Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 25

Durkheim's Pragmatism Lectures: A Contextual Interpretation

Author(s): Neil Gross


Source: Sociological Theory, Vol. 15, No. 2 (Jul., 1997), pp. 126-149
Published by: American Sociological Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/201950
Accessed: 21-03-2016 18:35 UTC

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Wiley, Sage Publications, Inc. and American Sociological Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Sociological Theory.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Durkheim's Pragmatism Lectures:

A Contextual Interpretation*

NEIL GROSS

University of Wisconsin

This article attempts to understand E'mile Durkheim s 1913-14 lectures on pragmatism

and sociology by situating them in the socio-intellectual context of the time. An analysis

of books and journal articles from the period reveals that the ideas of the Anglo-

American pragmatic philosophers Charles Peirce, William James, John Dewey, and

F.C.S. Schiller were very popular in pre-World War I France. The French term le prag-

matisme, however, was used to refer not only to the thought of these philosophers, but

also to the work of French thinkers, such as Henri Bergson and the Catholic Modern-

ists Maurice Blondel and Edouard Le Roy, who wrote extensively about human action.

Pragmatism, because of its associations with Bergsonian spiritualism and the theology

of the Modernists, came to have religious connotations for many French intellectuals.

Durkheim had a similar understanding of pragmatism and his critique of the pragma-

tists caznnot be fully grasped unless these religious connotations are considered. The

article concludes by discussing several implications of this interpretation for sociolog-

ical theory.

In the 1913-14 academic year, Emile Durkheim gave a twenty-lecture course at the Sor-

bonne on the topic of pragmatism and sociology. Declaring that the problem posed by

pragmatism was "of national importance" (Durkheim [1955] 1983:1),' Durkheim offered

an exegesis and critique of the thought of the Anglo-American pragmatic philosophers

Charles Peirce, William James, F.C.S. Schiller, and John Dewey. Although this course was

later described by Mauss (1925:10) as "the crowning philosophical achievement of the

work of Durkheim," the lectures remain largely unknown outside the circles of Durkhe-

imian scholarship (Joas 1993; Lukes 1972). This is especially surprising today given a

resurgence of interest in Durkheim (Schmaus 1996; Pickering and Martins 1994) and the

renaissance of American pragmatism in social theory and philosophy (Joas 1996, 1993;

Putnam 1995; Langsdorf and Smith 1995; Saatkamp 1995; Wiley 1994; Shalin 1992;

Rochberg-Halton 1986; Habermas 1983; Rorty 1982).

The few scholars who have examined Durkheim's lectures have offered divergent inter-

pretations of the text. To assess the historical validity of these interpretations, I employ the

methodology advocated by Skinner (1988), Jones (1994, 1977), and Camic (1987), and

situate the lectures in the socio-intellectual context of the time. I argue that existing inter-

pretations pay insufficient attention to the peculiar manner in which pragmatism was received

in France and to the way in which this reception colored the meaning of the lectures for

Durkheim.

* Address correspondence to the author, Department of Sociology, University of Wisconsin, 1180 Observatory

Drive, Madison WI 53706. I thank the following people for their helpful comments on various drafts of this

paper: Deborah Bardwick, Kelly Besecke, Jorge Cadena-Roa, Charles Camic, Mitchell Duneier, Nina Eliasoph,

Herb Gross, Warren Hagstrom, Black Hawk Hancock, Hans Joas, Jean de Lannoy, and Warren Schmaus.

J Dates in brackets are original dates of publication. All quotations from Durkheim are from existing English

translations. Other quotations originally written in French are my own translation.

Sociological Theory 15:2 August 1997

? Almerican Sociological Association. 1722 N Street NW, Washington, DC 20036

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 127

CONTEMPORARY INTERPRETATIONS OF THE PRAGMATISM LECTURES

An Epistemological Interpretation

A review of the sparse scholarship on Durkheim's pragmatism lectures reveals several

competing interpretative perspectives. According to one group of scholars, Durkheim's

attack on pragmatism was primarily epistemological. De Gaudemar (1969:82), for exam-

ple, claims that Durkheim viewed pragmatism as a threat to rationalism and to "theoretical

thought in general." Two assumptions underlie this claim. The first is that Durkheim was

a rationalist. Durkheim ([1895] 1938)2 had in fact described his sociological method as

rationalistic. Like Descartes, Durkheim believed that all aspects of reality could ultimately

be understood through scientific reasoning. Durkheim also believed that no mental oper-

ation other than the employment of reason could guarantee the certainty of scientific find-

ings. In addition, he adhered to the correspondence theory of truth, according to which the

truth of an idea depends on the degree to which that idea corresponds with the reality it

seeks to describe. This theory of truth is an important element of Cartesian rationalism

(Curley 1978) and was consistently upheld by Durkheim in his discussion of pragmatism

(Schmaus 1994).3

The second assumption is that Durkheim saw pragmatism as denying aspects of ratio-

nalism to which he clung tenaciously. Cuvillier ([1955] 1983:xviii), for example, inter-

prets the lectures as reflecting the epistemological opposition between Durkheim, who

held that "collective experience should be the object of rational thought," and pragma-

tism, which, seen as a version of logical utilitarianism, would deny that experience must

prostrate itself before the altar of reason. A similar view is advanced by Cladis (1991),

who describes Durkheim's main criticism as being that pragmatism shows a lack of con-

cern with the social world as it is found by individuals or by a rationalist science,

emphasizing instead the "worldmaking" potential of individuals. Rawls (1996), Lukes

(1972), and Bellah (1959) also characterize Durkheim's principal critique of pragmatism

as epistemological.

A Moral and Political Interpretation

According to a second group of scholars, Durkheim's moral and political disagreements

with pragmatism are primary. Kaufman-Osborn ( 1991 ), for example, represents Durkheim' s

rationalism as fused to an unwavering belief in the political philosophy of liberalism. In a

rationalist framework, a moral aura comes to surround truth and its pursuit. If individuals

feel the power of this aura as it applies to questions of social order, they will recognize the

need to place restraints on their claims to liberty and in so doing they will strengthen and

stabilize the democratic polity. According to Kaufman-Osborn, Durkheim saw pragma-

tism's defining feature to be the belief that the truth of an idea depends on its practical

benefit. This belief undermined what Durkheim called the "necessitating" power of truth

and hence aggravated the crisis of liberalism that the sociologist saw besetting France in

the first decade and a half of the century. Similarly, Allcock (1992, 1983) argues that the

pragmatism lectures must be understood in the context of Durkheim's efforts to inject the

findings of a science of morality into the French educational system:

2 For more nuanced accounts of Durkheim's relation to rationalism, see Schmaus (1994), Jones (1994), S.G.

Jones (1995), and Mestrovi6 (1993).

3 In the pragmatism lectures, Durkheim ([1955] 1983:84) does not say that the only defining feature of truth is

that it involves a correspondence between ideas and reality, but he says that by truth social agents mean such a

correspondence: "A representation is considered to be a true one when it is thought to express reality .... Let us

simply say that when we believe an idea to be true, it is because we see it as adequately conveying reality."

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
128 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

What is the substance of Durkheim's critique of pragmatism? In a nutshell, his attack

is based upon the premise that the weakness of pragmatism is a moral weakness.

What he finds in pragmatism is no less than intellectual anomie, in that there is

insufficient regulation of that which passes for truth in society. This point is the

fulcrum of his entire discussion of pragmatism .... (Allcock 1983:xxxvi-xxxvii)

Mestrovic (1993) echoes this view, but adds that Durkheim believed that pragmatism's

conception of truth tended to unleash the social equivalent of the Schopenhauerian will,

which would ultimately result in anomic forms of social solidarity.

An Anti-Sorel Interpretation

A third perspective on the lectures sees them as an attack on the French syndicalist Georges

Sorel. For example, Joas (1993:56), citing the German scholar Rene K6nig, questions

whether the lectures could be read "as a hidden polemic against. . . Sorel, and as an act of

resistance against the syndrome of decisionism, violence, and the immoralism of deca-

dence."4 Although Sorel's book, De l'Utilite du pragmatisme, was not published until

1921, there is evidence that he had been branded a pragmatist within the French intellec-

tual community many years earlier. For Sorel ([1908] 1950), the value of myth, especially

the myth of the general strike, lay in its ability to incite action, an idea that bears a passing

resemblance to James's argument for the value of belief in matters of faith (Thayer 1968).

Durkheim did not identify Sorel as one of the pragmatists he intended to target. However,

in developing a general criticism of pragmatism, and in keeping with his strategic reluc-

tance to discuss competing schools of French social thought (Karady 1983), Durkheim

may have intended to address Sorel, about whom he had written on only a few occasions.

An Anti-Bergson Interpretation

According to another interpretation, the true target of the pragmatism lectures was the

immensely popular philosopher Henri Bergson. Bergson's ([1907] 1911) stress on the

cultivation of intuition as a way to grasp the reality of mental life led him to distrust what

he saw as mechanistic explanations of social and psychic reality (Antliff 1993; Schwartz

1992; Hughes 1958). His philosophy was thus radically opposed to Durkheim's, whose

scientific method required the very forms of explanation Bergson denounced (Vialatoux

1939). Soon after his appointment in 1900 to the College de France, Bergson came to be

closely associated with Anglo-American pragmatism (Allcock 1983, 1992). Considering

this association, Grogin (1988) suggests that Durkheim's pragmatism lectures could be

understood as a critique of Bergson.

A Scholarly Differentiation Interpretation

One other view of the lectures also merits attention. While not denying that Durkheim's

general epistemology was opposed to that of the pragmatists, several scholars nevertheless

have asserted that the actual distance between Durkheim and the pragmatists on many

specific issues was considerably less than Durkheim admitted. Jones (1995), for example,

notes that Durkheim's refusal to regard religion as an error, even after having shown it to

spring from social causes, reflects the direct influence of James. Cladis (1991:152) describes

4 Joas (1993:56) also warns that "the actual substance of Durkheim's line of argumentation is all too easily

ignored if this view is taken."

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 129

Durkheim as a "mild-mannered pragmatist" because the sociologist was willing to "hold

... on to what is valuable" from several different philosophical approaches in order to

produce coherent accounts of the social world. Joas makes two different arguments to the

same effect. Joas (1995) suggests that Durkheim and James were among the first scholars

to use religious experience as the basis for general theories about religious phenomena.

