Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

INVITED COMMENT

Autism and Epistemology IV:


Does Autism Need a Theory of Mind?
Gene S. Fisch*
Department of Epidemiology and Health Promotion, NYU Colleges of Dentistry and Nursing, New York, New York

Manuscript Received: 9 January 2013; Manuscript Accepted: 2 June 2013

In their article, “Does the autistic child have a ‘theory of mind’?,”


Baron-Cohen et al. [1985] proposed a novel paradigm to explain How to Cite this Article:
social impairment in children diagnosed as autistic (AD). Much Fisch GS. 2013. Autism and epistemology
research has been undertaken since their article went to print. IV: Does autism need a theory of mind?
The purpose of this commentary is to gauge whether Theory of
Mind (ToM)—or lack thereof—is a valid model for explaining Am J Med Genet Part A 161A:2464–2480.
abnormal social behavior in children with AD. ToM is defined as
“the ability to impute mental states to oneself and to others” and
“the ability to make inferences about what other people believe to researchers and clinicians who may have only a passing familiarity
be the case.” The source for their model was provided by an with the matter. In this Commentary, I shall provide a brief
article published earlier by Premack and Woodruff, “Does the overview of the historical antecedents to the ToM, the possible
chimpanzee have a theory of mind?” Later research in chimpan- philosophical and epistemological bases for a ToM, a review of
zees did not support a ToM in primates. From the outset, ToM as studies which examine the evidence for and against its claims, with a
a neurocognitive model of autism has had many shortcomings— specific focus of ToM in autism; and, finally, its merits as a useful
methodological, logical, and empirical. Other ToM assumptions, scientific endeavor in autism research.
for example, its universality in all children in all cultures and
socioeconomic conditions, are not supported by data. The age at THE BASIS FOR THEORY OF MIND
which a ToM emerges, or events that presage a ToM, are too often
not corroborated. Recent studies of mirror neurons, their loca- ToM has its roots in Piagetian developmental psychology, although
tion and interconnections in brain, their relationship to social the linguists, Noam Chomsky and Paul Grice, also played signifi-
behavior and language, and the effect of lesions there on speech, cant roles historically regarding the relationship between language
language and social behavior, strongly suggests that a neurobio- and ToM. As with many other theories, Piaget’s theory of
logical as opposed to neurocognitive model of autism is a more child development reflected the spirit of its times. During the
parsimonious explanation for the social and behavioral pheno- early-to-mid 20th century, pediatricians assumed that behavior
types observed in autism. Ó 2013 Wiley Periodicals, Inc. patterns in infants were outcomes of neurodevelopmental process-
es that followed an orderly sequence—maturation [Gesell and
Key words: theory of mind; autism; cognition; mirror neurons; Amatruda, 1941; McGraw, 1943]. Piaget was not trained as a
mental states; validity pediatrician, nor did not view himself as a child psychologist;
rather, as a genetic epistemologist interested primarily in the
conceptual development of scientific knowledge [cf. Vonèche
and Vidal, 1985; p. 137], not children. Nonetheless, his theory of
INTRODUCTION child development—the central themes of which are that children’s
In their seminal article, “Does the autistic child have a ‘theory of cognitive abilities are innate, emerge at specific ages, appear in four
mind’?” Baron-Cohen et al. [1985] proposed a novel paradigm to major, distinct, sequentially invariant stages—is similar to the
explain a central element of social impairment of autism in chil-
dren. Specifically, the Theory of Mind (ToM), the cognitive ability
to impute beliefs to others, is lacking in children with autism. The Conflict of interest: none.

Correspondence to:
authors also claimed that a ToM is independent of intellectual
Gene S. Fisch, Ph.D., Department of Epidemiology and Health
disability (ID) and its absence is specific to autism. Promotion, NYU Colleges of Dentistry and Nursing, 250 Park Ave. S.,
According to a PubMed search, since its publication in 1985, 6th fl., New York, NY 10003.
there have been 486 articles published on ToM with terms related to E-mail: gene.fisch@nyu.edu
autism and ID in the title or abstract. Given the many articles Article first published online in Wiley Online Library
published on the topic, and controversies surrounding its legitima- (wileyonlinelibrary.com): 16 August 2013
cy and utility, I thought it an important area to consider for DOI 10.1002/ajmg.a.36135

Ó 2013 Wiley Periodicals, Inc. 2464


FISCH 2465

notions of children’s growth and development among pediatricians them with pairs of objects needed to work keyboard-related tasks,
of that period. Even so, the mechanics of Piaget’s theory, his only one of which was appropriate. Their two chimps also per-
definitions of terms, and, in particular, the emergence of sequen- formed extremely well, without having been presented with any
tially invariant stages at specific ages, have not been sufficiently well- formal problem to be solved. Based on their findings, these authors
validated empirically. On the other hand, Piaget did not consider doubted that the conclusions drawn by Premack and Woodruff
empirical verification or falsification of his theory a problem, since were justifiable. In another commentary, Beck [1978] argued that
“brute facts are misleading.” Piaget’s concept of theory and its ToM was not a logical requirement for the ability to predict
construction is generally at odds with modern scientific thought, is behavior in others. Similarly, Burge [1978] questioned whether
internally inconsistent, his terminology often nebulous and the experiments as depicted constitute a rationale to believe that
imprecise. Premack and Woodruff actually had a valid theory of mental states,
Like theories of child development, theories of autism epitomize since a simpler explanation could be provided without imputing
their epochs. From Bruno Bettelheim’s “refrigerator parents” of the ToM to the chimp. In a later study of ToM in chimpanzees, Povinelli
psychoanalytic 1950s, to the neurobehavioral dysfunction of the and Eddy [1996] found that chimps would gesture for food from a
1970s and 1980s, to the neurocognitive disorder currently in vogue, human even when the human was blindfolded or had his head
the reputed etiology of autism has changed markedly since Kanner’s covered, thereby indicating that the chimps had no concept of visual
time. In their article, Baron-Cohen et al. [1985] argued that deficits perception in others. In his target article, Heyes [1978] surveyed
in social skills experienced by children with autism are derived from studies of imitation, socialization, self-recognition, and deception,
an inability to conceive of mental states in others. As Baron-Cohen among other “mentalizing” behaviors in which nonhuman pri-
et al. stated, the precedent for this statement, ToM, was expounded mates were examined, and found in each instance that was inter-
in an article published earlier by Premack and Woodruff [1978], preted as a function of ToM, alternate behavioral explanations were
“Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?” ToM is defined as more parsimonious. As a result, the ability of chimpanzees to
“the ability to impute mental states to oneself and to others” and conceive of mental states in others was deemed questionable.
“the ability to make inferences about what other people believe to be Subsequent studies of chimpanzees by Woodruff and Premack
the case” [Baron-Cohen et al., 1985]. Premack and Woodruff involved a different aspect of ToM, the nature and understanding
[1978] stated that ToM is a well-founded ability in humans, and of false beliefs (FBs). Wimmer and Perner [1983], who developed
argue that chimpanzees are also endowed with such ability, one not the notion of “wrong belief,” now referred to as FB, sought to
very different from humans. Their study of chimpanzees was determine at what age children correctly identify the location of an
prompted by Köhler’s [1925] classic work, in which he showed object which has been moved from one location to another. The
that chimpanzees could use simple tools to solve problems. In FB task, and its many variants, became for ToM advocates the
Köhler’s time, the field of psychology had already divided into two crucial test the evidence from which confirmed their theory. As
separate camps: one which followed the principles of contiguity and Gallagher [2004] noted, experiments that employ the FB task
associationism (behaviorism); the other, which continued to in- illustrate both strengths and weaknesses of ToM, as will be made
corporate concepts of mind and consciousness (cognition) in clear below.
animal behavior as articulated by Charles Darwin a half century In their study, Kaminski et al. [2008] developed a novel method
earlier. (A more detailed historical account can be found in Fisch by which to test the concept of FB in eight chimpanzees, 20 3-year-
[2007].) old children, and 20 6-year-old children. Their study design was
Premack and Woodruff [1978] attempted to demonstrate based on the prototype developed by Wimmer and Perner [1983],
animal cognition empirically, not by directly observing the mind in which an object is placed in Box A by Person 1. Person 1 goes away
but, by utilizing ToM, to make predictions of behavior. The single and Person 2 comes forward. Person 2 takes the object from Box A
subject of their study, a 14-year-old female chimpanzee named and places it in Box B. Person 2 goes away and Person 1 returns.
Sarah, was shown videotapes of photographs representing solutions Question for the study participant: In which box does Person 1 look
to each of four problems, after which she was a pair of alternative for the object? According to theory, a participant with a functional
solutions to each of the problems and encouraged to select one or ToM would say Person 1 will look in Box A, a FB. Someone less than
the other. According to Premack and Woodruff, if a ToM exists in 4 years of age, or with a dysfunctional ToM, would say Box B. It
chimpanzees, she would choose the one which provided the correct should be remarked, as did Gallagher [2004], that it is not obvious
solution to each problem. She chose correctly on all occasions. that an observation by a third person—in this instance, the partici-
Premack and Woodruff interpreted their findings, arguing at length pant in the study—best depicts the participant’s ability to under-
against any form of associationism (read behaviorism) that might stand another individual without any form of interaction with that
have produced the outcome, and in favor of ToM (read cognition). other individual.
The study was published in The Brain and Behavioral Sciences The Kaminski et al. [2008] study design was a simpler variant of
(TBBS), which invited commentaries to their target article. One the FB task. Two subjects would face each other from behind a glass
of the commentaries, by Savage-Rumbaugh et al. [1978], observed partition and on opposite sides of a table. Subjects were trained to
that, among their concerns, there was no evidence other than take turns selecting buckets from the table and removing its
anecdotal that Sarah actually looked at the videotapes, perceived contents. One subject must select one of three buckets either before
the choice as a solution, or understood the features of the problems or after the other subject has made a selection. There were rewards in
and their respective solutions. To resolve these issues, Savage- some buckets, but the buckets were opaque, so that neither subject
Rumbaugh et al. tested two of their own chimpanzees, presenting could know in advance what the other subject had chosen. In the FB
2466 AMERICAN JOURNAL OF MEDICAL GENETICS PART A

