this is a very general idea indeed: the in-
strue this kind of amusement also as based on congruity between elevated styles of writing and
the perception of an incongruity: for example, lowly subject matter, between a formal occasion
that between the image of acceptability the per- and disordered dress, and between an enormous
son tries to maintain and the weakness which display of anger and a trivial provocation are all
inevitably reveals itself despite her efforts, or examples of it. If Hutcheson had employed this
between her perception of herself and others' conception, the incongruity between the digni-
perception of her. fied (in the sense of "elevated," "formal") and
I am inclined to accept that what amuses us is the mean would have retained its significance as
always something seen as incongruous. But a very important subclass of improprieties.
must the incongruity be between the dignified and What is the relationship between amusement
the mean? If dignity is always "grandeur, sanc- and the perception of incongruity supposed to
tity, perfection," as when Hutcheson first intro- be? Is Hutcheson simply equating the two? At
duces the notion, one is inclined to say that the the beginning of the third essay he says: "laugh-
theory does not cover all cases, though it does ter, like many other dispositions of our mind, is
apply to many important ones. But later Hutch- necessarily pleasant to us, when it begins in the
eson introduces the notion of man himself, his natural manner, from our perception in the mind
reason and his emotions, as having dignity, and of something ludicrous."'3 What does "neces-
so he is able to depict minor failures and mis- sarily pleasant" mean here? The passage is very
takes of many different kinds as incongruous similar to his claim in the Inquiry Concerning
because they are unbecoming to human dignity. 12Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design: "the ideas of
beauty and harmony, like other sensible ideas,
This is a very far-reaching idea. It can even cope
with such cases as our amusement at a row of are necessarily pleasant to us.'14 If we take the
tap-dancing children in a pantomime coming two cases to be parallel, we might interpret
on stage one by one, all in pink except the last Hutcheson thus: just as the perception of unity
who is in blue. At first sight this seems like a in variety gives rise to the idea of beauty, which
counterexample, because we cannot say that in its turn always gives rise to pleasure, so the
pink is dignified and blue mean or vice versa. perception of an incongruity between the digni-
But Hutcheson could say that the regularity is fied and the mean gives rise to the idea of the lu-
dignified because it expresses human order and dicrous, which in its turn always gives rise to
rationality, and the irregularity-deliberate in pleasure. But sometimes Hutcheson seems to
this case, of course-is mean because it sub- say that the idea of beauty actually is a kind of
verts them. pleasure, as when he equates "our power of per-
However, one might wonder at this point ceiving the beauty of regularity, order, har-
whether Hutcheson's theory has not become mony" with "the determination to be pleased
vacuous; if every human mistake or irregularity with certain complex forms" in the Preface to
can count as an example of incongruity between the two Inquiries. ' 5Perhaps he would similarly

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
362 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

