Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci.

39 (2008) 483–494

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci.


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

The psychology of Kant’s aesthetics


Paul Guyer
Department of Philosophy, University of Pennsylvania, 433 Claudia Cohen Hall, Philadelphia, PA 19104-6304, USA

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Keywords: Contrary to both his own intentions and the views of both older and more recent commentators, I argue
Alexander Gerard that Kant’s aesthetics remains within the confines of eighteenth-century aesthetics as a branch of empir-
Henry Home, Lord Kames ical psychology, as it was then practiced. Kant established a plausible connection between aesthetic expe-
Immanuel Kant rience and judgment on the one hand and cognition in general on the other, through his explanatory
Beauty
concept of the free play of our cognitive powers. However, there is nothing distinctly ‘a priori’ or ‘tran-
Taste
Free play of the cognitive powers
scendental’ in his claim that this state of mind is what causes our pleasure in beauty or other aesthetic
properties. Nor did Kant establish a genuinely a priori or transcendental principle that all human beings
have the same disposition to experience a free play of their cognitive powers, let alone in response to the
same objects. This failure, however, in no way limits the continuing significance of Kant’s aesthetic
theory.
Ó 2008 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

1. The psychology of Kant’s aesthetics: transcendental or we endorse the transcendental perspective of the third Critique.
empirical? For its specificity lays in a transcendental a priori principle, not
in a metaphysical or a psychological difference between ani-
Should Kant’s theory of beauty, sublimity, and taste be consid- mals, human beings, and pure spirits. (Nuzzo, 2006, p. 590)
ered a continuation of the eighteenth-century and especially Brit-
But are they right?
ish exploration of these topics as part of empirical psychology—
There can be no doubt that the claim that Kant’s aesthetics is a
the approach that David Hume, for example, had in mind when
genuine part of his transcendental psychology and not mere
he wrote that ‘criticism’, along with logic, morals, and politics, is
empirical psychology has Kant’s own authority behind it. Kant’s
part of the ‘science of man’, the ‘only solid foundation’ for which
own transition from the position that aesthetics is part of merely
‘itself must be laid on experience and observation’ (Hume, 2000,
empirical psychology to the position that it has a priori principles
p. 4)—or does it employ a different approach that can only be
that entitle it to transcendental status is evident in a series of com-
understood as part of a genuinely ‘transcendental’ psychology?
ments from the first edition of the Critique of pure reason to the sec-
Distinguished commentators have believed the latter; for example,
ond edition of the Critique of the power of judgment. In a footnote to
half a century ago Ernst Cassirer praised Kant for accomplishing a
the ‘Transcendental aesthetic’ in the 1781 first edition of the first
‘transition from the psychological to the transcendental approach’
Critique, Kant wrote that Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten’s coinage
in aesthetics, in spite of that fact that ‘In no other field’ was this
of the term ‘aesthetics’ represented a ‘failed hope . . . of bringing
transition ‘so hard to realize and burdened with so many system-
the critical estimation of the beautiful under principles of reason,
atic difficulties as in that of the fundamental problems of aesthet-
and elevating its rules to a science’. Such an effort is doomed, Kant
ics’ (Cassirer, 1951, p. 298), while most recently Angelica Nuzzo
explained,
has written that
For the putative rules or criteria are merely empirical as far as
Kant’s fundamental claim is that taste can indeed be seen as rep-
their sources are concerned, and can therefore never serve as
resenting an independent sphere of experience . . . if, and only if,
a priori rules according to which our judgment of taste must

E-mail address: pguyer@phil.upenn.edu

0039-3681/$ - see front matter Ó 2008 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2008.09.010
484 P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494

be directed, rather the latter constitutes the genuine touchstone such an approach would lead, Kant continues, is to ‘psychological
for the correctness of the former. (Kant, 1998, p. 156; A 21)1 remarks’ that are ‘extremely fine, and provide rich materials for
the favorite researches of empirical psychology’, but not to genu-
For the 1787 second edition, however, Kant modified this clear
ine judgments of taste that can ‘command’ the assent of others, for
relegation of judgments of taste and their rules to the empirical
these ‘must be grounded in some sort of a priori principle (whether
domain with the less commital statement that
objective or subjective), which one can never arrive at by scouting
the putative rules or criteria [for judgments of taste] are merely about among empirical laws of the alteration of the mind’ (Kant,
empirical as far as their <most prominent> sources are con- 2000, pp. 158–159; CPJ, General Remark following §29, 5:277–
cerned, and can therefore never serve as <determinate> a priori 278). And these are just a sample of Kant’s claims on behalf of his
rules according to which our judgment of taste must be direc- own approach.
ted. (Kant, 1998, p. 173; B 35) So there can be no question that Kant himself thought that he
had discovered an a priori and transcendental method for aesthetics
It is not clear what Kant’s first modification is supposed to mean, that is different from the method of empirical psychology employed
but the second certainly leaves room for the view that although aes- by Hume, Burke, and many others among his ‘acute’ contemporar-
thetics can never furnish determinate rules for the judgment of par- ies. My question is rather whether Kant was right to think that he
ticular objects—a position that Kant would never abandon—it does had succeeded in grounding aesthetics in some sort of transcenden-
yield some sort of indeterminate rules for the judgment of objects tal rather than empirical psychology. My answer is that he was not
that are in some way a priori and therefore cannot be grounded in right to think so, and that, at least so far as they are plausible, the
any merely empirical ‘experience and observation’ of human psy- central concepts and claims of Kant’s aesthetics remain within the
chology, but must have some sort of transcendental foundation. confines of eighteenth-century aesthetics as a branch of empirical
And then by the time he published the Critique of the power of judg- psychology. I will argue that Kant established a plausible connec-
ment in 1790, Kant was clearly committed to the view that aesthet- tion between aesthetic experience and judgment on the one hand,
ics does have a priori principles that cannot be grounded in any sort and cognition in general on the other, by tracing our pleasure in aes-
of empirical psychology. In the opening paragraphs of the work, thetic experiences to a free play between the cognitive faculties of
Kant states that imagination and understanding in the case of the beautiful, or
imagination and reason in the case of the sublime. I will also argue
those judgings that are called aesthetic, which concern the
that he showed that such experiences could include play with
beautiful and the sublime in nature or in art . . . although by
concepts, notably moral concepts, that are on Kant’s own account
themselves they contribute nothing at all to the cognition of
a priori, without sacrificing what makes them uniquely aesthetic.
things, still . . . belong to the faculty of cognition alone, and
In addition, however, I will argue that there is nothing distinctively
demonstrate [beweisen] an immediate relation of this faculty
a priori or transcendental in Kant’s claim that the free play of these
to the feeling of pleasure or displeasure in accordance with
powers is what causes our pleasure in the beautiful or the sublime. I
some a priori principle. (Kant, 2000, p. 57; CPJ, Preface, 5:169)
thus suggest that this thesis itself can only be understood as a piece
In a later section that defends the thesis that ‘No objective principle of empirical psychology, and that Kant does not succeed in estab-
of taste is possible’, Kant maintains that although Hume was correct lishing as a genuine a priori or transcendental principle the under-
to claim that as far as particular judgments of taste are concerned, lying assumption of judgments of taste that all human beings have
‘although critics . . . can reason more plausibly than cooks, they still the same disposition to experience a free play of their cognitive
suffer the same fate as them’,2 namely that they ‘cannot expect a powers, let alone in regard to particular objects. Kant translates
determining ground for their judgments from proofs’, nevertheless concepts of eighteenth-century aesthetics into his own distinctive
Hume was wrong to conclude that aesthetics (‘criticism’) can only language and refines them, but does not transform eighteenth-cen-
be part of an empirical science of man. Rather, Kant argues, although tury aesthetics from empirical into transcendental psychology.
‘Criticism, as an art, merely seeks to apply the physiological (here I argue for this conclusion in three steps. First, I consider some
psychological) and hence empirical rules, according to which taste examples of eighteenth-century conceptions of aesthetic experi-
actually proceeds to the judging of its objects (without reflecting ence that are clearly similar to Kant’s, but equally clearly make
on its possibility)’, his own account of the very possibility of judg- no pretensions to being anything but empirical, and then I argue
ments of taste that are universally valid even though they can nei- that Kant’s pre-critical theory of aesthetic response, while intro-
ther depend upon nor yield determinate rules about conditions ducing the key concepts of his mature view, does not differ in
under which particular objects are always beautiful or sublime, is method from these other eighteenth-century theories (Sections 2
a ‘science’ that ‘derives the possibility of such a judging from the and 3). Second, I examine Kant’s mature accounts of our experi-
nature of this faculty [that is, taste] as a faculty of cognition in gen- ences of beauty in nature and art and of sublimity chiefly in nature,
eral’, a ‘transcendental critique’ that ‘should develop and justify the showing that while they involve faculties that in other contexts
subjective principle of taste as an a priori principle of the power of Kant held to employ a priori concepts and principles, there is no
judgment’ (Kant, 2000, p. 166; CPJ, §34, 5:285–286). And on the sub- fundamental difference between Kant’s accounts of these aesthetic
ject of the sublime, Kant states that his ‘transcendental exposition of experiences and accounts by others, including that of his earlier
aesthetic judgments . . . can be compared with the physiological self—and thus that there is nothing essentially a priori and tran-
exposition’—indeed, in the first edition of the third Critique he wrote scendental about Kant’s model (Section 4). Finally, I argue that
‘psychological exposition’—‘as it has been elaborated by a Burke and Kant is not entitled to his claim that there is an underlying princi-
many acute men among us, in order to see where a merely empirical ple for judgments of taste that is essentially a priori and thus be-
exposition of the sublime and the beautiful would lead’. Where longs to transcendental rather than empirical psychology