More significant, both Durkheim and the pragmatists were opposed to certain aspects of

empiricism and apriorism; they "attempt to take the deduction of... [the a priori condi-

tions for experience] beyond the domain of transcendental philosophy by inquiring how

the individual intellect has to be equipped in order for any form of cognition to take place"

(Joas 1993:57). Despite these similarities, "what emerges clearly ... is Durkheim's rhe-

torical strategy of not accentuating the similarities but rather the differences between prag-

matism and his own program of sociology" (Joas 1993:59). Stone and Farberman ([1967]

1990) also allege that, late in his career, Durkheim began to move toward pragmatism and

the theory that would eventually be called symbolic interactionism.5 Accepting these char-

acterizations, the lectures could be read as Durkheim's attempt to distinguish himself from

the pragmatists, whose ideas in some ways resembled his own.

Each of these perspectives expresses some truth about the pragmatism lectures, yet each

ignores a key aspect of Durkheim's critique-that his attack relied heavily on arguments

originally developed in the context of his sociology of religion. That religious topics fig-

ured prominently in the lectures becomes apparent only when certain aspects of the socio-

intellectual context in which the lectures were delivered are "recovered."

THE RECEPTION OF PRAGMATISM IN FRANCE

Pragmatism was an exceptionally popular philosophy in pre-World War I France. The

philosopher Edouard Le Roy (1908:271) exclaimed at a conference in 1908 that "the word

pragmatism refers today to a vast movement of thought, which, under diverse forms,

without doubt, and with many varied nuances, but also with a common core, manifests

itself a little everywhere: in America, in England, in France, in Germany, in Italy." Jean

Bourdeau (1909:39) wrote of pragmatism that it "seems to have gone beyond the fashion

of the moment." The Belgian philosopher Rend Berthelot (1911:3) opened his three-

volume study of pragmatism with the claim that "pragmatism is today perhaps the princi-

pal adversary that rational idealism confronts among philosophers." Albert Schinz (1909:111)

referred to pragmatism's "astonishing success." And an article in the popular journal La

Revue de Paris described pragmatism as one of "the projects of religious philosophy most

characteristic of the present time" (Archambault 1914:291). Durkheim ([1955] 1983:1,9)

said of pragmatism that it was "almost the only current theory of truth" and pointed out

that pragmatic ideas, born in private discussions between Peirce, James, and others in and

around Cambridge, Massachusetts, "were not long in crossing the Atlantic."

One measure of pragmatism's success in France is the rapidity with which the writings

of the Anglo-American pragmatists were translated during the 25 or so years following

1890 (Allcock 1983; Thayer 1968; Leroux 1922; Simon 1918; Boutroux 1912). Several

works each by Peirce, Dewey, and Schiller were published in translation between 1878 and

the time of Durkheim's first lecture on pragmatism in 1913, and many of James's books

were translated.

5 Mead, of course, was an important pragmatist in his own right. I devote little attention to Mead's ideas

because Durkheim was completely unfamiliar with his work. It is because of this unfamiliarity that Jones (1977)

cites the Stone and Farberman ([1967] 1990) article as an example of "presentist" historiography. Given Durkheim's

ignorance of Mead and given that the term "symbolic interactionism" was not coined until well after Durkheim's

death, the statement that Durkheim was "moving toward symbolic interactionism" lacks historical meaning.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
130 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

In addition, pragmatism was discussed at several conferences attended or attended to by

prominent French intellectuals. For example, the American philosopher Josiah Royce gave

a presentation on pragmatism and the problem of truth at the third annual meeting of the

Congr&s de Philosophie held in Heidelberg in 1908. The journal Revue de metaphysique et

de morale reported extensively on these proceedings, noting that "from the first day, prag-

matism became for the Congress a central preoccupation and the object of the most ardent

discussions" (Anonymous 1908:930). Pragmatism was also the topic at a seance, or meet-

ing, of the Societe Francaise de Philosophie held in May 1908.

More important, a substantial secondary literature on pragmatism sprang up in France

in the years 1906-1914. Among the most important books were Abel Rey's La Philoso-

phie moderne (1908), Marcel Hebert's Le Pragmatisme (1908), Emile Boutroux's Science

and Religion in Contemporary Philosophy ([1908] 1911) as well as his William James

(1912), Schinz's Anti-Pragmatism (1909), Bourdeau's Pragmatisme et modernisme (1909),

and Berthelot's Un Romantisme utilitaire (1911). Nearly 70 articles or reviews relating to

pragmatism were published in the Revue philosophique between 1906 and 1912 (Claviere

1913). Leroux (1922) lists some 30 original articles on pragmatism by French thinkers

between 1905 and 1914, and Simon's (1918) dissertation6 cites many more.

When French writers of the day used the term le pragmatisme, they did not refer exclu-

sively to the work of Peirce, James, Dewey, and Schiller. Instead, le pragmatisme was

thought of as a vague and amorphous philosophical movement in which the Anglo-

American pragmatic philosophers played only a part. For example, in his presentation to

the Soci6te Francaise de Philosophie, Parodi (1908b) commented that pragmatism was an

exceptionally difficult doctrine to define, in large part because of its inherent ambiguities.

Berthelot (1911) compared pragmatism to the cloud seen by Hamlet-both were cease-

lessly changing shape. Schinz (1909:77) expressed his frustration with pragmatism: "you

can't get a grip on pragmatism; when you try to seize it, it slips through your fingers." And

Fouillee (1911:275) echoed this view: "It is impossible to rigorously define pragmatism. It

is ... a curious amalgam of very different doctrines." Durkheim ([1955] 1983:10) also

alluded to the "elusive" character of pragmatic thought.

That French authors complained about pragmatism's vagueness speaks less to the lack

of clarity in the writing of the Anglo-American pragmatists than to the fact that the French

word pragmatisme was frequently used to describe several diverse currents of thought.

Thus H6bert (1908:101) implored readers, when using the word pragmatism, "to explain

with precision in what sense, with what limits. It has become an equivocal term; it is, alas,

hardly the only one in philosophy."

H6bert was one of many authors to write about and attempt to classify the different

types of "pragmatic" philosophies floating about the philosophical scene. In a clear but

unacknowledged reference to an essay by Arthur Lovejoy, Berthelot (1911:3) pointed out

that "an American writer was able, in 1908, to count up to thirteen different pragmatisms."

Berthelot went on to distinguish the integral pragmatism of James, Dewey, and Schiller

from the partial pragmatism of Bergson, Poincare, and the Catholic Modernists Loisy, Le

Roy, and Blondel. Similarly, Bourdeau (1909) noted that in France, far from there being

only one school of pragmatism, there were instead pragmatists of various sorts, each dis-

playing differing affinities with their Anglo-American brethren.

Many of these authors focused their attention on James, Dewey, and Schiller, whom

Durkheim ([1955] 1983:9) called the "chief protagonists of pragmatism." But the philos-

ophy of pragmatism was not reducible to the ideas of these core figures. Instead, le prag-

' Simon's (1918) dissertation appears to be the only book-length study devoted to the reception of pragmatism

in France.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 131

matisme was thought of as a modern philosophical tendency, a general viewpoint on

knowledge and truth shared by many thinkers, French and Anglo-American. Thus, Parodi

(1908b) proposed to look to the "Anglo-Saxon" milieu in order to understand pragmatism

because, in the thought of Peirce, James, Dewey, and Schiller, the pragmatic tendency of

contemporary thought had crystallized into a distinct and identifiable doctrine.

One way to gauge French understandings of pragmatism at the turn of the century is to

examine the connections French texts drew between pragmatism and antecedent philo-

sophical traditions. James ([1907] 1987) subtitled his book Pragmatism "A New Name for

Some Old Ways of Thinking" and counted Socrates and Aristotle, Locke and Berkeley,

Mill and Hume among those philosophers who had employed something like the prag-

matic method under different guises in past epochs. While Peirce regarded pragmatism as

most heavily indebted to Kant, French commentators tended to view pragmatism's intel-

lectual ancestry differently, stressing its connections with utilitarianism and its dissimilar-

ities from idealism and rationalism. Parodi (1908a), for example, traced pragmatism back

to the English empiricists, but also to the utilitarianism of Bentham and the evolutionism

of Spencer. Bourdeau (1909) noted pragmatism's striking similarities to the philosophies

espoused by Bentham, Kant, and Goethe, while Fouillee (1911) maintained that insofar as

the pragmatists held that to appreciate a belief it was necessary to consider its conse-

quences for the race, group, or individual, pragmatism spoke the same language as Dar-

win, Mach, and Nietzsche.

Others characterized pragmatism as principally a departure from idealism. For exam-

ple, Lalande (1906) noted that Peirce and James shared a profound distaste for "philosoph-

ical dilettantism"; for abstract speculation bearing no relation to the actual issues that

humanity calls on philosophy to help it confront. In this sense, Lalande argued, pragma-

tism was diametrically opposed to the abstract systematizing of idealism. Hebert (1908)

came to much the same conclusion, alluding to the differences between pragmatism and

neo-Hegelianism.

That pragmatism's ancestry was often traced back to the utilitarian tradition and seen

as opposed to idealism is hardly surprising, given the fact that French thinkers generally

regarded pragmatism as a form of utilitarianism. Lalande (1906:135) approvingly cited

Schiller's definition of pragmatism as "the doctrine that truths are logical values and the

method that systematically tests assertions according to this principle." Robet (1912:595)

observed that inquiry, in the pragmatist scheme, always begins with a problem or doubt,

in response to which an idea, and an action, are generated; this idea is true "if the satis-

faction sought is obtained." And Dessoulavy (quoted in Lalande 1906:142) insisted that

for the pragmatists, "the true is what is useful; it is in this affirmation that pragmatism

consists." Whereas traditional utilitarianism used utility-maximization as a standard for

assessing moral value, the pragmatists were seen as using the same standard to assess

truth claims.

Moreover, pragmatism was frequently criticized on the grounds that it was essentially

utilitarian. Fouillee (1911:298) argued that truth could not be a source of satisfaction if it

were known that truth meant no more than satisfaction-"in the domain of intelligence,

evidence and the harmony of ideas are indeed a cause of satisfaction, but the first of the

needs of intelligence that must be satisfied is precisely that there exists a reality, and real

relationships, independent of our satisfaction." Similarly, Schinz (1909), who suspected

that pragmatism tended toward intellectualism more than it acknowledged, maintained

that James explained how an idea could be true pragmatically only if the idea were already

true rationally. Rationally true ideas, in other words, could be more or less useful, but the

usefulness of an idea is not a sufficient guarantee of its truth. And Le Roy (1908), defend-

ing pragmatism, identified two widespread "abusive" interpretations of it: first, that prag-

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
132 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

matism denied the role of intelligence in human action, and second, that pragmatism,

because of its implicit utilitarianism, allowed agents to hold any belief as true.