say that our power of perceiving the amusing- whereas with beauty the emphasis is on the unity,
ness of certain incongruities just is a disposition with humor it is on the variety.'6
to be pleased with them.
This is a complex issue which I cannot ex- The unity Kivy speaks of in connection with
plore at length here. It is impossible to be sure humor is the resemblance which, as we saw, ap-
precisely what Hutcheson has in mind, because plies to all types of humor according to Hutche-
he does not directly discuss the question in the son's account. But "variety" does not mean the
Reflections Upon Laughter, and it is not clear same in the accounts of beauty and humor. In
how closely his doctrines on the "ludicrous" are Hutcheson's aesthetic theory, variety is really
meant to mirror those on beauty and virtue. For multiplicity: Hutcheson sees beauty as the repe-
example, it is not clear whether the sense of the tition of one form in a number of instances. In
ludicrous is meant to be a specific sense, like the
his theory of humor, however, "variety" is vari-
sense of beauty. I think he should be saying ance or discrepancy, the failure to repeat a uni-
three things: (i) we can distinguish between per- fied motif. So it looks as though Hutcheson
ceiving the incongruities and being amused by should indeed be puzzled by our enjoyment of
them; (ii) being amused by incongruities is a humor.
species of enjoyment; and (iii) this enjoyment, In one sense, of course, the problem is solved
if keen enough, is naturally expressed in laugh- for him by his belief in a Divine Providence. As
ter. We can show that there is a distinction be- he shows in the third essay, the pleasures of
tween the perception of the incongruity and the humor are useful to us; that is why we have been
amusement by recalling those cases where we made capable of this kind of pleasure. But there
know that something would amuse us if we were is still a problem about how we can be capable
in a better mood, and those where we speak as of it if the amusing is a species of the ugly.
though we can choose our attitude toward the in- I think that two approaches to this problem
congruous situation: "I couldn't decide whether are open to Hutcheson. Within the constraints
to laugh or cry." But the possibility of drawing of his aesthetic theory, he might deal with
this distinction between perception and enjoy- humor on the analogy with discords in music,
ment does not mean that the perception of the which, he says, "often give as great a pleasure as
incongruity is simply a neutral observation of continued harmony, whether by refreshing the
facts. As Hutcheson himself says, seeing some- ear with variety, or by awakening the attention,
thing as incongruous may itself involve a value and enlivening the relish for the succeeding har-
judgment-about what degree of emotion is ap- mony of concords."'17 Perhaps what is funny can
propriate in a particular situation, for example. be seen as giving this kind of pleasure. But a
And to see things as incongruous may also re- more promising approach would be to see the
quire a particular kind of imagination. pleasure of humor not as aesthetic pleasure but
But why do we enjoy these incongruities? as the pleasure of play. Play involves activity
Though he does not say so, Hutcheson is in a which is seen as not mattering or not serious,
difficulty here: according to his own theory of done in fun or for fun. Humor is similarly con-
beauty, his account of the amusing as a kind of trasted with what is serious: of both words and
incongruity seems to make the comic into a actions, people say "I wasn't serious, it was only
species of ugliness. In particular, where what is a joke." I suggest then that people who make
amusing is a moral failing, it is a blot on its pos- jokes are either pointing out or creating incon-
sessor's moral beauty. It looks as though we gruities for fun-or ostensibly for fun: they can
ought to find these incongruities distressing have an ulterior motive, as we shall see. And
rather than delightful. Peter Kivy, in his in- people who laugh at others' jokes, or at things
troduction to the Reflections Upon Laughter, they themselves see as funny, are adopting a
makes a brave try at resolving the problem by playful attitude toward these incongruities-
assimilating Hutcheson's account of the amus- usually involuntarily, but sometimes apparently
ing to his account of beauty: by choice, as I have already said. If we see
humor as a kind of play or as involving a nonse-
In a certain sense ... the quality of humor, like that of rious attitude, we can explain why it tends to be
beauty, is based on the notion of unity in variety; but concerned with small weaknesses, petty mis-

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Telfer Hutcheson's Reflections Upon Laughter 363

takes, trifling mishaps, and so on. A playful at- escape from everyday restrictions or as a reassur-
titude involves a kind of detachment from see- ance that other people are as vulnerable as our-
ing something as mattering, and this detachment selves.
may be more difficult to achieve if in reality the
thing is harmful, frightening, or deplorable. (I III

