Kuhn, Lakatos, and Laudan: Applications in The History of Physics and Psychology

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 15

Kuhn, Lakatos, and Laudan

Applications in the History of Physics and Psychology


Barry Gholson and Peter Barker
Memphis State University

ABSTRACT." Kuhnians depict the history of any the history of physics and psychology are used to
scientific discipline as a succession of incommensu- illustrate the strengths and weaknesses of each ac-
rable paradigms. Empirical work done in one para- count.
digm is of little relevance to another, and comparisons
of paradigms on such familiar grounds as experi- Kuhn's Ideas
mental adequacy are said to be inconclusive. Different
According to Kuhn (1962) the history of any science
paradigms do not agree on what constitutes knowl-
reflects two distinct types of activities, which he
edge or the meaning of truth. The recent work of
other philosophers of science, such as Lakatos and called "normal science" and "revolutionary science"
Laudan, however, leads to expectations about the (Krasner & Houts, 1984; Popper, 1970; Weimer &
Palermo, 1973; Williams, 1970). The first of these,
history of a scientific discipline that are quite different
from Kuhn's. In this article, the authors show that normal science, involves long periods of calm in
Lakatos's and Laudan's accounts provide more ve- which the scientific community works to broaden
ridical analyses than popularized Kuhnian versions and deepen the explanatory scope of a theoretical
account based on a single set of fundamental beliefs.
when applied to episodes in the history of physics
For the most part, these beliefs are not questioned.
and psychology. Although different research programs
Revolutionary science occurs during brief periods
(paradigms) have regularly competed in both domains
of chaos, when the fundamental beliefs that previ-
of inquiry, scientific progress in both has been ra-
ously supported normal science are jettisoned and
tional critical experiments have been performed
replaced. To identify these sets of fundamental beliefs,
(that is, programs are not incommensurable), and
research programs themselves evolve in ways not which Pepper (1942)dubbed world hypotheses, Kuhn
used the term paradigm. Paradigms were taken to
predicted by Kuhn's account.
include unique combinations of ontology, episte-
mology, and methodology (Kuhn, 1962, pp. 4-5).
According to Kuhn, the beliefs constituting a
In this article we present a brief review, analysis, paradigm are so fundamental that they are immune
and application of some nonpositivist accounts of from empirical testing (1962, Ch. 3). Experimental
science and scientific change proposed since the failures may lead to the rejection of specific theories,
early 1960s. The individuals most prominently iden- but the paradigm itself remains untouched and thus
tiffed with these accounts are Kuhn (1962), Lakatos directs the construction of new theories. Because
(1970, 1978), and Laudan (1977, 1981a). We will the paradigm determines the way scientists make
show that the view commonly attributed to Kuhn, sense of the world, without it there is nothing about
although heuristically compelling, contains important which to construct theories. The occasional replace-
features that are inaccurate when applied to historical ment of one paradigm by another is, therefore, a
developments in physics, the psychology of learning, cataclysmic event. In a sense, the world of the old
and mediation theory. The account offered by Lak- paradigm is destroyed with it, and a new world is
atos (1970) provides an attractive solution to some born with its successor. This process, which repre-
of the difficulties posed by Kuhn's analysis but has sents the most spectacular type of scientific change,
liabilities of its own. These are remedied by Laudan is called a "scientific revolution." Examples include
(1977), who provided a critical synthesis of the the Copernican revolution, which replaced the world
accounts offered by Kuhn and Lakatos while making of Aristotle with that of Newton, and Einstein's later
a number of original contributions. In this article, replacement of Newton's world.
first Lakatos's ideas are outlined against a backdrop Two remarkable features separate Kuhn's ac-
of Kuhn's position. Next, some difficulties in Laka- count of science from those that preceded it. First,
tos's account are identified, and last, the solutions Kuhn removed experimental evidence from the cen-
offered by Laudan are described. Applications in tral place it occupied in earlier accounts. He denied

July 1985 • American Psychologist 755


Copyright 1985 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 0003-066X/85/$00.75
Vol. 40, No. 7, 755-769
that experimental evidence plays a decisive role in their implications. Different world views involve different
the most important kind of scientific change, when understanding of what is knowledge and hence the meaning
one paradigm replaces another (1962, Ch. 12). Sec- of truth. (p. 144)
ond, he argued that it is impossible to claim the Reese and Overton drew upon two main sources:
objective superiority of one paradigm over any other. Pepper (1942) and Kuhn (1962).
This is because the rules used to appraise scientific In the present article, the concern is not to
procedures--and experimental results--are supplied clarify Kuhn's theory of science. Kuhn himself has
by the paradigms themselves, with different rules attempted this (1970, postscript; 1977, Chs. 1 l - 13)
supplied by each. Judgments based on such rules, with little or no success in preventing the proliferation
then, would favor the paradigm from which they of misreadings of his work. Indeed, these misreadings
were selected. If no rules exist apart from specific are now so widespread that they have assumed a life
paradigms, there is no neutral standpoint from of their own. (For reviews, see Peterson, 1981, and
which to judge among rivals. Because arguments Gutting, 1980, pp. 1-21.)
against a rival paradigm talk past the standards
recognized by the rival (Kuhn, 1962, p. 94), Kuhn
concluded that paradigms are incommensurable.
Kuhnian Ideas
That is, there is no c o m m o n basis for comparing It is perhaps useful to introduce a terminological
one with another. Scientific revolutions are, therefore, distinction at this point. We will refer to "Kuhn's
not rule governed. To those who equated rationality ideas" when we believe the point in question can
with rules, this conclusion was tantamount to the reasonably be attributed to Kuhn himself, on the
claim that scientific change is not rational (for basis of his original work together with the clarifi-
example, Manicas & Secord, 1983; McGuire, 1982; cations he has published. We will refer to "Kuhnian
Scheffier, 1967; Suppe, 1977). Correspondingly, the ideas" when we believe the point in question to be
account of consensus formation Kuhn offered in generally associated with Kuhn's name, despite de-
place of rule-governed change was dismissed by nials on his part. An important example is the
some as an appeal to mob psychology (for example, frequent identification of paradigms with world hy-
Lakatos, 1970). potheses (Pepper, 1942) or worldviews (e.g., Palermo,
The problem of incommensurability and the 1984). Such an equation is explicit, for example, in
connected charge of irrationalism prevented many the work of Reese and Overton (1970) quoted above
philosophers of science from accepting Kuhn's ideas. (Overton & Reese, 1973). Despite initial evidence
Quite the reverse was true among scientists, partic- in favor of this reading o f " p a r a d i g m " (Kuhn, 1962,
ularly social scientists (Krasner & Hours, 1984; pp. 111-135), in his later work Kuhn clearly rejected
Murray, 1984; Palermo, 1971; Reese & Overton, the equation of paradigms with worldviews (1970,
1970; Weimer, 1974). The word paradigm rapidly pp. 174-210, 1977, Ch. I1). The identification of
became part of the jargon of working scientists, paradigms with worldviews will therefore be referred
many of whom seemed quite happy to accept extreme to as a Kuhnian idea. The strongest version of the
versions of the incommensurability thesis. Psychol- incommensurability thesis, the claim that empirical
ogists, sociologists, political scientists, and economists work in one paradigm has no relevance to other
adopted Kuhn's assumptions, pigeonholing ideas paradigms, is also clearly Kuhnian rather than
and theories by claiming the relativity of scientific Kuhn's (Gutting, 1980, pp. 1-21). Despite their
truth (see Gutting, 1980, for an extensive bibliogra- repudiation by Kuhn himself, these ideas, and others
phy). Consider, for example, an influential article already sketched, will be familiar to any reader of
published by Reese and Overton (1970) in which the psychological literature in the last 15 years. In
they concluded that this article the point of attack is the ideas set out
above that are, rightly or wrongly, associated with
pretheoretical models have a pervasive effect upon theory
construction. Theories built upon radically different models Kuhn's name in the psychological literature.
are logically independent and cannot be assimilated to Beginning in the late 1960s, a variety of new
each other. They reflect representations of different ways models of scientific methodology were proposed in
of looking at the world and as such are incompatible in a conscious attempt to improve upon Kuhnian ideas
and, more specifically, to avoid both the problems
The authors gratefullyacknowledgethe critical comments on an associated with the incommensurability of paradigms
earlier draft of this article provided by Harold I. Brown, Arthur and with irrationalism, although accepting Kuhn's
C. Houts, Larry Laudan, Frank C. Leeming, Edwin Koshland, notion that some aspects of science are relatively
David Morgan, Robert A. Neimeyer,Hayne W. Reese, Robert N. immune from empirical refutation (Lakatos, 1968,
Vidulich, and John H. Whiteley.
Requests for reprints should be sent to Barry Gholson, 1970, 1978; Laudan, 1977, 1981a; Stegmuller, 1976).
Department of Psychology,Memphis State University,Memphis, In order to demonstrate these developments, it will
Tennessee 38152. be useful to consider Lakatos's ideas before Laudan's.