Anglo-American pragmatism was also described in the French literature as a form of

anti-intellectualism or irrationalism. The psychologist Alfred Binet (1908:216), for exam-

ple, reporting the results of his survey of French teachers of philosophy, conflated prag-

matism and irrationalism when he noted that among lycee students, "irrationalism, as

much as pragmatism, is foreign to them." Boutroux (1912), equating intellectualism with

the correspondence theory of truth, suggested that James and the pragmatists departed

significantly from intellectualism insofar as they maintained that the object of a true idea

is reality as it is received by the mind through experience and not through a simple process

of conformity or copying. Bourdeau (1909) described pragmatism as a doctrine opposed to

all forms of purely speculative or intellectualistic philosophy. Finally, Fouill6e (1911)

concerned himself with pragmatism precisely because he saw it as one of several promi-

nent anti-intellectual doctrines.

Pragmatism was considered to be anti-intellectual for at least two reasons. First, to eval-

uate ideas, pragmatism turned to experience rather than to an abstract conception of reason.

Second, and considerably more important in the French context, pragmatism was under-

stood as claiming there were realms of being and experience-such as those of God, spirit,

and soul-that the intellect could not penetrate in any satisfactory way. Pragmatism, in other

words, was seen in France as a philosophy with clear religious or spiritual connotations.

Two arguments from James's religious writings impressed French commentators. The

first was James's claim that religious belief can produce its own verification. In his 1896

address "The Will to Believe," James ([1896] 1948:99) argued that in certain situations,

for example, when a decision must be made whether to believe in God, "the intellect, even

with the truth directly in its grasp, may have no infallible signal for knowing whether it be

truth or no." When situations like these arise, decisions must be made only on the basis of

faith. But faith is an appropriate guide to decision-making when it comes to religious

matters, for in the realm of religion, "faith in a fact can help create the fact" (James [1896]

1948:105). Acting faithfully in the world, James claimed, is one condition for salvation.

The world and the Absolute display no stultifying monism, but rather have an unfinished,

pluralistic character. It is humanity's responsibility to mold that world, that Absolute,

insofar as possible, into a satisfactory condition. James ([1907] 1987:618) later wrote, "on

pragmatistic principles, if the hypothesis of God works satisfactorily in the widest sense of

the word, it is true. Now whatever its residual difficulties may be, experience shows that it

certainly does work, and that the problem is to build it out and determine it so that it will

combine satisfactorily with all the other working truths." To believe in God is to live one's

life believing in God, and to live in that fashion, James claimed, is to do no less than to

help bring about God.

James was also known among French intellectuals for his argument that religious expe-

riences lose something of their vital qualities when they are understood only in intellectual

or scientific terms. James ([1902] 1987:50) argued that religion's distinctive feature is that

religious feeling constitutes "an absolute addition to the Subject's range of life." He held

that it was impossible to define religion per se, but insisted that a class of experience exists

that is distinctively religious, a class that consists of states of consciousness directed toward

a supernatural end. Religious experience is always accompanied by an intuition of the

supernatural or some greater power in the universe, a power with which humanity seeks to

enter into a harmonious relationship. The problem, according to James, is that rationalism

and modern philosophy have no room for mystics or those with intuitions of the divine.

However, even the rationalists should recognize two aspects of human experience-an

objective aspect and a subjective aspect. "The objective part is the sum total of whatsoever

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES
133

at any given time we may be thinking of, the subjective part is the inner 'state' in which the

thinking comes to pass" (James [1902] 1987:446). Science and rationalism have authority

over objective experience, but they cannot speak about subjective experience without trans-

lating it into objective terms. But both types of experience, according to James, must be

taken into account if the human condition is to be understood or lived-in its fullness.

"That unsharable feeling which each one of us has of the pinch of his individual destiny as

he privately feels it rolling out on fortune's wheel may be disparaged for its egotism, may

be sneered at as unscientific, but it is the one thing that fills up the measure of our concrete

actuality, and any would-be existent that should lack such feeling, or its analogue, would

be a piece of reality only half made up" (James [1902] 1987:447).

French authors commented extensively on James's religious writings (Lalande 1906;

Sorel 1909; Schinz 1909; Parodi 1908a; Bourdeau 1912; Robet 1912). Schinz (1909:162)

pointed to the alliance between theology and pragmatism in England and "upon the Euro-

pean continent, too, for that matter." Parodi (1908a) noted that a key feature of James's

philosophy was his inclination toward a concrete, pluralistic, and melioristic religion, a

religion that believed in the power of human action. And Bourdeau (1912) observed that

James's pluralism represented God as a particular form or aspect of life.

The philosopher Emile Boutroux was by far the most important popularizer of James's

religious thought. In Science iand Religion il Contempoiranr Philosophy, Boutroux ([ 19081

1911:306) described James as a proponent of a method of religious thought "especially

constituted so as to agree with living reality." Boutroux began with a discussion of James's

conception of religious experience, rehearsing James's claim that religious consciousness

is distinctive because it is permeated by a sense of the divine. This experienced sense of

divinity leads individuals to behave in saintly, moral ways. Thus, for James, "religion is

useful, and, in certain cases, irreplaceable: what more do we need in order to call it true?

If truth is, in the last analysis, that which is, that which continues, and that which engen-

ders, religion is quite as true as our belief in natural beings and forces" (Boutroux [1908]

1911:316-17).

As for the conflict between religion and science, Boutroux argued that according to

James, nature is multifaceted enough that it could be "handled" and "modified" in many

ways. Science is one way, but what evidence suggests that religion is not another? More-

over, while religion is for James "the fullest possible realisation of the human self," sci-

ence is merely "the selection and the classification of all that which, at any time and for

any mind, can be the object of clear and distinct knowledge" (Boutroux [1908] 1911:328).

The objective and impersonal kinds of experience that science deals with can never satisfy

the insatiable human demand for concepts and ideas that are "constantly revivified through

contact with reality, i.e., with the subjective" (Boutroux 11908] 191 1:329). Insofar as we

desire a philosophical system capable of satisfying the demand for "revivified" concepts,

we must find a way to incorporate science and religion into that system. Boutroux main-

tained that for James science and religion are opposed only if religion is understood to

consist of a system of dogmas and beliefs. But "if religion is essentially an experience-

something felt and lived-it need not, a priori, be contrary to a science which, itself, only

leads up to a certain interpretation of experience" (Boutroux [1908] 1911:330). Boutroux

([19081 1911:333) concluded-and this is crucial to understanding Durkheim-that James's

views "actually eliminate from the essence of religion all that is chiefly objective, intel-

lectual, or practical in the material sense ... for instance, dogmas, rites, traditions. They

put in the foreground the emotional and volitional element, which is embedded in person-

ality and cannot be separated from it." According to Boutroux, religion, for the pragma-

tists, is no strictly theoretical or intellectual affair, but instead is the stuff of subjective

experience.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
134 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

Why did pragmatism's religious dimensions receive so much attention in the French

literature of the period? Perhaps because Anglo-American pragmatism was seen as con-

fluent with several emerging lines of thought in French philosophy that were either overtly

theological or sympathetic to spiritual concerns.

PRAGMATISM, BERGSONISM, AND CATHOLIC MODERNISM

Despite the best efforts of the anticlerical government, the state could not wean the French

populace from its taste for things religious during the Third Republic. The state's distrust

of organized religion originated in the secular ideology of the Revolution and received

repeated experiential validation over the course of the nineteenth century as conspiracies

between the French Catholic Church and various royalist factions were exposed. Ferry's

laicization of education in the 1880s was in many ways a continuation of the demand

voiced in 1789 that the privileged institution of the Church, with its ties to the pre-

Revolutionary aristocracy, be weakened and its influence over the youth of France mini-

mized. The polarization of the polity during the Dreyfus years-when the republican

Dreyfusards, convinced that the Jewish army officer had been unjustly convicted, were

pitted against the royalist, Catholic, and anti-Semitic traditionalists-created a situation in

which the associations between republicanism and anticlericalism and between royalism

and Catholicism were solidified in the public consciousness (Arnal 1985). Bury (1950)

describes a sharp rise in anticlerical sentiment in the late 1890s. A coalition of Radicals

and Socialists took advantage of this situation and was swept into power in the elections of

1899, advancing a vigorously anticlerical platform. Waldeck-Rousseau, the premier who

headed the coalition, passed legislation mandating that all religious orders apply for state

certification. And under the tenure of Combes, Waldeck-Rousseau's successor, the gov-

ernment "insisted on a literal and punitive administration of the law" (Arnal 1985:34). The

conflict between Church and state worsened in 1905 when the Republic passed a separa-

tion law that ended state support for all forms of religious worship.

As the first decade of the century wore on, however, increasingly large segments of the

urban public tired of the Republic's hostility to religion. Weber (1968) and Arnal (1985) note

a revival of interest in Catholicism after the turn of the century. Support for the Church had

remained relatively strong in rural France despite the anticlerical crusades of Combes and

others, but increasingly, Parisians who had once given their minds to science and their hearts

to the Republic found themselves drawn toward traditional dogmas. Fiction from the period

also reflected a resurgence of interest in religion. Jean Barois, for example, the title character

in a novel set in the Third Republic, is raised a devout Catholic. As an adult, he becomes an

atheist and a Dreyfusard, but at the end of his life, he returns to the faith of his childhood. As

the elderly Barois explains to a colleague: "today I tell you this. Though dogmas may have

had their day, the religious emotion will persist .... You've only got to look around you and

you'll see that all the attacks of rationalism have failed to eradicate it. On the contrary, reli-

gious sentiment is permeating ourcivic life more and more" (Martin du Gard [ 1913] 1949:306).

The revival of interest in Catholicism coincided with a general resurgence of interest in

spiritual and religious matters. This resurgence was a reaction against what Grogin (1988)

calls the "mechanism" of the Third Republic, which had naively attempted to stamp out re-

ligious sentiment by besieging the Church and substituting the manifold discourses of ratio-

nalism for more spiritually satisfying systems of belief. Increasingly after the turn of the century,

however, spiritual concerns, although not specifically Catholic concerns, occupied intellec-

tuals on the fringes of the academy. As Weber (1986:32) writes: "the reaction against scien-

tific materialism and rational explanations . . . encouraged interest in mystery and the

supernatural, appreciation of faith for the sake of faith." Expressionist, Futurist, and neoprim-

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES
135

itivist painting celebrated the spiritual and the irrational, while symbolist writers in the tra-

dition of Arthur Rimbaud tried to capture in poetry and prose their "flights from reason" (Grogin

1988). Men and women of respectable social standing discussed-not dismissively-such

occult practices as hypnosis, communication with the dead, levitation, telekinesis, and the

like. Although the number of people actually engaged in these practices was small, the par-

ticipants were only the most explicit manifestation of a more general "trend away from ra-

tionalism and moderation, to action, to activism, to vitalism" (Weber 1986:237).