am not claiming that it is impossible to adopt


this playful attitude toward terrible things. A The third essay is on the effects and proper use
skillful use of humor can make us do just this, as of laughter, capacity for which Hutcheson as-
in Charlie Chaplin's film The Great Dictator, in sumes to be implanted in our natures by the
which he invites us to laugh at Hitler. In this Almighty for some good purpose. This ap-
case, the humor depends on the sharpness of the proach to laughter, as involving useful pleasure
contrast between our awareness that Hitler was given to us by God, is of course similar to the ap-
appalling and the playful attitude that we are proach to beauty and virtue in the Inquiry. In the
made to adopt toward him while watching the case of laughter, Hutcheson may have had an ad-
film.) ditional reason for stressing its God-given use-
The question of why we are intellectually fulness. Addison, in one of his Spectator papers
playful in this way is probably one for psychol- on the subject, had been rather ambivalent about
ogy rather than philosophy. Hutcheson, in the the basic value of laughter, quoting a suggestion
third essay, notes that laughter puts us in an that it essentially belongs to man's fallen nature
"easy, happy state" and cures "a soured temper."'18and lamenting the bad use people make of it:
This may be because the incongruities offer a
release from restraint, a mental holiday from the [the Talent of Ridicule] is generally made use of to
proprieties, whether these be the norms of re- laugh Men out of Virtue and Good Sense, by attack-
spectable behavior, the oppressive demands of ing everything that is Solemn and Serious, Decent
the sacred and sublime, or simply the rules of and Praise-worthy in Human Life.'9
language. Another possible psychological ex-
planation of many cases of amusement, as sev- Hutcheson does not mention Addison in the
eral commentators have said, is along Hobbes- third essay, as he does in the first. But the way
ian lines. That is to say, we might agree with in which he combines emphasis on laughter's
Hutcheson that to be amused by someone slip- providential status with words of caution about
ping on a banana peel is to enjoy the incongruity its dangers suggests that he may have the Spec-
between the dignity of his progress and the in- tator essay in mind.
dignity of his fall, but look to Hobbes for a psy- The third essay begins with brief general re-
chological explanation of why such things please marks about the beneficial effects of laughter,
us. It would be too extreme to say that we always but soon turns to consider its more specific uses
feel superior to people in such situations. But it and dangers. Most of the types of jokes which
might be plausible to say that we feel a kind of Hutcheson discusses are about individuals'
reassurance that we are not inferior, not the only foibles and weaknesses. But one group of topics
people to be subject to petty humiliations. may be called impersonal: jokes about things
I can now sum up my discussion of Hutche- which are truly great in every respect, jokes ap-
son's theory of the nature of amusement. I agree plying lofty sayings to mean subjects, and jokes
that what is amusing is a kind of incongruity. about the meaner aspects of important things.
But I think it is difficult to construe all amusing On the first of these topics, Hutcheson says
things as incongruities between the dignified that things which are truly great in every re-
and the mean without reducing these notions to spect, such as "the opinion of a good and wise
triviality; it would be better to see comic incon- mind governing the whole universe"20 or con-
gruity as some kind of impropriety. I also think spicuous virtue, cannot be joined to any mean
that Hutcheson needs a distinction between per- idea with any natural resemblance, and so any
ceiving the incongruity and being amused by it. joke about them will be "forced and remote."'21
The latter, I suggest, is a species of enjoyment, It will not please a man of sense and reflection,
more akin to play than to aesthetic appreciation; but will show the joker to be "void of just sense
perhaps we enjoy this kind of play as a mental of those things which are truly great."22

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
364 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