756 July 1985 • American Psychologist


Lakatos appraisals may become positive and vice versa. A
single program may be progressive in one era,
Lakatos replaced the Kuhnian paradigm with an degenerating in a second, and return to progressive-
entity called a "research program," which involves ness in a third (Lakatos, 1970). Consequently, choices
a succession of theories. The theories are linked by among programs are less than final. If one program
a common "hard core" of shared commitments. is progressive whereas another is degenerating, the
Each theory in the sequence involves a new and momentary choice between them is clear. However,
more detailed articulation of these commitments. A the choice may be revised if the weaker program
"protective belt" of dispensable hypotheses shelters undergoes a new spurt of theoretical or empirical
the hard core from immediate empirical refutation. progress. In most cases, though, even the momentary
Dispensable features, such as simplifying assump- choice is not so clear cut. Rather, the choice is
tions, are modified by successive theories in the usually between research programs that are pro-
program, but core assumptions remain intact. The gressing, but at different rates.
third important characteristic of any research pro- Kuhnian scientific revolutions are characterized
gram is its ability to stimulate the development of by Lakatos as the defeat of one research program
more complex and adequate theories. This capacity by another. A few historical cases, in which one
for development, which Lakatos called the "heuris- major scientific system was universally abandoned
tic," is taken as an objective feature of the program. in favor of an incompatible rival, may appear to fit
As research programs mature, the most com- the Kuhnian model quite well. The model does not,
mon reason for replacing a theory is an experimental however, provide a veridical account of most in-
failure (Lakatos, 1970). An acceptable new theory stances of program replacement and, as will be seen
must both accommodate the successes of its prede- below, even in the few aforementioned historical
cessor and explain the data that brought the earlier cases its applicability is problematic. Although the
theory into question. In addition, a really good revisability of judgment concerning whether a pro-
theory does even more: It leads to new predictions gram is progressing or degenerating makes it difficult
that are verified experimentally. Research programs to supply final appraisals to any contemporary sci-
composed of successor theories that meet these goals e n c e - r e c a l l i n g Kuhn's incommensurability prob-
are said to be "progressive." lem--Lakatos's model shows a clear way to make
Lakatos distinguished between empirical prog- long-term choices among rival research strategies.
ress and theoretical progress. A new theory is theo- Lakatos's view of history was very different
retically progressive if it leads to new predictions. It from the Kuhnian one. Lakatos assumed that the
is empirically progressive if some of the new predic- simultaneous existence of several research programs
tions receive empirical support. Because research is the norm. Rival programs may contribute elements
programs involve sequences of theories, the terms to each other, and degenerating programs are some-
may be applied to programs as well as to individual times revived. Although Kuhn did not specifically
theories. A progressive program is not always pro- state that a particular science could contain only
gressive at both levels simultaneously. The relative one paradigm at a given time, many drew that
independence of the two kinds of progress explains (Kuhnian) conclusion from his account (e.g. Schaff-
why the theoretical side of the program is, in the ner, 1972; Watkins, 1970). The incommensurability
short term, immune to empirical failure. Scientists thesis seems to imply that it is impossible for there
frequently disregard apparent counterevidence in to be any real continuity in content from one
the expectation that later work will convert it to paradigm to the next. Also, once superseded, a
empirical support, provided the program is theoret- paradigm should not reappear (Barker, 1980). Last
ically progressive and shows some empirical progress. and most important, Kuhn denied that the replace-
If a program is not progressive, it is said to be ment of one paradigm by another constituted prog-
"degenerating." This may mean that the program ress. For Lakatos, however, the appraisal of theoretical
has temporarily ceased to yield new predictions or and empirical progress permitted a reasoned pref-
empirical successes. But if empirical anomalies can erence for one research program over its rivals in
be met only by ad hoc maneuvers rather than by the most important historical cases.
introducing new successful theories, or if the new To illustrate these differences, a brief review of
theories raise more problems than they solve, then the Copernican and Einsteinian revolutions from
the heuristic may be exhausted and a new research the perspective of Lakatos's methodology is presented
program needed. below. The same account will then be applied to
The appraisal of a program as progressive or recent episodes in the history of psychology. Finally,
degenerating, though, is not absolute. A judgment some difficulties with Lakatos's account will be
is made at one point in time, based upon its recent identified, and Laudan's improved account will be
performance. Given sufficient time, however, negative illustrated by applications in physics and psychology.

July 1985 • American Psychologist 757


Applications to Physics concept and dispensing with theoretical entities like
atoms, ions, and molecules (Holt, 1977). These three
From a Kuhnian viewpoint, the Copernican revo. programs were succeeded by the Einsteinian pro-
lution occurred when Aristotle's paradigm was re- gram, involving the relativity theories, and by the
placed by Newton's. There is a clear separation in quantum physics program that led through the early
fundamental commitments in the two paradigms. theories of Bohr, to the theories of Heisenberg,
Aristotle's universe is finite and geocentric, whereas Schrodinger, and Dirac.
Newton's universe is infinite, and planetary motions Rather than depicting the Einsteinian revolution
are heliocentric. From Lakatos's perspective, however, as the defeat of Newton's research program, it would
not two but three large-scale scientific systems were be more accurate to say that Lorentz's electromag-
in competition during the 17th century. Aristotle's netic program had achieved a position of dominance
research program was first challenged during the by the opening years of the 20th century and was
1630s by that of Descartes. Newton's program ap- then overtaken by Einstein's, which became strongly
peared during the 1680s as a rival to Descartes's, progressive, both theoretically and empirically, almost
and the revolution ended in the defeat of both immediately after its founding in 1905 (Zahar, 1976).
Aristotle and Descartes by Newton (Lakatos, Although Lorentz's program was also progressive,
1978). the relativity program defeated it by being consis-
The programs of both Descartes and Newton tently more progressive. Einstein's program also
were, of course, progressive relative to that of Aris- assimilated the Lorentz transformations from its
totle. Both could account for the motions of comets rival, illustrating again a fruitful exchange between
and the tides, whereas Aristotle's program could rival programs.
not, and each made new predictions not made by In the first two decades of the 20th century,
its contemporary rival. The Cartesians, for example, quantum physics defeated the phenomenological
could explain why the moon always kept the same program and replaced Newtonian microphysics. But
face toward the earth and why all planets revolved the mathematics and ontology of the new program
in the same direction, whereas the Newtonians could were quite incompatible with the mathematics and
explain how the planets exerted forces on each other ontology of the relativity program. These programs
(Aiton, 1972). These differences resulted from dif- coexist to the present day. Fruitful exchange between
ferent hard cores. The core of the Cartesian program, them is dramatically illustrated by Dirac's 1928
for example, specified action by contact and explicitly theory of the electron, which was obtained by re-
denied the action-at-a-distance, gravitational concept quiring relativistic invariance in quantum theory,
that was central to the core of the Newtonian despite its incompatible ontology. Although the
program. quantum physics program remained strongly pro-
Newton's program also included elements from gressive, the relativity program became stagnant in
the older Cartesian program, such as action by the 1940s and 1950s, only to be revived by the
contact. This is an example of a fruitful exchange advent of radio astronomy. The discovery of new
between programs, which would not be expected classes of celestial objects, such as pulsars and
according to the incommensurability thesis. Also, quasars, gave new impetus to theoretical work and
empirical evidence played a crucial role in the led, in turn, to new empirical progress. The highly
exchange between the Newtonians and Cartesians, unequal distribution of activity between the two
particularly predictions about the tides, the moon, programs, which had strongly favored the quantum
and planetary motion. This evidence, of course, program, was redressed in the 1960s, and illustrates
eventually led to the demise of the Cartesian pro- Lakatos's description of initial success followed by
gram. stagnation and revival. This is, of course, in contrast
Themes o f plurality, fruitful exchanges among to the all-or-nothing kind of confrontation suggested
programs, and the role of demonstrated progress in by Kuhnians.
program replacement are also illustrated by the Numerous historical developments in the field
historical events surrounding the eventual success of of physics, then, are decisively at odds with Kuhn's
Einstein's program. At least five research programs (and the Kuhnian) model of scientific change. Lak-
were involved in the Einsteinian revolution. First, atos's account provides a powerful conceptual
o f course, was the Newtonian program, which in framework that is, like Kuhn's, derived from the
the late 19th century was challenged by a program analysis of historical episodes in physics. Unlike
championed by Lorentz (Zahar, 1976). Lorentz's Kuhn, however, Lakatos presented a methodology
program took electromagnetism to be more funda- that both (a) avoids the problems of incommensura-
mental than mechanics. A second rival, championed bility and irrationalism and (b) demonstrates that
by Ostwald and Mach, attempted to develop a purely empirical evidence is the final arbiter among com-
phenomenological physics, taking energy as a basic peting research programs.