1
Citations from the Critique of pure reason are from the translation by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Kant, 1998), and use the pagination of the first (‘A’) and/or second (‘B’)
edition. Translations from the Critique of the power of judgment are from the translation by Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews (Kant, 2000) and use Kant’s section numbers and the
pagination from the Academy edition (Kant 1900–), Volume 5, with the abbreviation CPJ. Quotations from the Critique of practical reason (CPracR) and the Metaphysics of morals
(MM) are from Kant (1996). Quotations from Kant’s Reflexionen (R) are from Kant (2005). Kant’s emphasis is rendered with boldface type, corresponding to his use of Fettdruck; his
use of Roman type for what he regarded as Lehnwörter is rendered with italics. Other uses of italics are for my own emphasis.
2
Kant refers to a remark in Hume’s essay ‘The sceptic’, in Hume (1987), p. 163.
P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494 485

(Section 5). I conclude by briefly suggesting that the enduring (ibid., §III, p. 31). As his division of taste into several simple princi-
interest of Kant’s aesthetics is in no way diminished by the rejec- ples has already shown, Gerard sees no need to reduce all aesthetic
tion of its putatively transcendental status (Section 6). experiences to any single phenomenon. For our purposes, we will
not need to consider all the kinds of beauty he recognizes, but
can focus on the ‘first species’ of beauty, belonging ‘to objects pos-
2. Empirical theories of aesthetic experience sessed of uniformity, variety, and proportion’, each of which qualities
by itself ‘pleases in some degree’ while ‘all of them united give
In this section I present a few examples of eighteenth-century exquisite satisfaction’. What is relevant for us is that each of these
analyses of our experiences of the beautiful and the sublime that varieties and subvarieties of experience of beauty is explained by
made no pretense to being anything but empirical. an appeal to a kind of free yet harmonious mental activity. Thus,
Let us consider the case of the beautiful first. The heart of Kant’s our pleasure in uniformity and simplicity is due to ‘Facility in the
mature theory of the judgment of the beautiful is that the mental conception of an object’, in which
state that grounds such a judgment is an activity of the free play
of the imagination with the forms intuited in the reception or cre- the mind thinks well of itself, when it is able to form it’s concep-
ation of an object which is in some way harmonious with the tion without pain or labour . . . Objects endued with these qual-
understanding’s demand for unity in experience in general. The ities enter easily into the mind: they do not distract our
pleasure in our experience of a beautiful object attention, or hurry us too fast from one scene to another: the
view of a part suggests the whole, and, impelling the mind to
can express nothing but its suitability to the cognitive faculties imagine the rest, produces a grateful exertion of its energy.
that are in play in the reflecting power of judgment, insofar as (Ibid., pp. 31–32)
they are in play . . . For that apprehension of forms in the imag-
ination can never take place without the reflecting power of The words are not exactly the same as Kant’s, to be sure, but several
judgment, even if unintentionally, at least comparing them to elements of Kant’s conception of the free and harmonious play of
its faculty for relating intuitions to concepts. (Kant, 2000, p. imagination and understanding are already suggested here: the
76; CPJ, Introduction, §VII, 5: 189–190) easy entrance of qualities into the mind, like Kant’s unintentional
comparison; the imagination of a whole that is intimated rather
The idea of aesthetic experience as an activity of the mind playing than directly given; and the pleasing exertion of the mind. Similarly,
with represented forms of objects was hardly original to Kant, but when Gerard describes the beauty of variety that complements the
was common among the British aestheticians who clearly intended beauty of uniformity, which, ‘when perfect and unmixed, is apt to
their theories of beauty and taste to be part of their empirical sci- pall upon the sense, to grow languid, and to sink the mind into an
ence of man, and entered Germany through their influence. uneasy state of indolence’ (could this be the source for Kant’s
Two British theorists whose works Kant knew well and men- description of what happens when beauty is too regular, as in Mars-
tioned often in his lectures on anthropology, a major source for den’s Sumatran pepper garden? (See Kant, 2000, p. 126; CPJ, General
the development of his aesthetics, are the Scots Alexander Gerard Remark following §22, 5:243), what he says is that ‘as our ideas vary
and Henry Home, Lord Kames. Gerard’s Essay on taste won the prize in passing from the contemplation of one part to that of another[,
of the Edinburgh Society for the Encouragement of Arts, Sciences, t]his transition puts the mind in action, and gives it employment,
Manufactures, and Agriculture in 1757, was published in 1759 with the consciousness of which is agreeable’ (Gerard, 1759, pp. 33–
translations of essays on taste by Voltaire, D’Alembert and Monte- 34). Here Gerard describes the mind’s sense of its own activity in
squieu appended, and translated into German in 1766 (Gerard, passing freely from the contemplation of one part of an object to an-
1759, 1766). Kames’s Elements of criticism was first published in other as a source of our pleasure in its beauty.
1762, and by 1763 had enjoyed both a second edition (the first of Gerard does not explicitly describe his own methodology as
many further editions) as well as the first volume of a German trans- that of empirical psychology, but in the train of Hume’s ‘science
lation, the latter completed in 1766, the same year as the publication of man’ did not need to. Kames, who was instrumental in setting
of the translated Gerard.3 Gerard ‘resolves’ taste into the ‘simple prin- the essay question for the Edinburgh Society and awarding Gerard
ciples’ of the sense or taste of novelty, sublimity, beauty, imitation, the prize, does not use this terminology either, but his empiricist
harmony, oddity and ridicule, and virtue (Gerard, 1759, p. iii). He be- methodology is evident in the language of tracing natural connec-
gins his discussion of the sense of novelty with the claim that ‘We have tions in which he describes his project:
a pleasant sensation, whenever the mind is in a lively and elevated
temper’, and ascribes such a ‘temper’ to the activity of the mind when The design of the present undertaking, which aspires not to
it overcomes some sort of difficulty or other: the mind morality, is, to examine the sensitive branch of human nature,
to trace the objects that are naturally agreeable, as well as those
attains this temper, when it is forced to exert its activity, and that are naturally disagreeable; and by these means to discover,
put forth its strength, in order to surmount any difficulty: and if we can, what are the genuine principles of the fine arts.
if is efforts prove successful, consciousness of the success (Kames, 2005 [1775], Original Introduction, Vol. I, p. 14)
inspires new joy. Hence moderate difficulty, such as exercises
the mind, without fatiguing it, is pleasant, and renders the Within this framework, Kames describes the paradigmatic aesthetic
object by which it is produced agreeable. (Gerard, 1759, Pt. I, ‘pleasures of the eye and the ear’ as mediating or effecting a har-
§I, pp. 3–4) mony between our lower and higher cognitive powers. These
pleasures,
The pleasure of novelty arises when we make new discoveries in
‘study and investigation of every kind’, even when that may require being . . . elevated above those of the other external senses,
considerable effort (ibid., p. 5). The sense of beauty is more com- acquire so much dignity as to become a laudable entertainment.
plex. ‘Beautiful objects’, Gerard writes, ‘are of different kinds, and They are not, however, set on a level with the purely intellec-
produce pleasure by means of different principles of human nature’ tual; being no less inferior in dignity to intellectual pleasures,