condition, the first subject watches the experimenter appear to place manifestation of what [Premack and Woodruff] called theory of
a reward in one bucket, but actually places it in another. The first mind.” [Leslie, 1987, p. 415]
subject then must “predict” the second subject’s selection. Kamin- Mental states such as pretense have three major properties. First,
ski et al. [2008] found that 6-year-old children were able to mental propositions need not be logically true (“My sister thinks I am
demonstrate correctly FB attribution, but chimpanzees were not. Australian”). Second, mental propositions need not refer to the
In another ToM test 30 years earlier, Premack and Woodruff [1979] actual existence of the referent (“This is a picture of my unicorn”).
attempted to demonstrate FB in chimpanzees by teaching their Third, pretend representations are not accurate representations of
animals to deceive a conspecific. Premack and Woodruff were only the natural environment but representations of representations, that
partly successful, teaching deceptive pointing to two of four chimps, is,second-orderrepresentations,or meta-representations[Pylyshyn,
and only after 5 months of intensive training. In a recent review of 1978]. To illustrate meta-representation using Leslie’s [Leslie, 1987]
the literature, Call and Tomasello [2008] reported that, while example: If a child pretends that a banana is a telephone, the child
chimpanzees may understand goals and intentions of others, there needs to be able to demonstrate how he/she is representing how the
is no experimental evidence to indicate that chimps have any real banana is used to represent the non-existent telephone. Accord-
conception of FB. ing to Leslie, pretend play in children is necessarily constructed from
In his commentary, Burghardt [1978] quoted the early 20th these properties, and their existence is a precursor of the child’s
century animal experimentalist, Margaret Washburn, as saying: typical or “folk” ToM. This ability initially allows the child to impute
“Knowledge regarding the animal mind, like the knowledge of mental states in oneself, then later in others, and ultimately to
human minds other than our own, must come by way of inference anticipate future behavior in others. This constitutes what Leslie
from behavior. Two fundamental questions then confront the com- [1987] and Premack and Woodruff [1978] refer to as a ToM.
parative psychologist. First, by what method shall he [sic] find out How does this relate to autism? Autistic disorder (AD) and
howtheanimal behaves?Second, howshallhe interpretthe conscious related pervasive developmental disabilities (PDD) are defined
aspect of that behavior?” In a similar vein, Penn and Povinelli [2007] broadly by DSM-IV-TR [American Psychiatric Association,
suggested that, instead of arguing over equivocal experimental 2000] as neurodevelopmental disorders involving impaired func-
findings, researchers should focus on the definition of and evidence tion in three domains: communication, socialization, and restricted
for ToM. These arguments are analogous to those posed to the interests or stereotyped behavior. The absence of pretend or
inferences drawn by Piaget in his theory of stages in child symbolic play has been noted frequently among children with
development. autism, but not among children whose only dysfunction may be
To summarize: The original article by Baron-Cohen et al. [1985] ID. In their study, Baron-Cohen et al. [1985] employed the previ-
on ToM as an explanation of social impairment in autistic children ously described Wimmer and Perner [1983] FB task to determine if
attributes their model to an earlier precedent set by Premack and children diagnosed as AD with ID exhibited ToM deficits compared
Woodruff [1978], the latter of whom claimed to ascertain ToM in to same-aged children with Down syndrome (DS) and ID (Baron-
chimpanzees. Results and interpretation of the findings from Cohen [1995] would later state that ToM was the sine qua non of
Premack and Woodruff, as well as subsequent research on ToM standard FB tasks.). Mean IQ of the children with autism was
in monkeys, demonstrate a lack of convincing evidence for same, significantly higher than those with DS (82 vs. 64). As for perfor-
casting doubt thereby as to whether inferences based on a ToM as mance on the FB task, only 4/20 (20%) of children with AD passed
articulated by Premack and Woodruff have internal validity vis-à- the test, whereas 12/14 (86%) children with DS did. The authors
vis nonhuman primates. Lack of internal validity suggests that there thus concluded that ToM deficits are independent of ID and specific
may well be problems establishing external validity for humans with to AD.
autism, as we shall see shortly.
EARLY REBUTTAL AND REJOINDER
FOUNDATIONS OF A THEORY OF MIND IN AUTISM Challenges to the results obtained by Baron-Cohen et al. [1985] first
appeared in an article by de Gelder [1987]. de Gelder focused on
The cognitive-theoretical foundations of ToM as related to autism three aspects of the study: the methodology itself; the verbal
are rooted in Leslie [1987]. According to Leslie [1987], the ability to interaction between experimenters and participants; and, the attri-
develop an internal representation, to “mentalize,” is inherent in bution of FB. First, knowing that children with AD do not pretend
humans and can be identified early in infancy in the form of play, then embedding the FB task in a pretend play protocol, finally
pretense or pretend play. Pretend play develops from about age testing for correctness in the FB task, is a flawed experimental
2 years and becomes increasingly elaborate as children become design. The logic of the argument, as might be posited by Leslie
older, using fewer real objects as symbols, and in story sequences [1987], would proceed as follows:
that become progressively more complex. Pretend play materializes
from a “decoupling” from the real world to an imaginary (repre-  If the child exhibits pretend play, then the child has a ToM.
sentational) one, “acting as if” something is true when in fact it is  The child does not pretend play.
not [Leslie, 1987]. Moreover, the pretender knows the difference.  Therefore, the child does not have a ToM.
For Leslie, the most important aspect is not so much the develop-
ment of ToM, but the “ability to characterize and manipulate [the This is a logically and scientifically invalid proposition (denying
mind’s] attitudes to information. In short, pretense is an early the antecedent). Second, the FB task is part of a verbal exchange
FISCH 2467

between experimenter and participant in which children with AD The MP distinction consisted of a child’s comprehension of mental
already have a linguistic disadvantage pragmatically, and may not phenomena, for example, dreams, and physical phenomena, for
completely understand the task expected of them, despite their example, food. He found only 4/13 (24%) children with AD passed
vocabulary. Third, and somewhat related to the first: If children the MP test, while a significantly higher proportion, 11/16 (69%), of
with AD did not have a ToM, they could not suitably partake in the children with ID passed the same test. Baron-Cohen [1989b] also
conversation and the experiment. Since children with AD could administered a third variant of the FB task: the Appearance-Reality
participate in answering some questions correctly, they must (AR) paradigm. An example of an AR task might be as follows: A
therefore have a ToM. child is given an object, such as a sponge, but made to look like
In their reply, Leslie and Frith [1987] contended that they could something else, such as a candy bar. The child is then asked: what is it
find only three problems with de Gelder’s argument. First, de Gelder (appearance vs. reality)? In both of Baron-Cohen’s studies, 20–35%
did not properly understand meta-representation in ToM. On the of children with AD passed any of these three ToM tests, while 16–
contrary, Boucher [1989] observed that the concept of meta- 30% of children with ID only fail them.
representation had not been completely well-formulated at the In contrast to Baron-Cohen’s results, other researchers employ-
time. As Leekam and Perner [1991] pointed out, Leslie’s [1987] ing similar FB tasks found much higher success rates among
interpretation of meta-representation was not the same as Pyly- children with AD, and lower rates of success among children
shyn’s [1978]. Second, Leslie and Frith [1987] noted that the verbal with ID only. In their study, Prior et al. [1990] found 60% of his
abilities of children with AD were higher than those with DS, so participants with AD passed the FB task. Grant et al. [2001] assessed
language should not be an issue. On the other hand, as Boucher 22 children with AD, ages 7–18 years, with four standard FB tasks,
[1989] also indicated, language skills evaluated by Baron-Cohen and found 12/22 [56%] were able to complete all tests successfully.
et al. [1985] were assessed using the British Picture Vocabulary Dahlgren and Trillingsgaard [1996] examined 20 high functioning
Scale, a vocabulary comprehension test; whereas, ToM experiments children with AD, 20 with Asperger syndrome—both groups of
assume a grammatical proficiency unrelated to vocabulary com- which had mean IQ scores in the normal range—and 20 TD
prehension that is likely beyond the ability of children with AD. children, ages 6–151/2 years, and tested them with first-order and
Finally, Leslie and Frith [1987] argue there was no evidence in the second-order FB tasks. Nearly all children with AD and Asperger
literature to suggest that a lack of ToM would prohibit participation passed the first order FB task, and 60% of each of these two groups
in any conversation. This is a peculiar response given that one could passed the second-order FB task. Conversely, Zelazo et al. [1996]
argue analogously that a person with no legs could enter a foot race examined 12 adolescents and adults with DS, 16–31 years, who were
since no one without legs had been prohibited from participating in severely ID, and found that they had marked difficulty performing
such a race before. Nevertheless, Baron-Cohen [1988] suggested the FB and AR tasks. In their meta-analysis of 24 separate studies
that de Gelder’s conjecture, which is based on a model of conver- that administered a variety of ToM tasks to TD children, children
sation developed by Grice [1975], should be examined. In addition, with AD, or children with ID, Yirmiya et al. [1998] reported that
he acknowledged that de Gelder’s claim may be correct. there were studies in which children with AD or ID only had
Boucher [1989] also raised separate concerns about the Baron- impaired ToM abilities. They also noted that, when known, the
Cohen et al. [1985] study, also at the epistemological level, and disorder’s etiology was a significant moderating factor. Yirmiya
having to do with the proper definition of meta-representation and et al. [1998] thus concluded that ToM impairment severity, rather
the scope (broad or narrow) of ToM. If, as Leslie [1987] stated, the than impairment in and of itself, was associated with AD. In
absence of pretend play (meta-representation) is the behavioral acknowledging these anomalies earlier on, Baron-Cohen [1989b]
marker for an impaired ToM, then, although it is not clear why, retreated from his original assertions and proposed that ToM
functional (appropriate) play should be not be impaired in children deficits in children with AD may not be completely obliterated,
with AD compared to children with ID only. However, Lewis and but may result from a more specific severe developmental delay
Boucher [1988] found that, in a free play situation, functional play unrelated to general developmental delay.
was as impaired as pretend play in children with AD, and occurred To examine the hypothesis of specific developmental delay,
at significantly lower levels than among control subjects. Interest- Baron-Cohen [1989c] conducted a follow-up study in which
ingly, they also found that, in an elicited play situation, children children with AD who passed his first FB test were then adminis-
with AD could, in fact, generate pretend play [Boucher and Lewis, tered another, more complicated (“second-order”) test of FB.
1989]. Consequently, Boucher [1989] suggested that meta-repre- Second-order FB tests are typically of the form, “Jane believes
sentation in autism is probably a secondary manifestation of that John believes that …” None of these children passed, from
impairment that occurs initially at the biological level, and therefore which Baron-Cohen [1989c] concluded that AD may be a case of
is not the primary deficit in autism. If, on the other hand, an specific developmental delay. This concession is markedly different
impaired ToM is to be considered the primary deficit in autism, from the original supposition, that children with AD lack a ToM.
then it needs to explain how other aspects of the disorder, for Burack [1992] presented an alternate interpretation of the results
example, repetitive behaviors, are a function of impaired meta- obtained by Baron-Cohen. He suggested that the behaviors ob-
representation. served by Baron-Cohen [1989c] could have been developmentally
Baron-Cohen [1989a] took issue with Boucher [1989], suggest- deviant, not delayed, to which Baron-Cohen [1992] replied that
ing alternate interpretations of her results, and adding that his more there was evidence for both delay and deviance. He referred to the
recent findings show children with AD failed three types of FB tasks, theory promulgated by Fodor [1983], that there is an innate
including the Mental-Physical (MP) test [Baron-Cohen, 1989b]. “module” for development, comparable to the innate module
2468 AMERICAN JOURNAL OF MEDICAL GENETICS PART A

posited by Leslie [1987]. Baron-Cohen [1992] proposed a modified from each group who passed diminished. The most difficult
ToM in which the developmental module could have two (second-order) FB task was passed by only 1/15 (7%) from the
“switches”: one which would, if turned off, elicit developmental low ability group, while 8/15 (53%) passed from the high ability
delay; the other, which if turned off, would produce deviant group. Contrary to Baron-Cohen [1989c], these researchers con-
behavior. Obviously, these additions make the innate module cluded that acquiring ToM and its related skills follows a general
ToM model more complex than originally conceived. Then again, developmental sequence in children with AD as it does with TD
the innate module ToM is but one of three types of ToM theories, to children. Moreover, since verbal ability affects performance on FB
which I will return later. tasks, linguistic proficiency is a necessary prerequisite to satisfactory
An alternate approach to how FB tasks could be successfully performance on ToM tasks. Indeed, Gernsbacher and Frymiare
completed was pursued by Sharrock and Coulter [2004]. They [2005] reported findings that also show successful performance on
thought that the ability to respond correctly to FB tasks may be a ToM tasks are a function of linguistic ability. They noted further
function primarily of acquired language. To test this hypothesis in that children with AD often fail ToM tasks because of a qualitative
children with AD, Perner et al. [1989] examined 10 children with impairment in communication, one of the three criteria deemed
AD and 12 MA-matched children with speech-language im- essential for a diagnosis of AD. In effect, failure on ToM tasks among
pairment (SLI), and found that children with SLI performed children with AD begs the question.
significantly better on the FB task than children with AD. Perner Linguistic ability of another sort has also been shown to affect
et al. concluded that language impairment and, therefore, language facility in completing FB tasks successfully—deafness. Peterson and
ability was unrelated to ToM. A decade later, Astington and Jenkins Siegal [1999] examined three groups of deaf children (severely and
[1999] examined 59 TD children, mean age 3 years, at three profoundly native deaf signers, oral deaf who had grown up with
different time points, to determine if language competence pre- spoken language, and severely and profoundly deaf signers from
dicted ToM development; or, whether ToM development predicted hearing homes) along with TD children and children with AD.
language competence. Their results show that language proficiency Verbal abilities and ages of the three groups of deaf children were
predicted ToM development, not the other way round. not significantly different. Children were tested using three stan-
Although Perner et al. [1989] matched children according to dard FB tasks. These researchers found that native signers per-
MA, mean chronological age (CA) in the SLI group was almost 9 formed no worse than TD children, but signing deaf children and
years, while mean CA among children with AD was significantly children with autism performed significantly worse. Interestingly,
older—15 years. Given the “Verbal MA” presented in their Table 2, children with autism passed 50–68% of the three FB tasks. Peterson
children with AD likely tested in the mild-to-moderate ID range; and Siegal [1999] suggested that there may be a neurobiological
whereas, children with SLI likely tested significantly higher, in the basis as well as a cultural deficit that could account for the failures in
borderline-to-low normal range. Despite this marked difference in FB tasks among deaf children.
intellectual levels, Perner et al. [1989] concluded that poor perfor- To summarize: As related to autism, ToM has come under attack
mance was not a function of general ID. from several fronts. First, as a methodology which embeds pretend
Miller [2001] noted that children with SLI lag in their ability to play in an FB task, it begs the question since children with AD do not
perform on FB tasks compared to same-aged typically developing pretend play spontaneously. Second, the linguistic sophistication
(TD) children. Considering the mean CA of children in the SLI needed to provide a correct response to the FB task is beyond the
group in Perner et al. [1989] was 9 years, they probably were old pragmatic language skills of most children with AD. Third, without a
enough to have acquired sufficient language skills to perform as well ToM, how could such a child possibly participate in a ToM experi-
as younger, TD children. To examine the effect of CA on SLI, Miller ment, a problem related to the first point. Baron-Cohen, Leslie, and
[2001] examined three younger age cohorts diagnosed with SLI, Frith countered these concerns, first by suggesting that their detrac-
whose ages ranged from 41/2 to 7 years, and compared them to TD tors did not understand the concept of meta-representation suffi-
children with limited language comprehension, and to TD children ciently well, although meta-representation was not only not a
without limited language skills. Miller [2001] found that children particularly well-formulated construct at the time, but there existed
from both the SLI group and the limited language group had different definitions of same. Second, despite its reputation as the
difficulty in passing the FB tests administered to them, but TD “litmus test” for a ToM, the FB experiment contains serious logical
children performed quite well and significantly better than either of and design flaws. Baron-Cohen, Leslie, and Frith also tried to show
the two language-impaired groups. Earlier, Sparrevohn and Howie that linguistic ability was unrelated to ToM, but researchers have
[1995] examined FB in children whose CA was comparable to those demonstrated otherwise, noting a high proportion of failures on
recruited for the Perner et al. [1989] study. Sparrevohn and Howie ToM-related tasks among speech-language impaired and deaf chil-
[1995] administered five FB tests of increasing difficulty, the first of dren. The matter of whether one needed a ToM to participate in a
which examined “inferred belief.” Inferred belief is a FB-like task ToM experiment remained unresolved, although this too seems to
that presages FB developmentally in TD children. The fifth task was beg the question.
the most complex verbally, a “second-order” FB test (“Jane believes
that John believes that …”). The tests were administered to two
groups of children with AD: one with low verbal ability, the second
BASIC ASSUMPTIONS FOR THEORY OF MIND
with high verbal skills. Sparrevohn and Howie [1995] found that As stated earlier, the argument for applying ToM—or lack thereof
100% of participants in each group passed the inferred FB task —to autism is based on the thesis presented by Leslie [1987], in
correctly; but, as tasks grew increasingly complex, the numbers which he asserted the following: (1) ToM is innate; (2) it is presaged
FISCH 2469