758 July 1985 • American Psychologist


Applications to the Psychology by about 1930, the conditioning program clearly
of Learning became progressive and the cognitive program de-
generated, in Lakatos's technical sense, in the ensuing
Lakatos, of course, generated his methodology in a decade. The conditioning program's progress may
conscious attempt to improve upon Kuhn's account be illustrated by two central examples: In each case
of historical developments (mostly) in the science of it resolved experimental problems posed by its rival
physics. Thus the model's robustness and utility can and made new predictions that its competitor could
be demonstrated best by applications to events in not make that were confirmed experimentally.
other disciplines. Because developments in the psy- The conditioning program was presented with
chology o f learning during the past half century a problem by Lashley's (1929) description of the
have involved competition between research pro- systematic response patterns that rats exhibited prior
grams that are said to be based on different "world to criterion in a simple learning task. He called
hypotheses" (Pepper, 1942) or "paradigms" (Kuhn, these response patterns "attempted solutions" and
1962, 1970), and because the clash has been taken showed that they had no effect on later acquisition
to support a Kuhnian account of the history of of the correct response. Krechevsky elaborated on
psychology (e.g., Palermo, 197 l; Reese, 1977; Reese Lashley's work, studying systematic response patterns
& Overton, 1970; Weimer & Palermo, 1973), this in a variety of learning tasks. In a series of research
history presents a fruitful case for analysis. reports, Krechevsky (1932a, 1932b, 1933, 1937;
As is well known, conditioning (i.e., associa- Tolman, 1932) contended that such response patterns
tionist, behavioral) theory, which is said to be based constituted the rats' guesses about the solution, or
on a "mechanistic" worldview or paradigm, was "hypotheses." He described them in the language of
firmly established in the psychology of learning by the cognitive program.
the early 1930s. The core commitments of the Conditioning theorists were quick to respond
program include the assumption that learning is to this challenge presented by the cognitive program.
achieved through the conditioning and extinction of Although many contributed to the dispute on both
specific stimulus-response pairs. The organism is sides, the general progress of the conditioning pro-
said to be reactive; that is, change is induced through gram may be illustrated by some of Spence's (1936,
the application of external force (reinforcement). 1937, 1940) work. Spence argued, convincingly, that
A competing program, which is said to be the systematic response patterns Krechevsky called
based on an "organismic" paradigm, was also well hypotheses were an uninteresting by-product of the
established by about 1930. The core of this program animal's conditioning history. Because all behavior
includes the assumptions that learning is achieved was assumed to result from conditioning and extinc-
through testing rules or hypotheses, that the organism tion processes (a core commitment of the program),
is cognitively active, and that change is induced by systematic response patterns were of no intrinsic
internal transformations. This program, which pro- interest. In one report, for example, Spence (1936)
duced representatives as diverse as gestalt theory, presented a reasonably precise mathematical account
Piaget's theory, and some versions of information in which he showed that conditioning theory not
processing theory, can be referred to as the "cogni- only predicted the occurrence of systematic response
tive" program. patterns, but that it also predicted which specific
Several points are emphasized in this sketch of patterns (e.g., position alternation, position prefer-
the rivalry between the programs that began in the ence) would occur and when they would occur
early 1930s. First, the two large-scale programs during the course of acquisition. Because neither
coexisted during most of the past half century. Krechevsky's theory nor any other in the cognitive
Second, the experimental commensurability of the program could make these predictions, Spetace's
programs is demonstrated by events in the mid- work illustrates a classic example of a research
1930s and in the early 1960s. Finally, the cognitive program overcoming an empirical anomaly in a
program showed an abrupt and progressive revival content-increasing fashion. That is, the program
in about 1960, after 20 years of degeneration. showed both theoretical and empirical progress ac-
Although both programs were well established cording to Lakatos's definition.
A second representative of the cognitive pro-
t The authors are aware that a number of scholars have
questioned the applicabilityto psychologyof Kuhn's or any other gram, gestalt theory, came into conflict with the
account of scientific growth and development based on the conditioning program at about the same time in the
physical sciences (Briskman, 1972; Gr/inbaum, 1979; Koch, context of "transposition" learning. For example,
1976, 1981; Peterson, 1981; Warren, 1971; Watson, 1977). This consider a two-choice task in which the animal
important and valid global issue is not addressed in this article. learns to choose the larger of two circles (10 cm vs.
Rather, the article simply demonstratesthe advantagesof Lakatos's
and Laudan's views in the examples drawn from the period of 15 cm in diameter). Once some learning criterion is
learning theory development,approximately 1930 to 1970. met, the 10-cm stimulus is removed and, in a

July 1985 • American Psychologist 759


transfer task, the 15-cm circle is paired with a 20- trial response of each new problem was needed to
cm circle. Given a free choice, animals nearly always achieve solution. Once the learning set was estab-
chose the 20-cm stimulus. Thus, they appear to lished, each monkey showed essentially perfect per-
make a relational response ("choose the larger"). It formance on consecutive problems, even though the
is a core commitment of the conditioning program, solution to each was different. This demonstration
however, that the stimulus-response bond is estab- was a clear challenge to one of conditioning theory's
lished between a specific stimulus (the 15-cm circle) core assumptions (cf. Reese, 1964; Restle, 1958);
and response. Transposition data were presented as that is, that learning occurs incrementally through
a critical refutation of the core of the conditioning the conditioning and extinction of specific stimulus-
program (K/Shier, 1918/1938; Kliiver, 1933), and response associations.
the anomaly remained an embarrassment to condi- Harlow also observed (cf. Lashley, 1929) that
tioning theory for more than a decade. several types of systematic response sequences (po-
In 1937, however, Spence showed that if two of sition alternation, stimulus perseveration) dominated
the theory's basic mechanisms, habit and inhibition, the monkey's behavior before learning set was
were expanded to include the notion of generaliza- achieved. He labeled these response sequences "error
tion, conditioning theory predicted the transposition factors." Because they appeared to mask the learning
data just described. In addition, Spence showed that process, Harlow concluded that it was important to
conditioning theory made a new prediction concern- chart the time course of each during acquisition.
ing transposition that gestalt theory did not make Initially Harlow identified four error factors.
and that the prediction was confirmed experimen- Each occurred in some monkeys, and different ones
tally. To illustrate, suppose that after learning to dominated behavior in successive phases of acquisi-
choose the 15-cm over the 10-cm circle, some animals tion. In the next few years Harlow, and other primate
are presented with the 15-cm versus 20-cm pairing, researchers, performed error-factor analyses on data
but others are presented with 20-cm versus 25-cm from a variety of learning-set tasks. Consequently,
circles. These are called "near" and "far" tests, the number of published accounts increased quickly,
respectively. Gestalt theory predicts relational re- as did the list of error factors. Each article, however,
sponses ("choose the larger") in both tests, but seemed to identify a different set, and those identified
conditioning theory predicts choice of the larger were, for the most part, not related to each other.
only in the 15-cm versus 20-cm pairing. The empir- Thus, the domain had become somewhat chaotic by
ical data, of course, supported conditioning theory, the late 1950s, when Levine (1959, 1963) defined
and the program again overcame an anomaly by error factors in a way that permitted a standard
demonstrating both theoretical and empirical prog- mode of measurement and provided a quantitative
ress.2 theory from which the measurement was derived.
Although occasional experiments were per- Levine enlarged the class of response patterns mea-
formed, gestalt approaches to learning, like hypoth- sured, redefined how each was identified, and in-
esis theory, entered a long period of degeneration. cluded a response pattern that corresponded to the
Skinner's (1938) classic was soon published, as was acquisition of learning set (i.e., correct responding).
Hull's (1943). The conditioning program remained Because the label error factor was not appropriate
theoretically and empirically progressive, reaching for the entire set of response patterns, Levine adopted
its zenith in the 1940s and 1950s. Little was heard the term hypothesis from the old cognitive program.
from the cognitive program for more than two He also emphasized that the term referred to a
decades. determinate of a systematic response pattern and
By the early 1950s, however, two readily iden- not the response pattern itself.
tifiable movements, one within the mainstream of A second contribution to the revival of the
the conditioning program and the other on its pe- cognitive program involved a group of conditioning
riphery, were poised to contribute to the revival of theorists (e.g., Bush & Mosteller, 1955; Estes &
the cognitive program in about 1960. One of these Burke, 1953; Restle, 1955) who elaborated contiguity
began with Harlow's (1949, 1950) demonstration of theory (Guthrie, 1935, 1942), or stimulus sampling
learning set in monkeys. He presented his animals theory, into what is commonly known as "mathe-
with a long series of short two-choice problems. A matical learning theory." These theorists successfully
learning set was said to be acquired when the applied their probabilistic versions of conditioning
monkey's solution to each new problem was im- theory to numerous tasks and subject populations,
mediate, that is, when feedback from only the first- ranging from rats traversing runways to college
students solving complex concept identification
2Although it was not apparent at the time, later analyses problems. The program made rapid theoretical and
revealed that Spence's predictions were only broadly supported empirical progress, with consecutive statements of
(see Reese, 1968, pp. 273-308). the theory broadening its scope and quickly resolving