3
Kames (1762); I cite the recent edition of Kames’s sixth edition (Kames, 2005 [1785]). The first edition of the German translation was by J. H. N. Meinhard, in three volumes
(Kames, 1763–1766), with a revised edition in 1772.
486 P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494

than superior to the organic or corporeal . . . Their mixt nature mind expands itself to the extent of that object, and is filled
and middle place between organic and intellectual plesures, with one grand sensation, which totally possessing it, composes
qualify them to associate with both: beauty heightens all the it into a solemn sedateness, and strikes it with a deep silent
organic feelings, as well as the intellectual: harmony, though wonder and admiration: it finds such a difficulty in spreading
it aspires to enflame devotion, disdains not to improve the rel- itself to the dimensions of its object, as enlivens and invigorates
ish of a banquet. (Ibid., p. 12) its frame: and having overcome the opposition which this occa-
sions, it . . . feels a noble pride, and entertains a lofty conception
The conception of the experience of beauty as harmonizing different
of its own capacity. (Gerard, 1759, Pt. I, §II, p. 14)
cognitive capacities is certainly present within empiricist
aesthetics. In this paragraph, Gerard describes the mind as active in the expe-
The foundation of Kames’s aesthetic theory is the idea that a rience of the sublime, as overcoming in some way the difficulty of
person is always conscious of a ‘continued train of perceptions grasping the vast dimensions of the object of its experience, and
and ideas passing in his mind’ (ibid., Ch. I, Vol. I, p. 21); that this as feeling a pride in its own capacity to do this. He also describes
train of ideas is often stimulated and directed by objects without the tone of the mind’s feeling in all of this as one of solemn admi-
any activity on the part of the person who experiences it, but that ration rather than grateful pleasure, the sorts of terms that Gerard
the train of ideas can also be directed in various ways by that per- used in his account of the experience of beauty. Gerard’s account
son; that pleasure arises when the train is orderly and connected; parallels Kant’s in both its description of the mind as overcoming
and that works of art in particular—art rather than nature is the an initial obstacle in an effort at comprehending or grasping an ob-
primary focus of Kames’s ‘criticism’—please when the train of ideas ject and its claim that the satisfaction in the sublime is qualitatively
they stimulate is conformable to the mind’s own tendency to or- different from the more straightforward or simpler pleasure in the
derly trains of ideas. Kames describes the mind as active in follow- beautiful. But in spite of these similarities, there can be no question
ing our orderly trains of ideas and in finding order in pleasing that Gerard’s account is meant to be strictly empirical.
works of art. First, Kames describes the pleasure that we take in ac- Kames’s account of ‘Grandeur and sublimity’ could well have
tively tracing or following natural connections: been a source for Kant’s account, since he uses the same examples
that Kant was subsequently to use: ‘Thus St. Peter’s church at
The principle of order is conspicuous with respect to natural
Rome, the great pyramid of Egypt, the Alps towering above the
operations; for it always directs our ideas in the order of nature;
clouds, a great arm of the sea, and above all a clear and serene
thinking upon a body in motion, we follow its natural course; the
sky, are grand’ (Kames, 2005 [1775], Ch. IV, Vol. I, p. 151).4 How-
mind falls with a heavy body, descends with a river, and ascends
ever, although many authors before Kames had used the terms
with flame and smoke; in tracing out a family, we incline to
‘grand’ and ‘sublime’ interchangeably, Kames uses them to mark a
begin at the founder, and to descend gradually to his latest pos-
distinction that neither his predecessors nor Kant made: for Kames,
terity . . . (Ibid., p. 25; my emphasis)
sublimity refers to the sheer magnitude of objects, while an object ‘is
This is a clearly description of unintentional but orderly mental not termed grand . . . unless, together with its size, it be possessed of
activity, finding connection and harmony among ideas and objects other qualities that contribute to beauty, such a regularity, propor-
without consciously subjecting them to any rule. Kames then lo- tion, order, or colour’, and in fact St. Peter’s and the pyramids are
cates beauty in art in its satisfaction of this disposition toward unin- called grand because they have such properties in addition to their
tentional yet orderly mental activity: magnitude, unlike ‘a huge mass of rubbish, the ruins perhaps of
some extensive building’, an ‘overgrown whale’, and so on, which
Every work of art that is conformable to the natural course of may be sublime but not grand (ibid., pp. 151–152). But the main
our ideas, is so far agreeable; and every work of art that reverses point here is that Kames, like Gerard before and Kant after him, char-
that course, is so far disagreeable. Hence it is required in every acterizes the experience of grandeur, which includes the element of
such work, that, like an organic system, its parts be orderly sublimity although some experiences of sublimity are not experi-
arranged and mutually connected, bearing each of them a rela- ences of grandeur, as a form of mental activity that results in a kind
tion to the whole, some more intimate, some less, according to of satisfaction that is qualititatively or tonally distinct from pleasure
their destination: when due regard is had to these particulars, in beauty.
we have a sense of just composition, and so far are pleased with
The qualities of grandeur and beauty are not more distinct, than
the performance. (Ibid., p. 27)
the emotions are which these qualities produce in a spectator
Kames describes beautiful nature as that with the sight or sound of . . . all the various emotions of beauty have one common charac-
which our minds can play freely yet harmoniously, and beautiful art ter, that of sweetness and gaiety. The emotion of grandeur has a
as that which stimulates the mind to the same kind of pleasing different character: a large object that is agreeable, occupies the
activity as beautiful nature does. whole attention, and swells the heart into a vivid emotion,
We can also find descriptions of the experience of the sublime which, tho’ extremely pleasant, is rather serious than gay. (Ibid.,
in Gerard and Kames that anticipate aspects of Kant’s account p. 152)
while remaining firmly within the domain of empirical psychology.
Both the point that the sublime occupies the mind fully and the
Gerard describes the experience of sublimity thus:
point that our emotion toward it is serious rather than gay are rep-
We always contemplate objects and ideas with a disposition resented, naturally in his own language, in Kant’s account; our
similar to their nature. When a large object is presented, the question for Kant’s account will be whether there is anything in

4
Kant uses the examples of St. Peter’s and the pyramids (Kant, 2000, pp. 135–136; CPJ, §26, 5:252). Since Kant never travelled to Italy or Egypt, he must have gotten these
examples from some literary source or sources. He does refer to the Lettres sur l’Egypte, où l’on offre le parallèle des moeurs anciennes et moderns de ses habitants of Claude-Etienne
Savary (1787) for the point that one must be at the right distance from the pyramids for them to have their proper impact, and likewise for sublime vistas in nature. But there is no
mention of St. Peter’s in Savary, so Kant may have been adding this point to these examples that he had taken from Kames years before he read Savary. Kant had also mentioned
both St. Peter’s and the pyramids in his early Observations on the feeling of the beautiful and sublime (1764), referring his comments on the pyramids there (2:210) to a work by
Frederik Hasselquist, Reise nach Palästina in den Jahren 1749–62 (Rostock, 1762). Given the subject of that work, presumably the reference to St. Peter’s came from elsewhere. Since
the first volumes of the German translation of Kames came out in 1763, Kant could have been reading them shortly before writing the Observations. But perhaps St. Peter’s and the
pyramids were such stock examples of the grand or sublime that both Kames and Kant obtained them from earlier sources.
P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494 487