by pretend play which appears at age 18–24 months; and (3) that the tasks compared to false pretense tasks. Previously, Jarrold et al.
“decoupling” of mental representations from real world phenom- [1994] had examined pretend play in three groups: children with
ena—forming meta-representations (the banana representing the AD; children with learning disabilities; or TD children. These
absent telephone)—is the mechanism by which ToM emerges. researchers found no significant differences among the three groups
Hobson [1990] took issue with each of Leslie’s premises. First, regarding their success on the pretend play tasks presented, nor did
infants’ understanding of other people’s minds comes about from they find impairment in the ability to comprehend pretense by
their reciprocal social relations with other humans, that is, it is not children with AD. Bloom and German [2000] also cite several
innate. Second, this knowledge appears much earlier in the infant’s studies in which children younger than 2 years are able to initiate
development—9 months as opposed to 18 months. As these pretend play and understand pretense in others.
phenomena relate to autism, Leslie postulated that children with Social development has also been shown to materialize prior to
AD inherently lack a ToM; whereas, Hobson [1990] would argue the age at which pretending appears, as Hobson [1990] noted. In his
that, in Kanner’s original description [Kanner, 1943], they lack the review of social behavior in children with autism, Volkmar [2011]
inborn biological ability to form reciprocal affective relationships reported that newborns are more attentive to face-like movements
with others. Klin et al. [1992] tested these two hypotheses by than inanimate objects. And, at 4–5 months of age, infants can
examining 58 children, 29 of whom were diagnosed with AD detect changes in gaze direction by others. Carpenter et al. [1998]
and 29 were diagnosed with ID only. Mean age in both groups examined social cognition via shared (joint) attention and gaze-
was about 4 years. Klin et al. found that social deficits in AD following tasks in 24 infants, 9–15 months old, and found the
included adaptive behaviors that were fundamental and emerged number of infants passing attention-following, point-following,
early in infancy, and are usually present in children at an age prior to and gaze-following tests increased from age 9 months to age 15
when putative meta-representational abilities appear, as Hobson months. Language learning and development, which begins
[1990] noted. Klin et al. concluded that their findings were consis- with infants’ prelinguistic babbling and vocalizations, can be
tent with Kanner’s conjecture, not Leslie’s. modified by social feedback from their caregivers [Goldstein and
In their reply to Hobson [1990], Leslie and Frith [1990] quoted Schwade, 2008]. On the other hand, children with AD have
him as saying “Leslie’s nondevelopmental, nonsocial, and restric- difficulties recognizing faces and identifying facial expressions,
tively cognitive account (p. 114) … (a)ll three of these epithets are and have difficulty using gaze in activities that involve joint atten-
inappropriate” [Leslie and Frith, 1990, p. 122]. In fact, no such tion. Osterling and Dawson [1994] examined videotapes of
remark was made by Hobson on p.114. In comparing Kanner’s view 22 infants less than 1 year, 11 who were later diagnosed with
of autism to Leslie’s ToM, what Hobson did say was that Kanner’s autism, and 11 TD children. Osterling and Dawson found infants
“account seems to offer a more coherent view of impairments in subsequently diagnosed with AD displayed significantly fewer
symbolic play and social understanding among autistic … children social and joint attention behaviors and significantly more autistic
than does Leslie’s [1987] nondevelopmental, essentially nonsocial symptoms.
explanation” [Hobson, 1990; p. 119]. Leslie and Frith [1990] Another cornerstone of Leslie’s [1987] thesis is that the mecha-
counter Hobson’s “nondevelopmental” remark by stating that nism that permits a ToM to emerge is contained in an innate
all theories of development are, at their core, concerned with innate module. With age, the child reaches a distinct, inborn develop-
features which unfold as the child ages. This is certainly true of mental stage at which point he/she is able to marshal a “folk
Piaget’s theory, but not necessarily that of Albert Bandura, or psychology” to create a ToM. By folk psychology is meant a
Dollard and Miller, or Vygotsky for that matter, for whom the commonsense psychology that typically embraces concepts such
interbehavioral, cultural, social, and linguistic factors affecting as “belief,” “desire,” “fear,” “hope,” and “intent.” On the other
child development were of greater concern. Leslie and Frith hand, there are those like Perner [1991] who argue that, at a certain
[1990] argued further that ToM could hardly be considered non- age, children begin to cultivate theories about themselves and
social, since pretending is a special case of understanding pretense others, in order to better understand themselves and others. This
in others. Sadly, Leslie and Frith [1990] never demonstrate how theory development in children parallels theory development in
pretend play relates to social understanding, nor do they provide science and is analogous to the genetic epistemology posited by Jean
empirical evidence to support their conjecture about understand- Piaget [Lillard, 1998b]. The difference in the set of assumptions
ing pretense in others. made by Leslie compared to those by Perner indicates that there is
Other researchers who did examine pretense in children could more than one ToM, which we shall now consider.
not establish those presumed deficits among children with AD. In his review of the field, Flavell [1999] noted that three major
Jarrold et al. [2010] examined true and false pretense in 34 children ToMs have been proposed. One model is that proposed by Leslie, in
with AD, ages 10–17 years, compared to 37 TD children, 3–5 years. which an innate mechanism or module exists in brain, and that a
True and false pretense tasks are similar to the Wimmer and Perner ToM develops in concert with neurological maturation. The mod-
[1983] FB tasks, but in Jarrold et al. [2010], involved the use of red or ule contains three mechanisms: a Theory of Body mechanism
green paint as the object of belief (cf. Jarrold et al. [2010], for a more (ToBM) and two Theory of Mind mechanisms (ToMM1 and
complete description). Among children with AD, 21/34 (62%) ToMM2). The ToBM develops in the first year of life and allows
passed the FB tasks presented, while 17/37 (46%) of TD children the neonate to explore the environment. ToMM1 comes into being
passed. Those who passed had significantly higher verbal MA, in at the end of the first year, allowing the infant to relate to other
both the AD and TD groups, compared to those who failed. Both people and things. ToMM2 develops in year 2, and allows the
TD and AD groups performed significantly better on true pretense toddler to draw inferences about other individuals, what Flavell
2470 AMERICAN JOURNAL OF MEDICAL GENETICS PART A

[1999] referred to as propositional attitudes, for example, pretend- test the second of these hypotheses, Wahi and Johri [1994] assessed
ing, believing, desiring, imagining. 42 Indian children, ages 3–8 years, from two distinctly different
The second model, put forth by Perner [1991], is referred to as socioeconomic strata, using a FB task to distinguish between real
“Theory–Theory.” That is, our knowledge of other’s minds comes and mental items (toys and concrete items vs. stories). As expected,
about from how we “frame” our daily experience and interactions age made a significant difference in the percent correct responses
into a ToM. Knowledge of other’s minds consists of three essential made. However, they also found that socioeconomic factors made
elements: First, it must be specific to a particular domain of for significant differences in percent correct. Shahaeian et al. [2011]
information and no other; second, the notion of cause and effect recruited 135 Australian and Iranian children ages 3–6 years and
is specific to the domain in question; and third, this knowledge is examined their performances on a variety of ToM tasks. These
part of a network of related concepts and beliefs. A third major researchers found that, on average, both nationalities passed the
ToM, Simulation Theory, assumes that an influential role is played same number of tasks, but for three types of tasks—FB, Diverse
by experience. By way of repetition, children simulate what they Beliefs, Knowledge Access—the two groups differed significantly
would think if they were in someone else’s place. However, it has on percent correct. Tardif et al. [2004] tested Cantonese- and
been Leslie’s ToM module and Perner’s Theory–Theory that have Mandarin-speaking Chinese children, ages 3–5 years, using three
monopolized studies of ToM in autism, and it is these that will be FB tasks: change in location (the Sally–Anne paradigm), the
examined in greater detail. deceptive object task (A pen that looks like a lollipop: what is it
According to Astington and Dack [2008], Leslie’s innate modu- really?); and an unexpected contents task (a candy box that contains
larity ToM has two major features: First, it is universal among all pencils instead). Results again show an expected age effect: Older
humans; and second, it is not subject to modification based on children from both language groups perform better than younger
interactions with the environment. Alterations in the ToM results ones. However, Tardif et al. [2004] also noted that Cantonese
from the individual’s maturation, not experience. children performed significantly better on the deceptive object
The concept of an innate module in brain implies there is some task than did same-aged English-speaking children reported by
localization of function or neural network the specific purpose of Gopnik and Astington [1988]. Kobayashi et al. [2007] approached
which is to produce a ToM. However, Stone and Gerrans [2006] the cultural dissimilarity question from a different perspective.
note that, although certain neural substrates may be necessary to These researchers used fMRI to examine neural correlates in
produce behavior, it does not therefore imply that that substrate is 12 monolingual American and 12 bilingual Japanese children,
specific to a ToM. (Impaired performance on FB tasks will be ages 8–11 years, on both ToM and non-ToM tasks, and found
revisited in a later section.) For example, Brüne and Brüne-Cohrs significant differences in brain function between groups for both
[2006] cite several studies in which patients with brain lesions not sets of tasks. Kobayashi et al. [2007] concluded there were both
present in early development demonstrated impaired perform- language- and culture-dependent neural bases for ToM develop-
ances on FB tasks as adults. However, these lesions were not ment. Guajardo and Watson [2002] manipulated children’s expo-
localized to any one area in brain but were found in many different sure to social communication with story-telling and discussion of
regions—left-hemisphere, frontal cortex, left amygdala, and pre- episodes involving mental concepts, and found that children in the
frontal cortex. Stone and Gerrans [2006] also found that individuals story-telling group performed better on post-test FB and AR ToM
with damaged orbitofrontal cortices make impaired responses to tasks than non-trained controls.
ToM tasks. Stone and Gerrans proposed two model systems: One As for ToM’s universality: In her review of ethnopsychologies,
which processes sensory information via domain-specific input Lillard [1997, 1998a] noted that the concept of mind among
systems—visual, auditory, etc.—which includes a ToM module Europeans and Americans is likely culture specific, and that there
to draw inferences about the physical world (their Fig. 1); and a are other cultures which do not identify mind with brain that is
second model identical to the first, except that it does not inherent in Cartesian dualism. Moreover, some cultures do not
include the ToM module (their Fig. 2). In discussing both models, even have a specific lexicon for mind, and its members consistently
Stone and Gerrans [2006] indicate how a ToM module is not fail ToM tasks [cf. Garfield et al., 2001]. So, despite assumptions to
needed to draw inferences about the physical world or other the contrary, cultural differences are a significant factor in deter-
individuals. Specifically, they note that children with AD have mining a successful outcome on ToM tasks, and the concept of
deficits in these lower-level, domain-specific, input systems, for mind is not universal across cultures.
example, face recognition, gaze direction, and joint attention, as According to the other major ToM variant, Theory–Theory (T-
reported previously by Volkmar [2011]. Therefore, an input– T), children use their intellectual abilities to develop a “folk
output system devoid of a ToM module more parsimoniously psychology” or commonsense theory of the mental states of others
explains the inability of children with AD to draw inferences about in a manner similar to what scientists do when testing hypotheses
their environment in general and the behavior of other individuals from data collected from an experiment [Perner, 1991]. This ability
in particular. may either be innate or acquired by early experience, emerging at
To return to the two other basic features in Leslie’s [1987] about age 4 years; and children are constantly upgrading and
modular ToM: Specifically, that it is universal in every child; and revising their ToMs with respect to others. Finally, as the child
that changes in ToM results from maturation and not experience. grows, he/she also explores and interacts with the environment
That is to say, all cultures should have some common form of ToM; incorporating this information and revising its ToM. These three
and sociological and cultural differences should not significantly components—an innate conception of ToM, the innate ability to
affect the development of a ToM among different nationalities. To modify this conception, and the ability to incorporate information
FISCH 2471