760 July 1985 • American Psychologist


the defects of earlier versions (e.g., Bourne & Restle, in retrospect, a reasonable restatement places this
1959). The theory was mathematically cast, rigorous, set of response-determining cues in some repertoire
and clear in its implications. Thus, it set a demanding inside the subject, to be selected and tested until
standard for competitors. one is sampled that results in solution. Restle (1962,
Beginning in the late 1950s, however, several 1965), another leading figure in the mathematical
developments occurred, mostly within the main- learning movement, announced this innovation in
stream of mathematical learning theory itself, that 1962. He noted that his model was similar to
eventually persuaded its leading proponents to aban- Krechevsky's, and because conditioned cues no longer
don the conditioning program in favor of the cog- seemed an appropriate label for the class of response
nitive. Because full expositions are available elsewhere determinants Restle, like Levine, substituted the
(e.g., Gholson, 1980; Hilgard & Bower, 1975; term hypothesis'.
Kintsch, 1977; Levine, 1975), only a few of the Episodes in the psychology of learning, then,
events are identified here. like those in physics, more closely approximate
In 1957 Rock presented strong evidence that Lakatos's description of scientific change than the
learning, at least in college students, was an all-or- Kuhnian analysis. Several points support this con-
none rather than an incremental process. If learning clusion. The two large-scale positions clearly coex-
was not incremental, then a core commitment of isted throughout the half century in question, with
the conditioning program was suspect, no matter each showing periods of progress and degeneration.
how elegant the theories. Thus, Rock's (1957) results The experimental commensurability of the cognitive
were critically examined by many active researchers. and conditioning programs is most clearly evidenced
For example, Estes (1959, 1960), a leading figure in by the conflict in the mid-1930s, and again in the
the mathematical learning movement, investigated contributions made by conditioning theorists to the
the issue in a series of precisely designed experiments. revival of the cognitive program. These theorists
He eventually concluded, like Rock, that learning also incorporated important elements (e.g., Markov
was indeed an all-or-none process. Estes presented models) from the conditioning program into later
his findings and rejected an incremental view in cognitive accounts--although the theoretical ratio-
1960. nales eventually changed (cf. Hilgard & Bower, 1975,
A related development in mathematical learning p. 426). Finally, in order to put some of the liabilities
theory that was important to the revival of the of Lakatos's account in perspective (Laudan, 1977),
cognitive program, which is discussed in detail by it must be emphasized that the core commitments
Hilgard and Bower (1975, pp. 374-427) and by of those identified with both learning set and math-
Levine (1975, pp. 104-108), concerned the cues ematical learning theory underwent a constant evo-
sampled from trial to trial and how best to represent lution between about 1950 and 1965. Also, both
them mathematically. Early theories in the program groups of theorists eventually adopted core commit-
(e.g., Burke, Estes, & Hellyer, 1954; Bush & Mosteller, ments from the old cognitive program due, in part,
1955; Restle, 1955) assumed there were a large to the recognition that earlier conditioning theories
number of environmental cues and the sample size embodied important conceptual problems (Barker
on any given trial varied randomly. The resulting & Gholson, 1984a).
theories, however, embodied conceptual problems
that could not be ignored: The models were com-
plicated relative to the data they described, and their Laudan
probabilistic mathematical formulations were fre- Before identifying specific deficiencies in Lakatos's
quently intractable i n the absence of simplifying methodology, a brief sketch of Laudan's (1977)
assumptions that, all too often, were counterintuitive. views will be useful. Laudan replaced research pro-
Consequently, by about 1960 (e.g., Estes, 1959; grams with a super-theoretical entity called a "re-
Suppes & Atkinson, 1960) Markov models based on search tradition." A research tradition consists of a
the assumption that the number of sampled cues family of theories sharing a common ontology and
ranges from one to three were becoming common. methodology. The ontology and methodology sub-
Several advantages of these models over earlier al- sume many of the functions of Lakatos's hard core
ternatives were immediately apparent. The most and heuristic, respectively, but both are seen to
important of these are that (a) they are mathemati- change as a research tradition evolves. Also, a wider
cally more tractable and (b) they predict all-or-none range of factors than those proposed by Lakatos is
learning (Bower, 1962; Trabasso, 1963). used to appraise theories and research traditions. In
The final event in this scenario involved a addition to empirical factors, Laudan explicitly
restatement of stimulus sampling theory, which says, identified conceptual factors as important in theory
of course, that conditioned cues from the environ- appraisal, independent of a theory's experimental
ment are sampled and determine responses. Thus, success or failure. A discussion of several deficiencies

July 1985 • American Psychologist 761


in Lakatos's position clearly demonstrates these dif- the behavior of children in both stages of develop-
ferences. ment, Kuenne did not explore the mechanisms that
Lakatos's requirement that core commitments accounted for the change.
pass unchanged through successor theories in a The Kendlers (H. H. Kendler & Kendler, 1962;
research program is unrealistic for a number of T. S. Kendler & Kendler, 1959), however, presented
reasons. It has proven impossible to locate core a more detailed account. They posited, as did Reese
principles of the required sort for some of the most (1962), that the young child's behavior, like the rat's,
crucial episodes in the history of physics. In the case may be accounted for by a single stimulus-response
of the Copernican revolution, for example, it has association. To account for the older child's behavior,
not been possible to locate even one core principle however, two stimulus-response associations must
accepted by Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, and Newton be chained together. The second link was said to be
(cf. Lakatos & Zahar, 1976). Yet, clearly these necessary because the child's verbal processes become
scientists were developing a single coherent body of involved in the behavioral sequence, mediating be-
ideas, as indicated by their own statements and tween environmental input and behavioral output.
those of their successors. Thus the older child or adult uses covert verbal
For Lakatos, a core commitment is part of a labels to classify environmental cues by dimensional
theory that is actually used to make predictions. In properties and the covert labels control observable
the context of prediction, a core commitment's behavior.
status is no different from any other part of the The next developments in the theory involved
theory. Any plausible candidate for historical iden- a partial abandonment of the core of the conditioning
tification as a core commitment, therefore, must program. Later theoretical statements by mediation
have been explicitly stated by the scientist who used theorists (e.g., Kendler, 1979; Reese, 1972, 1977;
it to make predictions. Thus, unless we deny that White, 1965) abandoned the assumption that all
we know how Copernicus or Newton made predic- learning must be accounted for in terms of condi-
tions, we must assume that the core commitments tioning processes. Instead, there are said to be two
of their research program changed with successor modes of learning, one involving conditioning and
theories. the other cognitive processes. Younger children learn
mostly through conditioning processes, but older
Changing Core Commitments children and adults learn by testing hypotheses. This
In psychology, of course, the aforementioned changes is another instance, then, of the cognitive and con-
in mathematical learning theory and in error factor ditioning programs interacting fruitfully (cf. Kuhn,
theory are clear examples of changing cores. In 1962) and of core commitments undergoing major
mathematical learning theory, the change is from change with consecutive theories in a program (cf.
probabilistic models that predict incremental learning Lakatos, 1970).
to Markov models that predict all-or-none learning, This analysis of core commitments highlights
and from responses dictated by conditioned cues a second difficulty with Lakatos's account. To qualify
located in the environment to hypotheses located in as part of the core, a statement must be used as
the organism that are tested and rejected until one part of a theory in making predictions. Thus, it
is sampled that results in solution. In error factor must be explicitly stated. But the underlying meta-
theory, systematic response patterns that impeded physical principles identified by Pepper and discussed
learning became determinants of behavior, or hy- by Kuhn were neither explicitly stated nor used in
potheses, that were selectively evaluated until the making predictions. Despite their obvious and im-
correct one was located. portant role in science, then, they are not plausibly
As a further example of changing core com- identified as constituents of theories. According to
mitments with theory development, consider media- Lakatos, of course, a research program's core is
tion theory, which had its beginnings in Kuenne's immune from direct experimental refutation and
(1946) suggestion that language alters basic learning thus is functionally metaphysical. But core principles
processes in children when they reach age six or must be explicitly stated and used to make predic-
seven. She found that young children, just like tions. Thus, if the underlying metaphysical principles
animal subjects, exhibit transposition on "near" that created so much interest in Kuhn's paradigms
tests, but fail to do so on "far" tests. Children older are to be admitted into science at all, according to
than six or seven, however, show transposition re- Lakatos's model they must be identified with the
sponses on both tests. Kuenne concluded that her shadowy "heuristic" rather than the sharply defined
findings implied "two developmental stages so far as core.
the relation of verbal responses to overt choice Laudan offered a two-part solution to these
behavior is concerned" (1946, p. 488). Although she difficulties. First, he observed that core principles
assumed that conditioning processes accounted for do not pass unchanged through successive theories