Bergsonian philosophy fit in with this trend. Reacting against mechanistic attempts to

explain human life using concepts derived from the physical sciences, Bergson argued that

states of mind bear no ontological relation to material objects (Schwartz 1992). Conscious-

ness existed only in quality, not in quantity, and hence was mathematically unmeasurable.

The inner time of consciousness in which states of mind flutter in and out of being and

interpenetrate one another was, for Bergson ([1907] 1911:299), a succession without dis-

tinction, a "dlure reelle" that could only be grasped through intuition, a method of appre-

hension in every way contrary to intellectual analysis. Bergson did not oppose intellectual

apprehension per se, but claimed it could only grasp objects materially; that is, by concep-

tualizing them as distinct, fragmented entities situated in time and space (Gunter 1966).

That was fine for apprehending inert matter, but if used to apprehend states of conscious-

ness, spirit, life, God, and other realities that "exhibit liberty, indetermination, and creativ-

ity" (Morkovsky 1972:44), a distorted picture would inevitably result. Bergson explored

these ideas in such popular works as Time and Free Will (1889), Matter and Memory

(1896), and Creative Evolution (1907).

Bergson had participated in more than one seance and was regarded by some in the

occult movement as a prophet, but he was regarded by others as the expositor of a philos-

ophy that could be put to many uses. Bergson's insistence on the irreducibility of life and

spirit to any sort of mechanical process was consistent with the efforts of those who

wished to undermine the dominant ideology of rationalism and the legitimacy of the Repub-

lic that it supported. Many in the syndicalist movement, for example, were sympathetic to

Bergsonism. Although the philosopher was not concerned with issues of class and labor,

his stress on conceptual fluidity and the vital power of ideas appealed to those who wished

to exploit the emotive energy of violence to bring about revolutionary social change (Gro-

gin 1988). Because Bergson was a professor at the College de France, his work was also

embraced by critics of the New Sorbonne like Henri Massis as an example of all that could

be accomplished if rationalism and empiricism were decentered from their positions of

dominance (Stock 1966; Bompaire-Evesque 1988).

For a variety of reasons, Bergsonian anti-intellectualism became identified with Anglo-

American pragmatism. Whereas the pragmatists maintained that reality was neither com-

plete nor ready-made, Bergson argued that objects always appear to the mind as objects of

action on which the dissecting, spatializing intellect inevitably goes to work (Jacoby 1912).

James sought a framework in which to argue that intellectual and conceptual knowledge

was relative to human action, and Bergson provided such a framework, claiming that

objects of consciousness are continuous and indistinct and that their representation by

discontinuous, fixed concepts was an act of representation, and often an act of misrepre-

sentation (Boutroux 1912). Grogin (1988) enumerates four similarities between James and

Bergson: Both displayed a contempt for mechanistic conceptions of life; they treated the

human personality as a functioning whole; they wrote on mysticism and religion; and both

were interested in psychic phenomena. James and Bergson were also friends and frequent

correspondents and James regarded Bergson's thinking as complementary to his own.

After James's death in 1910, Bergson authored the introduction to the French translation

of Pragnmlltisn. Following the book's publication in 1911, "Jamesian pragmatism ...

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
136 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

[became] closely associated with the thought of [Bergson], this highly influential and

popular figure" (Allcock 1983:xxviii). In fact, Bergsonism was often confused with prag-

matism. For example, a respondent in Binet's (1908) survey claimed there were enough

varieties of pragmatism floating about in academic circles for him to find one with which

he could align himself, and the variety of le pragmatisine he said he felt the most sympathy

for was that developed by Bergson. Similarly, Berthelot's (1911) text contains a substan-

tial treatment of Bergsonism and discusses its relationship to and fundamental overlap

with pragmatism.

Pragmatism was also frequently associated with Catholic Modernism. The Modernists,

a small but influential group of theologians and philosophers active from the 1880s until

their condemnation by the Holy See in 1907, addressed what they saw as a conflict between

science and Catholicism (Kurtz 1986). A key figure in the Modernist movement was Mau-

rice Blondel, a Catholic philosopher who had studied under Durkheim's teacher, the neo-

Kantian Boutroux. Blondel argued that science, or at least the philosophies on which

science was grounded, "could demonstrate man's need ('exigence') for the supernatural"

(Daly 1980:29). He argued that Kant had erred in separating pure and practical reason. For

Blondel, action, and not thought or belief or pure reason, was the "point on which the

powers of Nature, the light of intelligence, the strength of the will, and even the benefits of

grace, converge" (Blondel, quoted in Ranchetti 1969:40). Blondel showed that a careful

analysis of human action would always reveal something of the Absolute, and that the

presence of God can be revealed by taking the correct attitude toward action (Thayer

1968). Opening space for such a revelation was significant, for Blondel suggested that the

entire edifice of modern philosophy rested on the notion of immanence, the idea that

"nothing can enter into man which does not emerge from him and correspond in some way

to a developmental need" (Blondel, quoted in Ranchetti 1969:39) But the idea of imma-

nence conflicts with the insistence of the Catholic Church on the supernaturalness of the

Divine; by definition, the supernatural cannot emerge from the human mind. If it were

possible, by developing a method of immanence in which the distinction between the

supernatural and the transcendent was recognized, to find the Absolute, the transcendent,

emerging from the human mind, then modern philosophy could be reconciled with the

teachings of the Church. It was in action that Blondel sought signs of transcendence, for all

of humanity's action was "a journey toward the absolute which ... is, objectively consid-

ered, nothing less than the supernatural revelation given in Christ and made available to us

in Christian tradition" (Daly 1980:40).

The mathematician and philosopher Edouard Le Roy took a different approach to Cath-

olic apologetics. Le Roy (1907:4) believed that traditional demonstrations of the validity

of Christian doctrines were no longer persuasive given the state of modern science and

philosophy: "Catholic thought is, at this time, without notable influence on the diverse

intellectual movements that are developing around us." To remedy this situation. Le Roy

published in 1905 a controversial essay entitled "Qu'est-ce qu'un dogme?" and a book in

1907 entitled Dognme et critique. There are, Le Roy argued, at least four standard philo-

sophical objections to dogmas: (1) Dogmas are neither provable nor proven; (2) dogmas

often rely on indirect proofs, while science rests on and accepts only direct proofs; (3)

dogmas are often based on long-abandoned philosophies; (4) because dogmas and their

proofs are not on the same ideational plane as the axioms and demonstrations of positive

science, accepting dogmas requires a break in the unity of thought. Le Roy granted that

these are valid objections, but claimed they misconceive the nature of Catholic dogmas

and thus do not apply to them.

Le Roy (1907:25) denied that dogmas are intellectual propositions, arguing that "reli-

gion is less an intellectual adhesion to a system of speculative propositions than a real-life

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 137

[vecue] participation in mysterious realities." Dogmas have to do with action: "It [a dogma]

expresses above all a prescription of a practical kind. It is, more than anything else, the

formula of a rule of practical conduct" (1907:25). He did not mean that actions were to be

deduced firom dogmas, but that its action component was what was essential about a dogma.

Dogmas, moreover, have only negative meaning. For example, the dogma "God is per-

sonal" is not an intellectual statement about the nature of God, but an indication that God

is not to be treated as a formal category or an abstract concept. As negative prescriptions

for action, Le Roy (1907:91 ) argued, dogmas have absolute authority: "A dogma is a truth

of a vital order, it presents us its object under the rubric of action commanded of us by

Him, and the obligation to adhere which accompanies it concerns properly its practical

meaning, its value for life." Le Roy acknowledged that each dogma may encounter certain

theoretical, scientific, or philosophical problems. And he made clear that dogmas have no

special authority to address scientific or philosophical questions. But while the theoretical

problems posed by dogmas and the degree to which they seem acceptable given the state

of science change throughout the ages, Catholics have always had and always will have

"the same practical attitude concerning Jesus" (Le Roy 1907:34). Religion and dogmatic

authority are of the realm of action, while science and philosophy are of the realm of the

theoretical. Each has supreme authority within its realm, and only when one tries to over-

step the boundaries of its authority does a conflict between religion and science occur.

Blondel and Le Roy, because of their discussions of the relation between religion and

action, were often referred to in France as pragmatists. For example, Hebert (1908:75)

claimed that "the pragmatic tendency seems to me to have manifested itself, in our coun-

try, under forms belonging more or less to one of these three modes of expression of

religious experience: moralism, fideism, symbolism." He noted that Blondel continued to

describe his philosophy as a form of pragmatism as late as 1902, after which, in order to

distance himself from James, he abandoned the depiction. As Thayer (1968:315) explains,

Blondel thought of ideas "as ways of furthering life, and the truth of an idea depends upon

its so functioning." For this reason Blondel called his theory le pragmatisme, despite the

fact that his work had little in common with the thought of Peirce or James. Hebert went on

to ask: Should Blondel and Bergson, who both speak frequently about action, be described

as pragmatists? "Yes," responded Hebert (1908:72), "if one goes by etymology alone, but

that would be to introduce a new equivocation into philosophical language." Bourdeau

(1909:vii), less concerned with equivocation, described modernism as "an application of

pragmatism to religious beliefs." Insofar as pragmatism celebrated the utility of individual

religious experience, it was a form of thought opposed to ecclesiastical institutions, and

thus "Rome justly condemned [pragmatism] under the name of modernism" (Bourdeau

1909:82). "The pragmatic state of mind," Bourdeau (1909:153) wrote, "is that of M. Edouard

Le Roy." Later, Bourdeau (1912:3) averred that "Catholic Modernism was inspired by

pragmatism." He argued that Le Roy's modernism was merely an outgrowth of the phi-

losophy of Bergson: "M. Le Roy builds modernism on Bergsonian philosophy" (Bourdeau

1912:60). Fouillee (1911:320-21) described modernism's relation to pragmatism as one

of appropriation: "The apologists of the different religions are always on the track of all

that could serve the grand cause; they clothe their apologetic according to the fashion of

the day; they adapt it to the theories in style. Pragmatism has furnished the apologists a

unique occasion to rejuvenate worn arguments."

A CONTEXTUAL INTERPRETATION OF DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES

Clearly, pragmatism's reception in France was conditioned by the religious, theological,

and spiritual concerns of the intellectual field of the day. This point has been overlooked in

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
138 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

much of the existing commentary on the French reception of pragmatism. Two questions

arise from this finding: (1) Is there textual evidence to support the claim that Durkheim,

too, gave substantial attention to the religious dimensions of pragmatism?; and (2) does

this textual evidence alter the interpretation of Durkheim's lectures?

Pragmatism as Logical Utilitarianism

A noncontextual reading of the 1913-14 lectures leaves the impression that religious issues

were not at the forefront of Durkheim's critique. Distinguishing pragmatism as a method

from pragmatism as a theory of truth, Durkheim ([1955] 1983) made clear early in the

lectures that he would focus on the latter. Durkheim explained that pragmatism rallies

against the "dogmatic" conception of truth subscribed to in one form or another by Plato,

Mill, Leibniz, Kant, and Hegel that holds that a true idea is a copy or mental representation

of reality.