It is hard to understand Hutcheson's argument (It is not clear whether Hutcheson thinks that Dr.
here. If we link a truly great thing with a mean Pitcairn was making a joke, or making a pious
thing, we have surely produced just the kind of comment without realizing that it was all too apt.)
incongruity which he says is the basis of humor. Hutcheson does not condemn this type of
Why must such a connection be "forced and re- joke as "forced or unnatural," presumably be-
mote"? Perhaps Hutcheson thinks this because cause he cannot help appreciating its possible
he assumes that the connection must involve im- aptness. He is doubtful about the propriety of
puting to the perfect thing a deficiency which, Biblical jokes (though he says so in the second
by definition, it cannot have. This need not be essay,24 not the third), so he does realize that
so: the film Monty Python's Life of Brian, for ex- a joke can be both neat and improper. But the
ample, links the life of Christ to an absurd par- point he is most eager to make, both about jokes
allel story without in any way imputing imper- on truly great things and about the misapplica-
fection to Christ's life. But Hutcheson does not tion of lofty words, is that such jokes are harm-
make clear at this point that there is also a dif- less even though tasteless: he says that people
ferent kind of objection to such jokes. The man are not going to lose their admiration of con-
of sense and reflection may concede that a re- spicuous virtue or great literature simply be-
semblance is natural and apt, but still fail to be cause jokes are made about them.25 In saying
amused because he thinks that the subject mat- this, he is presumably relying on his doctrine
ter is too sublime to be linked with something that there is a basic natural sense of beauty and
lowly for the sake of a joke. In other words, he virtue. But one might wonder whether his confi-
thinks the joke is not silly but tasteless. dence is misplaced. It may be possible to under-
But is it not possible to be amused by jokes mine people's reverence for something by per-
which one sees as tasteless? Throughout this sistent joking about it. Jokes treat a thing as not
essay Hutcheson writes as though this is not mattering even if it does matter; and it may be
possible for the man of sense. Hutcheson says that in the end, for good or ill, people's percep-
that when a joke is unsuitable, a man of sense tions can be shifted. This is one context where
cannot relish it; in other words, the man of sense Hutcheson underestimates the dangers of humor.
does not merely think he ought not to be amused The last case of impersonal humor is laughter
by such jokes, he is genuinely not amused. Pre- at the mean aspects of things which are basi-
sumably Hutcheson's idea is that any pleasure cally important. Hutcheson talks of what is truly
that might have been taken in the incongruity isvaluable in any "character, institution, or of-
banished by dislike of the impropriety, and fice,"26 so, presumably, jokes about the faults of
probably he would say that a man cannot count public figures would be an example. He says
as a man of sense-of proper feeling-unless that the danger is that "people of little judg-
his reactions are coherent in this way. ment" may be misled into thinking that the
The second kind of impersonal joke is the ap- whole thing, not only the mean aspect, is con-
plication of grand words to mean subjects. temptible. But his suggestion for avoiding the
Hutcheson gives an example by referring again danger is problematic: he says we should always
to the true story which he tells as follows in the join "just veneration" of the good aspects of our
first essay: target to our jokes about the mean aspects. Pre-
sumably, we have to express the just veneration
Many an orthodox Scotch Presbyterian, which sect if we are to avoid misleading the people of little
few accuse of disregard for the holy Scriptures, has judgment. Now it is true that we sometimes have
been put to it to preserve his gravity, upon hearing the an instinct to do just this if we feel our jokes are
application of Scripture made by his countryman Dr. going too far: having made the joke, we say
Pitcairn, as he observed a crowd in the streets about a things like "It's a shame to laugh at him, he does
mason, who had fallen along with his scaffold, and a lot of good." But there are valuable kinds of
was overwhelmed with the ruins of the chimney which jokes in this class, such as satirical criticism of
he had been building, and which fell immediately the government of the day or other institutions,
after the fall of the poor mason: "Blessed are the dead which depend on the absence of a softening fac-
which die in the Lord, for they rest from their labours,tor. Satire will be neither funny nor effective if
and their works follow them."23 it always has to have a cautionary footnote, be-

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Telfer Hutcheson's Reflections Upon Laughter 365