762 July 1985 • American Psychologist


in a program. Although some continuity is needed, assumption that light was a transverse wave in a
no element of a research tradition is so essential material medium called "aether." The aether was
that it cannot be changed. It is relatively easy to assumed to have the physical properties of an elastic
find principles shared by Copernicus and Galileo, solid. This permitted the application of existing
by Copernicus and Kepler, or by Kepler and Galileo methodology, taken from the study of solids in
separately, or by Newton and each predecessor as Newtonian mechanics, in developing detailed models
the program evolved. These are not the same prin- of the aether. Because light traveled only in aether,
ciples in every case, but all share some principle in it was assumed that aether pervaded all space and
common with other members of the group. Similarly, all transparent objects. Thus, in order to derive the
consecutive statements of mathematical learning, familiar laws of reflection and refraction, it was
error factor, and mediation theory share some com- necessary that a decision be made about the differ-
monalities. For Laudan, then, the principles of the ence between the aether inside and the aether outside
core are not functionally metaphysical, in that they transparent objects. Two basic moves were possible:
can be modified in response to empirical testing. (a) to assume that the density of the aether was
Second, however, Laudan also recognized a constant everywhere but its elasticity varied inside
class of metaphysical propositions that a r e uniquely and outside transparent objects or (b) to assume
associated with a research tradition at any given aether's elasticity was constant everywhere but its
time. Although the metaphysical commitments may density varied inside and outside transparent objects.
change as a research program develops (Laudan, These options generated separate groups of theories,
1977, pp. 101-103), they direct research by stimu- and although the tv~ groups literally contradicted
lating the construction of theories that articulate a each other, both were articulations of an elastic-
particular ontology as they inhibit the construction solid aether (Whittaker, 1973, pp. 128-169; Schaffner,
of theories that are incompatible with that ontology. 1972, pp. 40-75). This commitment demarcated the
These principles need not be explicitly stated; indeed, elastic-solid research tradition from both the cor-
they may come to light only after prolonged (philo- puscular theories of the preceding tradition and the
sophical) analysis. Hence, these principles naturally electromagnetic theories of the subsequent tradition.
accommodate the underlying metaphysics of Pepper Similar examples of competing theory chains
or the Kuhnians. sharing a common ontology and methodology are
familiar in the recent history of psychology. Guthrie's
Theory Clusters (1935, 1942, 1959) contiguity theory (later called
A further indication that Lakatos's core commit- mathematical learning theory), HuU-Spence theory
ments are not an effective way to represent the (Hull, 1943, 1951; Spence, 1936, 1937, 1956, 1960),
underlying metaphysics identified by the Kuhnians and Skinnerian theory (Skinner, 1938, 1957, 1968)
and Pepper is the simultaneous existence of more are all conditioning theories that were in the main-
than one sequence of theories of the type Lakatos stream of the program or research tradition in its
described, all exemplifying the same set of funda- heyday. Each of the three, however, involved a
mental commitments. In Lakatos's model, a research distinct theory chain with successor theories devel-
program consists of a sequence of theories, with oped in relative isolation from the other chains (see
each successive theory better articulating the core. Guttman, 1977; Hilgard & Bower, 1975, pp. 90-
Theories within a program form chains, but never 121, 152-251; Krantz, 1971). In part, their separate
clusters or families of related theories that are viable development was due to different assumptions con-
competitors. cerning (a) the role of unobservable variables in
Research traditions (Laudan, 1977), however, theory construction, (b) the analysis of stimuli and
provide a natural way of accommodating a number responses, (c) the exact mechanisms involved in the
of theory chains within a single historical entity, formation of associations, and (d) the nature and
determined by the dominance of a particular set of role of motivation and reinforcement.
metaphysical commitments. A research tradition A second example from the recent history of
involves a set of theories (or theory chains) with a psychology involves mediation theory. At about the
common ontological and methodological base, but same time the Kendlers (e.g., H. H. Kendler &
these commitments do not rigidly determine the Kendler, 1962; Reese, 1962) presented their analysis
development of theories. Indeed, in some cases of mediation in terms of verbal processes and the
contradictory theories may be developed from the chaining of stimulus-response pairs, a second inter-
same basic commitments, as illustrated by events pretation of the mechanisms involved in mediation
from the history of physics and psychology. Consider was offered by Zeaman and House (1963). The latter
first an episode from physics. proposed that the mediational response, or mediator,
In the second quarter of the 19th century, all involved a conditioned attentional response rather
theories of light were constructed on the ontological than a verbal response. They also postulated that all

July 1985 • American Psychologist 763


learning, in lower animals as well as in humans of the theory after 1887 also requires explanation. Why
all ages, involved an attentional mediator. was one more piece of experimental evidence so
The competing theoretical positions were both important? Maxwell's program was clearly progres-
within the conditioning program. Scores, if not sive, both theoretically and empirically, for nearly
hundreds, of experiments were reported in the decade three decades prior to 1887, but was n o t accepted
following the original publications (H. H. Kendler in preference to a stagnant (or degenerating) rival.
& Kendler, 1962; Reese, 1962; Zeaman & House, According to Lakatos, this should never happen.
1963), each attempting to resolve the controversy in The solution lies in a conceptual problem.
favor of one theory or the other. The controversy Among other difficulties, Maxwell introduced a new
engendered a large n u m b e r of side issues (e.g., Gollin concept of force that conflicted with the concept in
& Rosser, 1974; Cole & Medin, 1974; White, 1970), the accepted Newtonian mechanics. In Newtonian
but the original problem was never really resolved. mechanics, physical forces acted only along straight
More recent theoretical statements representing the lines and only at the location of the object influenced
attentional position have, like those by the Kendlers by the force. Maxwell's force, however, acted along
(eg., T. S Kendler, 1979, 1981), tended to emphasize curved lines, and at all points in the space between
hypothesis-testing processes (House, 1979; Kemler, objects, as well as at locations of the objects them-
1978; Kemler, Shepp, & Foote, 1976), that is, they selves. Hertz's work provided the first convincing
have incorporated parts of the cognitive program. evidence that electrical systems produced effects
(forces) in the space surrounding them. Thus, his
Conceptual Factors in Theory Appraisal experiments were important not just as empirical
The final distinction between Lakatos's and Laudan's evidence per se, but because the detection of radio
accounts concerns the factors involved in theory waves provided the first convincing evidence bearing
appraisal. Laudan added "conceptual factors" to the on the conflict between Maxwell's concept of force
measures of progress specified by Lakatos. A theory, and the accepted Newtonian concept. With this
and hence the research tradition to which it belongs, conceptual problem resolved, Maxwell's program
may have liabilities or assets that are independent was rapidly accepted in the next few years.
of Lakatos's measures of progress. These are con- We have identified above some conceptual
ceptual factors. Examples of conceptual defects in- problems that were recognized by mathematical
clude concepts that are introduced in a circular learning theorists and that eventually led them to
manner, or novel concepts that are regarded as ill- abandon the conditioning program or tradition. Res-
founded, sometimes because they conflict with es- tle, in a personal communication to Levine (1975),
tablished notions. described some of the events that led to his own
Instances in which conceptual factors delayed transition:
the acceptance of a theory, and in which they It is true that the earlier cue-adaptation theory was quite
hastened the rejection of a theory, will illustrate successful in calculations of many experimental results.
their importance. First, consider the early history of What does not come out of that statement is the additional
Maxwell's theory of light, which eventually su- fact that the calculations were rather laborious; further-
perseded the elastic-solid tradition described above more, they did not simplify. The equations of that earlier
(Schaffner, 1972; Whittaker, 1973). Maxwell identi- theory are almost entirely intractable, and it was very
difficult to obtain even an approximate expression for the
fied light as an electromagnetic wave, unifying optics
total errors made to solution, let alone anything fancier.
with electricity and magnetism. Although he retained In the years from 1953 to about 1958, I became incredibly
the concept of aether, it was not as an elastic solid. quick at reading tables of logarithms, including reading
Maxwell presented his theory in the early 1860s and complements, and at fingering Monroe calculators. By
reformulated it several times before his death in about 1957 I was thoroughly tired of so gluey a theory.
1879, but the theory gained few adherents before In 1957 I made a desperate attempt to revise this theory
Hertz's detection of radio waves in 1887. with a complicated process, long happily forgotten, by
It would be a caricature of history to suggest which subjects compared one cue or dimension with
that the theory's acceptance followed simply from another and decided which, if either, should be deleted.
Hertz's empirical evidence, because, in fact, before At the end of my talk, Professor W. K. Estes gently
1887 Maxwell's theory had been both theoretically inquired if I was trying for the prize for the most compli-
and empirically progressive. It had, for example, cated model of the year. This remark, though justified,
successfully explained the transmission of light in was sharp enough to redirect my thinking toward a
isotropic media and crystals and had explained for simplified model. (p. 105)
the first time why metals are opaque (Whittaker, Estes's remark draws attention to a feature of re-
1973, p. 265). Something else must, therefore, have search programs noted by Lakatos as a symptom of
been responsible for the long period of hostility to degeneration. Degenerating programs frequently
Maxwell's theory. The rapid universal acceptance of produce overcomplex theories. Restle's main dissat-

