Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 2

MODULE 1: (and also Elis, 

Tegea, and Thasos) a smaller body, the boulē, which decided or


OVERVIEW prioritised the topics which were discussed in the assembly. In addition, in times
of crisis and war, this body could also take decisions without the assembly
This module discusses about the problems of administration and organization in meeting. The boulē or council of 500 citizens was chosen by lot and had a
Ancient Greece. It will talk about the different forms of political and social limited term of office, which acted as a kind of executive committee of the
organizations in Ancient Greece. The module will also present the problems of assembly. The decrees of the Assembly could also be challenged by the law
knowledge, existence and virtue. courts. Similar in function to the boulē  was the council of elders (selected men
over 60), the gerousia, of Sparta, which also had the two Spartan kings as
Objectives:  members and had certain legal powers. Similar bodies of elders existed
in Corinth and Stymphalos. In Athens, the Areopagus was a similar such council,
 Identify the problems faced by Ancient Greece regarding administration where elders were made members for life.
and organization.
 Explain the different forms of political and social organizations in Ancient In other Greek states then, there were also democratic assemblies, sometimes,
Greece. though, with a minimum property stipulation for attendees (as in the Boiotian
 Acquire virtues using the theory of Virtue Ethics. federation 447-386 BCE). Some city-states also mixed democratic assemblies
with a monarchy (for example, Macedonia and Molossia).

MONARCHY
TOPIC 1: PROBLEMS OF ADMINISTRATION AND SOCIAL
ORGANIZATION SINCE ANCIENT GREECE  Rule by an individual who had inherited his role

Ancient Greece witnessed a wide variety of government systems as people In the Greek world monarchies were rare and were often only distinguishable
searched for the answers to such fundamental questions as who should rule and from a tyranny when the hereditary ruler was more benevolent and ruled in the
how? Should sovereignty lie in the rule of law, the constitution, officials, or the genuine interest of his people. The most famous monarchies were those in the
citizens? Not settling on a definitive answer, governments in the Greek world states of Macedonia and Epeiros, where the ruler shared power with an assembly,
took extraordinarily diverse forms, from tyranny to democracy. limited though these were in practice. Although Sparta also possessed a citizen
assembly, it is most famous for its system of two kings. Not absolute monarchs,
Across different Greek city -states and over many centuries, political power they did, however, hold great power when they led the Spartan army in times of
expressed itself in different forms of government, often in the same city as it war. During peacetime the kings were kept in check by ephors (ephoroi) who
evolved. Power could rest in the hands of a single individual, an elite or in every were themselves elected by the assembly. Clearly, a degree of political
male citizen: democracy - widely regarded as the Greeks' greatest contribution consensus was necessary for this overlapping apparatus to function. The kings
to civilization. were also members of the  erousia and were admitted from a young age, so that
they must have had a significant advantage over the other members who couldn’t
The four most common systems of Greek government were: join until they were 60. Spartan kings could, however, be put on trial and even
exiled.
 Democracy - rule by the people (male citizens).
 Monarchy - rule by an individual who had inherited his OLIGARCHY
role.  Rule by a select group of individuals
 Oligarchy - rule by a select group of individuals.
 Tyranny - rule by an individual who had seized power by An oligarchy is a system of political power controlled by a select group of
unconstitutional means. individuals, sometimes small in number but it could also include large groups.
For the Greeks (or more particularly the Athenians) any system which excluded
Our knowledge of the political systems in the ancient Greek world comes from a power from the whole citizen-body and was not a tyranny or monarchy was
wide range of sources. Whilst for Athens, it is possible to piece together a more described as an oligarchy. Oligarchies were perhaps the most common form
complete history, we have only an incomplete picture of the systems in most of city-state government and they often occurred when democracy went wrong.
city-states and many details of how the political apparatus actually functioned Unfortunately, information concerning oligarchies in the Greek world is sparse.
are missing. Surviving, though, are over 150 political speeches and 20,000 We know that in 411 BCE in Athens, 'the oligarchy of the 400' took power out of
inscriptions which include 500 decrees and 10 laws. There are also two the hands of the Assembly and were themselves superseded by a more moderate
specifically political texts with the same title, The Constitution of the Athenians, oligarchy of 5000. In 404 BCE, following the defeat of the Athenian military
one written by Aristotle or one of his pupils and the other attributed (by some) forces in Sicily, there was an oligarchy of 'the Thirty Tyrants' in Athens which
to Xenophon. Other sources which discuss politics and government include was a particularly brutal regime, noted for its summary
Aristotle's Politics and the historical works of Herodotus, Thucydides, and executions. Megara and Thebes were other states which had an oligarchic
Xenophon. In addition, politics is often lampooned in the comedies system.
of Aristophanes.
TYRANNY
DEMOCRACY
 Rule by an individual who had seized power by unconstitutional
 Rule by the people (male citizens) means