it that transforms it from empirical into transcendental The essence of both the creation and the reception of poetry is a free
psychology. play of thought that is stimulated by the themes of the poem and
Before turning to Kant, we might note another aspect of facilitated by the formal features of the verse such as rhythm and
Kames’s account of the sublime that is not paralleled in either rhyme; here we have Kant’s later theory of ‘aesthetic ideas’ in a nut-
Gerard’s or Kant’s accounts. This is Kames’s observation of the shell, and a contrast between poetry as play and other forms of dis-
bodily as well as mental aspect of the experience of the sublime: course as labor that he would always preserve (ibid., p. 198; CPJ,
§51, 5:321). In the discussion of poetry in the Friedländer lectures
A great object makes the spectator endeavour to enlarge his
in anthropology of several years later (1775–1776), Kant’s com-
bulk; which is remarkable in plain people who give way to nat-
ments on aesthetics similarly begin with this account of the experi-
ure without reserve; in describing a great object, they naturally
ence of poetry:
expand themselves by drawing in the air with all their force. An
elevated object . . . makes the spectator stretch upward, and The play of thoughts and sensations is the correspondence [or
stand a-tiptoe. (Ibid., p. 151) harmony: Übereinstimmung] of subjective [or subjectivistic:
This emphasis on the bodily effect of aesthetic experience and the subjektivischen] laws; if the thoughts correspond with my sub-
bodily expression of that effect might not be recognized again until ject then that is a play of them. Secondly, it is to be observed
the aesthetics of R. G. Collingwood, John Dewey, and Maurice about these thoughts that they stand in relation to the object,
Merleau-Ponty—but that would be a story for another day. and then the thoughts must be true, and that the course of
the thoughts corresponds with the nature of the mental powers,
thus with the subject, and therefore the succession of thoughts
3. Kant’s early account of aesthetic experience
corresponds with the powers of the mind. This harmonious play
of thoughts and sensations is the poem. (25:525–526)
We can turn now to Kant’s accounts of the experiences of the
beautiful and sublime, and ask whether they differ from their pre- This passage suggests a number of points. First, Kant describes the
decessors in a way that would entitle them to be considered part experience of the poem as a harmonious play between thoughts
of transcendental rather than empirical psychology. We may be- and sensations, or we might say between intellectual and sensible as-
gin, however, by observing that Kant already had accounts of aes- pects of our experience; this prefigures his later conception of a free
thetic experience that were substantially similar to the core of his play between imagination, which includes sensibility, and under-
mature account at a time when he himself, to judge from the note standing. Second, Kant describes this experience as in harmony with
in the ‘Transcendental aesthetic’, still firmly held that aesthetics the ‘subjective’ laws of the mind, but there is no suggestion that there
belonged to empirical rather than transcendental psychology. is anything a priori about these laws; on the contrary, at least at this
The sources for Kant’s early views about aesthetics are primarily stage of Kant’s development, the term ‘subjective’ implies that even if
his Reflexionen on anthropology and logic, that is, his notes, chiefly these laws are common to many human minds, they (and that fact
in his interleaved textbooks, for his lectures on those subjects, as about them) can be known only empirically, as Kant makes clear in
well as the student transcriptions of his lectures on anthropology a note from the same period as the Friedländer lectures:
beginning in 1772–1773.5 This fact in itself is of great significance,
because the text for Kant’s lectures on anthropology was the What agrees with the universal subjective laws of cognition . . .
section on empirical psychology in Baumgarten’s Metaphysics; so of human beings pleases in reflection, merely because it is in
unless there were explicit evidence to the contrary, it must be as- harmony with the conditions of reflection . . . (The subjective
sumed that Kant intended his theories in these lectures to be con- laws cannot, to be sure, be cognized a priori, but we can have
sidered as part of empirical psychology. Further, the influence of insight into their universality from our self-consideration. . .).
the British aestheticians on Kant is evident throughout these (Kant, 2005, p. 511; R 878, 15:385, dated 1776–1778)
materials.
Third, Kant suggests that in the experience of a successful poem the
None of these sources contain any extensive discussion of the
thoughts are in harmony not only with each other and with the
sublime, but they all contain extensive discussions of the beautiful.
laws of the mind but also with their object as well; this can hardly
In fact, the very first note on aesthetics that we find in Kant’s
fail to remind us of Kames’s view that the connections among the
Reflexionen on anthropology, which concerns neither the beautiful
train of our ideas in an experience of art are ‘natural’ both with re-
nor the sublime in nature but rather the art of poetry, immediately
gard to the mind and to the object of the work. Thus, Kant’s concep-
introduces the concept of an active play of the mind:
tion of the experience of poetry, while clearly prefiguring his later
Poetic art is an artificial play of thoughts. We play with account of aesthetic experience, is entirely consistent with the
thoughts if we do not labor with them, that is, are [not] neces- empiricist approach to this subject.
sitated by an end. One merely seeks to entertain oneself with The Friedländer lectures are also significant because they gener-
thoughts. For this it is necessary that all the powers of the alize Kant’s early account of the experience of poetry to other art
mind are set into an harmonious play. Thus they must not forms as well, although not to the case of natural beauty, in spite
be a hindrance to themselves and to reason, although they of the fact that Kant’s later account will begin with the experience
must also not promote it. The play of images, of ideas, of of natural beauty and only later turn to the case of the fine arts. In
affects, finally of mere impressions in the division of time, of the anthropology lectures, Kant’s initial discussion of poetry al-
rhythm (versification) and unison (rhymes) . . . The sensible ways comes in the section on the Dichtungsvermögen (creative fac-
play of thoughts consists in the play of speech (versification) ulty) in the first part, on the cognitive faculties, and then he returns
and of words (rhyme). It goes well with music. It awakens to aesthetic matters in the second section, on the ‘feeling of plea-
the mind. (Kant, 2005, pp. 481–482; R 618, 15:266, dated sure and displeasure’. In the latter section of the Friedländer lec-
1764–1769) tures, Kant says that

5
In spite of its title, the Observations on the feeling of the beautiful and sublime offers only the most conventional and brief accounts of the beautiful and sublime themselves
(Sect. I) before proceeding to the description of differences in preferences for the beautiful or sublime in different genders, nations, races, and so on, a topic that became a staple in
his anthropology lectures under the rubric of ‘Anthropological Characteristic’ and must have been a sure-fire crowd-pleaser. Kant’s lectures on anthropology were only published
in the Academy edition (Vol. 25) in 1997, and thus have only recently entered into the usable Kantian corpus.
488 P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494

The senses are the receptivity of impressions, which promote Or, from a note from the same period,
our sensible enjoyment, but we cannot bring our mental powers
into agitation through objects just insofar as they make an The feeling of the life of spirit pertains to understanding and
impression on us, but rather insofar as we think them, and that freedom, where one has the grounds of cognition and choice
is the ideal enjoyments, which are, to be sure, sensible, but not in oneself . . . Everything that pleases us in such a way that we
enjoyments of sense. A poem, a novel, a comedy are capable of are dependent on it is to that extent not in our power and
affording us ideal enjoyments, they arise from the way in which proves to be a hindrance to the supreme life, namely to the
the mind makes cognitions for itself out of all sorts of represen- strength of the power of choice to have its state and itself under
tations of the senses. Now if the mind is sensitive of a free play its own freedom . . . All taste consists in finding that which is
of its powers, that which creates this free play is an ideal enjoy- satisfying, the source of the sensuously touching, in our actions,
ment. (25:560) comparisons, imaginings, etc.; thereby it is one’s own . . . The
feeling of life is greater in sensation, but I feel a greater life in
Here Kant again uses the idea of free play while pointing toward his voluntary animation, and I feel the greatest principium of life
later distinction between merely agreeable pleasures that involve in morality. (Kant, 2005, p. 507; R 824, 15:368)
the senses alone and the pleasure in beauty that involves a harmony
between imagination and understanding as higher cognitive pow- There is some confusion in this passage, due either to Kant himself
ers: Kant’s claim that the pleasure of our experiences of works in or to the difficulty of the editor (Erich Adickes) in deciphering his
the various media he has mentioned are not ‘enjoyments of sense’ handwriting, but the idea seems to be that activity qua life is pleas-
but are both ‘sensible’ and ‘ideal’ is a move in this direction. But ing, and that there is a scale of activity from simpler sensation to the
all of this remains within the framework of aesthetics as part of free play of the cognitive powers in aesthetic experience to the free-
empirical psychology. dom of choice and action in morality. Of course for Kant the last
Kant’s early remarks on aesthetics are also vital to understand- feeling of life or pleasure is the greatest, but no eighteenth-century
ing his mature theory because they make explicit the basis for his theorist held that the pleasures of taste are greater or more signif-
association of aesthetic pleasure with the free play of our cognitive icant than the feelings connected with morality. What is important
powers in a way that the Critique of the power of judgment never for us is that while the younger Kant actually generalizes the ac-
really does, namely his view that we enjoy such free play because count of aesthetic pleasures in such writers as Gerard and Kames
it is a form of activity and activity is our most fundamental source into a theory of value that comprises morality as well as aesthetics,
of pleasure. This is evident in another early note, this one from he does all of that within the framework of empirical psychology or
1769–1770. Here Kant is discussing our enjoyment of fireworks, what he calls anthropology.
which is not as complex an aesthetic experience as our experience So now our question is whether Kant’s mature account of the
of poetry because it involves only a ‘play of shapes and sensations’ experiences of the beautiful and the sublime adds anything to this
but not a play between these and more intellectual ideas. But what early account that will transform it from empirical to transcenden-
is crucial is his explanation of our enjoyment of such play, which is tal psychology.
entirely general:
4. Kant’s mature theory of aesthetic experience
One is sensitive either to one’s state in action or in passiv-
ity, insofar as one feels oneself to be dependent or to be a The core of Kant’s aesthetic theory throughout his career was an
ground of one’s state. Hence sensation is either active or pas- analysis of the aesthetic judgments (properly, the aesthetic judg-
sive. The sensation is active in the case of the form of appear- ment of reflection or judgment of taste) as the claim that the plea-
ances on account of the comparison that one makes. The sure one has oneself felt in the experience of an object should be
active sensation is in itself always agreeable as well as all pas- experienced by all human subjects encountering that object under
sive ones that promote the active one . . . but the sensation of ideal conditions, coupled with the theory that such claims can be
oneself as an object of other forces is passive; and the more it justified if the pleasure is explained as due to the free play of the
is merely passive, the more disagreeble it is. (Kant, 2005, p. cognitive powers that are common to all human beings. Prior to
490; R 655, 15:289) the Critique of the power of judgment, as we have seen, Kant in-
Activity as such is intrinsically pleasing, and play is a form of activ- cluded this theory as part of ‘anthropology’, or empirical psychol-
ity, indeed a particularly pleasing one precisely because it is not ogy. In the third Critique, he suddenly claimed that this theory
constrained as labor is. Of course, to be maximally enjoyable, rests on a priori principles and is part of transcendental philosophy
any form of activity including play must be harmonious or coher- rather than empirical psychology. Our question now must be
ent, that is, not undercut or diminished by internal conflicts as whether Kant’s mature theory of the free play of the cognitive
well as by external constraints. These premises are the basis for powers as the basis of aesthetic experience and of its universal
Kant’s early conception of a moral theory based on our pleasure validity as the justification of judgments of taste really does rest
in freedom of choice and action as well as for his aesthetic theory on any a priori principles that would entitle it to this new status.
of the pleasure of the free play of our cognitive powers.6 Kant also My argument in this section is that, while there may be an advance
expresses this theory by characterizing life itself as activity, and in the logical analysis of the claims of judgments of taste in Kant’s
the feeling that arises from free yet harmonious activity as the ‘feel- mature presentation of his theory, there is nothing in Kant’s ma-
ing of life’. For example, from the Friedländer lectures on ture concept of the harmony of the faculties as the ground for judg-
anthropology, ment of taste that differs from his earlier theory in a way that
would transform it from a piece of empirical psychology into a
The feeling of the promotion of life is gratification or pleasure. piece of transcendental psychology or philosophy.
Life is the consciousness of a free and regular play of all the Kant introduces the concept of the free play of the cognitive
powers and faculties of human beings. The feeling of the pro- powers at key moments in the exposition of his overall theory in
motion of life is that which constitutes pleasure and the feeling both versions of the introduction to the third Critique and in the
of the hindrance of life is displeasure. (25:559). ‘Analytic of the beautiful’ and the ‘Deduction of pure aesthetic