cause its effectiveness rests on the fact already portant-important to everyone-such as the
noted: that ridicule can undermine awe and conspicuous virtues already mentioned as truly
make us realize that it is possible to criticize great, and that strong emotion about other
things which we are apt to revere unthinkingly. things is misplaced. But then the second prob-
Of course, there is also a danger of making peo- lem arises: does ridicule always produce the cor-
ple cynical about the whole thing, as Hutcheson rect degree of emotion, or does it simply lessen
this time realizes. But this is a risk which satire emotion, whether appropriately or not? Sup-
has to run if it is to be useful. pose, for example, I get heated about some in-
The personal uses of humor discussed by justice or cruelty. Someone wishing to cheer me
Hutcheson are of two kinds. First, we can use it up may succeed by ingenious jokes in making
to lessen another person's excessive emotion, of me feel that my passion is ridiculous. But it does
fear, veneration, resentment, and so on. Second, not follow that it is. And whereas Hutcheson is
we can use it to criticize trivial faults. On the writing here about "well-wishers," the same tech-
first use he says: nique of ridicule can be used by opponents to
undermine people's commitment to their cause
When any object either good or evil is aggravated and by getting them to feel that they are over-con-
increased by the violence of our passions, or an enthu- cerned about it. This is just the kind of thing that
siastic admiration, or fear, the application of ridicule Addison was worried about, and it constitutes
is the readiest way to bring down our high imagina- an example of Hutcheson's failure to see that
tions to a conformity to the real moment of the affair. humor can be dangerous for the same reasons
Ridicule gives our minds as it were a bent to the con- which make it useful.
trary side; so that upon reflection they may be more Hutcheson does not mention another impor-
capable of settling in a just conformity to nature.27 tant use of ridicule, later pointed out by Thomas
Reid: to expose intellectual absurdity. Reid says:
And later:
We may observe that opinions which contradict first
by our sense of the ridiculous, we are made capable of principles, are distinguished, from other errors, by
relief from any pleasant, ingenious well-wisher, by this:-that they are not only false, but absurd; and, to
more effectual means, than the most solemn, sedate discountenance absurdity, nature hath given us a par-
reasoning. Nothing is so properly applied to the false ticular emotion-to wit, the use of ridicule-which
grandeur, either of good or evil, as ridicule.28 seems intended for this very purpose of putting out of
countenance what is absurd, either in opinion or prac-
It is not clear whether Hutcheson is talking of tice.
ridicule which attaches something incongruous This weapon, when properly applied, cuts with as
to the object of fear or awe, points out incon- keen an edge as argument. Nature hath furnished us
gruities in it, or laughs at the disproportion of with the first to expose absurdity; as with the last to re-
emotion to its object. Presumably, any of these fute error. Both are well fitted for their several offices,
types of ridicule might achieve its aim. and are equally friendly to truth when properly used.
There are two problems about Hutcheson's Both may be abused to serve the cause of error; but
doctrine here. First, he writes as though there is the same degree of judgment which serves to detect
always an objectively correct degree of admira- the abuse of argument in false reasoning, serves to de-
tion, fear, resentment, and so on; thus he writes tect the abuse of ridicule when it is wrong directed.
of "conformity to the real moment or impor- ... But it must be acknowledged that the emotion of
tance of the affair" and "a just conformity to na- ridicule, even when most natural, may be stifled by an
ture." But is it always possible to say what the emotion of a contrary nature, and cannot operate till
"real moment or importance" of a thing is? In- that is removed.
deed, in the second essay29 Hutcheson himself Thus, if the notion of sanctity is annexed to an ob-
makes the point that people differ over the im- ject, it is no longer a laughable matter; and this visor
portance of ceremony, of gallantry, of financial must be pulled off before it appears ridiculous.30
security, and therefore over the degree of emo-
tion appropriate to them. Perhaps he thinks that It is interesting to compare this passage with
there are some things which are naturally im- Hutcheson's account of the use of ridicule to

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
366 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

lessen excessive emotion. Reid writes as though Laughter is received in a different manner by the per-
ridicule's exposure of absurdity is purely intel- son ridiculed, according as he who uses the ridicule
lectual and can take place only after the hearers evidences good-nature, friendship, and esteem of the
have lost the notion of sanctity which they pre- person whom he laughs at, or the contrary.3'
viously attached to the absurd thing. It is surely
more plausible to say, as Hutcheson does, that And later:
a very important aspect of the role of this kind
of ridicule is that it can also undermine the awe Ridicule upon the smallest faults, when it does not ap-
itself and so enable the absurdity to be per- pear to flow from kindness, is apt to be extremely
ceived. provoking, since the applying of mean ideas to our
The other personal use of humor is in cur- conduct discovers contempt of us in the ridiculer, and
ing people of minor faults by ridiculing them. that he designs to make us contemptible to others.32
Hutcheson says this is effective if at the same
time the ridiculer testifies his esteem of the goodHutcheson thus gives us a twofold classification
qualities of the person ridiculed, so that the vic-of personal jokes. On the one hand, there is con-
tim realizes it is done for his own good. This temptuous ridicule; some of this, despite the
reminds one of nothing so much as an agony laughter, does not really involve amusement,
aunt's advice. Reader: My friend has B.O.- though Hutcheson does not point this out. (This
how can I tell her? Agony Aunt: Make a joke of is one context where laughter can be a deliberate
it, but tell her at the same time how marvelous action.) On the other hand, there is friendly
you think she is, so she knows you're not just ridicule, sometimes with the aim of improving
being unkind! the butt. The first kind of ridicule is resented,
But is Hutcheson right, nonetheless, in think- the second (according to Hutcheson) accepted.
ing that it is easier to cope with criticism if it is But even friendly ridicule can seem to the vic-
couched in the form of a joke? This sounds like tim like an attack. Indeed, Hutcheson seems to
an empirical question; but my analysis of the admit this elsewhere. At the beginning of the
amusing shows why Hutcheson may be right. If third essay he says: "We are disposed by laugh-
a person makes a straightforward criticism of ter to a good opinion of the person who raises
me, I have to take up a position on it: for exam- it, if neither ourselves nor our friends are made
ple, challenge his right to make it, attempt to the butt."33 Here he implies that people dislike
rebut it, or admit its probable justice. If a joke being laughed at, whether or not they think the
is made, however, I need not do any of these laughter is contemptuous. If this is so, there is a
things, because as we saw, a joke is in itself an general problem, which he does not discuss,
invitation not to take something seriously. I can about the morality of laughing at people: why is
therefore save my face and avoid confrontation it not regarded as unkind to enjoy oneself, and
by apparently taking the joke at face value and give pleasure to others, by using other people's
laughing merrily, while privately taking the crit- oddities and weaknesses in a way they tend to
icism to heart. However, this technique of criti- dislike?
cism is not foolproof. One danger is that I may I can suggest three possible answers to this
not realize that a criticism is implied and may question, which seem to me to be complemen-
assume that my failing is merely pleasantly tary rather than mutually exclusive. First, we
funny. The other danger is that I might see thatmight
a think of joking as a kind of game or con-
criticism is intended but resent the fact that test, in which the rule is that it is fair to laugh at
making it is turned into an occasion for others toothers provided you are willing to let them laugh
enjoy themselves at my expense: "If what you at you. On this view, being laughed at can be
mean is that I shouldn't eat with my mouth open, seen as rather unpleasant, but the compensation
why can't you simply say 'Don't eat with your is that if one can "take a joke" oneself, one has
mouth open'?" Hutcheson is not alert to this sec- the right to laugh at others. According to this
ond problem, because he thinks that whether or view, it is unkind to laugh at someone who is not
not we are hurt by jokes depends only on how in a position to retaliate. Second, there is the
we interpret the motive of the person making view suggested by Roger Scruton in his paper on
them: laughter.34 He says in effect that although peo-