764 July 1985 • American Psychologist


isfaction with the contemporary theory, however, Due to this focus, then, several related issues in the
was not connected with Lakatos's criteria for degen- philosophy of science were purposely not addressed.
eration, which are experimental failures and the Although they are tangential to the material presented
inability to explain new results achieved by rival in this article, some of these issues should be con-
theories. Restle's main source of unease was the sidered before the major conclusions of this article
state of the theory considered quite apart from its are presented.
success (or otherwise) in explaining experimental First, consider the realist-instrumentalist divi-
results, and hence properly falls under Laudan's sion in logical empiricist philosophy of science.
category of "conceptual problems." Restle went on Realists propose that there is a relation between the
to explain how these and similar conceptual issues observational and theoretical vocabulary that is
led him to adopt the "Krechevsky" type hypothesis- strong enough to support ontological claims using
sampling model (Levine, 1975, p. 106). the theoretical vocabulary. Instrumentalists hold that
Other examples of conceptual problems, of theory is a mere instrument for systematically con-
course, abound in the conditioning program. Con- necting observations, and the concepts of the theory
sider, for example, the circularity of the concept of have no additional support, that is, they do not
"reinforcer." A (positive) reinforcer increases the correspond to real entities. In reacting to this his-
probability of a response it follows, but this increase torical division, one group of thinkers, including
is also the only way to identify a reinforcer. It is Bhaskar (1978), Fine (in press), and Harr6 (1980,
acknowledged that people cannot behave randomly, 1984), have attempted to replace these categories in
but most probabilistic models assume some type of ways that do justice to the prephilosophical consensus
randomness. Similarly, conditioning theorists never in favor of realism (see Manicas & Secord, 1983).
seem to have agreed on exactly what the stimulus Lakatos's work, however, provides a different
(e.g., proximal, distal, etc.) or response (e.g., molar, basis for criticism of the realist-instrumentalist di-
molecular, effect on the environment, etc.) was. In vision. Instead of viewing these as exclusive catego-
structural theories such as Piaget's, central concepts ries, his methodology suggests that research programs
like equilibration, construction, assimilation, and evolve from an initial state resembling instrumen-
organization have never been defined precisely talism to a mature state that resembles realism. In
enough even to be theoretically or experimentally particular, in discussing Newton's research program
useful. This lack of precision may account, in part, (Lakatos, 1978, pp. 50-51), he suggested that the
for the fact that Piaget's theory, like the conditioning first theory in a program may be so crude that it is
program, appears to have entered a period of stag- known not to represent anything (the hallmark of
nation (see Beilin, 1984; Brainerd, 1978). instrumentalism). The successive theory replace-
In any case, according to Laudan, the preferable ments as the program progresses, however, have the
theory is one that maximizes empirical successes effect of changing the initial model into a more and
while minimizing conceptual liabilities, and the more plausible candidate for reality. Lakatos sug-
preferable research tradition is one that supports the gested that an important part of the heuristic of the
most successful theories. The relative importance of program consists of recommendations for the incor-
these factors is not the same, but may vary from poration of new features, which are known to be
case to case historically and may change over time. absent from the initial theory, but are thought to be
Thus, a new theory that presents conceptual diffi- required for real-world representations. Thus the
culties may be resisted despite both empirical and research program, Lakatos's basic unit of analysis,
theoretical progress. Similarly, conceptual problems combines features of "realism" and "instrumental-
may hasten the abandonment of an otherwise pro- ism" in ways that are inconsistent with the mutually
gressive theory, as soon as a replacement becomes exclusive categories presented by logical empiricists.
available. Mature theories of a research program, however,
offer only candidates for reality. Recall that multiple
Discussion and Conclusions competing research programs are the norm in sci-
The main purpose of this article was, of course, to ence. To the extent that these programs embody
show that it is possible to give an account of different core commitments, they offer incompatible
scientific disciplines that avoids the problems asso- representations of reality. Laudan recognized this
ciated with radical incommensurability ("relativity feature explicitly and distinguished research tradi-
of scientific truth") and that retains a clear sense in tions by their differing ontologies and heuristics.
which a discipline may be said to progress, even Only in the rare case in which a single research
when fundamental commitments are replaced. The program dominates a discipline for a relatively long
strategy was to show how these problems arose in period will there be the kind of unanimity of opinion
Kuhn's work (and Kuhnian ideas), but can be on the existence of fundamental entities that is
resolved by accounts offered by Lakatos and Laudan. desired by philosophical realists. In the more usual

July 1985 • American Psychologist 765


case of program competition, attack and defense of must show features of psychology that are shared by
the fundamental entities of the various rivals will be some other science or sciences.
one of the most lively centers of scientific conflict. A final set of issues that must be acknowledged
Laudan (1984a, 1984b) has developed these issues, before a few conclusions are drawn is raised by the
among others, into a sustained critique of contem- work of sociologists of science, who, like Toulmin
porary philosophical realism. (1972), took Kuhn's work as their starting point.
Another issue familiar from pre-Kuhnian phi- This "sociological" reading of Kuhn has been expli-
losophy of science concerns the demarcation problem cated by Barnes (1982), Bloor (1976), Overton
(Popper, 1957), that is, the problem of distinguishing (1984), Palermo (1971, 1984), Reese and Overton
science from pseudoscience. Again, although the (1970), and Weimer (1974), among others. A dis-
issue is not central to the historical methodologies cussion of the relation of this sociological reading of
described herein, a coherent response to the demar- K u h n to the work of Lakatos and Laudan appears
cation problem follows from them. Each model in another article (Barker & Gholson, 1984b), in
proposes a detailed developmental structure for cer- which, among other things, it is denied that the
tain disciplines that are inarguably scientific. A historical approach sketched in this article has a
reasonable response to the demarcation problem, monopoly on truth. What each approach has to
therefore, is to classify a discipline as scientific if it offer is underscored in an exchange between Bloor
conforms to the developmental structure of an ac- (1981) and Laudan (1981b), to which the interested
cepted mature science. reader is referred.
A difficulty with this proposal is that it may It would, of course, require a separate article
easily be misunderstood as requiring that all sciences to do justice to the realist-instrumentalist division,
conform to a single methodological pattern. The the demarcation problem, or the issues raised by the
most prevalent and objectionable version of this sociologists of science. Thus, all that is attempted
thesis is the demand that sciences like psychology here is to acknowledge their importance and explore
conform to the paradigm of sciences like physics. a few implications relevant to the models under
Neither outcome is inevitable: Each thesis prejudges discussion. Similarly, because a succinct summary
the issue, which must be decided by research in of the issues treated in the body of this article is
which various methodologies are actually applied to difficult, in the remainder of this section only some
the histories of the sciences in question. One reason important issues and attendant conclusions will be
examples from physics, as well as from psychology, highlighted.
were used in this article is that in many ways physics Kuhn's most important contribution to the
represents the hardest case. The demonstration that view of science developed by Lakatos and Laudan
psychology clearly displays structures parallel to was to establish the existence of scientific commit-
those found in physics counts as a datum on which ments that are not directly vulnerable to experiment.
more refined accounts o f both sciences may be Because they are metaphysical, these commitments
constructed. At the same time, these parallels are were excluded from consideration by the logical
strong evidence against those analyses that seem to empiricists' accounts of science that were influential
question the scientific status of psychology (e.g., among social scientists in the 1940s and 1950s. Part
Carnap, 1956; Feigl, 1958). of the appeal of Kuhn's account among working
As demonstrated throughout this article, devel- scientists no doubt derives from his emphasis upon
opments in the psychology of learning, like those in the need to consider commitments of this sort. On
physics, conform in detail to the historical patterns the negative side, and perhaps against Kuhn's inten-
described by Lakatos and Laudan. One could argue, tions, his work became associated with the notion
then, that if what makes a discipline scientific is that paradigms are monopolistic and strongly in-
captured by these models, then the evidence that commensurable. Among other consequences, this
psychology is scientific is as strong as the evidence led to the denial that progress ever occurs when one
that physics is scientific. This should not be mistaken, paradigm replaces another. The mutually exclusive
though, for an entirely different--and objection- nature of paradigms was also taken to imply that
able--argument: that psychology, or any other sci- fruitful exchange between rivals is impossible. As
ence, must conform to the pattern established by Lakatos and Laudan have shown, however, these
physics (or any particular science). At the same views are philosophically avoidable a n d historically
time, however, an argument to the effect that psy- problematic.
chology is a science must avoid disciplinary solipsism In this article, it is argued that Lakatos's meth-
(Peterson, 1981; Toulmin, 1972), the view that only odology of scientific research programs applies in
psychology is a science because of the reasons that detail to various episodes in the history of physics
make psychology a science. That is, any successful and psychology. Although metaphysical principles
defense of the claim that psychology is a science retain an important place in this account, they are