According to Durkheim, the pragmatists offered five objections to the dogmatic theory

of truth. (1) If truth were merely a copy of reality, it would have no intrinsic purpose or

value; God would have no reason to create the concept of truth and humanity would have

no reason to seek truth as an end in itself. (2) For the reality known by truth to be external

to the mind and yet graspable by the mind, ideas and experience would have to exist on the

same plane of reality. But by many accounts, ideas and experience are separated by an

epistemological "abyss" or "chasm" that the mind should have difficulty crossing. (3)

Truth could not impose itself on minds as an end to be sought if truth were not wholly a

human concept. But as conceived in the dogmatic theory of truth, "truth is impersonal, it is

foreign to man, it is extra-human. How, then, can it act on the human mind, attracting and

fascinating it?" (Durkheim [1955] 1983:16). (4) That which is true in the dogmatic con-

ception of truth is true for everybody and remains true for all times. But most truths do not

have this character-what is regarded as true changes radically over the ages and varies

considerably even among peoples of the same epoch. "What a difference there is between

the ideal, immutable truth of dogmatism and the real, concrete truths that we experience!"

(Durkheim [1955] 1983:19). (5) The dogmatic theory of truth permits no diversity of

opinion and is morally objectionable because it promotes intolerance.

In place of the dogmatic conception of truth, pragmatism posits that "the true and the

good are simply two different aspects of the useful, the advantageous" (Durkheim [1955]

1983:44). Overcoming the Cartesian separation of mind and body, ideas and actions, the

pragmatists maintain that ideas have truth only in relation to action-"thought and reality

are part of one and the same process" (Durkheim [1955] 1983:38). Thought, in apprehend-

ing reality, does not efface itself to engage in copying, but rather actively creates that

which it apprehends. Reality is always in the process of being created-it is fluid, dynamic,

pluralistic-and thought participates in this constant remaking, especially when belief

helps provide its own verification. For the pragmatists, "since reality is not something

completed, truth cannot be something immutable. Truth is not a ready-made system: it is

formed, de-formed and re-formed in a thousand ways; it varies and evolves like all things

human" (Durkheim [1955] 1983:24).

Thus, Durkheim ([1955] 1983:72) characterized pragmatism as a form of logical utili-

tarianism: "We shall see that the proposition that the useful is the true is a formula that

brings us back to utilitarianism. The pragmatist theory of truth is a logical utilitarianism."

He acknowledged that the satisfaction produced through the interaction of ideas and real-

ity was a criterion of truth for James only when satisfaction was understood in a circum-

scribed way. Still, Durkheim objected to the idea that truth should be defined in relation to

satisfaction or utility of any kind. He argued instead that truth has two essential properties:

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 139

a moral obligation attaches to truth, such that "in truth, there is something which com-

mands respect, and a moral power to which the mind feels properly bound to assent"

(Durkheim [1955] 1983:73), and truth is almost impossible for us to resist. These two

properties of truth, Durkheim argued, are consistent only with a rationalist theory of truth

and therefore are incompatible with pragmatism. By placing truth in the realm of the

useful, the pragmatists transformed the moral obligation to seek truth into a mere desire to

seek utility. Moreover, truth, far from always producing utility, sometimes causes the truth-

seeker displeasure or pain. That humans should feel compelled to accept the authority of

that which is true, even when truth is painful, was, for Durkheim, the hallmark of truth. In

short, Durkheim denied that the truth of an idea depends upon its ability to provide satis-

faction; instead, a true idea corresponds to the aspect of reality it seeks to express.

Pragmatism and Speculative Religious Thought

It is clear that Durkheim characterized pragmatism in terms of the Jamesian theory of truth

and set out to discredit the pragmatic project by invoking the tropes of rationalism.7 How-

ever, Durkheim also viewed pragmatism much as his French contemporaries did-as a

general philosophical movement that, in its religious moments, denied that what was essen-

tial about religious or spiritual experience had anything to do with ideas or the intellect. It

was in this context that Durkheim offered his most original, and most genuinely sociolog-

ical, argument against pragmatism.

As Grogin (1988) points out, Durkheim saw pragmatism as closely related to Berg-

sonism. While Durkheim ([1955] 1983:9) claimed in the second lecture that "the pragma-

tists are a little too apt to claim some thinkers who are far from accepting all their theses.

In this way James recruits Henri Poincare, and also Henri Bergson," his references to the

work of Bergson indicated the applicability of his critique to Bergson's philosophy. For

example, Durkheim ([1955] 1983:32) averred in the fifth lecture that "to a very great

extent, James's whole argument closely follows developments in Bergson. The positive

conclusions at which the two men arrive are not identical, but their attitude toward classic

rationalism is the same." Similarly, in the eighth lecture, which included an extended

discussion of James's argument that concepts need not be thought of as copies of objects,

Durkheim ([1955] 1983:47) noted that James's view "is reminiscent of Bergson's schema

dynamique." And the twentieth lecture, which examines the heterogeneity that pragmatism

alleges exists in the relation between thought and reality, is as much a discussion of the

Bergsonian elan vital as it is a critique of James.

Durkheim also saw a connection between pragmatism and religious modernism. Inter-

preting James's argument for the right to believe in God as akin to Pascal's wager,8 Durkheim

([1955] 1983:7) wrote that "preoccupation with religion is to be found in the work of all

the pragmatists." He later noted that "the only question to which the pragmatist method

has been consistently applied is that of religion" (Durkheim [1955] 1983:60). Durkheim

([1955] 1983:9) also made this highly significant statement: "In France, pragmatism appears

chiefly in the neo-religious movement described as 'modernist.' Edouard Le Roy claims to

base his religious apologetics on principles borrowed from pragmatism."

These points alone, of course, do not establish that Durkheim's lectures were centrally

concerned with the pragmatic treatment of religion. Durkheim had gone on record on

7 In the lectures, Durkheim remained faithful to an argument he had made throughout his career; namely, that

rationalism, while essentially sound, needed reform because it placed reason outside the realm of that which

could be analyzed by science.

8 For a lucid discussion of James's religious philosophy, see Vanden Burgt (1981). James was less interested

in the benefits that religious devotion might bring in the hereafter than he was in the this-worldly moral strenu-

ousness that faith could inculcate.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
140 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

previous occasions as opposing pragmatism's view of religion, and it is conceivable that

he was doing no more in the pragmatism lectures-by noting the religious or spiritualistic

dimensions to pragmatism-than reiterating objections he had made elsewhere.9

But Durkheim's arguments against the pragmatists in the lectures went far beyond the

largely methodological criticisms he had voiced contra James, for example, in The Ele-

menta,r Forms. After his lengthy summary of the thought of the pragmatists, Durkheim

identified what he saw as the hallmark of pragmatic thinking: Pragmatism denies the value

of purely speculative thought. At the end of the twelfth lecture, Durkheim ([1955] 1983:64)

noted that pragmatism's "preoccupation with action, which has been seen as the defining

characteristic of pragmatism, is not, in my view, its major feature"; pragmatism is "much

less of an undertaking to encourage action than an attack on pure speculation and theoret-

ical thought." Durkheim ([1955] 1983:76-77) ended the fifteenth lecture with the claim

that "for pragmatism, truth has no speculative function: all that concerns it is its practical

utility," and in the following lecture stated that "the pragmatist philosophers, and Schiller

in particular, deny that thought has a speculative value."

Without knowing something about pragmatism's reception in France, it would be dif-

ficult to know how to understand Durkheim's argument. In point of fact, the pragmatists

did not deny that some speculative thought has value. James, for example, was not averse

to engaging in metaphysical speculation as long as he was convinced that his speculative

statements could pass the pragmatic test of meaning."' To say, as the pragmatists did, that

all meaningful thought is bound up with action, is not to say there is only one type of action

that can be connected with thought. For the pragmatists, meaningful speculative thought

could consist of those ideas that are phases of actions that are not immediately perceptible

as actions but which, on examination, turn out to be actions nonetheless. James's views

about the "pluralistic" character of the universe were certainly speculative, but they had

meaning inasmuch as they were tied to certain practical attitudes toward the world.

However, by portraying pragmatism as denying the speculative value of thought,

Durkheim could apply his sociology to the basic premises of pragmatism. In the lectures,

Durkheim argued that pragmatism's ideas about the nature of thought should be under-

stood as empirical claims, and then argued that these claims were empirically untrue.

Durkheim could make this argument only because he and his audience understood prag-

matism to be of a piece with Bergsonism and Catholic Modernism and therefore as deny-

ing that the intellectual or ideational aspects of religion were essential to religious experience.

Durkheim took this to mean that the pragmatists denied that religious ideas and beliefs

stem from an intellectual desire on the part of agents to understand their worlds, especially

their social worlds. Yet Durkheim's work on the sociology of religion provided proof that

religious ideas and myths are indeed speculative and intellectual in nature. If so, and if

religious ideas were the evolutionary precursors of the ideas of modern science and phi-

losophy, then the validity of the pragmatic understanding of thought could be called into

question.

Thus, Durkheim's characterization of pragmatism as an attack on speculative thought

was bound up with his understanding of French pragmatism-the pragmatism of Bergson

and the Modernists. In Creative Evolution, Bergson ([ 1907] 1911 ) tried to show that thought

9 Durkheim took issue with pragmatism's analysis of religion at a 1908 meeting of the French society of

philosophy (see Jones 1995), as well as in The Elementary Forms. He repeated many of these criticisms in the

twelfth lecture on pragmatism.

)0 For example, James ([19091 1943:249-50) wrote: "I am quite willing to part company with Professor

Bergson, and to ascribe a primarily theoretical function to our intellect, provided you on your part then agree to

discriminate 'theoretic' or scientific knowledge from the deeper 'speculative' knowledge aspired to by most

philosophers, and concede that theoretic knowledge, which is knowledge about things, as distinguished from

living or sympathetic acquaintance with them, touches only the outer surface of reality."

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 141

is never purely speculative in that it is never completely divorced from action. Bergson

argued that a distinctive feature of human intelligence is its ability to fabricate tools or

instruments out of "unorganized matter," matter that in its natural state is not an obvious

instrument for practical use. It does not matter that the objects apprehended by intelligence

are sometimes ideas rather than physical objects-intelligence sees ideas, too, as unorga-

nized matter that can be organized in some coherent, instrumental way. Even when intel-

ligence engages in speculative thinking, then, it is transforming the objects of its perception

and engaging in action, and the ideas and concepts it employs are in no sense "pictures" or

"copies" of those objects.