6
See my discussion of this in ‘Kant on the theory and practice of autonomy’, in Guyer (2005a), as well as in Guyer (2007), Ch. 2.
P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494 489

judgments’ in the body of the work.7 In the first introduction, Kant brought under some determinate concept, this felt unity must be
distinguishes judgments of taste as ‘aesthetic judgments of reflec- understood more precisely as a degree or kind of unity that goes
tion’ from ‘aesthetic judgments of sense’, or first-person reports of beyond anything that can be connected with the determinate con-
our pleasure or displeasure in response to purely sensory stimuli, cept or concepts that do obviously apply to the object and are used
for which we claim no intersubjective validity (Kant, 2000, p. 26; to recognize and refer to it in the first place. Thus, a beautiful ob-
FI, §VIII, 20:224), and then characterizes the experience that causes ject differs from an ordinary one that falls under the same con-
our pleasure in an object of taste and grounds the claim to intersub- cepts by leading us to experience it as possessing some greater
jective validity as a relationship between the cognitive powers of or different kind of unity than the degree or kind of unity it must
imagination and understanding that is harmonious but, unlike ordin- share with the latter.8
ary cases of cognition, does not involve—that is, neither depends These explications of Kant’s central concept from the First Intro-
upon nor leads to—the predication of a determinate concept of the duction do not actually use the idea of play that we saw to be cen-
object triggering this experience. He describes this relation in a num- tral to Kant’s earlier accounts. However, Kant employs this concept
ber of ways: in his first explication of the concept in the published Introduction
to the third Critique, and also explicitly connects play with
If the form of a given object in empirical intuition is so consti-
pleasure:
tuted that the apprehension of its manifold in the imagination
agrees with the presentation of a concept of the understanding If pleasure is connected with the mere apprehension . . . of the
(though which concept be undetermined), then in the mere form of an object of intuition without a relation of this to a
reflection understanding and imagination mutually agree for concept for a determinate cognition, then the representation
the advancement of their business, and the object will be per- is thereby related not to the object, but solely to the subject,
ceived as purposive merely for the power of judgment, hence and the pleasure can express nothing but its suitability to
the purposiveness itself will be considered as merely subjec- the cognitive faculties that are in play in the reflecting power
tive; for which, further, no determinate concept of the object of judgment, insofar as they are in play . . . For that apprehen-
at all is required nor is one thereby generated . . . (Ibid., p. 23; sion of forms in the imagination can never take place without
FI, §VII, 20:220–221) the reflecting power of judgment, even if unintentionally, at
. . . in the power of judgment understanding and imagination least comparing them to its faculty for relating intuitions to
are considered in relation to each other, and this can, to be sure, concepts. Now if in this comparison the imagination . . . is
first be considered objectively, as belonging to cognition. . .; but unintentionally brought into accord with the understanding
one can also consider this relation of two faculties of cognition . . . through a given representation and a feeling of pleasure
merely subjectively, insofar as one helps or hinders the other in is thereby aroused, then the object must be regarded as purpo-
the very same relation . . . (Ibid., p. 25; FI, §VIII, 20:223) sive for the reflecting power of judgment. Such a judgment is
an aesthetic judgment on the purposiveness of the object,
A merely reflecting judgment about a given individual object which is not grounded on any available concept of the object
. . . can be aesthetic if (before its comparison with others and does not furnish one . . . this pleasure is also judged to
is seen), the power of judgment, which has no concept ready be necessarily combined [with the representation of such an
for the given intuition, holds the imagination (merely in the object], consequently not merely for the subject who appre-
apprehension of object) together with the understanding (in hends this form but for everyone who judges at all. The object
the presentation of a concept in general) and perceives a rela- is then called beautiful. (Ibid., p. 76; CPJ, Introduction, §VII,
tion of the two faculties of cognition which constitutes the sub- 5:189–190)
jective, merely sensitive condition of the objective use of the
Here Kant says that the apprehension of forms in the imagination is
power of judgment in general (namely the agreement of those
compared with the faculty for relating intuitions to concepts, which
two faculties with each other). (Ibid., p. 26; FI, §VIII, 20:223–
we can take to mean that the play of forms in the imagination stim-
224)
ulated by the experience of an object is experienced as satisfying
Kant’s key claims here are that in the experience that grounds a the general condition for subsuming a manifold of intuitions under
judgment of taste, the relation between imagination and under- a concept, namely its unity, without that feeling of unity within the
standing does not depend upon nor lead to the predication of a play being grounded in any available concept nor leading to one.
determinate concept of its object, but nevertheless seems to satisfy Note especially that Kant says that the feeling of unity is not
the subjective condition of the use of these faculties and is felt to grounded in any available (vorhandenen, literally ‘ready to hand’)
be purposive, and thus pleasurable, because of that. Apart from the concept—thus Kant is not denying that the beautiful object falls un-
metaphors of ‘advancing their mutual business’ and ‘helping or der one or many determinate concepts, but is maintaining only that
hindering’ each other, Kant gives us very little information about such concepts are not available to explain the distinctive unity of a
what this relation between imagination and understanding might beautiful object.
actually be. I have suggested that what he means by the satisfac- Kant also uses the concept of play in his first introduction of
tion of the subjective condition of the use of the power of judg- the concept of the harmony of the faculties into the argument
ment in general, in a way that neither depends upon nor leads of the ‘Analytic of the beautiful’, in the section that he says is
to the application or ‘presentation’ of a determinate concept, is the ‘key to the critique of taste’ (ibid., p. 102; CPJ, §9, 5:216),
the feeling rather than conceptual recognition of unity and coher- and here he also explicitly says that the play is active rather than
ence in the manifold of intuitions presented by an object, but that, passive; that is, something we initiate rather than merely some-
since it is part of both common sense and Kant’s own epistemol- thing an object triggers in us. He describes the experience of
ogy that no object can be recognized or referred to without being beauty, the ‘sensations whose universal communicability is

7
Kant wrote a first draft of the introduction in early 1789, now referred to as the ‘First Introduction’ (FI), and then wrote the new version that was actually published in the
finished book in early 1790, when the rest of the manuscript was already at the printer. Ernst Cassirer was the first to publish the whole first introduction for what it was, in 1914
(see Kant, 2000, p. xliii). By the ‘body of the work’, I mean the first half of the Critique of the power of judgment, the ‘Critique of the aesthetic power of judgment’; the second half of
the work, the ‘Critique of the teleological power of judgment’, is not addressed in this paper.
8
For my most recent and, I hope, most refined argument for this approach, see Guyer (2005b).
490 P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494