from the environment to further modify the ToM—are essential to evidence of “fragmentary FB understanding.” Gopnik’s comments
T-T. notwithstanding, other researchers found evidence that children
The central thesis of T-T consists of the ability of one child’s mind younger than age 4 years pass FB tasks. In their review, Baillargeon
to form a theory to understand representations of others’ minds, et al. [2010] noted various studies in which the ability to attribute FB
that is, to “mentalize.” Those who cannot form a theory of correctly is present at an earlier age. Onishi and Baillargeon [2005]
representations cannot understand the thoughts, beliefs, desires, tested toddlers, age 15 months, using a “violation-of-expectations”
or intentions of others. Also as noted above, the attainment of a protocol, and found infants’ behavior consonant with what one
ToM does not develop until age 4 years [cf. Bloom and German, would expect from an older child’s response to a FB task. In a similar
2000; Gallagher, 2004], at which time it empowers children in their experiment, Surian et al. [2007] tested 13-month-old infants, and
ability to deceive others by keeping secrets, lying and by other forms obtained comparable results. And, curiously, even Gopnik found
of deception. However, many studies have shown that children are that 18-month olds use emotional cues to infer desires on the part of
capable of deception prior to age of 4 years [Chandler et al., 1989; others, despite the absence of behavioral cues [Repacholi and
Hala et al., 1991; Reddy and Morris, 2004; Melis et al., 2010]. Gopnik, 1997]. Bloom and German [2000] observe quite acutely
The assumption that ToM does not develop until age 4 years has that, when examining children using the FB task, TD 3-year olds are
been a point of contention among different factions of T-T adher- inherently different from older children with autism. TD 3-year
ents. In an attempt to resolve the issue, Chandler et al. [1989] olds have substantially greater communication and socialization
proposed to examine the Wimmer and Perner [1983] FB prototype skills than do older children with autism. In accord with that
by employing a novel paradigm of “hide-and-seek” which allowed remark, Abbeduto et al. [2004] found that individuals with ID
participants to make use of five levels of deceptive strategies: and limited language skills perform less well on FB tasks than do
withholding evidence (the simplest level), destroying evidence, matched TD controls. Therefore, the inability to perform success-
lying, making false trails, destroying evidence to produce false trails fully on a ToM task calls into question what it is that the standard FB
(the most complex). They recruited 56 children, ages 2–5 years. task is actually assessing.
Although there were modest age differences in outcomes across Another important methodological consideration is the test–
tasks, the differences were not statistically significant. Interestingly, retest reliability of ToM tasks. Mayes et al. [1996] presented video-
children from all age groups made greater use of the more complex tapes demonstrating three different FB tasks to children ages 4–5
deceptions than the simpler ones. From these results, Chandler et al. years, testing for correctness. Three weeks later, the children were
[1989] concluded that children as young as 21/2 years were capable of assessed again on all three FB tasks. The kappa coefficient was used
utilizing any number of deceptive techniques in order to instill FBs in to assess agreement from Time 1 to Time 2. The kappa statistic
others. In their follow-up study, Hala et al. [1991] also employed adjusts for the possibility of chance agreement. For one Sally–Anne
protocols involving deceptive hiding strategies by 33 children, ages task, kappa coefficients were moderately high. For the second Sally–
3–41/2 years, and found no significant difference in correct responses Anne task, however, kappa coefficients ranged from 0.25 to 0.47.
by age for tasks that involved hide-and-seek or FB predictions. What Mayes et al. [1996] concluded that performance on FB tasks may
was found associated with age was the increased frequency and not be stable in children 4–5 years old; and consequently, that the FB
intricacy of the lies [Reddy & Morris, 2004]. protocol employed may not be a reliable indicator of children’s
According to Reddy and Morris [2004], the main problem with T- ToM abilities. In their study of reliability, Charman and Campbell
T is its central canon; that the innate conception of mind begins and is [1997] tested 36 children with learning disabilities, 71/2 to 191/2 years
maintained at the level of thought, without acknowledging the effects of age, on three FB tasks and two belief-desire tasks administered on
of the child’s constant interaction with the environment and with two different occasions, 3 weeks apart. Kappa coefficients for the FB
other individuals. T-T supporters challenge any such behavioral tasks ranged from 0.26 to 0.49, similar to the results obtained by
account, even though the latter may be the more parsimonious Mayes et al. [1996]. For the belief-desire tasks, kappa ranged from
explanation for the child’s responses. By rejecting empirical data that 0.48 to 0.78. Although there are no precise kappa values for what is
areatvariancewith T-T beliefs,theorists againdenytheapplication of considered acceptable agreement, Shrout [1998] suggested that
modern scientific thought to hypothesis-testing. kappa < 0.80 should not be considered satisfactory. Consequently,
At its core, experiments are used to demonstrate ToM, and the the reliability of FB tasks as the “litmus test” for ToM should not be
several types of tasks that have been developed are administered to thought of as convincing.
affirm or refute ToM capability in the participants assessed. The Another facet of mentalizing reflects empathy, and researchers
classic experiment, the Sally–Anne FB designed by Wimmer and have developed ToM tasks that examine empathic ability (EA), the
Perner [1983], has been described previously. Also noted briefly capacity to put oneself in another’s shoes. Dyck et al. [2001]
were the AR task, the deception task, and the object removal task. examined 174 children, ages 9–16 years, from one of five groups:
Central to any experiment must be the validity and reliability of the AD; Asperger syndrome; ADHD; mild ID; and TD children, testing
tasks employed to test a ToM hypothesis and infer the conjecture them for EA, among other assessments. These researchers found
from the results obtained. We have already noted that language used that children with AD showed the greatest deficits in EA, but that
to tell the Sally–Anne story may be too difficult for children with children with ID also performed similarly poorly. The correlation
limited linguistic skills to pass such a test with any regularity. Bloom between IQ and EA was r ¼ 0.84, as was the correlation between IQ
and German [2000] cite several studies in which modified, simpler and a ToM metric (r ¼ 0.77). In a related and complementary
and pragmatically neutral FB tasks are passed by 3-year olds, study, Williams et al. [2012] examined whether children diagnosed
although Gopnik [1993], a supporter of T-T, believes that this is with AD could be trained to develop skills to identify emotions.
2472 AMERICAN JOURNAL OF MEDICAL GENETICS PART A

These researchers recruited 55 children, ages 4–7 years, and assigned FB and AR tasks, results similar to those obtained initially by Baron-
them to an intervention or control group. The intervention con- Cohen et al. [1985] for children with DS. Grant et al. [2007]
sisted of the presentation of an animated children’s series—Trans- recruited 3 groups of CA- and MA-matched adolescent males: 2
porters—designed to develop emotional recognition in children in groups of males with the FMR1 mutation, 15 with few autistic
this age group with AD. Tests of identification and matching of four features and 15 with sufficiently many to be in the range for a
emotions—happiness, sadness, anger, and fear—were adminis- diagnosis of autism according to the SCQ, and 15 males with ID
tered to both groups. Results showed small to moderate increases only etiology unknown. Grant et al. [2007] found that a significantly
in the intervention group in identifying all four emotions. Control greater number of correct responses were produced by the ID only
participants showed smaller increases for two emotions, and de- group compared to either FMR1 group on one ToM task (location
creased ability in two others. Williams et al. [2012] concluded that change), but no significant differences between the number correct
Transporters could improve recognition of emotions. However, in the “non-autistic” FMR1 group (6/15) and the ID group (9/15)
this improvement did not generalize to improved ToM skills that on another ToM task (deceptive box). Porter et al. [2008] examined
were also assessed at the time. 31 individuals with Williams–Beuren syndrome (WBS), ages 5–44
Moral understanding is another aspect of development related to years, compared to CA- and MA-matched controls, and found
communication and socialization. Therefore, impaired moral un- significant differences between groups on FB, pretense, and inten-
derstanding would be related to impaired socialization. Grant et al. tion tasks. Despite the variability of passing rates within the WBS
[2005] examined 56 children, mean age 12–13 years, and their group, Porter et al. [2008] concluded that there were ToM deficits in
ability to understand the importance of motive and intention in WBS.
judging others’ behavior. Three groups were assessed: children with Individuals with neurodegenerative disorders have also been
AD, children with mild LD, and TD children. Participants were assessed for ToM. Allain et al. [2011] administered three ToM tasks
administered six pairs of stories involving motives and outcomes. to adults, ages 36–70 years, 18 with Huntington disease (HD) and 18
Results showed that children with AD were able to demonstrate controls. Results showed significant impairment in the HD group
moral understanding and judgment, comparable to that of children on motor tasks and executive function (EF) (frontal lobe) tasks, as
from the other two groups, and of judging damage to people as well as significantly lower scores on two of the three ToM tasks
more serious than damage to property. Therefore, despite their given. Kobayakawa et al. [2012] examined 9 middle-aged men and
impaired socialization, children with AD are capable of moral women with adult-onset myotonic dystrophy (DM), and compared
understanding. them to 12 controls. Unlike the study by Allain et al. [2011], these
In summary, basic assumptions regarding ToM, its universality researchers excluded individuals who demonstrated cognitive de-
in all children, unaffected by exogenous factors such as culture, terioration at the time of recruitment. Participants were adminis-
ethnicity and socioeconomic factors, are not well-supported by tered two ToM tasks. Results indicate significantly lower scores on
empirical findings. Differences in ToM theories related to suppo- both ToM tasks for individuals with DM compared to controls.
sitions regarding its innateness, whether as a module or as theory– Poletti et al. [2011] reviewed 10 studies in which ToM was examined
theory, the age at which a ToM emerges or events that presage the in patients with Parkinson Disease (PD). Typical ToM tasks
emergence of a ToM, are likewise not validated empirically. Specific presented included a faux pas test, other’s beliefs, and the “Reading
features, such as the age at which pretend play or social interactions of Minds in the Eyes” (RME), another ToM task developed by
are supposed to materialize, or the earliest age at which children can Baron-Cohen et al. [2001]. The RME task was also employed by
practice deception using ToM or understand FBs, are also not well Allain et al. [2011] and Kobayakawa et al. [2012] as part of their
corroborated by research findings. The inability to incorporate the ToM battery of tests. Patients with PD performed poorly although,
effects of social interaction into the model as they influence according to Poletti et al. [2011], working memory may have played
behavior is another weakness in ToM paradigms. Differences on an important role in the execution of each of these undertakings in
FB tasks between children with AD compared to those with ID only the PD group.
have been found to be insignificant in many studies. Test–retest The basic format of the RME task is to show the participant a
reliability of various FB tasks, the “litmus test” for ToM [Baron- photograph of the region around the eyes, then ask the respondent
Cohen, 1995], have not been shown to be consistent. Other features to select which mental-state descriptor the eyes best exhibit. Var-
of behavior that are limited in children with AD, such as lack of iations of the RME task have been validated by Calder et al. [2002]
empathy, are related to intellectual ability and not specific to AD, and Peterson and Slaughter [2009], although Hallerbäck et al.
while morality can be made more manifest in children with AD. [2009] found test–retest reliability only moderately correlated
(r ¼ 0.6); and, of the 28 items in the task, 12/28 (42%) were
correctly responded to by less than 75% of the non-clinical adult
THEORY OF MIND IN NON-AUTISTIC POPULATIONS sample tested, while as many as 6/28 (21%) show chance correct
ToM took a curious turn recently as researchers began to exploit the agreement.
model to examine disorders other than autism. Given the “autistic- Children with other disabilities have also been assessed using
like” behaviors in fragile X syndrome, Cornish et al. [2005] admin- ToM tasks. Buitelaar et al. [1996] administered a series of ToM tasks
istered the FB and AR tasks to 54 children, 7–15 years, 28 males with to a non-autistic 9-year-old boy with a diagnosis of Non-Verbal
the FMR1 full mutation and 26 males with DS, matched for CA and Learning Disability. He passed only 50% of the first-order ToM
verbal age. Results showed that pass rates were about 75% and tasks, and failed all second-order tasks. Based on their results,
comparable in both groups. That is, about 25% of each group failed Buitelaar et al. [1996] proposed that social-cognitive abilities in
FISCH 2473