The Catholic Modernists also downplayed the importance of purely speculative thought,

at least within the realm of religion. At the 1908 seance on pragmatism, Le Roy (1908:280-

81) said of its theory of religious knowledge: "What pragmatism affirms is that the point is

to try and perceive moral realities, and, for this, moral conditions are required; further, that

religious truths are in the realm of givens and facts instead of theories, and thus that we

apprehend them first as moments of life instead of as materials of science." While prag-

matism asserted the superiority of practical reasoning, it did not exclude or subordinate

intelligence: "Does this mean that pragmatism condemns all uses of abstract, analytical,

discursive thought? Not at all, as this thought itself can be conceived of and practiced as a

moment of life. Only, it is up to experience to decide where, when, and in what degree it is

legitimate" (Le Roy 1907:274). For the Catholic Modernists and James (at least as the

latter was interpreted by Boutroux), dogmas and religious ideas have authority only when

they pertain to action, not when they speculate about the nature of the world. This was why

Blondel's "philosophy of action," as well as Le Roy's apologetics, were referred to as

varieties of pragmatism.

But Durkheim ([1955] 1983:77) insisted that the pragmatists' denial of the importance

of purely speculative thought within the realm of religion was empirically false: "How

valid is that opinion [that thought has no speculative value]? It is contradicted by the

facts." About "primitive" systems of classification, he elsewhere claimed that "these sys-

tems, like those of science, have a purely speculative purpose. Their object is not to facil-

itate action, but to advance understanding, to make intelligible the relations which exist

between things" (Durkheim and Mauss [1903] 1963:81). Durkheim's ([1912] 1915:169)

well-known argument, which he developed in The Elementary Forms, was that systems of

classification are "modeled upon the social organization, or rather that they have taken the

forms of society as their framework." "Primitive" taxonomies and mythologies provide

aboriginal peoples with ideational systems that explain the world around them, and these

systems are important components of religion: "Feasts and rites, in a word, the cult, are not

the whole religion. This is not merely a system of practices, but also a system of ideas

whose object is to explain the world; we have seen that even the humblest have their

cosmology" (Durkheim [1912] 1915:476).

While Durkheim was more interested in socially efficacious religious action, which lay

at the heart of collective effervescence, than in religious belief, he retained a strong inter-

est in what Pickering (1984) calls the "cognitive aspects" of religion. The pragmatists,

particularly the Catholic Modernists, either denied that religion had any such cognitive

component or downplayed the importance of the ideational aspects of religion for reli-

gious experience. But Durkheim often repeated in the pragmatism lectures that speculative

religious thought exists. Myths, he said, "are groupings of representations aimed at explain-

ing the world, systems of ideas whose function is essentially speculative . . . what lies at

the root of myths is not a practical need: it is the intellectual need to understand" (Durkheim

[1955] 1983:76-77). The twentieth lecture contained the assertion that "religious life ...

contains a rich abundance of forms of thought and activities of all kinds. In the field of

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
142 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

thought, these include myths and religious beliefs, an embryonic science, and a certain

poetry" (Durkheim [1955] 1983:94). Durkheim also distinguished mythological truths

from scientific truths: Both involve collective representations, shared understandings about

the realities they apprehend. "What religion expresses in its representations, its beliefs and

myths, is social realities and the way in which they act upon individuals ... [while science

expresses] the world as it is" (Durkheim [1955] 1983:87-88). Mythological thought and

scientific thought differ mostly in content; they are not radically different modes of appre-

hension. Having insisted that purely speculative mythological thought exists, Durkheim

could claim that speculative thought in general-that is, thought entirely removed from

the world of action-must exist as well, and can have intrinsic value.

Durkheim's argument lent empirical support to the correspondence theory of truth in

two ways. First, purely speculative thought was, by definition, thought that was not reflected

in action. Such thought could have no bearing on the practical problems of life and there-

fore could not be judged by any standard of utility. Second, purely speculative thought

could not produce its own verification. The only possible relations between purely spec-

ulative thought and reality were relations of correspondence or noncorrespondence and

these were consistent only with versions of the dogmatic theory of truth.

Interpretative Implications

Ample textual evidence indicates that Durkheim not only considered the religious dimen-

sions of pragmatism in the lectures, but made this consideration a cornerstone of his soci-

ological critique.

This implies, first, that Durkheim's attack on pragmatism was in part a defense of his

sociology of knowledge. Given the way pragmatism was received in France, Durkheim

may have viewed pragmatism's conception of religious experience as a threat to his own

attempts to explain the origin of certain types of knowledge by reference to sociological

data about the cognitive aspects of religion-aspects that, according to the pragmatists,

were not an essential part of religious experience.' I

Second, Durkheim's critique of the pragmatists should be understood within the con-

text of his religious politics. If, in expressing his objections to pragmatism, Durkheim was

opposing the diverse currents of religious and spiritualistic thought that Jamesian pragma-

tism, Bergsonism, and Catholic Modernism seemed to support, then his lectures can be

seen as a move in the ongoing rhetorical contest between supporters of the secular state

and traditionalistic proponents of religion. Durkheim, of course, was committed, for per-

sonal, sociological, and moral reasons, to a secular politics. As an assimilated Jew who had

carved out an identity for himself as a scientist and moralist for the French democracy

(Pickering 1994), Durkheim had a vested interest in the maintenance of a secular ideolog-

ical sphere that valued such an identity. Durkheim also favored, for sociological reasons, a

radical separation of Church and state and an eventual weakening of the moral role of the

Church. While Durkheim praised Christianity for its tolerance, its idealistic concern with

the interior moral life of the human being, and its emphasis on the need to discipline the

human passions (Pickering 1984), it is well known that he felt organized religion was

becoming outdated. Durkheim's moralistic vision for sociology, a vision that appealed to

administrators of the French Republic and thus provided an ideological basis for the insti-

tutionalization of the discipline, was that sociology would be offered to a populace whose

collective moral life had been threatened by the declining interest in religion (Grogin

1 l Further research is required to discover whether the pragmatists' ideas were actually used by Durkheim's

critics to challenge his sociology of knowledge. Such an historical finding would considerably bolster this inter-

pretation.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 143

1988; Greenberg 1981; Clark 1973). Finally, despite his protestations that sociological

explanations of religious belief were not intended to undermine such belief, the scientific

vantage point from which Durkheim's sociology of religion was initiated was, at its core,

a secular one.

The revival of interest in religion after the turn of the century must have made Durkheim

uneasy. Tied to attacks on rationalism and empiricism, this revival threatened the Durkhe-

imian program. Because pragmatism was understood in France as providing philosophical

support for this revival, if only by defending the experiential validity of religious or spir-

itual belief against the objections of science, it is hardly surprising that Durkheim ([1955]

1983:1) challenged the pragmatists, declaring the threat posed by pragmatism to be "of

national importance." The complete history of Durkheim's response to the resurgence of

religious sentiment in the early twentieth century in France has not been written, but the

1913-14 pragmatism lectures will be an important part of the story.

CONCLUDING REMARKS

My analysis reveals a layer of critique in Durkheim's pragmatism lectures that has gone

largely unnoticed. While the lectures were an attack on the Jamesian theory of truth, they

were also a substantive defense of a crucial component of Durkheim's sociology of reli-

gion and, by extension, his sociology of knowledge. The lectures also were an attempt to

erode the support that various pragmatic philosophies were lending to the cause of reli-

gious apologetics. While my findings neither contradict nor confirm previous perspectives

on the lectures, they do suggest that interpretations that ignore Durkheim's treatment of

the religious dimensions of pragmatism are incomplete.

What are the implications of this conclusion for sociological theory? This depends on

what is meant by sociological theory. To the extent that Durkheim's pragmatism lectures

are regarded as part of the classical social-theoretical canon, an interpretation of the lec-

tures that provides historical evidence that they were intended to be understood differently

than they are currently understood is indeed of theoretical relevance. However, this does

not show that my interpretation of the lectures has implications for contemporary theoret-

ical efforts to understand the social world.

Nevertheless, there are at least two implications for contemporary sociological theory. First,

Durkheim's confrontation with the pragmatic understanding of religion was the occasion for

his lapsing into a highly unusual and highly revealing cognitive essentialism. Schmaus (I 1995),

Godlove (1986), and Lukes (1972) have observed that Durkheim frequently attempted to re-

solve philosophical disputes empirically by referring to sociological data. This is evident in

the pragmatism lectures vis-a-vis the use of data about the speculative aspects of myth and

religion. How successful was Durkheim's use of empirical evidence in the context of phil-

osophical argument? In fact, Durkheim did little more than assert the existence of purely spec-

ulative mythological thought. Certainly James, if he admitted that the mythologies of aboriginal

peoples fell under the rubric of religion, would have argued that mythological thought is tied

to action. To conceptualize the origin of the world in two different ways is to adopt two dif-

ferent practical attitudes toward the world. Durkheim would not have denied this, but would

have claimed that practical attitudes are analytically separable from the processes of thought.

Ultimately, however, Durkheim's recourse to empirical data served only to illustrate-not

resolve-the philosophical quarrel.

Perhaps anticipating criticism along these lines, Durkheim advanced several strictly

philosophical arguments about the relationship between thought and action. Dewey argued

that consciousness emerges when agents confront action-problematic situations, but

Durkheim ([1955] 1983:79) insisted that thought and action are antagonistic processes and

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
144 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

that sometimes "consciousness slows down, overloads or paralyzes action." He cited the

case of the pianist whose perfect playing is interrupted only when excessive conscious

attention is paid to the task. Thought, according to Durkheim ([1955] 1983:80), is "a

hyperconcentration of consciousness [whereas] action ... is a sudden release." Because

thought and action are opposed, action could not give rise to consciousness. What, then,

produces consciousness? Durkheim would answer that it is the human mind's essential

need for knowledge:

The role of consciousness is not to direct the behavior of a being with no need of

knowledge: it is to constitute a being who would not exist without it. ... Conscious-

ness is therefore not a function with the role of directing the movements of the body,

but the organism knowing itself.... Consciousness, far from having only the role of

directing the movements of beings, exists in order to produce beings.... Reducing

the conscious being to nothing but his actions means taking from him the very thing

which makes him what he is." ([1955] 1983:82-83)

In fact, Durkheim ([1955] 1983:77) defended his interpretation of the speculative char-

acter of myths in the following way: "What lies at the root of myths is not a practical need:

it is the intellectual need to understand. Basically, therefore, a rationalist mind is present

there, perhaps in an unsophisticated form, but nevertheless enough to prove that the need

to understand is universal and essentially human."