766 July 1985 • American Psychologist


not embodied in monopolistic paradigms. For Lak- concerning the role of conceptual factors in scientific
atos, multiple competing research programs are the development must await further analysis, but their
norm, as illustrated by both the Copernican and importance in specific episodes is easy to demonstrate
Einsteinian revolutions. Furthermore, rational cri- (e.g., Maxwell's theory, mathematical learning
teria are available to use in selecting among research theory).
programs. Thus empirical evidence is restored to a The main aim in this article was to show that
key position in the account of scientific change. it is now possible to give a sophisticated account of
Once-and-for-all elimination of paradigms is tem- the development of scientific disciplines that avoids
pered by the additional possibilities of degeneration the problems of incommensurability and retains a
and revival. A clear sense again attaches to the clear sense in which a science may be said to
concept of scientific progress. This article provides progress, even when fundamental commitments are
a detailed description of how this account applies to modified. For the most part, these problems arose
the history of learning theory, represented as an in appropriations of Kuhn's work and can be resolved
ongoing rivalry between the conditioning research by the accounts offered by Lakatos and Laudan.
program and the cognitive program. Spence's work Although the latter views cannot be considered final
in support of the conditioning program in the mid- and much work remains to be done, for example,
1930s illustrates Lakatos's notions of scientific prog- in elucidating the nature of the guiding heuristic of
ress and empirical commensurability. The cognitive research programs and in Laudan's category of
program was superseded by its rival and was stagnant conceptual problems, it is clear that episodes in the
during the 1940s and 1950s. Mathematical learning history of physics and psychology are more congenial
theory and learning set theory provided important to the patterns described by Lakatos and Laudan
bases for a revival o f the cognitive program in the than those embodied in the Kuhnian model.
early 1960s. 3 The cognitive program became strongly
progressive and is generally accepted as having out- REFERENCES
performed its rival since the mid-1960s.
Although Lakatos's account captures important Aiton, E. J. (1972). The vortex theory of planetary motions.
features of the recent history of both physics and London: MacDonald.
Barker, P. (1980). Can scientific history repeat? In P. D. Asquith
psychology that were omitted by previous accounts, & R. N. Giere (Eds.), PSA 1980 (Voi. 1, pp. 20-28). East
its application reveals some important liabilities. Lansing, MI: Philosophyof Science Association.
Research program cores are not an effective way of Barker, P., & Gholson, B. (1984a). The history of the psychology
representing the metaphysical commitments identi- of learning as a rational process: Lakatos versus Kuhn. In
fied by Pepper and Kuhn. Cores change as research H. W. Reese (Ed.), Advances in child development and behavior
(Vol. 18, pp. 227-244). New York: AcademicPress.
programs mature, as illustrated by episodes like the Barker, P., & Gholson, B. (1984b). From Kuhn to Lakatos to
Copernican revolution in physics and the modifica- Laudan. In H. W. Reese (Ed.), Advances in child development
tion of core commitments embodied in consecutive and behavior (Vol. 18, pp. 277-284). New York: Academic
statements of mathematical learning, learning set, Press.
Barnes, B. (1982). T. S Kuhn and social science. New York:
and mediation theory. Another feature of scientific Columbia University Press.
development neglected by Lakatos's analysis of re- Beilin, H. (1984). Research programs and revolutions in devel-
search programs involves the development of com- opmental psychology.In H. W. Reese (Ed.), Advances in child
peting chains of theories based upon the same development and behavior (Vol. 18, pp. 245-257). New York:
fundamental commitments. The appearance of such Bhaskar, R. (1978). Academic Press.
A realist theory of science. New York: Hu-
chains, for example, in 19th century aether-based manities Press.
theories of light, and in the multiple competing Bloor, D. (1976). Knowledge and social imagery. London:Routledge
theory chains of both the cognitive and conditioning and Kegan Paul.
programs, is naturally accommodated by Laudan's Bloor, D. (1981). The strength of the strong program. Philosophy
of the Social Sciences, 11, 199-213.
concept of a research tradition, with its malleable Bourne, L. E., & Restle, F. (1959). Mathematical theory of
core and clusters o f theories sharing an ontology concept identification. Psychological Review, 66, 278-296.
and heuristic. Equally valuable is Laudan's recog- Bower, G. H. (1962). An association model for response and
nition that the conceptual liabilities and assets of a training variables in paired-associate learning. Psychological
Review, 69, 34-53.
research tradition are involved in the appraisal of Brainerd, C. J. (1978). Piaget's theory of intelligence. Englewood
scientific progress, independent of the experimental Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
factors recognized by Lakatos. General statements Briskman, L. B. (1972). Is a Kuhnian analysis applicable to
psychology?Science Studies, 2, 87-97.
Burke, C. J,, Estes, W. K., & Hellyer, S. (1954). Rate of verbal
3Many other events, both within psychologyand within conditioning in relation to stimulus variability. Journal of
related disciplines (e.g., linguistics, computer science), of course, Experimental Psychology, 48, 153-161.
affected the revival of the cognitive program. A discussion of Bush, R. R., & Mosteller, F. (1955). Stochastic models for
these events is far beyond the scope of this article. learning. New York: Wiley.

July 1985 • American Psychologist 767


Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical development and behavior (Vol. 13, pp. 83-117). New York:
concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies Academic Press.
in philosophy of science (Vol. l, pp. 38-76). Minneapolis: Kendler, T. S. (1981). Development of discrimination learning
University of Minnesota Press. and problem solving: A critical review of The cognitive-
Cole, M., & Medin, D. (1974). Comment on Gollin and Rosser. developmental basis of human learning. Developmental Review,
Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 17, 545-546. 1, 146-162.
Estes, W. K. (1959). The statistical approach to learning theory. Kendler, T. S., & Kendler, H. H. (1959). Reversal and nonreversal
In S. Koch (Ed.), Psychology: A study of a science, (Vol. 2, pp. shifts in kindergarten children. Journal of Experimental Psy-
380-491). New York: McGraw-Hill. chology, 58, 56-60.
Estes, W. K. 0960). Learning theory and the new "mental Kintsch, W. (1977). Memory and cognition (2nd ed.). New York:
chemistry." Psychological Review, 67, 207-223. Wiley.
Estes, W. K., & Burke, C. J. (1953). A theory of stimulus Klfiver, H. (1933). Behavior mechanisms in monkeys. Chicago:
variability in learning. Psychological Review, 60, 276-286. Chicago University Press.
Feigl, H. (1958). The "mental" and the "physical.'" In H, Feigl, Koch, S. (1976). Language communities, search cells, and the
M. Scriven,& G. Maxwell (Eds,), Minnesota studies in philos- psychological studies. In J. K. Cole & W. J. Arnold (Eds.),
ophy of science (Vol. 2, pp. 370-497). Minneapolis: University Nebraska Symposium on Motivation 1975: Conceptual foun-
of Minnesota Press. dations of psychology (pp. 477-559). Lincoln: University of
Fine, A. (in press). The natural ontological attitude. In J. Leplin Nebraska Press.
(Ed.), Essays in scientific realism. Berkeley: University of Koch, S. (1981). The nature and limits of psychological knowledge:
California Press. Lessons of a century qua "science." American Psychologist, 36,
Gholson, B. (1980). The cognitive-developmental basis of human 257-269.
learning. Studies in hypothesis testing. New York: Academic K6hler, W. (1938). Simple structural functions in the chimpanzee
Press. and in the chicken (Condensed and trans.) In W. E. Ellis (Ed.),
Gollin, E. S., & Rosser, M. (1974). On mediation. Journal of A source book of gestalt psychology (pp. 17-54). New York:
Experimental Child Psychology, 17, 539-544. Harcourt, Brace. (Original work published 1918)
Griinbaum, A. (1979). Is Freudian psychoanalytic theory pseu- Krantz, D. L. (1971). The separate v~arlds of operant and non-
doscientific by Karl Popper's criterion of demarcation? American operant psychology. Journal of Applied Behavioral Analysis, 4,
Philosophical Quarterly, 16, 131-141. 61-70.
Guthrie, E. R. (1935). The psychology of learning. New York: Krasner, L., & Houts, A. C. (1984). A study of the "value"
Harper & Row. systems of behavioral scientists. American Psychologist, 39,
Guthrie, E. R. (1942). A theory of learning in terms of stimulus, 840-850.
response and association. In The psychology of learning." Part Krecbevsky, 1. (1932a). "Hypotheses" in rats. PsychologicalReview,
H. 41st yearbook of the National Society for the Study of 39, 516-532.
Education (pp. 17-60). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Krechevsky, I. (1932b). "Hypotheses" versus "chance" in the pre-
Guthrie, E. R. (1959). Association by contiguity. In S. Koch solution period in sensory discrimination learning. University
(Ed.), Psychology: A study of a science, (Vol, 2, pp. 158-195). of California Publications in Psychology, 6, 27-44.
New York: McGraw-Hill. Krechevsky, I. (1933). The docile nature of "hypotheses." Journal
Gutting, G. (1980). Paradigms and revolutions. Notre Dame: of Comparative Psychology, 15, 429-443.
University of Notre Dame Press. Krechevsky, I. (1937). A note concerning "the nature of discrim-
Guttman, N. (1977). On Skinner and Hull: A reminiscence and ination learning in animals." PsychologicalReview, 44, 97-104.
projection. American Psychologist, 32, 321-328. Kuenne, M. R. (1946). Experimental investigation of the relation
Harlow, H. F. (1949). The formation of learning sets. Psychological of language to transposition behavior in young children. Journal
Review, 56, 51-65. of Experimental Psychology, 36, 471--490.
Harlow, H. F. (1950). Analysis of discrimination learning by Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago:
monkeys. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 40, 26-39, University of Chicago Press.
HarrY, H. R. (1980). Social being: A theoryfor social psychology. Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd,
New York: Littlefield.
ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
HarrY, H. R. (1984). Personal being: A theory for personal
psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension. Chicago: University of
Hilgard, E. R., & Bower, G. H. (1975). Theories of learning (4th Chicago Press.
ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Lakatos, 1. (1968). Criticism and the methodology of scientific
Holt, N. R. (1977). Wilhelm Ostwald's "The Bridge." British research programmes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
Journal for the History of Science, 10, 146-150. 69, 149-162.
House, B. J. (1979). Attention to components or compounds as a Lakatos, 1. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific
factor in discrimination transfer performance. Journal of Ex- research programs. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.) Criticism
perimental Child Psychology, 27, 321-331. and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91-196). Cambridge, England:
Hull, C. L. (1943). Principles of learning. New York: Appleton. Cambridge University Press.
Hull, C. L. (1951). Essentials of behavior. New Haven: Yale Lakatos, I. (1978). The methodology of scientific researchprograms.
University Press. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Kemler, D. G. (1978). Patterns of hypothesis testing in children's Lakatos, I., & Zahar, E. G. (1976). Why did Copernicus's program
discriminative learning: A study of the development of problem- supersede Ptolemy's? In R. Westman (Ed.), The Copernican
solving strategies. Developmental Psychology, 14, 653-673. achievement (pp. 354-383). Los Angeles: University of California
Kemler, D. G., Shepp, B. E., & Foote, K. E. (1976). The source Press.
of developmental differences in children's incidental processing I_ashley, K. S. (1929). Brain mechanisms and intelligence. Chicago:
during discrimination trials. Journal of Experimental ChiM University of Chicago Press.
Psychology,, 21, 226-240. Laudan, L. (1977). Progressand its problems. Berkeley: University
Kendler, H. H., & Kendler, T. S. (1962). Vertical and horizontal of California Press.
processes in problem solving. Psychological Bulletin, 69, 1-16. Laudan, L. (1981 a). Science and hypothesis. Boston: Reidel.
Kendler, T. S. (1979). Toward a theory of mediational development. Laudan, L. (1981b). The pseudoscience of science. Philosophy of
In H. W. Reese & L. P. Lipsitt (Eds.), Advances in chiM the Social Sciences, 11, 173-198.