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Telfer Hutcheson's Reflections Upon Laughter 367

ple do not generally like being laughed at they person of moral sensibility should not be able to
may still seek it, because it is impossible to love make or enjoy such jokes. In other words, we
those who are so perfect that they cannot be would apply to this kind of case the very point
laughed at. In other words, it is endearing to be about the man of sense which Hutcheson makes
funny, and so people put up with being laughed about profane jokes but does not employ here.
at because others then love them all the more. The same issues arise about Hutcheson's sec-
This view fits with three ideas we tend to have: ond unsuitable subject for personal humor,
that some jokes against us are acceptable from namely "imperfections which one cannot
friends but not from acquaintances; that making amend"37-presumably such things as stam-
a joke about someone in his presence is some- mers and enormous noses. We would expect him
times a gesture of friendship and acceptance to say that these jokes too, like the jokes about
rather than of criticism; and that those who great misfortunes, are heartless when made in
make perpetual butts of themselves seek not the subject's presence-as surely they are. But
laughter but affection. The third defense of jok- he does not say so, perhaps because he thinks it
ing is that people who are upset by jokes at their is obvious. What he does say is that such jokes
expense often reveal a failing in themselves are "useless," because "men of sense cannot rel-
rather than in the joker. Since there are plenty of ish them," and "foolish and trifling minds" can
things about ourselves which we would laugh at be led by them to despise worthy people. How-
in someone else, those who have a sense of pro- ever, he does not say why he thinks that men of
portion and some humility should be able to see sense cannot relish such jokes; prima facie "im-
the joke (not merely "take a joke") and enjoy it perfections which one cannot amend" give rise
themselves. to just the kind of incongruity which is funny.
None of these considerations would show that Perhaps he thinks that compassion for the af-
all jokes have to be put up with-indeed, there flicted person should prevent us from being able
can be a lack of self-respect in being willing to to make or appreciate such a joke, even in his
accept any and every joke, however harsh. Nor absence; in other words, perhaps he is employ-
do they confirm Hutcheson's view that jokes ing the idea of moral tastelessness to which he
about non-disgraceful attributes are always ac- should have appealed in connection with jokes
ceptable to the butt.35 Such jokes (for example, about great misfortunes. Or perhaps he thinks
jokes about a person's striking good looks or that because the blemish cannot be amended,
silly name) can still be seen by the victim as an such jokes are unjust. This would make the func-
attack, if they are persistent (as they tend to be); tion of jokes as moral criticisms essential rather
this is because they can give the victim the feel- than incidental-an interesting idea, but not one
ing that she or he is- valued only for the scope she he endorses earlier. Or perhaps he simply thinks
or he gives for others' humor. it is undignified to take notice of such things,
Finally, Hutcheson discusses some unsuitable which are, after all, the very stuff of children's
subjects for personal humor. Great misfortunes, jokes. It seems impossible to say which is the
he says, provoke pity rather than laughter, and most plausible interpretation.
"forced" connections with them for the sake of I think we can agree with Hutcheson that
a joke will seem heartless to the sufferer.36 This jokes about great misfortunes or incurable blem-
seems to miss the point; a joke about a great ishes are in general unattractive. But there are
misfortune can be unforced and ingenious, but situations, not mentioned by him, where we re-
still seem heartless to the sufferer. For example, joice in them. One such situation is that where
Dr. Pitcairn's mason would certainly have the sufferer himself makes the joke. We can
thought the joke heartless if he had lived long enjoy such jokes without moral unease because
enough to hear it. Nor is the effect on the suf- they show a kind of courage, an ability to take
ferer the only possible ground for criticism of one's own misfortunes lightly; whereas lack of
such jokes. Suppose Dr. Pitcairn had made his compassion is morally ugly, courage is beauti-
joke later, or out of earshot. We might still dis- ful. Another such situation is farcical comedy, in
approve of it on moral grounds, because we which grievous calamities and incurable imper-
would feel that although it caused no distress it fections are both standard ingredients, as are
showed an unpleasant lack of compassion; a barbarous crimes, another subject which Hutch-