The word democracy derives from the Greek dēmos which referred to the entire Tyrants were sole rulers of a state who had taken power in an unconstitutional
citizen body and although it is Athens which has become associated with the manner, often murdering their predecessor. However, Greek tyrants were not
birth of democracy (demokratia) from around 460 BCE, other Greek states did necessarily evil rulers (as the word signifies today); they simply looked after
establish a similar political system, notably, Argos, (briefly) Syracuse, Rhodes, their own interests. Syracuse in Sicily had a run of famous tyrants, for example,
and Erythrai. Athens is, however, the state we know most about. The assembly Dionysios from 405 BCE and his son Dionysios II, who took over in 367 BCE.
of Athens met at least once a month, perhaps two or three times, on the Pnyx hill Others include Peisistratos in Athens (from c. 560 BCE) - a typical benevolent
in a dedicated space which could accommodate 6000 citizens. Any male citizen tyrant who actually paved the way for democracy, Pheidon in Argos (c. 660
18 years or over could speak (at least in theory) and vote in the assembly, usually BCE), Lycophron in Thessaly, the Kypselidai, which included Periander, in
with a simple show of hands. Attendance was even paid for in certain periods Corinth (c. 657-585 BCE), and Polycrates in Samos (530-522 BCE). For
which was a measure to encourage citizens who lived far away and couldn't Athenians, tyranny became the exact opposite of democracy, a position that
afford the time-off to attend. allowed the citizens of Athens to feel a certain superiority. This feeling was
especially evidenced in the demonizing of the Persian kings Darius and Xerxes,
Citizens probably accounted for 10-20% of the polis population, and of these it the tyrants par excellence.
has been estimated that only 3,000 or so people actively participated in politics.
Of this group, perhaps as few as 100 citizens - the wealthiest, most influential,
and the best speakers - dominated the political arena both in front of the TOPIC 2: THE PROBLEMS OF KNOWLEDGE, EXISTENCE AND
assembly and behind the scenes in private conspiratorial political meetings VIRTUE
(xynomosiai) and groups (hetaireiai). Critics of democracy, such as Thucydides
and Aristophanes, also pointed out that the dēmos could be too easily swayed by VIRTUE ETHICS
a good orator or popular leaders (the demagogues) and get carried away with
their emotions. Perhaps the most famous bad decision from the Athenian Virtue ethics is currently one of three major approaches in normative ethics. It
democracy was the death sentence given to the philosopher Socrates in 399 BCE. may, initially, be identified as the one that emphasizes the virtues, or moral
character, in contrast to the approach that emphasizes duties or rules
Issues discussed in the assembly ranged from deciding magistracies to organising (deontology) or that emphasizes the consequences of actions (consequentialism).
and maintaining food supplies to debating military matters. There was in Athens
Suppose it is obvious that someone in need should be helped. A utilitarian will A complete account of virtue will map out 1) its field, 2) its mode of
point to the fact that the consequences of doing so will maximize well-being, a responsiveness, 3) its basis of moral acknowledgment, and 4) its target. Different
deontologist to the fact that, in doing so the agent will be acting in accordance virtues are concerned with different fields. Courage, for example, is concerned
with a moral rule such as “Do unto others as you would be done by” and a virtue with what might harm us, whereas generosity is concerned with the sharing of
ethicist to the fact that helping the person would be charitable or benevolent. time, talent, and property. The basis of acknowledgment of a virtue is the feature
within the virtue’s field to which it responds. To continue with our previous
This is not to say that only virtue ethicists attend to virtues, any more than it is to examples, generosity is attentive to the benefits that others might enjoy through
say that only consequentialists attend to consequences or only deontologists to one’s agency, and courage responds to threats to value, status, or the bonds that
rules. Each of the above-mentioned approaches can make room for virtues, exist between oneself and particular others, and the fear such threats might
consequences, and rules. Indeed, any plausible normative ethical theory will generate. A virtue’s mode has to do with how it responds to the bases of
have something to say about all three. What distinguishes virtue ethics from acknowledgment within its field. Generosity promotes a good, namely, another’s
consequentialism or deontology is the centrality of virtue within the theory benefit, whereas courage defends a value, bond, or status. Finally, a
(Watson 1990; Kawall 2009). Whereas consequentialists will define virtues as virtue’s target is that at which it is aimed. Courage aims to control fear and
traits that yield good consequences and deontologists will define them as traits handle danger, while generosity aims to share time, talents, or possessions with
possessed by those who reliably fulfil their duties, virtue ethicists will resist the others in ways that benefit them.
attempt to define virtues in terms of some other concept that is taken to be more
fundamental. Rather, virtues and vices will be foundational for virtue ethical PLATONISTIC VIRTUE ETHICS
theories and other normative notions will be grounded in them.
The fourth form a virtue ethic might adopt takes its inspiration from Plato. The
EUDAIMONIST VIRTUE ETHICS Socrates of Plato’s dialogues devotes a great deal of time to asking his fellow
Athenians to explain the nature of virtues like justice, courage, piety, and
The distinctive feature of eudaimonist versions of virtue ethics is that they define wisdom. So it is clear that Plato counts as a virtue theorist. But it is a matter of
virtues in terms of their relationship to eudaimonia. A virtue is a trait that some debate whether he should be read as a virtue ethicist (White 2015). What is
contributes to or is a constituent of eudaimonia and we ought to develop virtues, not open to debate is whether Plato has had an important influence on the
the eudaimonist claims, precisely because they contribute to eudaimonia. contemporary revival of interest in virtue ethics. A number of those who have
contributed to the revival have done so as Plato scholars (e.g., Prior 1991;
The concept of eudaimonia, a key term in ancient Greek moral philosophy, is Kamtekar 1998; Annas 1999; and Reshotko 2006). However, often they have
standardly translated as “happiness” or “flourishing” and occasionally as “well- ended up championing a eudaimonist version of virtue ethics (see Prior 2001 and
being.” Each translation has its disadvantages. The trouble with “flourishing” is Annas 2011), rather than a version that would warrant a separate classification.
that animals and even plants can flourish but eudaimonia is possible only for Nevertheless, there are two variants that call for distinct treatment.
rational beings. The trouble with “happiness” is that in ordinary conversation it
connotes something subjectively determined. It is for me, not for you, to
pronounce on whether I am happy. If I think I am happy then I am—it is not
something I can be wrong about (barring advanced cases of self-deception).  
Contrast my being healthy or flourishing. Here we have no difficulty in
recognizing that I might think I was healthy, either physically or psychologically,  
or think that I was flourishing but be wrong. In this respect, “flourishing” is a
better translation than “happiness”. It is all too easy to be mistaken about
whether one’s life is eudaimon (the adjective from eudaimonia) not simply
because it is easy to deceive oneself, but because it is easy to have a mistaken
conception of eudaimonia, or of what it is to live well as a human being,
believing it to consist largely in physical pleasure or luxury for example.