These arguments indicate that contemporary commentators may be misreading Durkheim

as subscribing to an entirely nonuniversalistic conception of reason. Durkheim's theoret-

ical work on the cultural construction of cognition, especially in Primitive Classification

and The Elementary Forms, has given rise to decades of anthropological fieldwork attempt-

ing to document cultural variability in the basic categories of human thought. In recent

years, Durkheim's underlying premises have come increasingly under attack from neo-

Kantians (Godlove 1986) and others (Gell 1992). According to his critics, when Durkheim

attempted to derive a metaphysics by looking out on the heterogeneity of the social world,

he abandoned the idea that there are certain categories of thought that all humans share by

virtue of their common status as thinking beings. While Durkheim recognized that all

social agents, across societies, have some categories and concepts in common, he never

satisfactorily answered the question of whether these common forms of thought resulted

from the universal functional requirements of social life or from the a priori necessities of

thought, whether these necessities are understood in Kantian terms or in terms of the

essential qualities of the human psyche (Schmaus 1994). Given this alleged lack of cog-

nitive universalism in Durkheim's work, the principal anti-Durkheimian argument has

been that while there is variability in the cultural understanding of the categories, there is

no variability in the categories themselves. For example, although agents in different soci-

eties may weave temporality into their religious rituals in different ways, this does not

demonstrate the variability across cultures of the nature of time itself (Gell 1992).

However, by positing a "need to understand" and the existence of at least an unsophis-

ticated "rationalist mind" as part of the make-up of all human beings, Durkheim, in the

pragmatism lectures, adumbrated a theoretical model in which the cultural variability of

reason is superimposed on a rudimentarily universal cognitive base. If, as Durkheim sug-

gests, there does exist a basic human need to understand the world-particularly the social

world-does this not imply that there must also exist certain inborn mental capacities that

could facilitate this understanding? What are these capacities? What is their relation to the

categories of thought whose origin Durkheim tried to explain sociologically? To what

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 145

extent was Durkheim's cognitive constructivism dependent on his essentialism? While

these questions cannot be answered in reference to the pragmatism lectures alone, one

clear implication of my interpretation of the lectures is that such questions should be

asked. The answers may bear on contemporary controversies in the sociology of knowl-

edge and culture and could support the claims by Schmaus and others that Durkheim was

in no final sense a relativist.

Second, the "religious" interpretation of Durkheim's lectures raises a problem with

contemporary sociological theory's efforts to utilize elements of both pragmatism and

Durkheimian sociology. Whether these efforts take the form of analytic theorizing about

interaction (Turner 1988), new undertakings in action theory (Alexander 1988 and else-

where), or sociological semiotics (Wiley 1994), they usually involve combining some

element of pragmatism's focus on the interactional self with the Durkheimian interest in

social solidarity and the socially integrative effects of shared cultural understandings. For

example, Wiley (1994:104, 132) attempts to demonstrate the existence of a complemen-

tarity between Durkheim's theory of solidarity and the pragmatic theory of the self; he

tries to "show what solidarity means in Durkheim's macro theory and then show how this

idea can be 'lowered,' not only to the level of interaction but also to that of the self" and

to establish that "reflexivity and solidarity can be formally integrated.... Durkheim's

solidarity has always been implicit in Mead's reflexivity."

Although Durkheim is not concerned with interaction in the pragmatism lectures, the

conceptual ground underlying Meadian interactionism had much in common with that

underlying the pragmatic theory of religion. Mead argues that, while meanings always

arise in a context of interaction in which the attitudes of sets of "generalized" others are

interiorized, the sociality of the self exists in a constant state of tension with the unique-

ness of personal experience. The self is constituted of ongoing internal conversations that

depend on available social signs and meanings and of the individual's unique chains of

experience. As Park ([1926] 1967) pointed out in his sociological rendering of pragma-

tism, this tension in the constitution of the self makes communication-involving the

coming together of experientially unique selves who interact only on the basis of what they

have in common-a precondition of moral order. Similarly, James's focus in the 1902

Gifford lectures on the personal aspects of religious experience stemmed in part from his

conviction that all such experience has a common character. By showing the convergence

of all religious experience compared with the divergent nature of different systems of

religious belief, James hoped to lay the theological groundwork for a religious pluralism or

moral order that would defend the right to believe in the existence of the Divine. Solidarity

was to be established not on the basis of collective symbols and ideas, but around the

irreducible commonality of a certain order of experience.

In both Meadian interactionism and the pragmatic theory of religion, then, personal

experience is opposed and yet inextricably tied to common or collective experience. A

different conception of the relationship between individual and collective experience under-

lies the Durkheimian theoretical project. For Durkheim, sociality does not arise from a

common experiential base, but from the ontological nature of the world. The sociality of

experience, in the Durkheimian scheme, largely reflects the extent of the individual's

participation-via collective representations and socially efficacious action-in the onto-

logical order of the social. Thus, experience provides the micro-foundation for the macro-

level variability of social solidarity. But it is unclear whether the pragmatists' conception

of the self, in which the self at any moment is not considered more or less social (though

experience can be more or less personal), is compatible with these Durkheimian micro-

foundations. It is hard to imagine selves, social through and through as pragmatism under-

stands them to be, experiencing anomie in the Durkheimian sense of an inadequate

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
146 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

introjection of the morally regulative aspects of society into the psyche of the individual.

It is therefore worth reconsidering whether pragmatism's theory of the self and Durkheim's

theories of anomie and solidarity can co-exist within the same theoretical frame.'2 I have

tried to show that one of Durkheim's objections to the pragmatic understanding of religion

involved a disagreement over the nature of religious experience, and that this disagreement

was central to Durkheim's pragmatism lectures. Analyses of the relation between the Durkhe-

imian and pragmatic conceptions of religious experience-analyses that could help assess

the theoretical compatibility of Durkheim's views on solidarity and the pragmatic under-

standing of the self-should therefore start with an examination of the lectures.

Advocates of the contextualist method contend that situating a text in its socio-

intellectual context can elucidate an author's intentions. Here the method has highlighted

a dimension of Durkheim's critique that might otherwise have gone unnoticed. While

many questions about Durkheim's relationship to the pragmatists remain unanswered, my

analysis should direct future research on the topic to Durkheim's treatment of Bergsonism,

Catholic Modernism, and other French intellectual discourses that offered experiential and

pragmatic defenses of religious faith.

REFERENCES

Alexander, Jeffrey C. 1988. Action and Its Environments: Toward a New Synthesis. New York: Cambridge

University Press.

Allcock, John B. 1983. "Editorial Introduction to the English Translation." Pp. xxiii-xli in Emile Durkheim,

Pragmatism and Sociology, edited by J. Allcock. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

1992. "Emile Durkheim's Encounter with Pragmatism." Journal of the History of Sociology 4:27-51.

Anonymous. 1908. "Ille Congres de Philosophie -Heidelberg: Le Pragmatisme." Revue de metaphvsique et de

morale 16:930-50.

Antliff, Mark. 1993. Inventing Bergson. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Archambault, P. 1914. "L'oeuvre philosophique de M.E. Boutroux." La Revue de Paris 21:276-96.

Arnal, Oscar L. 1985. Ambivalent Alliance: The Catholic Church and the Action Francaise 1899-1939. Pitts-

burgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

Bellah, Robert N. 1959. "Durkheim and History." Americani Sociological Review 24:447-61.

Bergson, Henri. [1907] 1911. Creative Evolution, translated by A. Mitchell. New York: H. Holt and Company.

Berthelot, Rene. 1911. Un Romantismne utilitaire: Etude sur le mouvement pragmatiste. Paris: Alcan.

Besnard, Philippe. 1987. L'Anomie, ses usages et ses foictions dans la discipline sociologique depuis Durkheim.

Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

Binet, Alfred. 1908. "Une Enquete sur 1'evolution de l'enseignement de la philosophie." L'Annde psychologique

14:152-231.

Blumer, Herbert. 1966. "Sociological Implications of the Thought of George Herbert Mead." American Journal

of Sociology 71:535-44.

Bompaire-Evesque, Claire-Francoise. 1988. Un Debat sur I'universitd au temps de la Troisibme Republique: La

lutte contre la Nouvelle Sorbonne. Paris: Aux Amateurs de Livres.

12 There are at least two objections to this argument. First, the inherent sociality of the self may be distinct

from the degree to which the self is entered by society in a morally determinative sense (Wrong 1961). To say that

Durkheim tended to conflate these two properties of the self hardly proves that they are theoretically incompat-

ible. Second, social disorganization can exist at the level of the aggregate without the members of that aggregate

being in some way less than fully social. Would these objections satisfy Durkheim? If not, what aspects of

Durkheim's sociology-if we accept the presuppositional base underlying the pragmatic theory of the self-are

we deprived of using if we want to advance an internally consistent theoretical position? See Besnard (1987:159-

163) on the Chicago School's treatment of anomie, Blumer (1966:544) on the incompatibilities of the views of

Mead and Parsons (and by extension Mead and Durkheim) on the nature of social unity and solidarity, and

Lehmann (1995) on the postulated asociality of women in Durkheim's theory. Lehmann argues that Durkheim

did not conclude that all humans are social from the fact that all humans live in and negotiate a linguistic/symbol-

laden environment. Moreover, Lehmann claims that Durkheim used women's putative asociality and its osten-

sible biological basis to attempt to explain away certain anomalies in his theory of suicide. Durkheim could not

have made such an argument had he employed a different conception of sociality. This suggests there may be

similar problems with recent efforts that use a notion of solidarity originally designed around an ontological, as

opposed to an interactional, understanding of the social.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES
147

Bourdeau, Jean. 1909. Pragmatisme et modernisme. Paris: Alcan.

. 1912. La Philosophie affective. Paris: Alcan.

Boutroux, Emile. [1908] 1911. Science and Religion in Contemporary Philosophy, translated by J. Nield. New

York: The Macmillan Company.

. 1912. William James, translated by A. Henderson and B. Henderson. New York: Longmans, Green, and

Co.

Bury, J.P.T. 1950. France 1814-1940. London: Methuen.

Camic, Charles. 1987. "The Making of a Method: A Historical Reinterpretation of the Early Parsons." American

Sociological Review 52:421-39.

Cladis, Mark S. 1991. "Durkheim, Goodman, Rorty, and Mild-Mannered Pragmatism: French and American

Style." Stanford French Review 15:139-63.

Clark, Terry N. 1973. Prophets and Patrons: The French University and the Emergence of the Social Sciences.

Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Claviere, J. 1913. "Table Analytique des Matieres, 1906-1912: Pragmatisme, Pragmaticisme, Empirisme radical,

Humanisme, Psychologisme, Sociologisme, Volontarisme." Revue philosophique (supplement) 76:93-94.

Curley, E.M. 1978. Descartes Against the Skeptics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Cuvillier, Armand. [1955] 1983. "Preface to the French Edition of 1955." Pp. xi-xxii in Emile Durkheim, Prag-

matism and Sociology, edited by J. Allcock. Translated by J.C. Whitehouse. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Daly, Gabriel. 1980. Transcendence and Immanence: A Study in Catholic Modernism and Integralism. Oxford:

Clarendon Press.