children should be examined with respect to their neuropsycho- children with a genetic or congenital abnormality who failed the
logical profiles. Peterson and Siegal [1995] examined 26 deaf ToM tasks administered to them. Therefore, it is the not necessary
children, ages 8–13 years, who grew up in homes where sign to have a diagnosis of autism to show ToM deficits. That is, ToM
language was not used, therefore they had communication expe- deficits are neither necessary nor sufficient to produce autism. As
riences similar to those of autistic children. Children were assigned for research among individuals with TBI, these researchers seem to
to one of two groups: Those administered the standard FB task; and conclude that ToM tasks used to identify ToM in children can now
those who were administered a conversationally modified FB task. be used to detect ToM deficits produced by various damaged
Of the 12 children administered the standard FB task, only 2/12 regions or lesions in brain in adults as a consequence of their
(16%) passed; whereas, 7/14 (50%) passed the conversationally inability to perform certain types of tasks, particularly tasks
modified task. Consequently, Peterson and Siegal [1995] concluded that require a good working memory. Considering the respective
that ToM deficits were not specific to autism. Minter et al. [1998] ages of their participants, it is likely not known whether any of the
administered an FB task and a second ToM task to 42 CA- and IQ- adults would have successfully completed the ToM tasks had they
matched visually impaired and sighted children, mean age 6 years, been administered in childhood. Since PD, HD, and adult-onset
and found that visually impaired children performed significantly DM are neurodegenerative disorders that occur in adults, it is not
worse than sighted children on both tasks. To examine the role of clear what ToM as a model of childhood development has to do with
language in the development of ToM, Dahlgren et al. [2010] failure on ToM tasks that result in neurological deterioration in
administered a FB task and a second ToM task to 28 children, adulthood.
ages 5–13 years. Fourteen children were diagnosed with cerebral
palsy and had severe speech/language impediment; 14 were TD
children. Groups were matched on linguistic-age and MA. Results
MODIFYING DYSFUNCTIONAL BEHAVIOR IN AUTISM
showed that children with cerebral palsy performed significantly Another problem left unresolved by ToM regards the effect of
less well on the standard Sally-and-Anne FB task but not on the behavioral interventions on children with AD. If, as ToM models
“thought picture” ToM task. suggest, some innate module or brain component is obliterated or
Several researchers have gone so far as to examine ToM in at best, severely damaged in children with AD, and is unaffected by
individuals with traumatic brain injury (TBI). Changes in social exogenous factors such as culture and socioeconomic status, what
behavior have been observed frequently in individuals with TBI. An could possibly be the effects of behavioral mediation to ameliorate
early article by Bibby and McDonald [2005] examined 15 adults the disorder? To examine the effects of behavioral intervention,
with TBI to either their frontal, temporal, parietal, or occipital brain Dawson et al. [2010, 2012] employed the Early Denver Start Model
regions. Compared to CA-matched controls, TBI individuals per- (EDSM), a comprehensive behavioral program to improve a variety
formed significantly less well on first- and second-order ToM tasks. of behaviors in children with AD. After 2 years’ intensive treatment,
Muller et al. [2010] explored ToM in individuals with severe TBI to Dawson et al. [2010] found that children with AD showed signifi-
the same regions of brain as found in participants in Bibby and cant improvements in adaptive behavior and language compared to
McDonald study. However, the participants in Muller et al. [2010] controls. Dawson et al. [2012] later examined brain activity in
were significantly more impaired cognitively (mean FSIQ ¼ 70). children who received EDSM intervention compared to an IQ-
Individuals in the Muller et al. [2010] study performed significantly matched group of children with AD who did not. These researchers
worse than controls on four of the ToM tasks administered, found children with AD showed EEG responses to faces similar to
although curiously not on the FB task. In their meta-analysis of that of TD children, and significantly better than the IQ-matched
studies examining ToM in TBI, Martı́n-Rodriguez and León-Car- AD controls. That is to say, intensive behavioral interventions in
rión [2010] found large effect size differences (about 1 SD) on four young children with AD can improve neurological function.
ToM tasks between subjects with TBI and unaffected controls.
The problem with all these studies is that a core component for
ToM seems to have been circumvented. For Piaget, ToM appears at
AUTRES TEMPS, AUTRES THEORIES
one phase of a developmental sequence of discrete stages as the child From its inception, theories about the etiology of autism have been
ages, and which emerges early in the child’s life. And, in accordance proposed. However, in the past 30 years these theories have
with Piaget’s theory of child development, whether one invokes increased in number, one might be inclined to say, in an exponential
Leslie’s [1987] innate module or Perner’s [1991] T-T, it is the ability fashion much as the putative prevalence of autism. Kanner’s earliest
to form a mental representation at age four which emerges as account of autism was as an inborn error of affect, later described as
pretend play at age 2 years in the TD child. In addition, its “infantile autism” [1949]. Asperger referred to the disorder he
manifestation is universal among TD children. Thus, one conclu- observed in his patients as a “personality disorder” [1944]. These
sion from the results obtained by Cornish et al. [2005] is “autistic- humble beginnings have proliferated into the raft of theories in
like” behaviors that appear as part of a fragile X syndrome are not vogue currently: Theory of Mind, Simulation, Executive Function,
sufficient for, nor are they specifically associated with, a ToM deficit Central Coherence, the Social Brain, Sensorimotor Theory, among
in male children with the FMR1 full mutation who have not been the most widely recognized. EF theory argues that there are areas in
diagnosed as autistic, though results obtained by Grant et al. [2007] brain, primarily the prefrontal cortex, which are involved with goal-
seem to produce a somewhat more mixed picture. On the other setting, focused attention, and decision-making; and, these skills
hand, from the results obtained by Porter et al. [2008], Peterson and are deficient in individuals with autism [Ozonoff et al., 1991]. Yet,
Siegal [1995], and Minter et al. [1998], there were non-autistic deficits in EF are not specific to AD [cf. Gallagher, 2004; Volkmar,
2474 AMERICAN JOURNAL OF MEDICAL GENETICS PART A

2011]. Central coherence (CC) theory argues that individuals with Everything should be made as simple as possible, but not
AD attend to detail rather than global assessment more so than do simpler.
TD individuals; and they are unable to switch easily from figure to
global perception, and vice-versa. Unfortunately, ToM, EF, and CC Albert Einstein, (attributed)
theory all come up short as cognitive models for autism, the
consequence of conflicting results in studies which attempt to Less is more.
examine the empirical basis for each theory. Of late, ToM has
evolved into “mind-blindness” [Baron-Cohen, 1995], with addi- Ludwig Mies van der Rohe
tional innate mechanisms such as an “eye direction detector” and an
“intentionality detector.” To address issues that arose from studies In his landmark article, Kanner [1943] thought that social
that challenged the original ToM article, Baron-Cohen [2009] deficits were primary in autism and resulted from an inborn deficit.
proposed a revised model referred to as “Empathizing–Systematiz- More than 40 years later, Fein et al. [1986] restated Kanner’s original
ing Theory” (EST), in which a second factor is incorporated to position, that autism is a neurological disorder that primarily
account for non-social deficits in AD. ToM was expanded to include disrupts social and affective development. Although Fein et al.
a dimension to assess emotional reactivity. Baron-Cohen [1995] also argued the case that social deficits were primary, they main-
also put forward a two-factor theory to distinguish AD from other tained that children with AD had some specific neurological
disorders, with disappointedly mixed results. Finally, two core dysfunction subserving attachment and social behavior, even
deficits associated with AD were dimensionalized to account for though no single anatomical or physiological locus of dysfunction
the fact that there are degrees of impairment in AD that “blend in” had been found at that time.
to the general population. EST also incorporated Baron-Cohen’s For much of the past 40 years, the neurobehavioral paradigm of
Extreme Male Brain (EMB) theory of AD [Baron-Cohen, 2009]. autism has been at the forefront of theories regarding the etiology of
Unfortunately for Baron-Cohen’s EMB theory, Voracek and Dress- autism, and ToM has been the leading neurocognitive model for the
ler [2006] found that when they examined the second-to-fourth past generation. Recently, however, Minshew et al. [2011] have
digit ratio—an established biomarker for sexual differentiation found a broad range of sensory-perceptual, sensorimotor, and
between males and females—they found individual differences memory deficits associated with AD which suggests that the nature
to be unrelated to EST and autistic-like characteristics in the general and degree of involvement of neurological functions have not been
population. appropriately dealt with by ToM, EF, or CC, or any of the other
The modifications and additions to the original model proposed neurobehavioral theories extant. In her earlier work, Minshew et al.
by Baron-Cohen et al. [1985] are reminiscent of the efforts by [2004] found neurological impairments in vestibular, visual and
the Ptolemaicists and neo-Aristotelians to salvage the geocentric postural senses in children with autism. Rogers [2009] examined
theory of the universe composed of concentric spheres. The geo- infants who were the younger siblings of children diagnosed with
centric theory was rescued—for a time—by adding epicycles to AD and therefore at a higher risk of developing AD, and found the
celestial objects in the spheres which did not conform to the earliest signs of autism were not social impairment, but unusual
original theory, a line of reasoning noted by Stone and Gerrans responses to sensory stimulation and unusual motor activities that
[2006] regarding ToM. When the first set of epicycles still did not heralded the disorder. Consequently, Minshew et al. [2011] pro-
conform to the data, more epicycles were affixed to the model. posed shifting the etiological paradigm for autism, conceptualizing
Curiously, and in a similar vein, despite the wealth of data which it as a neurological and neurobiological disorder, as opposed to a
demonstrate that ToM is neither necessary nor sufficient as a model neurobehavioral or neurocognitive one.
to depict AD, Frith [2012] continues to assert that, while we can In support of a neurobiological hypothesis, Courchesne et al.
observe and assess autistic behavior, and find and measure the [2011] found substantial evidence that children diagnosed with AD,
concomitant neurological phenomena associated with those behav- irrespective of etiology, exhibit a too-rapid growth in brain prior to
iors, we must somehow insert another level of explanation, a age 2 years, followed by a too-steep decline in growth afterward,
cognitive model between brain and behavior, in order to explain comparedtoTDchildrenofthesameage.Frontalandtemporallobes,
behavior already accounted for by brain [cf. Stone and Gerrans, and the amygdala, were brain areas primarily affected. Levy et al.
2006]. Cromwell and Panksepp [2011] note that this is precisely the [2009] noted that damage in these regions have been linked to motor
problem with much of cognitive theory: Cognitive-behavioral difficulties, as well as problems associated with communication and
concepts that are but hypothetical constructs which simply do socialization. As noted earlier, Brüne and Brüne-Cohrs [2006]
not correspond to specific neurological mechanisms that generate reported that patients with brain lesions in these regions—left-
behavior. hemisphere, frontal cortex, left amygdala, and pre-frontal cortex—
demonstrated impaired performances on FB tasks as adults. Zielinski
et al. [2012] examined structural features in brain regions containing
EVERYTHING OLD IS NEW AGAIN network nodes. In particular, they examined the salience network
Any intelligent fool can make things bigger, more complex, (SN) and default mode network (DMN). The SN contains, among
and more violent. It takes a touch of genius—and a lot of other areas, the frontoinsular and orbitofrontal cortex, both involved
courage—to move in the opposite direction. with social functioning. The DMN is comprised of, among other
regions, the medial and ventral prefrontal cortex, anchored by the
Albert Einstein, (attributed) posterior cingulate cortex. The DMN is believed to regulate internal
FISCH 2475