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
368 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

eson thinks unsuitable for laughter.38 Is Hutche- humor, sometimes not fearful enough, as I have
son committed to the view that a "man of sense" tried to show. If we endeavor to make it ab-
cannot relish farce? And if so, should we agree solutely safe by adding warning notices to our
with him? jokes, as Hutcheson suggests in connection with
This is a difficult question to answer. Hutch- satire, we will not be able to benefit from it. But
eson might claim that his remarks are not in- if we are too ready to assume, as Hutcheson
tended to cover stage humor. But real-life comic does, that some things are immune to the danger
narrations also can be stylized performances, in of being undermined by persistent mockery, we
which the humor depends, not on suffering and may be harmed by humor.
wrongdoing as such, but on the mechanical, Humor is an important topic. One must not be
one-sided way in which they are presented. The misled by its quality of presenting things as not
man of sense might think that in these stylized mattering into thinking that humor itself has no
circumstances, the suspension (which the suc- significance in human interaction. Hutcheson
cessful farce or farcical narration produces) of realizes this and tries to explain and assess its
the normal reactions of pity, disapproval, and importance. His account has many limitations,
even disgust is permissible and even useful, as a but it also contains many interesting and impor-
kind of holiday in safe surroundings from the tant insights.40
"proper" attitudes. Another example of useful
but normally unsuitable humor is gallows ELIZABETH TELFER
humor, or the black humor characteristic of doc- Department of Philosophy
tors, soldiers, and others who work in distress- University of Glasgow
ing situations and use such jokes to distance Glasgow G12 8QQ
themselves from the emotions which would oth- United Kingdom
erwise make their work impossible.
But perhaps in all this there is also a danger, INTERNET: AJM@ARTS.GLA.AC.UK