De Gaudemar, Paul. 1969. "Les Ambiguites de la critique Durkheimienne du pragmatisme." La Pensee 145:81-

88.

Durkheim, Emile. [1895] 1938. The Rules of Sociological Method, translated by S. Solovay and J. Mueller.

Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

. [1912] 1915. The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life, translated by J. Swain. New York: Collier.

[1955] 1983. Pragmatism and Sociology, edited by J. Allcock. Translated by J.C. Whitehouse. Cam-

bridge: Cambridge University Press.

Durkheim, Emile and Marcel Mauss. [1903] 1963. Primitive Classification, translated by R. Needham. Chicago:

The University of Chicago Press.

Fouillee, Alfred. 1911. La Pensee et les nouvelles ecoles anti-intellectualistes. Paris: Alcan.

Gell, Alfred. 1992. The Anthropology of Time. Oxford: Berg.

Godlove, Terry J. 1986. "Epistemology in Durkheim's Elementary Forms of Religious Life." Journal of the

History of Philosophy 24:385-401.

Greenberg, Louis M. 1981. "Architects of the New Sorbonne: Liard's Purpose and Durkheim's Role." History of

Education Quarterly 21:77-103.

Grogin, Robert C. 1988. The Bergsonian Controversy in France 1900-1914. Calgary: The University of Calgary

Press.

Gunter, Pete A. 1966. "Bergson's Reflective Anti-intellectualism." The Personalist 47:43-60.

Habermas, Jurgen. 1983. The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1-2, translated by T. McCarthy. Boston:

Beacon Press.

Hebert, Marcel. 1908. Le Pragmatisme. Etude de ses diversesformes Anglo-Americaines, Francaises, Italiennes

et de sa valeur religieuse. Paris: Emile Nourry.

Hughes, H. Stuart. 1958. Consciousness and Society. New York: Vintage Books.

Jacoby, Gunther. 1912. "Henri Bergson, Pragmatism and Schopenhauer." The Monist 22:593-611.

James, William. [1896] 1948. "The Will to Believe." Pp. 88-109 in William James: Essays in Pragmatism, edited

by A. Castell. New York: Hafner.

. [1902] 1987. The Varieties of Religious Experience. Pp. 1-477 in William James: Writings 1902-1910,

edited by B. Kuklick. New York: The Library of America.

. [1907] 1987. Pragmatism. Pp. 479-624 in William James: Writings 1902-1910, edited by B. Kuklick.

New York: The Library of America.

[1909] 1943. A Pluralistic Universe. New York: Longmans, Green and Co.

Joas, Hans. 1996. The Creativity of Action, translated by J. Gaines and P. Keast. Chicago: The University of

Chicago Press.

1993. Pragmatism and Social Theory. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

1995. "The Constitution of Ultimate Values in Human Action: A Comparison of Durkheim's Elementary

Forms and the Pragmatic Theory of Religion." Presented at a conference on "Re-assessing Durkheim's Ele-

mentary Fortns," British Centre for Durkheimian Studies, July 12-15, Oxford, UK.

Jones, Robert A. 1977. "On Understanding a Sociological Classic." American Journal of Sociology 83:279-319.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
148 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

. 1994. "Ambivalent Cartesians: Durkheim, Montesquieu, and Method." American Journal of Sociology

100:1-39.

. 1995. "Religion and Science in Les Formes elementaires de la vie religieuse." Presented at a conference

on "Re-assessing Durkheim's Elementary Forms," British Centre for Durkheimian Studies, July 12-15, Oxford,

UK.

Jones, S.G. Stedman. 1995. "Charles Renouvier and Emile Durkheim: 'Les Regles de la methode sociologique'."

Sociological Perspectives 38:27-40.

Karady, Vincent. 1983. "The Durkheimians in Academe. A reconsideration." Pp. 71-89 in The Sociological

Domtain: The Durkheimians and the Founding of French Sociology, edited by P. Besnard. Cambridge: Cam-

bridge University Press.

Kaufman-Osborn, Timothy V. 1991. Politics/Sense/Experience. A Pragmatic Inquiry into the Promise of Democ-

racy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Kurtz, Lester R. 1986. The Politics of Heresy: The Modernist Crisis in Roman Catholicism. Berkeley and Los

Angeles: University of California Press.

Lalande, Andre. 1906. "Pragmatisme et pragmaticisme." Revue philosophique 61:121-46.

Langsdorf, Lenore and Andrew R. Smith, eds. 1995. Recovering Pragmatisn's Voice: The Classical Tradition,

Rorty, and the Philosophy of Communication. Albany: SUNY Press.

Lehmann, Jennifer. 1995. "Durkheim's Theories of Deviance and Suicide: A Feminist Reconsideration." Amer-

ican Journal of Sociology 100:904-30.

Leroux, Emmanuel. 1922. Le Pragmatisme, Americain et Anglais, Etude historique et critique. Paris: Alcan.

Le Roy, Edouard. 1907. Dogme et critique. Paris: Bloud.

. 1908. Contribution to Discussion. Bulletin de la Socidte Francaise de Philosophie 8:249-96.

Lukes, Steven. 1972. Emile Durkheim. His Life and Work. New York: Harper and Row.

Martin du Gard, Roger. [1913] 1949. Jean Barois, translated by S. Gilbert. New York: The Viking Press.

Mauss, Marcel. 1925. "L'oeuvre inedite de Durkheim et de ses collaborateurs." L'Annee sociologique n.s. [1923-

1924] 1:7-29.

Mestrovic, Stjepan G. 1993. Emile Durkheim and the Reformation of Sociology. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman

and Littlefield.

Morkovsky, Mary C. 1972. "Intellectual Analysis in Bergson's Theory of Knowing." Journal of the History of

Philosophy 10:43-54.

Park, Robert E. [1926] 1967. "The Urban Community as a Spatial Pattern and a Moral Order." Pp. 55-68 in On

Social Control and Collective Behavior, edited by R. Turner. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Parodi, Dominique. 1908a. "Le Pragmatisme d'apres MM. W. James et Schiller." Revue de metaphysique et de

miorale 16:93-112.

. 1908b. Contribution to Discussion. Bulletin de la Societe Francaise de Philosophie 8:249-96.

Pickering, W.S.F. 1994. "On the Enigma of Durkheim's Jewishness." Pp. 10-39 in Debating Durkheim, edited by

W.S.F. Pickering and H. Martins. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

. 1984. Durkheim 's Sociology of Religion: Themes and Theories. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Pickering, W.S.F and Herminio Martins. 1994. "Introduction." Pp. 1-9 in Debating Durkheim, edited by W.S.F.

Pickering and H. Martins. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Putnam, Hilary. 1995. Pragmatism: An Open Question. Oxford: Blackwell.

Ranchetti, Michele. 1969. The Catholic Modernists: A Study of the Religious Reform Movement 1864-1907,

translated by I. Quigly. London: Oxford University Press.

Rawls, Anne. 1996. "Durkheim's Epistemology: The Neglected Argument." American Journal of Sociology

102:430-82.

Rey, Abel. 1908. La Philosophie moderne. Paris: Flammarion.

Robet, Henri. 1912. "La Signification et la valeur du pragmatisme." Revue philosophique 74:568-601; 75:156-

83.

Rochberg-Halton, Eugene. 1986. Meaning and Modernity: Social Theory in the Pragmatic Attitude. Chicago:

The University of Chicago Press.

Rorty, Richard. 1982. Consequences of Pragmatismn. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Saatkamp, Herman J., ed. 1995. RortY and Pragmatism: The Philosopher Responds to his Critics. Nashville:

Vanderbilt University Press.

Schinz, Albert. 1909. Anti-Pragmatism: An Examination into the Respective Rights of Intellectual Aristocracy

and Social Democracy, translated by A. Schinz. Boston: Small, Maynard and Comany.

Schmaus, Warren. 1994. Durkheim 's Philosophy of Science and the Sociology of Knowledge: Creating an Intel-

lectual Niche. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

. 1995. "Durkheim on the Causes and Functions of the Categories." Presented at a conference on "Re-

assessing Durkheim's Elementary Forms." British Centre for Durkheimian Studies, July 12-15, Oxford, UK.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DURKHEIM'S PRAGMATISM LECTURES 149

.1996. "Introduction: Durkheimian Sociology in Philosophical Context." Journal of the History of the

Behavioral Sciences 32:327-29.

Schwartz, Sanford. 1992. "Bergson and the Politics of Vitalism." Pp. 277-305 in The Crisis in Modernism:

Bergson and the Vitalist Controversy, edited by F. Burwick and P. Douglass. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-

sity Press.

Shalin, Dmitri. 1992. "Critical Theory and the Pragmatist Challenge." American Jounllal of Sociology 98:237-

79.

Simon, Paul. 1918. "Der pragmatismus in der modernen franzoesischen philosophie." Doctoral Thesis, Univer-

sitat Freiburg.

Skinner, Quentin. 1988. "Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas." Pp. 29-68 in Meaning and

Context: Quentin Skitnner and His Critics, edited by J. Tully. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Sorel, Georges. [1908] 1950. Reflections on Violence, translated by T. Hulme and J. Roth. Glencoe: The Free

Press.

.1909. "La Religion d'aujourd'hui." Revue de metaphysique et de morale 17:240-73; 17:413-47.

Stock, Phyllis H. 1966. "New Quarrel of Ancients and Moderns: The French University and Its Opponents,

1899-1914." Ph.D. Dissertation, Yale University.

Stone, Gregory and Harvey Farberman. [1967] 1990. "On the Edge of Rapprochement: Was Durkheim Moving

Toward the Perspective of Symbolic Interaction?" Pp. 26-42 in Emile Durkheim: Critical Assessments, edited

by P. Hamilton. London: Routledge.

Thayer, H.S. 1968. Meaning and Action.' A Critical History of Pragmatism. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill

Company.

Turner, Jonathan H. 1988. A Theory of Social Interaction. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Vanden Burgt, Robert J. 1981. The Religious Philosophy of William James. Chicago: Nelson-Hall.

Vialatoux, J. 1939. De Durkheim C Bergson. Paris: Bloud & Gay.

Weber, Eugen. 1968. The Nationalist Revival in France, 1905-1914. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of

California Press.

.1986. France: Fin de Siecle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Wiley, Norbert. 1994. The Semiotic Self. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Wrong, Dennis. 1961. "The Oversocialized Conception of Man in Modern Sociology." American Sociological

Review 26:183-93.

This content downloaded from 193.140.143.174 on Mon, 21 Mar 2016 18:35:32 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like