processes such as attention. Zielinski et al. [2012] found the SN to be “PF neurons” [Rizzolatti et al., 2001]. It is thought that other areas of
underdeveloped in volume, while the DMN exhibited both over- brain, for example, the amygdala and orbitofrontal cortex, are also
developed and underdeveloped regions in children and adolescents part of the mirror neuron network. Fogassi and Ferrari [2007]
with AD compared to controls. It should be noted that neither the SN determined that language is also part of the complex. Thus, language
nor DMN are modules in the usual sense, if by module is meant one of development, social behavior, and the understanding of intention-
a set of standardized parts or independent units used to construct a ality appear to be related to a particular type of neuron and located in
more complex structure. well-defined interconnected brain regions.
In a somewhat parallel development, action recognition, a basis As for Kanner’s impression that autism was inborn: AD is now
upon which social behavior is understood, was found in the neural considered as a highly heritable disorder, mostly multi-monogenic
substrates of primates. So-called “mirror neurons” are triggered but possibly polygenic in nature; and it is increasingly the case that
when a primate observes a conspecific performing a goal-directed genetic mutations associated with AD have been found to have a
action using its hand, mouth or foot. And, according to Buccino known neurobiological effect. Recent estimates are that 15% of
et al. [2004], there are neurophysiological, behavioral, and brain- individuals diagnosed with AD have a known genetic cause [Carter
imaging studies that also demonstrate the existence of mirror and Scherer, 2013]. Creak [1963] was probably the first to note a
neurons in human brains. Sato et al. [2012b] presented dynamic genetic disorder, tuberous sclerosis complex (TSC), associated with
and static facial expressions to high-functioning adults diagnosed AD. Phenylketonuria (PKU) was later shown associated with AD
with ASD, and to age- and sex-matched controls, and examined [Friedman, 1969]. Later still, the FMR1 full mutation was discov-
their brain activity. These researchers found regions in the social ered in young males with autism [Brown et al., 1982]. TSC, the
brain network show lower activity in ASD subjects compared to FMR1 mutation, and more recently discovered mutations in the
controls. Fadiga and Craighero [2003] observed that action-related PTEN gene, probably account for more than 10% of the known
neural responses are not only a function of visual stimuli but genetic causes for autism [Smalley, 1991]. As it happens, TSC,
acoustical stimuli as well. In effect, mirror neurons allow humans PTEN, and FMRP—the protein produced by the FMR1 gene—
to represent in one’s brain other humans’ behavior. Bolling et al. form part of the mTOR complex in brain, the pathways for which
[2011] found neurobiological differences in processing social ex- dovetail to inhibit mTOR signaling. Genetic mutations in TSC and
clusion and rule violation in a game of Cyberball in a group of TD FMR1, PTEN, as well as STRADa and other regulatory genes, have
children compared to children with AD. As noted earlier, problems known adverse consequences on the structure of the neocortex
of social processing have been a hallmark of dysfunction in AD from [Crino, 2011]. As importantly, even among known genetic abnor-
Kanner’s time to the present. Thus it has been demonstrated that malities, such as the FMR1 mutation, TSC and PTEN, in which the
neural material in brain regions directly involved in social process- probability that a child born with one or the other mutation will
ing have been identified, that neural activity in these regions differs develop autism is markedly increased, variability in the behavioral
in individuals with AD compared to non-AD controls, and can now features of AD has also been reported.
be studied in greater detail. More recently, mutations in members of the neuroligin family,
As remarked earlier, the concept of intentionality is rooted in the NLGN3 and NLGN4, have been found in children with AD [Jamain
folk psychology inherent in ToM. To address the issue of inten- et al., 2003; Laumonnier et al., 2004; Yanagi et al., 2012]. Members
tionality in mirror neurons, Iacoboni et al. [2005] used fMRI to of the neurexin family, from the beta-neurexin complex [Feng et al.,
study 23 human subjects exposed to three different film clips: a hand 2006], CNTNAP2 [Alarcón et al., 2008], NRXN1 [Ching et al.,
grasping a cup (no context); a tea setting (context but no hand 2010], as well as the SHANK3 gene [Sato et al., 2012a], have also
grasping); and a hand grasping a cup in the tea setting. Results been found in individuals with AD. Neuroligins have been shown to
showed increased signals in the premotor motor areas during the affect synapse formation, while NXRN protein is associated with
third (embedded context) condition suggested that neural mech- presynaptic binding with NLGN and CNTNAP2, and shows ho-
anisms are involved in the intentionality of the action. Fogassi et al. mology to SHANK3, the latter of which regulates the structure of
[2005] examined inferior parietal lobule (IPL) neurons in monkeys dendritic spines [Bourgeron, 2009].
when they performed various motor activities, and when they Chromosomal regions in which microdeletions or duplications
observed the experimenter performing similar actions. These were found among individuals diagnosed with AD have become
researchers found that IPL neurons fired only when embedded hotspots for candidate genes. Bundey et al. [1994] and Koochek
in an activity was associated with some forthcoming goal. Their et al. [2006] reported instances in which duplication in 15q11-13
results suggest that in addition to the recognition of a motor were found in individuals diagnosed with AD. Depienne et al.
activity, mirror neurons can anticipate the goal of the activity, [2009] examined 522 individuals diagnosed with ASD and found 4
that is, its “intention.” That is, cognitive functions typically ascribed with 15q11-13 abnormalities. In an earlier report using linkage
to a ToM could be explained more pragmatically by the triggering of disequilibrium mapping, Cook et al. [1998] found a candidate gene,
a related sequence of mirror neurons in brain. GABRB3, in the 15q11-13 region associated with AD. Hogart et al.
Mirror neurons were first found in the monkey’s ventral premotor [2007] showed that MeCP2 binds to sites with GABRB3 and
cortex, area F5, the latter of which is considered the homologue of organizes GABRB3 in neurons.
Broca’s area in humans [Rizzolatti et al., 1996; Rizzolatti and Arbib, Other researchers have found higher than expected rates of AD in
1998]. Other brain regions in monkey, such as the superior temporal the many genetic disorders they have studied. Vorstman et al.
sulcus (STS), also contain neurons responding to biological actions. [2006] examined 60 children and adolescents with deletion 22q
Both F5 and STS are linked to the IPL, area PF, and are referred to as and found 50% of those assessed with standard protocols were
2476 AMERICAN JOURNAL OF MEDICAL GENETICS PART A

diagnosed with AD. Fisch et al. [2010] examined children with believed his theory fell outside the purview of the modern scientific
one of four subtelomeric deletions—2q37, 4p16, invdupdel8p22- explanation.
23, or 11q24-25—and found 11/43 (30%) of children met The original article by Baron-Cohen et al. [1985], in which
criteria consistent with a diagnosis of AD, although none of the the authors account for social impairment in autistic children
children with 4p16 exhibited autistic behaviors. In their review because they lack a ToM, ascribes the source of their model to
of genetic disorders that produce developmental disabilities, Premack and Woodruff [1978], the latter of whom claimed to
Vorstman and Ophoff [2013] highlight a number of known genetic have ascertained ToM in a chimpanzee. The methodology used
abnormalities in which individuals with AD have been identified. by Premack and Woodruff [1978] was not without its short-
Although candidate genes have yet to be discovered in many of comings, its findings open to question and conclusions criti-
these regions, current technologies using genome-wide association cized. Ensuing research found a lack of evidence for a ToM in
studies will likely identify the genetic variants associated with primates, which suggested strongly that the research design
AD. employed and results obtained by Premack and Woodruff lacked
These findings demonstrate that there are numerous genetic both internal and external validity. The consequences stemming
mutations associated with AD, which in turn appear to disrupt from the many weaknesses identified by the empirical outcomes
various neurobiological processes. If these neurobiological process- of studies of ToM in primates should have forewarned future
es are located in, or in some way influence, the mirror neuron researchers of problems that might arise in attempting to
complex, the consequence of which would disturb normal com- implement a ToM in children with autism.
munication and socialization, we may well be on the way to From the outset, ToM has had many shortcomings as a neuro-
establishing neurobiological markers for AD. One step toward cognitive model of autism. From a methodological perspective, a
that end has been provided by Skafidas et al. [2012], who examined research design that embeds a pretend play component in a FB task
SNPs in 2,609 probands with ASD. Using pathway analysis, these is illogical since children with AD do not pretend play spontane-
researchers identified 775 SNPs that were significantly modified in ously. Second, the linguistic sophistication needed to provide a
the presence of ASD. Of these, 237 were used to discriminate correct response to the FB task is beyond the pragmatic language
between ASD and non-ASD controls with prediction accuracy of skills of all too many children with AD whose impaired communi-
about 85%. cative ability is embedded in the diagnosis of AD. Third, without a
As novel neurobiological and neurophysiological studies are ToM, how was it possible for a child to participate actively in a ToM
begun, progress, and results obtained, brain–behavior and gene– experiment? Although the FB test was supposed to the “gold
brain–behavior pathways associated with AD will become more standard” for a ToM, the experiment itself contains many serious
clearly delineated and the underlying neurological phenomena logical and design flaws. Leslie and Frith [1987] argued that
elucidated. All of which is to say that by establishing brain– linguistic ability was unrelated to ToM, but many researchers
behavior relationships in this fashion, a ToM, or any other subsequently showed otherwise. The matter of whether one needed
metaphysical neurobehavioral entity, will be found redundant. a ToM to participate in a ToM experiment remained unresolved,
To paraphrase Searle [1990], it is one thing to speak of inten- although this too seems to beg the question.
tions metaphorically, as “as-if” ascriptions. It is quite another to Other assumptions that form the basis for a ToM, its universality
take them literally. in all children in all cultures and socioeconomic conditions, are not
supported by empirical findings. Differences in versions of ToM
related to underlying assumptions about innateness, whether as a
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION module or as a theory, the age at which a ToM emerges, or events
that herald the emergence of a ToM, are likewise not often validated
A belief in dialectical materialism necessitates that one also empirically. Specific model features, such as the age at which
believe in the omnipotence of thought. pretend play or social interactions are supposed to materialize,
or the earliest age at which children can practice deception using
-Anonymous
ToM or understand FBs, are at variance with many research
ToM has its roots in Piagetian developmental child psychology. findings. Other weaknesses in ToM include the inability to utilize
Although Piaget did not consider himself as a child psychologist, his the early acquisition social skills in the life of the infant to explain
theory of child development became widespread during the 1960s interbehavioral interactions. Differences on FB tasks between chil-
and was adopted by cognitive psychologists seeking to oust behav- dren with AD and those with ID only are insignificant in many
iorism from its prominent position in psychology. The central studies. Test–retest results from various FB tasks, the “litmus test”
themes of Piagetian theory are that children’s cognitive abilities are for ToM [Baron-Cohen, 1995], do not have good reliability. Other
innate, emerge at specific ages, and appear in four major, distinct, features of behavior that are limited in children with AD, such as
sequentially invariant stages. However, the methodological aspects lack of empathy, are correlated with intellectual ability and not
of the theory, particularly the emergence of sequentially invariant specific to AD.
stages at specific ages, have not been well-validated empirically. As Recent findings regarding mirror neurons, their location and
formulated, Piaget’s theory of child development lacks construct interconnections in brain, their relationship to social behavior,
and predictive validity, his terminology often murky and lacking in intentionality, and language, and the effect of lesions in these areas
precision. Despite these concerns, Piaget did not consider empirical on speech, language and social behavior, strongly suggests that a
verification or falsification of his theory problematic, since he neurobiological as opposed to neurocognitive model of autism is a
FISCH 2477