postulated by the judgment of taste’, as ‘the animation of both of their determinate concepts, it cannot be his claim that aesthetic
faculties (the imagination and the understanding) to an activity experience is grounded upon the a priori concepts of the under-
that is indeterminate but yet, through the stimulus of the given standing, the categories. Of course, if it is true that we do sub-
representation, in unison, namely that which belongs to a cogni- sume any object of aesthetic experience under some empirical
tion in general’; our universally communicable pleasure in a concept or other, that will entail that we also subsume it under
beautiful object is thus the ‘sensation of the effect that consists the categories, since the categories are nothing but the pure forms
in the facilitated play of both powers of the mind (imagination of empirical concepts (the category of causation is the pure form
and understanding), enlivened through mutual agreement’ (ibid., of empirical concepts of this or that particular kind of causation,
p. 102; 5:219). Here Kant’s suggestion is that the lively activity and so on). But Kant has made it clear that the experience of uni-
of both imagination and understanding in the experience of a son or free lawfulness in the free play of the cognitive powers has
beautiful object possesses the kind of unity that is the condition nothing to do with the subsumption of the object under any
of cognition in general, in contrast, of course, to the unity of a determinate concepts, so a fortiori it can have nothing to do with
determinate cognition. In his summary of the ‘Analytic of the the subsumption of the object under the a priori categories. The
beautiful’, Kant varies his account slightly by suggesting not that apriority of the categories is simply not part of the explanation
both the imagination and understanding are actively at play, but of our pleasure in beauty.
rather that the play of the imagination with its representations of The same argument can be made with regard to the a priori
the forms of objects is in harmony with the understanding’s gen- forms of intuition, that is, the pure forms of space and time. In
eral requirement of lawfulness. ‘Everything flows from the con- the passage from the published Introduction in which Kant speaks
cept of taste as a faculty for judging an object in relation to the of the unintentional accord of the imagination and understanding,
free lawfulness of the imagination’. A beautiful object can pro- he does parenthetically describe the imagination ‘as the faculty of a
vide the imagination priori intuition’ (ibid., p. 76; CPJ, Introduction, §VII, 5:190; I previ-
ously elided this remark). But of course every object that is repre-
with a form that contains precisely such a composition of the
sented in space and/or time, whether beautiful, ugly, or
manifold as the imagination would design in harmony with
aesthetically indifferent, conforms to the a priori forms of intuition,
the lawfulness of the understanding in general if it were left
that is, the necessary structure of space and time themselves. So
free by itself . . . Thus only a lawfulness without law and a sub-
the a priori forms of intuition themselves do not contribute to
jective correspondence of the imagination to the understanding
beauty; as in the case of concepts, beauty must lie in some partic-
without an objective one—where the representation is related
ular way in which the forms of beautiful objects give us a sense of
to a determinate concept of an object—are consistent with the
some form of harmony or unity that goes beyond what is required
free lawfulness of the understanding . . . and with the peculiar-
for the mere possibility of representing them as spatial and/or tem-
ity of a judgment of taste. (Ibid., pp. 124–125; CPJ, General
poral at all. The beauty of an object may lie in its particular spatial
Remark following §22, 5:240–241)
and/or temporal form, but that is only constrained, not determined
Finally, Kant varies his explication one more time in his restatement by the a priori forms of sensibility.
of his entire theory of the judgment of taste, that is, both its analysis It follows from these arguments that even should Kant be
and its justificatory explanation, in the ‘Deduction of pure aesthetic wrong about the apriority of the basic forms of sensibility and
judgments’ (CPJ, §§30–40). Here Kant says that since the ‘judgment understanding, his explanation of aesthetic response would not
of taste differes from logical judgment in that the latter subumes a be affected: at least as far as anything considered thus far is
representation under concepts of the object, but the former does concerned, should the categories and forms of intuition turn
not subsume under a concept at all’, such a judgment must instead out to be some sort of no doubt deep-seated empirical represen-
depend upon the ‘subsumption of the imagination itself . . . under tations, beauty would still lie in the way in which certain objects
the condition that the understanding in general advance to from give us a sense of harmony beyond anything that can be
intuitions to concepts’. Kant does not explain here or elsewhere attributed to those sources. Thus far, at least, Kant’s conception
what it means to subsume one faculty under another rather than of the harmony of the faculties seems neither to depend upon
an object under a concept, but his explication of this puzzling re- the genuine apriority of the forms of sensibility and understand-
mark makes it clear that he has in mind the same relation between ing nor to add anything genuinely transcendental to Kant’s
imagination and understanding by which he summed up the argu- psychology.
ment of the ‘Analytic’: Is there another way in which Kant’s account of aesthetic
experience might be genuinely transcendental? Kant’s idea that
I.e., since the freedom of the imagination consists precisely in
the harmony of the faculties constitutes a subjective satisfaction
the fact that it schematizes without a concept, the judgment
of the general conditions of cognition or judgment, or a state in
of taste must rest on a mere sensation of the reciprocally ani-
which it seems to us that our desire for unity is satisfied indepen-
mating imagination in its freedom and the understanding with
dently of the predication of any determinate concept of the object,
its lawfulness, thus on a feeling . . . for the promotion of the fac-
is pleasurable or subjectively purposive, seems to rest on the
ulty of cognition in its free play . . . (Ibid., p. 167; CPJ, §35,
premise that the satisfaction of a goal is always pleasurable, but
5:286–287)
particularly so when that satisfaction seems unexpected or con-
So now we have before us all of Kant’s mature explications of his tingent. Kant suggests this premise in Section VI of the Introduc-
core idea of the harmony or free play of the cognitive powers in tion to the third Critique, when he writes that ‘The attainment of
aesthetic experience, or more precisely of imagination and under- every aim is combined with the feeling of pleasure’, but that it is
standing in the first case of aesthetic experience that he considers, particularly in the case of an ‘accord . . . with our faculty of cogni-
that of beauty—and even more precisely of free beauty (see CPJ, tion, which we regard as merely contingent, [that] pleasure will
§16). We are now ready to ask whether this account differs from be felt’ (ibid., pp. 73–74; CPJ, Introduction, §VI, 5:187–188). But
his earlier account in any way that would entitle its promotion is there anything a priori about the claim that pleasure is always
from empirical to transcendental psychology. Where in this ac- connected with the attainment of a goal, and particularly notice-
count is there an a priori principle that could earn it this promo- able pleasure with what strikes us as being the contingent satis-
tion? Since Kant has insisted throughout that the faculties of faction of a goal? Sometimes Kant writes as if it is the definition
ordinary cognition are involved in this experience but not any of happiness that it consists in the satisfaction of one’s desires
P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494 491

or the attainment of the ends that desires suggest.9 But if this a ground that is a priori’ and that the universal validity of judgments
definition is accepted, then, first, that would make the connection of taste depends upon that a priori ground. Is there some way in
between the attainment of a goal and happiness a priori but ana- which the harmony of the faculties is a priori and part of a genuinely
lytic, not synthetic a priori, and, second, it would not follow from transcendental psychology that my argument thus far has failed to
this definition alone that there is any phenomenologically distinct notice and exclude? I take it that what Kant has in mind as a priori
feeling, namely the feeling of pleasure, that is connected to the here is the principle that every normal human mind will, under
attainment of a goal. Thus the claim that happiness always results ideal or optimal conditions, respond with a free play of its imagina-
from the attainment of a goal may be a priori but is merely analytic, tion and understanding to any object to which any normal human
while the claim that a feeling of pleasure results from the mind under ideal conditions so responds, which would entitle any-
attainment may be synthetic but seems a posteriori, an empirical one who has truly experienced such a state in response to a partic-
discovery of psychology—to be sure, the most elementary folk-psy- ular object to judge that under ideal conditions everyone should,
chology, apparent to us all very early in our development. The that is, to make a judgment of taste. That is the principle that Kant
underlying premise of Kant’s explanatory concept of the harmony attempts to establish in his ‘Deduction of pure aesthetic judgments’.
of the faculties thus does not seem to be transcendental. So in order to complete my argument that Kant’s theory of taste is
Here we should also note that Kant himself insists that there is not genuinely transcendental, obviously I must turn to this. Before I
one case in which a feeling is connected a priori to a certain state of do so, however, I want to consider briefly several of Kant’s explica-
the mental powers, but he does not make this claim about the con- tions of aesthetic response beyond his basic account of beauty that
nection of the feeling of pleasure to the harmonious relation of patently appear to contain a priori elements, and to argue that these
imagination and understanding; he makes it about the connection still do not make his aesthetics transcendental.
of the feeling of respect to the determination of the will to make the I refer to Kant’s accounts of the sublime and of fine art. I will
moral law the supreme limiting condition of all its maxims and ac- take them in reverse order, since Kant explicates our experience
tions. In the Critique of practical reason, Kant says that ‘we can see a of fine art as a special case of beauty but treats the experience of
priori that the moral law, as the determining ground of the will, the sublime as a distinct form of aesthetic experience. For Kant,
must by thwarting all our inclinations produce a feeling that can works of fine art and our experience of them are distinctive be-
be called pain’, but then also, ‘since this law is still something in it- cause they involve an ‘aesthetic idea’, that is, ‘a representation of
self positive . . ., it is an object of the greatest respect and so too the the imagination that occasions much thinking without it being
ground a positive feeling that is not of empirical origin and is cog- possible for any determinate thought, i.e., concept, to be adequate
nized a priori’. But Kant also says that ‘here we have the first and to it’. ‘One can call such representations of the imagination ideas’,
perhaps the only case in which we can determine a priori from con- he continues, ‘because they at least strive toward something lying
cepts the relation of a cognition (here the cognition of a pure prac- beyond the bounds of experience, and thus seek to approximate a
tical reason) to a feeling of pleasure or displeasure’ (Kant, 1996, p. presentation of concept of reason (intellectual ideas)’, in fact ideas
199; CPracR, 5:73). It might be objected that Kant left a loophole connected with morality. At the same time, the imagination ‘aes-
with his ‘perhaps’ and that three years later he he allowed a second thetically enlarges the concept itself in an unbounded way’, thus
a priori connection between a feeling of pleasure and a state of our ‘is creative, and sets the faculty of intellectual ideas (reason) into
cognitive powers, namely that between their free play in our expe- motion, that is, at the instigation of a representation it gives more
rience of beauty and our pleasure in it, to get through this loophole. to think about than can be grasped and made distinct in it’ (ibid.,
But he gives no indication that he has changed his mind about the pp. 192–193; CPJ, §49, 5:314–315). Genius or the ‘talent for art’
uniqueness of the moral feeling of respect even after the third Cri- thus consists in ‘the exposition or expression of aesthetic ideas’
tique; thus, when he says about moral feelings in the ‘Doctrine of through ‘material, i.e., of the intuition, for the presentation of this
virtue’ of the 1797 Metaphysics of morals that ‘Consciousness of concept’, yet in such a way that ‘the free correspondence of the
them is not of empirical origin; it can, instead, only follow from imagination to the lawfulness of the understanding presupposes
consciousness of a moral law, as the effect this has on the mind’ a proportion and disposition of this faculty that cannot be pro-
(Ibid., p. 528; MM, 6:399), he still seems to be treating moral duced by any following of the rules’ (ibid., p. 195; CPJ, §49,
feelings as unique in their apriority. But in any case, our question 5:317–318). I interpret all this to mean that in the mental activity
is not what Kant thought, but what his conception of aesthetic of the creative artist on the one hand, and in the response of the
experience really entails. Kant’s emphasis on the unique apriori- audience for the artist’s work on the other, the imagination plays
ty of moral feeling only adds support to the argument already not merely with form but with both form and intellectual content
made that his explanation of aesthetic response as a free play of in a way that freely satisfies the understanding’s general interest in
the cognitive powers does not require any distinctively transcen- lawfulness. In other words, the experience of art is an experience of
dental psychology consisting of synthetic a priori propositions. beauty, but beauty lying in an harmonious relation between form
The observant reader, however, will immediately notice that and content and not just within form alone (see Guyer, 1994, rep-
once again I have quoted Kant incompletely; more fully, the first rinted in Guyer, 1997, pp. 351–366). Having introduced this theory
part of my last quote from Kant is of art, Kant actually goes on to argue that all ‘Beauty (whether it be
beauty of nature or art) can in general be called the expression of
The attainment of every aim is combined with the feeling of
aesthetic ideas’ (Kant, 2000, p. 197; CPJ, §51, 5:320), but let us
pleasure; and, if the condition of the former is an a priori repre-
ignore that claim. Our question is whether the fact that an aes-
sentation, as in this case a principle for the reflecting power of
thetic experience, of fine art only or more generally, can express
judgment in general, then the feeling of pleasure is also deter-
an aesthetic idea suffices to remove Kant’s account from the realm
mined through a ground that is a priori and valid for everyone.
of empirical to that of transcendental theory. Let us stipulate that
(Kant, 2000, p. 73; CPJ, Introduction, §VI, 5:187)
the ideas that furnish the content of works of fine art are, as Kant
This suggests that even if the principle that the attainment of every supposes, typically moral ideas, and let us further allow Kant’s sup-
end produces pleasure is not itself a priori, still the feeling of plea- position that such ideas are ‘intellectual’ and a priori, originating in
sure in the special case of aesthetic response ‘is determined through pure practical reason rather than, as many of his contemporaries