AGENT-BASED AND EXEMPLARIST VIRTUE ETHICS

Rather than deriving the normativity of virtue from the value of eudaimonia,
agent-based virtue ethicists argue that other forms of normativity—including the
value of eudaimonia—are traced back to and ultimately explained in terms of the
motivational and dispositional qualities of agents.

It is unclear how many other forms of normativity must be explained in terms of


the qualities of agents in order for a theory to count as agent-based. The two
best-known agent-based theorists, Michael Slote and Linda Zagzebski, trace a
wide range of normative qualities back to the qualities of agents. For example,
Slote defines rightness and wrongness in terms of agents’ motivations: “[A]gent-
based virtue ethics … understands rightness in terms of good motivations and
wrongness in terms of the having of bad (or insufficiently good) motives” (2001:
14). Similarly, he explains the goodness of an action, the value of eudaimonia,
the justice of a law or social institution, and the normativity of practical
rationality in terms of the motivational and dispositional qualities of agents
(2001: 99–100, 154, 2000). Zagzebski likewise defines right and wrong actions
by reference to the emotions, motives, and dispositions of virtuous and vicious
agents. For example, “A wrong act = an act that the phronimos characteristically
would not do, and he would feel guilty if he did = an act such that it is not the
case that he might do it = an act that expresses a vice = an act that is against a
requirement of virtue (the virtuous self)” (Zagzebski 2004: 160). Her definitions
of duties, good and bad ends, and good and bad states of affairs are similarly
grounded in the motivational and dispositional states of exemplary agents (1998,
2004, 2010).

TARGET-CENTERED VIRTUE ETHICS

The touchstone for eudaimonist virtue ethicists is a flourishing human life. For
agent-based virtue ethicists it is an exemplary agent’s motivations. The target-
centered view developed by Christine Swanton (2003), by contrast, begins with
our existing conceptions of the virtues. We already have a passable idea of which
traits are virtues and what they involve. Of course, this untutored understanding
can be clarified and improved, and it is one of the tasks of the virtue ethicist to
help us do precisely that. But rather than stripping things back to something as
basic as the motivations we want to imitate or building it up to something as
elaborate as an entire flourishing life, the target-centered view begins where most
ethics students find themselves, namely, with the idea that generosity, courage,
self-discipline, compassion, and the like get a tick of approval. It then examines
what these traits involve.

You might also like