more parsimonious explanation for the social, linguistic and be- Beck BB. 1978. Talkers and doers. Behav Brain Sci 4:557.
havioral phenotypes observed in autism. Bibby H, McDonald S. 2005. Theory of mind after traumatic brain injury.
All of which is to say: Does autism really need a Theory of Mind? Neuropsychologia 43:99–114.
Bloom P, German TP. 2000. Two reasons to abandon the false belief task as a
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS test of the theory of mind. Cognition 77:B25–31.
Bolling DZ, Pitskel NB, Deen B, Crowley MJ, McPartland JC, Kaiser
I thank Miriam S. Grosof, Irv Gottesman, and an anonymous MD, Wyk BC, Wu J, Mayes LC, Pelphrey KA. 2011. Enhanced neural
reviewer for their comments on an earlier version of this manu- responses to rule violation in children with autism: A comparison to
script. Any errors contained herein are solely my own. social exclusion. Dev Cogn Neurosci 1:280–294.
Boucher J. 1989. The theory of mind hypothesis of autism: Explanation,
REFERENCES evidence and assessment. Br J Disord Commun 24:181–198.
Boucher J, Lewis V. 1989. Memory impairments and communication
Abbeduto L, Short-Meyerson K, Benson G, Dolish J. 2004. Relationship in relatively able autistic children. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 30:99–
between theory of mind and language ability in children and adolescents 122.
with intellectual disability. J Intellect Disabil Res 48:150–159.
Bourgeron T. 2009. A synaptic trek to autism. Curr Opin Neurobiol
Alarcón M, Abrahams BS, Stone JL, Duvall JA, Perederiy JV, Bomar JM, 19:231–234.
Sebat J, Wigler M, Martin CL, Ledbetter DH, Nelson SF, Cantor RM,
Brown WT, Friedman E, Jenkins EC, Brooks J, Wisniewski K, Raguthu S,
Geschwind DH. 2008. Linkage, association, and gene-expression analyses
French JH. 1982. Association of fragile X syndrome with autism. Lancet
identify CNTNAP2 as an autism-susceptibility gene. Am J Hum Genet
1:100.
82:150–159.
Brüne M, Brüne-Cohrs U. 2006. Theory of mind—Evolution, ontogeny,
Allain P, Havet-Thomassin V, Verny C, Gohier B, Lancelot C, Besnard J,
brain mechanisms, and psychopathology. Neurosci Biobehav Rev
Fasotti L, Le Gall D. 2011. Evidence for deficits on different components
30:437–455.
of theory of mind in Huntington’s disease. Neuropsychology 25:741–751.
Buccino G, Binkofski F, Riggio L. 2004. The mirror neuron system and
American Psychiatric Association. 2000. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual
action recognition. Brain Lang 89:370–376.
of Mental Disorders (4th Ed.): Text Revision. Washington, DC: The
American Psychiatric Association. Buitelaar JK, Swaab H, van der Wees M, Wildschut M, van der Gaag RJ.
1996. Neuropsychological impairments and deficits in theory of mind
Asperger H. 1944. Die “Autistischen Psychopathen” im kindesalter. Arch
and emotion recognition in a non-autistic boy. Eur Child Adolesc
Psychiatr Nervenkr 117:76–136.
Psychiatry 5:44–51.
Astington JW, Dack LA. 2008. Theory of mind. In: Haith MM, Benson JB,
Bundey S, Hardy C, Vickers S, Kilpatrick MW, Corbett JA. 1994. Duplica-
editors. Encyclopedia of infant and early childhood development, Vol. 3.
tion of the 15q11–13 region in a patient with autism, epilepsy and ataxia.
San Diego, CA: Academic Press. pp 343–356.
Dev Med Child Neurol 36:736–742.
Astington JW, Jenkins JM. 1999. A longitudinal study of the relation
between language and Theory-of-Mind development. Dev Psychol Burack JA. 1992. Debate and argument: Clarifying developmental issues in
the study of autism. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 33:617–622.
35:1311–1320.
Burge T. 1978. Concept of mind in primates? Behav Brain Sci 4:560–562.
Baillargeon R, Scott RM, He Z. 2010. False-belief understanding in infants.
Trends Cogn Sci 14:110–118. Burghardt GM. 1978. Closing the circle: The ethology of mind. Behav Brain
Sci 4:562–563.
Baron-Cohen S, Leslie AM, Frith U. 1985. Does the autistic child have a
“theory of mind?” Cognition 21:37–46. Calder AJ, Lawrence AD, Keane J, Scott SK, Owen AM, Christoffels I, Young
Baron-Cohen S. 1988. Without a theory of mind, one cannot participate in AW. 2002. Reading the mind from eye gaze. Neuropsychologia 40:1129–
1138.
a conversation. Cognition 29:83–84.
Call J, Tomasello M. 2008. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30
Baron-Cohen S. 1989a. The theory of mind hypothesis in autism: A reply to
Boucher. Br J Disord Commun 24:199–200. years later. Trends Cogn Sci 12:187–192.
Carpenter M, Nagell K, Tomasello M. 1998. Social cognition, joint atten-
Baron-Cohen S. 1989b. Are autistic children “Behaviorists”? An examina- tion, and communicative competence from 9 to 15 months of age.
tion of their mental-physical and appearance-reality distinctions. J Monogr Soc Res Child Dev 63:1–174.
Autism Dev Disord 19:579–600.
Carter M, Scherer S. 2013. Autism spectrum disorder in the genetics clinic:
Baron-Cohen S. 1989c. The autistic child’s theory of mind: a case of specific A review. Clin Genet 83:399–407.
developmental delay. J Child Psychol Psychiat 30:285–297.
Chandler M, Fritz AS, Hala S. 1989. Small-scale deceit: Deception as a
Baron-Cohen S. 1992. Debate and argument: On modularity and develop-
marker of two-, three-, and four-year olds’ early theories of mind. Child
ment in autism: A reply to Burack. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 33:623–629. Dev 60:1263–1277.
Baron-Cohen S. 1995. Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of Charman T, Campbell A. 1997. Reliability of Theory of Mind task perfor-
mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. mance by individuals with a learning disability: A research note. J Child
Baron-Cohen S. 2009. Autism: The Empathizing-Systematizing (E-S) Psychol Psychiatry 38:725–730.
Theory. Ann NY Acad Sci 1156:68–80. Ching MS, Shen Y, Tan WH, Jeste SS, Morrow EM, Chen X, Mukaddes NM,
Baron-Cohen S, Wheelwright S, Hill J, Raste Y, Plumb I. 2001. The Yoo SY, Hanson E, Hundley R, Austin C, Becker RE, Berry GT, Driscoll K,
“Reading the Mind in the Eyes” Test revised version: A study with Engle EC, Friedman S, Gusella JF, Hisama FM, Irons MB, Lafiosca T,
normal adults, and adults with Asperger syndrome or high-functioning LeClair E, Miller DT, Neessen M, Picker JD, Rappaport L, Rooney CM,
autism. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 42:241–251. Sarco DP, Stoler JM, Walsh CA, Wolff RR, Zhang T, Nasir RH, Wu BL,
2478 AMERICAN JOURNAL OF MEDICAL GENETICS PART A

Children’s Hospital Boston Genotype Phenotype Study Group. Fisch GS. 2007. Animal models and human neuropsychiatric disorders.
2010. Deletions of NRXN1 (neurexin-1) predispose to a wide Behav Genet 37:1–10.
spectrum of developmental disorders. Am J Med Genet Part B
Fisch GS, Grossfeld P, Falk R, Battaglia A, Youngblom J, Simensen R. 2010.
153B:937–947.
Cognitive-behavioral features of Wolf–Hirschhorn syndrome and other
Cook EH Jr, Courchesne RY, Cox NJ, Lord C, Gonen D, Guter SJ, Lincoln subtelomeric microdeletions. Am J Med Genet Part C 154C:417–426.
A, Nix K, Haas R, Leventhal BL, Courchesne E. 1998. Linkage-disequi-
librium mapping of autistic disorder, with 15q11-13 markers. Am J Hum Flavell J. 1999. Cognitive development: Children’s knowledge about mind.
Genet 62:1077–1083. Annu Rev Psychol 50:21–45.

Cornish K, Burack JA, Rahman A, Munir F, Russo N, Grant C. 2005. Theory Fodor J. 1983. The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford
of mind deficits in children with fragile X syndrome. J Intellect Disabil Res Books.
49:372–378. Fogassi L, Ferrari PF. 2007. Mirror neurons and the evolution of embodied
Courchesne E, Webb SJ, Schumann CM. 2011. From toddlers to adults: The language. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 16:136–141.
changing landscape of the brain in autism. In: Amaral DG, Dawson G, Fogassi L, Ferrari PF, Gesierich B, Rozzi S, Chersi F, Rizzolatti G. Parietal
Geschwind DH, editors. Autism spectrum disorders. Oxford: Oxford lobe: From action organization to intention understanding. Science 2005.
University Press. pp 611–631. 308:662–667.
Creak EM. 1963. Childhood psychosis: A review of 100 cases. Br J Psychiatry Friedman E. 1969. The autistic syndrome and phenylketonuria. Schizo-
109:84–89. phrenia 10:249–261.
Crino PB. 2011. mTOR: A pathogenic signaling pathway in developmental Frith U. 2012. The 38th Sir Frederick Bartlett Lecture: Why we need
brain malformations. Trends Mol Med 17:734–742. cognitive explanations of autism. Q J Exp Psychol 65:2073–2092.
Cromwell HC, Panksepp J. 2011. Rethinking the cognitive revolution from Gallagher S. 2004. Understanding interpersonal problems in autism:
a neural perspective: How overuse/misuse of the term ‘cognition’ and the Interaction theory as an alternative to Theory of Mind. Philos Psychiatry
neglect of affective controls in behavioral neuroscience could be delaying Psychol 11:199–217.
progress in understanding the BrainMind. Neurosci Biobehav Rev
35:2026–2035. Garfield JL, Peterson CC, Perry T. 2001. Social cognition, language
acquisition and the development of the theory of mind. Mind Lang
Dahlgren SO, Trillingsgaard A. 1996. Theory of mind in non-retarded 16:494–541.
children with autism and Asperger’s syndrome. A research note. J Child
Psychol Psychiatry 37:759–763. Gernsbacher MA, Frymiare JL. 2005. Does the autistic brain lack core
modules? Division of Learning Disabilities Journal, 1:3–16.
Dahlgren S, Dahlgren Sandberg A, Larsson M. 2010. Theory of mind in
children with severe speech and physical impairments. Res Dev Disabil Gesell A, Amatruda CS. 1941. Developmental diagnosis: normal and
31:617–624. abnormal child development. New York: Paul B. Hoeber, Inc. pp 3–25.
Dawson G, Rogers S, Munson J, Smith M, Winter J, Greenson J, Donaldson Goldstein MH, Schwade JA. 2008. Social feedback to infants’ babbling
A, Varley J. 2010. Randomized, controlled trial of an intervention for facilitates rapid phonological learning. Psychol Sci 19:515–523.
toddlers with autism: The Early Start Denver Model. Pediatrics 125:e17– Gopnik A, Astington JW. 1988. Children’s understanding of representa-
e23. tional change and its relation to the understanding of false belief and the
Dawson G, Jones EJ, Merkle K, Venema K, Lowy R, Faja S, Kamara D, appearance-reality distinction. Child Dev 59:26–37.
Murias M, Greenson J, Winter J, Smith M, Rogers SJ, Webb SJ. 2012. Early Gopnik A. 1993. How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person
behavioral intervention is associated with normalized brain activity in knowledge of intentionality. Behav Brain Sci 16:29–113.
young children with autism. J Am Acad Child Adolesc Psychiatry
51:1150–1159. Grant CM, Grayson A, Boucher J. 2001. Using tests of false belief with
children with autism: How valid and reliable are they? Autism 5:135–145.
de Gelder B. 1987. On not having a theory of mind. Cognition 27:285–
290. Grant CM, Boucher J, Riggs KJ, Grayson A. 2005. Moral understanding in
children with autism. Autism 9:317–331.
Depienne C, Moreno-De-Luca D, Heron D, Bouteiller D, Gennetier A,
Delorme R, Chaste P, Siffroi JP, Chantot-Bastaraud S, Benyahia B, Grant CM, Apperly I, Oliver C. 2007. Is theory of mind understanding
Trouillard O, Nygren G, Kopp S, Johansson M, Rastam M, Burglen L, impaired in males with fragile X syndrome? J Abnorm Child Psychol
Leguern E, Verloes A, Leboyer M, Brice A, Gillberg C, Betancur C. 2009. 35:17–28.
Screening for genomic rearrangements and methylation abnormalities of Grice HP. 1975. Logic and conversation. In: Cole R, Morgan J, editors.
the 15q11-q13 region in autism spectrum disorders. Biol Psychiatry Syntax and semantics: Speech acts. New York: Academic Press. pp 41–58.
66:349–359.
Guajardo NR, Watson AC. 2002. Narrative discourse and theory of mind
Dyck MJ, Ferguson K, Shochet IM. 2001. Do autism spectrum disorders development. J Genet Psychol 163:305–325.
differ from each other and from non-spectrum disorders on emotion
recognition tasks? Eur Child Adolesc Psychiatry 10:105–116. Hala S, Chandler M, Fritz AS. 1991. Fledging theories of mind: Deception as
a marker of three-year olds’ understanding of false belief. Child Dev
Fadiga L, Craighero L. 2003. New insights on sensorimotor integration: 62:83–97.
From hand action to speech perception. Brain Cogn 53:514–524.
Hallerbäck MU, Lungnegård T, Hjärthag F, Gillberg C. 2009. The reading of
Fein D, Pennington B, Markowitz P, Braverman M, Waterhouse L. 1986. mind in the eyes test: Test-retest reliability in a Swedish population. Cogn
Toward a neuropsychological model of infantile autism: Are the social Neuropsychiatry 14:127–143.
deficits primary? J Am Acad Child Psychiatry 25:198–212.
Heyes CM. 1978. Theory of mind in nonhuman primates [with commen-
Feng J, Schroer R, Yan J, Song W, Yang C, Bockholt A, Cook EH Jr, Skinner taries]. Behav Brain Sci 21:101–148.
C, Schwartz CE, Sommer SS. 2006. High frequency of neurexin 1beta
signal peptide structural variants in patients with autism. Neurosci Lett Hobson RP. 1990. On acquiring knowledge about people and the capacity
409:10–13. to pretend: Response to Leslie (1987). Psychol Rev 97:114–121.
FISCH 2479