9
For example, in the Critique of practical reason, Kant says that ‘happiness’ is ‘only the general name’ for what would result from realizing the object of ‘subjective determining
grounds’: Kant (1996), p. 159; CPracR, 5:25.
492 P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494

supposed, in sentiment, experience, custom, and so on. Would ble empirical laws sufficient kinship among them to enable
accepting these stipulations make the fact that we can freely play them to be brought under empirical concepts (classes) and
with such ideas in our creation and experience of art something these in turn under more general laws (higher genera) and thus
that we can know to be true a priori, and thus part of a transcen- for an empirical system of nature to be reached. (Kant, 2000, pp.
dental psychology? It is hard to see why it would; it would seem 15, 19; FI, §V, 5:211, 215).
to be a contingent fact about us and thus something we know
In the published Introduction, Kant explicitly labels this principle
through empirical psychology—although, again, the most rudimen-
‘transcendental’ in the official sense that it ‘is one through which
tary folk-psychology—that our imaginations can generate a free
the universal a priori conditions under which alone things can be-
and enjoyable play between form and content, even when the con-
come objects of our cognition at all is represented’ (ibid., p. 68;
tent itself is intellectual or a priori.
CPJ, Introduction, §V, 5:181), even though he is also going to argue
Perhaps a better case can be made for the aesthetics of the sub-
that it is regulative of our inquiry into nature rather than constitu-
lime being part of a genuinely transcendental psychology, because
tive of nature itself. The key point for us now, however, is that this
here the claim that certain of our faculties produce a priori ideas or
cannot be the a priori principle, whether regulative or constitutive,
principles seems even more central and indispensable to Kant’s ac-
of aesthetic judgments of taste, because such judgments, by Kant’s
count of the experience than it is to his account of fine art. Put
own lights, are independent of concepts except insofar, as in the
briefly, Kant’s explication of the experience of the sublime is that
case of aesthetic ideas, concepts or more properly ideas of reason
in its attempt to grasp something vast (in the case of the mathe-
enter into their content. Judgments of taste neither depend upon
matical sublime) or mighty (in the case of the dynamical sublime)
nor lead to determinate concepts of objects, so the principle that
in a single image or apprehension, the imagination is frustrated,
for all objects determinate concepts, indeed systematically ordered
and we are initially pained. Then, however, we are pleased when
determinate concepts, can be found is irrelevant to the process of
we realize, at some level, that the very attempt of the imagination
aesthetic response and making aesthetic judgments. As we have
to accomplish this impossible task was itself imposed upon it by
seen, beauty, whether natural or artistic, and as it turns out sublim-
our own reason, theoretical reason with its transcendent idea of
ity as well, always lie in a region of our response to objects that is
the infinite in the case of the mathematical sublime and practical
not determined by any of the determinate concepts that do apply
reason with its transcendent idea of a capacity of our will for inde-
to the objects, and so a principle that postulates that determinate
pendence from and superiority over nature in the case of the
concepts apply to every object has nothing to do with aesthetics.
dynamical sublime (see ibid., pp. 134–148; CPJ, §§26–28). In this
And in the ‘Analytic of the beautiful’ and the ‘Deduction of pure
account, that we have a faculty of pure reason that has a priori
judgments of taste’, appropriately enough, Kant entirely ignores
ideas of infinitude and moral purity seems essential. Even so, the
this supposedly general a priori and transcendental principle of
claim that the failed efforts of the imagination to apprehend cer-
reflecting judgment. Instead, he introduces a different principle
tain natural phenomena—vast seas and mighty waterfalls, and all
that is clearly intended to be the a priori and transcendental prin-
of the usual eighteenth-century examples of the sublime—are both
ciple of judgments of taste. Let us consider just the ‘Deduction’
triggered by the faculty of reason and in some way make us aware
properly so called. In Section 37, Kant asks ‘What is really asserted
of that faculty and its ideas and ambitions seems empirical; it does
a priori of an object in a judgment of taste?’ He then argues that the
not seem to be a condition of the very possibility of our experience
fact that I can only know empirically that I do experience any par-
that imagination and reason be connected in this way, but a con-
ticular object with pleasure, so that my report merely that I do so
tingent fact about us that we know to be true (if we do)10 by expe-
experience an object, would ‘yield a merely empirical judgment’.
rience. As in the case of fine art, a priori ideas may enter into our
Thus, he concludes, ‘it is not the pleasure but the universal valid-
experience through imagination, but the fact that they do so does
ity of this pleasure perceived in the mind as connected with the
not itself seem to be necessarily true of us or something that we
mere judging of an object that is represented in a judgment of taste
could know a priori. The account of our experience of the sublime
as a universal rule . . . valid for everyone’; so ‘It is an empirical judg-
also seems to be part of empirical psychology.
ment that I perceive and judge an object with pleasure. But it is an
a priori judgment that I find it beautiful, i.e., that I may require that
5. The deduction of pure aesthetic judgments satisfaction of everyone’ (ibid., p. 170; CPJ, §37, 5:289). It is there-
fore strictly my claim that the object I have found pleasurable
We may now turn to the last hope for an interpretation of Kant’s should also be found pleasurable by everyone else that needs an
aesthetics as genuinely transcendental rather than empirical, a priori principle as its foundation. Kant’s argument in Section 38,
namely Kant’s claim that the universal validity of judgments of the heart of the deduction, is then that since in the case of a gen-
taste must rest on an a priori ground. I have dealt with Kant’s uine aesthetic response ‘the power of judgment . . . can be directed
deduction of judgments of taste at length elsewhere, and here I only to the subjective conditions of the use of the power of jud-
confine myself to two points.11 First, it must be clear that what Kant ment in general’, it is therefore directed ‘to that subjective element
characterizes as the general transcendental principle for the power that one can presuppose in all human beings (as requisite for pos-
of reflecting judgment cannot be the a priori principle for aesthetic sible cognitions in general)’, and thus that ‘the correspondence of a
judgment. Kant says that ‘The principle of reflection on given objects representation with these conditions of the power of judgment’ in
is that for all things in nature empirically determinate concepts can one person who experiences the harmony of the cognitive powers
be found’, or at greater length that in response to an object ‘must be able to be assumed valid for
This principle can be none other than that of the suitability for everyone a priori’ (ibid.; CPJ, §38, 5:290). Kant’s argument assumes
the capacity of the power of judgment itself for finding in the that we can know a priori that everyone else has the same sort of
immeasurable multiplicity of things in accordance with possi- cognitive powers that we do and that they work in the same