of the kind Hutcheson points out in other con-


texts, of being led to take real sufferings and
1. The Spectator, vol. I, ed. Donald F. Bond (Oxford:
crimes too lightly. As we saw, Hutcheson says
Clarendon Press, 1965), pp. 200-204 (No. 47, Tuesday,
that "weak and foolish minds" can be misled by April 24, 171 1).
humor into feeling contempt for what is worth- 2. Thomas Hobbes, Human Nature, chap. IX, par. 13, in
while and important, instead of simply laughing The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, vol.
IV, ed. Sir William Molesworth (London: John Bohm,
at blemishes in it or funny associations set up
1840), pp. 45-47.
with it. Perhaps the same thing can happen with 3. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, part I, chap. 6, in The En-
jokes about suffering or crime. In all these cases, glish Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, vol. III, ed.
after all, we have a motive for allowing this to Sir William Molesworth (London: John Bohm, 1839), p. 46.
happen. Funny things are presented as things 4. Plato, Philebus, ed. and trans. R. Hackworth as Plato's
Examination of Pleasure (Cambridge: Cambridge University
we need not take seriously or do anything about,
Press, 1945), pp. 92-98 (Stephanus 47d5-50e2).
so the more things we can think of as merely 5. Francis Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, ed. R. S.
funny, the more we are let off the hook. Downie (London: Everyman, J. M. Dent, 1994), p. 52.
Humor, then, is a weapon to be used with 6. The meaning of the word "ludicrous" has shifted. In
Hutcheson's time the word often meant what we now mean
care, as Hutcheson saw:
by "amusing," rather than bearing the pejorative sense ("ab-
surd," ridiculous") which is the only sense now current.
Ridicule, like other edged tools, may do good in a 7. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 57.
wise man's hands, though fools may cut their fingers 8. I owe this point to Simon Blackburn.
with it, or be injurious to an unwary bystander.39 9. For modern discussions of humor as incongruity, see
D. H. Monro, "Humor," in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
vol. 4, ed. Paul Edwards (New York: Macmillan Publishing
The usefulness of humor, as well as its pleasure, Company and the Free Press/London: Collier Macmillan
depends on the same anarchic quality which Publishers, 1967, 1972), pp. 90-93; Michael Clark, "Hu-
makes it risky: it is because the play of humor mour as Incongruity," Philosophy 45 (1970): 20-32; and
Roger Scruton, "Laughter," in his The Aesthetic Under-
loosens our attachment to rigid attitudes and
standing: Essays in the Philosophy of Art and Culture (Man-
ideas that it pleases and helps us. Hutcheson chester: Carcanet New Press, 1983), pp. 153-165. Scruton
sometimes seems too fearful of the dangers of discusses Clark's article in the course of his own.

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Telfer Hutcheson's Reflections Upon Laughter 369

10. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 53. ner parodies of Anna Russell, which are particularly cher-
1 1. Ibid. ished by Wagner devotees.
12. Compare Roger Scruton: "If I were to propose a can- 25. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 54.
didate for the formal object of amusement then the human 26. Ibid., p. 6 1.
(in its widest significance) would be my choice," Scruton, 27. Ibid., p. 59.
"Laughter," p. 162. 28. Ibid., pp. 60-61.
13. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 57. 29. Ibid., pp. 55-56.
14. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 12. 30. Thomas Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of
15. Ibid., p. 4. Man, essay VI, chap. IV, in The Works of Thomas Reid, D.D.,
16. Francis Hutcheson, An Inquiry Concerning Beauty, ed. Sir William Hamilton (Edinburgh: Maclachlan and
Order, Harmony, Design, ed. Peter Kivy (The Hague: Mart- Stewart, 1863), pp. 438-439. I am grateful to Professor
inus Nijhoff, 1973), p. 99. The essays on laughter are in- Donald Todd for bringing Reid's discussion to my attention
cluded in this book as an appendix, with their own intro- and for many other valuable suggestions on this paper.
duction by Kivy. 31. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 59.
17. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 18. 32. Ibid., p. 60.
18. Ibid., p. 57. 33. Ibid., pp. 57-58.
19. The Spectator, vol. II, ed. Donald F. Bond (Oxford: 34. Scruton, "Laughter."
Clarendon Press, 1965), pp. 465-469 (No. 249, Saturday, 35. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 60.
December 15, 171 1). 36. Ibid., p. 59.
20. Hutcheson, Philosophical Writings, p. 58. 37. Ibid., p. 62.
2 1. Ibid. 38. Ibid., p. 59.
22. Ibid. 39. Ibid., p. 61.
23. Ibid., pp. 47-48. 40. This paper is based on one read at a conference on
24. A modern example of how admiration for great works Francis Hutcheson, held at Glasgow University in April
of art can survive humorous attack is provided by the Wag- 1994, to commemorate the tercentenary of Hutcheson's birth.

This content downloaded from 176.88.136.198 on Sat, 02 May 2020 14:35:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like