Hogart A, Nagarajan RP, Patzel KA, Yasui DH, Lasalle JM. 2007. 15q11-13 Lillard AS. 1998a. Ethnopsychologies: Cultural variations in theory of
GABAA receptor genes are normally biallelically expressed in brain yet are mind. Psychol Bull 123:3–32.
subject to epigenetic dysregulation in autism-spectrum disorders. Hum
Lillard A. 1998b. Theories behind theories of mind. Hum Dev 41:40–46.
Mol Genet 16:691–703.
Martı́n-Rodriguez JF, León-Carrión J. 2010. Theory of mind deficits in
Iacoboni M, Molnar-Szakacs I, Gallese V, Buccino G, Mazziotta JC,
patients with acquired brain injury. Neuropsychologia 48:1181–1191.
Rizzolatti G. 2005. Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own
mirror system. PLoS Biology 3:0529–0535. Mayes LC, Klin A, Tercyak KP Jr, Cicchetti DV, Cohen DJ. 1996. Test-retest
reliability for false-belief tasks. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 37:313–319.
Jamain S, Quach H, Betancur C, Råstam M, Colineaux C, Gillberg IC,
Soderstrom H, Giros B, Leboyer M, Gillberg C, Bourgeron T, Paris McGraw MB. 1943. The neuromuscular maturation of the infant. New
Autism Research International Sibpair Study. 2003. Mutations of the X- York: Columbia University Press. pp 3–23.
linked genes encoding neuroligins NLGN3 and NLGN4 are associated
Melis AP, Call J, Tomasello M. 2010. 36-month-olds conceal visual and
with autism. Nat Genet 34:27–29.
auditory information. Dev Sci 13:479–489.
Jarrold C, Smith P, Boucher J, Harris P. 1994. Comprehension of pretense
Miller CA. 2001. False belief understanding in children with specific
in children with autism. J Autism Dev Disord 24:433–455.
language impairment. J Commun Disord 34:73–86.
Jarrold C, Mansergh R, Whiting C. 2010. The representational status of
Minshew NJ, Sung K, Jones B, Furman JM. 2004. Underdevelopment of the
pretence: Evidence from typical development and autism. Br J Dev
postural control system in autism. Neurology 63:2056–2061.
Psychol 28:239–254.
Minshew NJ, Scherf KS, Behrmann M, Humphreys K. 2011. Autism as a
Kaminski J, Call J, Tomasello M. 2008. Chimpanzees know what others
developmental neurobiological disorder: New insights from functional
know, but not what they believe. Cognition 109:224–234.
imaging. In: Amaral DG, Dawson G, Geschwind DH, editors. Autism
Kanner L. 1943. Autistic disturbances of affect contact. Nervous Child spectrum disorders. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp 632–650.
2:217–250.
Minter M, Hobson RP, Bishop M. 1998. Congenital visual impairment and
Kanner L. 1949. Problems of nosology and psychodynamics of early ‘theory of mind’. Br J Dev Psychol 16:183–196.
infantile autism. Am J Orthopsychiatry 19:416–426.
Muller F, Simion A, Reviriego E, Galera C, Mazaux J-M, Joseph P-A. 2010.
Klin A, Volkmar FR, Sparrow SS. 1992. Autistic social dysfunction: Some Exploring theory of mind after severe traumatic brain injury. Cortex
limitations of the theory of mind hypothesis. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 46:1088–1099.
33:861–876.
Onishi KH, Baillargeon R. 2005. Do 15-month-old infants understand false
Kobayakawa M, Tsuruya N, Kawamura M. 2012. Theory of mind im- beliefs? Science 308:255–258.
pairment in adult-onset myotonic dystrophy type 1. Neurosci Res
72:341–346. Osterling J, Dawson G. 1994. Early recognition of children with autism: A
study of first birthday home videotapes. J Autism Dev Disord 24:247–257.
Kobayashi C, Glover GH, Temple E. 2007. Cultural and linguistic effects on
neural bases of ‘Theory of Mind’ in American and Japanese children. Ozonoff S, Pennington BF, Rogers SJ. 1991. Executive function deficits in
Brain Res 1164:95–107. high-functioning autistic individuals: Relationship to theory of mind. J
Child Psychol Psychiatry 32:1081–1105.
Köhler W. 1925. The mentality of apes. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Penn DC, Povinelli DJ. 2007. On the lack of evidence that non-human
Koochek M, Harvard C, Hildebrand MJ, Van Allen M, Wingert H, animals possess anything remotely resembling a ‘theory of mind’. Philos
Mickelson E, Holden JJ, Rajcan-Separovic E, Lewis ME. 2006. 15q Trans R Soc B 362:731–744.
duplication associated with autism in a multiplex family with a familial
cryptic translocation t(14;15)(q11.2;q13.3) detected using array-CGH. Perner J. 1991. Understanding the representational mind. Cambridge, MA:
Clin Genet 69:124–134. MIT Press.

Laumonnier F, Bonnet-Brilhault F, Gomot M, Blanc R, David A, Moizard Perner J, Frith U, Leslie AM, Leekam SR. 1989. Exploration of the autistic
MP, Raynaud M, Ronce N, Lemonnier E, Calvas P, Laudier B, Chelly J, child’s theory of mind: Belief, and communication. Child Dev 60:689–
Fryns JP, Ropers HH, Hamel BC, Andres C, Barthélémy C, Moraine C, 700.
Briault S. 2004. X-linked mental retardation and autism are associated Peterson CC, Siegal M. 1995. Deafness, conversation and theory of mind. J
with a mutation in the NLGN4 gene, a member of the neuroligin family. Child Psychol Psychiatry 36:459–474.
Am J Hum Genet 74:552–557.
Peterson CC, Siegal M. 1999. Representing inner worlds: Theory of mind in
Leekam SR, Perner J. 1991. Does the autistic child have a metarepresenta- autistic, deaf, and normal hearing children. Psychol Sci 10:126–129.
tional deficit? Cognition 40:203–218.
Peterson CC, Slaughter V. 2009. Theory of Mind (ToM) in children with
Leslie AM. 1987. Pretense and Representation: The origins of “Theory of autism or typical development: Links between eye-reading and false-
Mind. Psychological Review 94:412–426. belief understanding. Res Autism Spectr Disord 3:462–473.
Leslie AM, Frith U. 1987. Metarepresentation and autism: How not to lose Poletti M, Enrici I, Bonuccelli U, Adenzato M. 2011. Theory of mind in
one’s marbles. Cognition 27:291–294. Parkinson’s disease. Behav Brain Res 219:342–350.
Leslie AM, Frith U. 1990. Prospects for a cognitive neuropsychology of Porter MA, Coltheart M, Langdon R. 2008. Theory of mind in Williams
autism: Hobson’s choice. Psychol Rev 97:122–131. syndrome assessed using a nonverbal task. J Autism Dev Disord 38:806–
Levy SE, Mandell DS, Schultz RT. 2009. Autism. Lancet 374:1627–1638. 814.
Lewis V, Boucher J. 1988. Spontaneous, instructed and elicited play in Povinelli DJ, Eddy TJ. 1996. What young chimpanzees know about seeing.
relatively able autistic children. Br J Dev Psychol 6:325–339. Monogr Soc Res Child Dev 61:1–152
Lillard AS. 1997. Other folks’ theories of mind and behavior. Psychol Sci Premack D, Woodruff G. 1978. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of
8:268–274. mind? Behav Brain Sci 4:515–526.
2480 AMERICAN JOURNAL OF MEDICAL GENETICS PART A

Premack D, Woodruff G. 1979. Chimpanzee problem comprehension: Sparrevohn R, Howie PM. 1995. Theory of mind in children with autistic
Insufficient evidence. Science 206:1201–1202. disorder: Evidence of developmental progression and the role of verbal
ability. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 36:249–263.
Prior M, Dahlstrom B, Squires TL. 1990. Autistic children’s knowledge of
thinking and feeling states in other people. J Child Psychol Psychiatry Stone VE, Gerrans P. 2006. What is domain-specific about theory of mind?
31:587–601. Soc Neurosci 1:309–319.
Pylyshyn ZW. 1978. When is attribution of beliefs justified? Behav Brain Sci Surian L, Caldi S, Sperber D. 2007. Attribution of beliefs by 13-month-old
1:592–593. infants. Psychol Sci 18:580–586.
Reddy V, Morris P. 2004. Participants don’t need theories: Knowing minds Tardif T, Wellman HM, Cheung KM. 2004. False belief understanding in
in engagement. Theory Psychol 14:647–665. Cantonese-speaking children. J Child Lang 31:779–800.
Repacholi BM, Gopnik A. 1997. Early reasoning about desires: Evidence Volkmar FR. 2011. Understanding the social brain in autism. Dev Psycho-
from 14- and 18-month-olds. Dev Psychol 33:12–21. biol 53:428–434.
Rizzolatti G, Arbib MA. 1998. Language within our grasp. Trends in Vonèche J, Vidal F. 1985. Jean Piaget and the child psychologist. Synthese
Neurosciences 21:188–194. 65:121–138.
Rizzolatti G, Fadiga L, Gallese V, Fogassi L. 1996. Premotor cortex and the Voracek M, Dressler SG. 2006. Lack of correlation between digit ratio
recognition of motor actions. Brain Res Cogn Brain Res 3:131–141. (2D:4D) and Baron-Cohen’s “Reading the Mind in the Eyes” test,
empathy, systematizing, and autism-spectrum quotients in a general
Rizzolatti G, Fogassi L, Gallese V. 2001. Neurophysiological mechanisms
population sample. Pers Individ Differ 41:1481–1491.
underlying the understanding and imitation of action. Nat Rev Neurosci
2:661–670. Vorstman JA, Ophoff RA. 2013. Genetic causes of developmental disorders.
Curr Opin Neurol 26:128–136.
Rogers S. 2009. What are infants teaching us about autism in infancy?
Autism Res 2:125–137. Vorstman JA, Morcus ME, Duijff SN, Klaassen PW, Heineman-de Boer JA,
Beemer FA, Swaab H, Kahn RS, van Engeland H. 2006. The 22q11.2
Sato D, Lionel AC, Leblond CS, Prasad A, Pinto D, Walker S, O’Connor I, deletion in children: High rate of autistic disorders and early onset
Russell C, Drmic IE, Hamdan FF, Michaud JL, Endris V, Roeth R, of psychotic symptoms. J Am Acad Child Adolesc Psychiatry 45:1104–
Delorme R, Huguet G, Leboyer M, Rastam M, Gillberg C, Lathrop M, 1113.
Stavropoulos DJ, Anagnostou E, Weksberg R, Fombonne E, Zwaigen-
baum L, Fernandez BA, Roberts W, Rappold GA, Marshall CR, Bour- Wahi S, Johri R. 1994. Questioning a universal theory of mind: Mental-real
geron T, Szatmari P, Scherer SW. 2012a. SHANK1 deletions in males with distinctions made by Indian children. J Genet Psychol 155:503–510.
autism spectrum disorder. Am J Hum Genet 90:879–887. Williams BT, Gray KM, Tonge BJ. 2012. Teaching emotion recognition
Sato W, Toichi M, Uono S, Kochiyama T. 2012b. Impaired social brain skills to young children with autism: A randomized controlled trial of
network for processing dynamic facial expressions in autism spectrum an emotion training programme. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 53:1268–
disorders. BMC Neurosci 1313:99. 1276.

Savage-Rumbaugh ES, Rumbaugh D, Boysen S. 1978. SArah’ problems of Wimmer H, Perner J. 1983. Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and
comprehension. Behav Brain Sci 4:555–557. constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding
of deception. Cognition 13:103–128.
Searle JR. 1990. Consciousness, explanatory inversion, and cognitive
science [target article]. Behav Brain Sci 13:585–642. Yanagi K, Kaname T, Wakui K, Hashimoto O, Fukushima Y, Naritomi K.
2012. Identification of four novel synonymous substitutions in the X-
Shahaeian A, Peterson CC, Slaughter V, Wellman HM. 2011. Culture and linked genes neuroligin 3 and neuroligin 4X in Japanese patients with
the sequence of steps in theory of mind development. Dev Psychol autistic spectrum disorder. Autism Res Treat ID724072:1–5.
47:1239–1247.
Yirmiya N, Erel O, Shaked M, Solomonica-Levi D. 1998. Meta-analyses
Sharrock W, Coulter J. 2004. ToM A critical commentary. Theory Psychol comparing theory of mind abilities of individuals with mental retarda-
14:579–600. tion, and normally developing individuals. Psychol Bull 124:283–307.
Shrout PE. 1998. Measurement reliability and agreement in psychiatry. Stat Zelazo PD, Burack JA, Benedetto E, Frye D. 1996. Theory of mind and rule
Meth Med Res 7:301–317. use in individuals with Down’s syndrome: A test of the uniqueness and
Skafidas E, Testa R, Zantomio D, Chana G, Everall IP, Pantelis C. 2012. specificity claims. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 37:479–484.
Predicting the diagnosis of autism spectrum disorder using gene pathway
Zielinski BA, Anderson JS, Froehlich AL, Prigge MB, Nielsen JA, Cooper-
analysis. Mol Psychiatry Sep 11 [Epub ahead of print].
rider JR, Cariello AN, Fletcher PT, Alexander AL, Lange N, Bigler ED,
Smalley SL. 1991. Genetic influences in autism. Psychiatr Clin N Am Lainhart JE. 2012. scMRI reveals large-scale brain network abnormalities
14:125–139. in autism. PLoS ONE 7:e49172.
Copyright of American Journal of Medical Genetics. Part A is the property of John Wiley &
Sons, Inc. and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv
without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print,
download, or email articles for individual use.

You might also like