10
Malcolm Budd has argued that Kant’s interpretation of the experience of the sublime is excessively moralized and misrepresents the character of the experience; Budd (2002),
Ch. III. But what kind of argument can this be? It can only be an argument that Budd, or Budd speaking for many of us at the start of the twenty-first century, does not find Kant’s
interpretation of the sublime a convincing explication of his own experience before the kinds of objects that Kant refers to as sublime; that leaves it open that Kant or Kant and
many of his contemporaries at the end of the eighteenth century did find his explication convincing. This only goes to show that Kant’s theory is in fact empirical rather than
transcendental.
11
For my detailed treatment of the deduction, see Guyer (1997), Chs. 7–9. For critical responses, see Ameriks (2003) and Allison (2001).
P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494 493

way, including responding with a free play to the same objects that ments of taste and the psychological accounts of aesthetic experi-
produce that response in ourselves. But it is not clear that we can ence that he adopted from his predecessors. In particular, he
really know any of these things a priori. Whether we know that transformed the somewhat crude distinctions between absolute
others have minds and that their minds work in the same general and relative beauty and the beauty of form (species) and of appear-
way as our own is certainly debatable: Donald Davidson’s principle ance that he found in Hutcheson and Hume (Hutcheson, 1738,
of charity, for example, might be an a priori assumption that this is Treatise I, §§II, IV; Hume, 2000, Book III, Pt. iii, §6) into a complex
so, but it is far from clear that this amounts to a priori knowledge account of the similarities and differences between free and depen-
(Davidson, 1973). But even if we were to suppose that we really dent beauty and natural and artistic beauty. Kant’s transformation
do know a priori that all human minds work in the same general of Alexander Baumgarten’s idea of the analogon rationis (Baumgar-
way, we certainly do not know a priori that all human minds work ten, 2007 [1750], Vol. I, §1) into the idea of the free and indetermi-
in the same particular ways; on the contrary, we know empirically nate play of the cognitive powers, rather than their ordinary,
that different human individuals and groups carve up their experi- determinate, concept-guided use, provides a foundation for more
ence with different empirical concepts. Nor does it seem obvious recent accounts of aesthetic or critical discourse, according to
that all human beings are equally capable of responding to objects which we can only use ordinary concepts to try to get people to
with a free play of their cognitive powers, let alone all capable of so see or hear in a work of art or other aesthetic object what we do,
responding to the same objects. We certainly know empirically but cannot prove to them that they must. Kant’s recognition of
that human beings have very different degrees of potential for the multiple dimensions for significance and pleasure in the expe-
artistic creativity, some Mozarts and Dickenses being able to in- rience of art (CPJ, §51), which we have not discussed, avoids many
vent melodies and characters with extraordinary facility, and the of the pitfalls of more reductive concepts of art from Hegel through
rest of us only with more difficulty or, alas, not at all. Why should the present. But our appreciation and use of these contributions do
it be different on the side of response—why should not some minds not depend upon taking at face value the claim of Kant and some of
that have the general power to apply concepts to objects also be his admirers that he transformed aesthetics from empirical to tran-
able to respond with a free play of their imagination and under- scendental psychology.
standing to some objects, while others who have the first power
alas lack the second? Just as some people are tone-deaf or color-
blind, the latter of which at least we trace to a specific deficiency References
of their sense organs, why should not some otherwise normal peo-
ple be more generally deaf to the harmony of the faculties, capable Allison, H. E. (2001). The deduction of pure judgements of taste. In idem, Kant’s
theory of taste: A reading of the Critique of aesthetic judgment (pp. 160-192).
of a concept-guided use of their cognitive powers but incapable of
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
free play with them? At the very least, that this is not the case Ameriks, K. (2003). How to save Kant’s deduction of taste as objective. In idem,
would seem to be something that has to be established empiri- Interpreting Kant’s Critiques (pp. 285-306). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Baumgarten, A. G. (2007). Aesthetica (D. Mirbach, Ed.). Hamburg: F. Meiner. (First
cally—unless we just stipulate that normal people are capable of
published 1750)
the free play of the cognitive powers, and all normal people capa- Budd, M. (2002). The aesthetic appreciation of nature: Essays on the aesthetics of
ble of that in response to the same objects, in which case the prin- nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
ciple that all normal people will have the same aesthetic response Cassirer, E. (1951). The philosophy of the Enlightenment (F. C. A. Koelln, & J. P.
Pettegrove, Trans.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
will be analytically true, and not a synthetic a priori and transcen- Davidson, D. (1973). Radical interpretation. Dialectica, 27, 313–328. (Reprinted in
dental principle at all. idem, Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 125–139). Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1984)
Gerard, A. (1759). An essay on taste, with three dissertations on the same subject by Mr.
De Voltaire, Mr. D’Alembert, and Mr. De Montesquieu. London: A. Millar;
6. Conclusion Edinburgh: A. Kincaid and J. Bell.
Gerard, A. (1766). Versuch über dem Geschmack, nebst Zwo Abhandlungen über eben
die Materia vom Herrn von Voltaire und Hrn. v. Alembert (K. F. Flögel, Trans.).
Kant’s aesthetic theory consists of an analytic part, the analysis Breslau & Leipzig: J. E. Meyer.
of what is asserted in a judgment of taste, and a synthetic part, the Guyer, P. (1994). Kant’s conception of fine art. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
account of aesthetic experience that is supposed to make it reason- 52, 175–185.
Guyer, P. (1997). Kant and the claims of taste (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge
able for us to assert judgments of taste under appropriate condi-
University Press.
tions. Leaving Quinean worries aside, the former part of Kant’s Guyer, P. (2005a). Kant’s system of nature and freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
theory is certainly a priori. I have found no reason to regard the Guyer, P. (2005b). The harmony of the faculties revisited. In idem, Values of beauty:
synthetic part as a priori, however, and thus no reason to regard Historical essays in aesthetics (pp. 77-109). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. (Reprinted in R. Kukla (Ed.). Aesthetics and cognition in Kant’s critical
Kant’s theory as transcendental rather than empirical psychology. philosophy (pp. 162–193). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006).
The harmony of imagination and understanding in the simple case Guyer, P. (2007). Kant’s groundwork for the metaphysics of morals: A reader’s guide.
of pure or free beauty does not depend upon any of the a priori London: Continuum Books.
Hasselquist, F. (1762). Reise nach Palästina in den Jahren 1749–62. Rostock.
forms, concepts, or principles of sensibility or understanding, and Hume, D. (1987). Essays moral, political, and literary (rev. ed.) (E. F. Miller, Ed.).
even where a priori concepts, such as the ideas of reason, enter into Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
the play of imagination, as content in the case of fine art or as ulti- Hume, D. (2000). A treatise of human nature (D. Fate, & M. J. Norton, Eds.). Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
mate significance in the experience of the sublime, there seems to Hutcheson, F. (1738). An inquiry into the original of our ideas of beauty and virtue (4th
be no synthetic a priori principle that they must do so, or that we ed.). London.
must be capable of aesthetic play with them. The principle that Kames, H. H., Lord. (1762). Elements of criticism (3 vols.). London: A. Millar;
Edinburgh: A. Kincaid & J. Bell.
the attainment of any end, even under unusual and apparently Kames, H. H., Lord. (2005). Elements of criticism (2 vols.) (P. Jones, Ed.). Indianapolis:
contingent circumstances, will be accompanied with a feeling of Liberty Fund. (6th ed. first published Edinburgh: J. Bell & W. Creech; London: T.
pleasure does not seem to be synthetic a priori. And the assump- Cadell & G. Robinson, 1785).
Kames, H. H., Lord. (1763-1766). Grundsätze der Critik (3 vols.) (J. H. N. Meinhard,
tion that all human minds will respond to particular objects with
Trans.). Leipzig. (Rev. ed. published 1772)
the same free play of the cognitive powers does not seem to be Kant, I. (1900–). Kants gesammelte Schriften (Königlich Preussischen Akademie der
synthetic a priori. Wissenschaften, Ed.) (29 vols. to date). Berlin: G. Reimer [later W. de Gruyter].
Does the failure of Kant’s aesthetics to transform empirical into Kant, I. (1996). Practical philosophy (M. J. Gregor, Ed. & Trans.). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
transcendental psychology mean that is a complete failure? By no Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason (P. Guyer, & A. W. Wood, Eds. & Trans.).
means. Kant clearly refined both the analysis of the claims of judg- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
494 P. Guyer / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 483–494

Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgment (P. Guyer, Ed.; P. Guyer, & E. Nuzzo, A. (2006). Kant and Herder on Baumgarten’s Aesthetica. Journal of the History
Matthews, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. of Philosophy, 44, 577–597.
Kant, I. (2005). Notes and fragments (P. Guyer, Ed.; C. Bowman, P. Guyer, & F. Savary, C. E. (1787). Lettres sur l’Egypte, où l’on offre le parallèle des moeurs anciennes
Rauscher, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. et modernes de ses habitants. Paris.

You might also like