768 J u l y 1985 • A m e r i c a n P s y c h o l o g i s t
Laudan, L. (1984a). Realism without the real. Philosophy of Schaffner, K. (1972). Nineteenth century aether theories. Oxford,
Science, 51, 156-162. England: Pergamon.
Laudan, L. (1984b). Science and values. Berkeley: University of Schefller, I. (1967). Science & subjectivity. Indianapolis: Bobbs
California Press. Merrill.
Levine, M. (1959). A model of hypothesis behavior in discrimi- Skinner, B. E (1938). The behavior of organisms: An experimental
nation learning set. Psychological Review, 66, 353-366. analysis. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Levine, M. (1963). Mediation processes in humans at the outset Skinner, B. E (1957). Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-
of discrimination learning. Psychological Review, 70, 254-276. Century-Crotts.
Levine, M. (1975). A cognitive theory of learning: Research on Skinner, B. F. (1968). The technology of teaching. New York:
hypothesis testing. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Manicas, P. T., & Secord, P. F. (1983). Implications for psychology Spence, K. W. (1936). The nature of discrimination learning in
of the new philosophy of science. American Psychologist, 38, animals. Psychological Review, 43, 427-449.
339-413. Spence, K. W. (1937). The differential response in animals to
McGuire, S, (1982). Incommensurability and relativism. Current stimuli varying within a single dimension. Psychological Review,
Perspectives in Social Theory, 3, 161-188. 47, 271-288.
Murray, F. B. (1984). The application of theories of cognitive Spence, K. W. (1940). Continuous versus noncontinuous interpre-
development. In B. Gholson & T. L. Rosenthal (Eds.), Appli- tations of discrimination learning. Psychological Review, 47,
cations of cognitive-developmental theory (pp. 3-18). New York: 271-288.
Academic Press. Spence, K. W. (1956). Behavior theory and conditioning. New
Overton, W. F. (1984). World views and their influence on Haven: Yale University Press.
psychological theory and research: Kuhn-Lakatos-Laudan. In Spence, K. W. (1960). Behavior theory and learning: Selected
H. W. Reese (Ed.) Advances in child development and behavior papers. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
(Vol. 18, pp. 191-226). New York: Academic Press. Stegmuiler, W. (1976). The structure and dynamics of theories.
Overton, W. E, & Reese, H. W. (1973). Models of development: New York: Springer.
Methodological implications. In J. R. Nesselroade & H. W. Suppe, E (1977). The structure of scientific theories (2nd ed.).
Reese (Eds.), Life-span developmental psychology: Methodological Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
issues (pp. 65-86). New York: Academic Press. Suppes, P., & Atkinson, R. C. (1960). Markov learning models
Palermo, D. S. (1971). Is a scientific revolution taking place in for multiperson interactions. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
psychology? Science Studies, 1, 135-155. Press.
Palermo, D. S. (1984). In defense of Kuhn: A discussion of his Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive behavior in animals and men.
detractors. In H. W. Reese (Ed.), Advances in child development New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
and behavior (Vol. 18, pp. 259-276). New York: Academic Toulmin, S. (1972). Human understanding. Princeton, N J: Prince-
Press. ton University Press.
Pepper, S. (1942). World hypotheses. Berkeley: University of Trabasso, T. (1963). Stimulus emphasis and all-or-none learning
California Press. of concept identification. Journal of Experimental Psychology,
Peterson, G. L. (1981). Historical self-understanding in the social 65, 395-406.
sciences: The use of Thomas Kuhn in psychology. Journal for Warren, N. (1971). Is a scientific revolution taking place in psy-
the Theory of Social Behavior, 11, 1-30. chology? Doubts and reservations. Science Studies, I, 407-413.
Popper, K. R. (1957). The aim of science. Ratio, 1, 24-35. Watkins, J. W. N. (1970). Against normal science. In I. Lakatos
Popper, K. R. (1970). Normal science and its dangers. In I. & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge
Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of (pp. 25-38). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
knowledge (pp. 51-58). Cambridge, England: Cambridge Uni- Watson, R. I. (1977). Psychology: A prescriptive science. In J.
versity Press. Brozek & R. B. Evans (Eds.), R. L Watson's selected papers on
Reese, H. W. (1962). Verbal mediation as a function of age level. the history of psychology (pp. 95-112). Hanover, NH: University
Psychological Bulletin, 59, 502-509. Press of New England.
Reese, H. W. (1964). Discrimination learning set in Rhesus Weimer, W. B. (1974). The history of psychology and its retrieval
monkeys. Psychological Review, 71, 321-340. from historiography: I. The problematic nature of history.
Reese, H. W. (1968). The perception of stimulus relations: Dis- Science Studies, 4, 235-258.
crimination learning and transposition. New York: Academic Weimer, W. B., & Palermo, D. S. (1973). Paradigms and normal
Press. science in psychology. Science Studies, 3, 211-244.
Reese, H. W. (1972). Acquired distinctiveness and equivalence of White, S. H. (1965). Evidence for a hierarchical arrangement of
cues in young children. Journal of Experimental Child Psy- learning processes. In L. P. Litsitt & C. C. Spiker (Eds.),
chology, 13, 171-182. Advances in child development and behavior (Voi. 2, pp. 187-
Reese, H. W. (1977). Discriminative learning and transfer: Di- 220). New York: Academic Press.
alectical perspectives. In N. Datan & H. W. Reese (Eds.), Life- White, S. H. (1970). The learning theory approach. In P. H.
span developmental psychology: Dialectical perspectives on ex- Mussen (Ed.), Carmichael's manual of child psychology (3rd
perimental research (pp. 205-252). New York: Academic Press. ed., Vol. 1, pp. 657-701). New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Reese, H. W., & Overton, W. E (1970). Models of development Whittaker, E. (1973). A history of the theories of the aether and
and theories of development. In L. R. Goulet & P. B. Baltes electricity. New York: Humanities Press.
(Eds.), Life-span developmentalpsychology (pp. 115-145). New Williams, L. P. (1970). Normal science, scientific revolutions and
York: Academic Press. the history of science. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.),
Restle, E (1955). A theory of discrimination learning. Psychological Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 49-50). Cambridge,
Review, 62, 1 I- 19. England: Cambridge University Press.
Restle, E (1958). Toward a quantitative description of learning Zahar, E. (1976). Why did Einstein's programme supersede Lo-
set data. Psychological Review, 65, 77-91. rentz's? In C. Howson (Ed.), Method and appraisal in the
Restle, E (1962). The selection of strategies in cue learning. physical sciences (pp. 21 !-275). Cambridge, England: Cambridge
Psychological Review, 69, 329-343. University Press.
Restle, E (1965), Significance of all-or-none learning. Psychological Zeaman, D., & House, B. J. (1963). An attention theory of
Review, 64, 313-325. retardate discrimination learning. In N. R. Ellis (Ed.), Handbook
Rock, 1. (1957). The role of repetition in associative learning. of mental deficiency (pp. 159-223). New York: McGraw-Hill.
American Journal of Psychology, 70, 186-193.

J u l y 1985 • A m e r i c a n P s y c h o l o g i s t 769

You might also like