Juris Syllabus Sem 4

You might also like

Download as pdf
Download as pdf
You are on page 1of 246
Syllabus for B.A. LL.B. 2" Year Students 4.6 JURISPRUDENCE - IL SEMESTER PERIOD JANUARY - JUNE 2015 COURSE CODE 5 MAXIMUM MARKS 100 _| TOTAL TEACHING HOURS 80 TUTORIAL / PRESENTATION HOURS | 10-15 MEDIUM OF INSTRUCTION, | ENGLISH TEACHING METHOD LECTURE CUM DISCUSSION METHOD Course Objectives: Law is a social process to solve social needs. Jurisprudence is a science which studies the methods to meet these needs. For a comprehensive understanding of any existing law, the philosophy and the basic theoretical fundamental premise of such law is inevitable. ‘Most of the schools of thought known in the area of jurisprudence has been introduced to the students in Jurisprudence ~ I. The jurisprudential theories discussed in previous semester, are cast within the intellectual tradition of political liberalism. There are significant differences among those theories, but they are ultimately grounded in liberal views of law and society. This course discusses the challenges to the fundamental assumptions of liberal legal theory that came to prominence during the latter decades of the 20th century, It will focus in particular on the ideas of the critical legal studies (CLS) movement, postmodernist legal theory and feminist theory. It studies the relation between law, concepts, life of society, interest protected and methods to satisfy them, therefore, it is the functional study of concepts of which legal systems develop and interest which law protects. Previous semester had focused on theories about definitions and descriptions of the law as it is or as it ought to be, and of how law is made or emerges in society. This semester emphasizes on another vital aspect of law: namely, the internal structure of legal norms and the basic conceptions that are used in legal statements, the conceptions without which law maker cannot make a law. Students shall be introduced with legal concepts of Rights, Duties, Obligations, Person, Possession, and Ownership. Furthermore, the interaction of law and society shall be introduced to the students to enable them to understand the fundamental role of law as an instrument of social change and the inherent shortcomings in law itself. The course will enhance analytical ability of the student in socio-legal studies. The course is divided into five modules. Module one will focus on the background and issues dealt in feminist jurisprudence, critical legal movements and postmodernism, Module Two of the course will continue with juristic concepts of law relating to possession and ownership. The word ‘possession’ has variety of uses and a variety of meaning, The opinions of jurists differ as to why possession is protected by law, when the possessor is not the owner. Student will be acquainted with the opinions of Salmond, Kant, Hegel, Savigny, Ihering, Holland and others. Further, the concept of ownership, its nature and kind will be studied in detail. This module will also cover the concept of ‘Act’ and ‘Negligence’ and its significance, Module Three will deal with the administration of justice, Broadly speaking administration of justice means justice according to law. Module aims to provide insight into the development of principles of administration of justice from primitive societies to the modern state. Module four of the course will introduce the students with the juristic concepts of law relating to right, duties and person. In this module, the concepts of legal ‘rights’ and ‘duties’ in a wider sense of the term shall be discussed in detail. The Module will also cover the Marxist critique of the rights based approach of law. Further, student will be acquainted with the concept of legal person and its relevance. Module five covers a discourse on the interrelationship between law and social change, the identification of specific social problems and an assessment of the efficacy of relevant laws to deal with such problems especially in the context of Indian scenario. Further, the role of the judiciary in the pursuit to bring about social transformation shall be discussed to enable the student to appreciate the complementary role played by the judiciary in filling the vacuum created by the legislative and executive inactions. Teaching Methodology: ‘The teaching methodology to be adopted in this course paper shall be a collaboration of lecture method as well as discussion method. The former method is a direct instruction method by the teacher while the latter is a kind of co-operative learning wherein it gives enough scope to the students for an active participation in the classroom discussion. ‘The lecture method can be used to introduce a new topic or idea to the students and this can be ideally followed by a discussion method which is an applied or analytical approach based on the basic theoretical or the foundational understanding of the topics taught. The students shall be asked to apply their theoretical understanding to practical problems or issues. The students shall be required from time to time to give class room presentation on the topics assigned to them either in groups or individually. This will facilitate student's capabilities to work as a team, leadership skills and presentation abilities, The students shall be informed in advance about the topic which would be taught and discussed in the class and along with the relevant study reference materials. ‘The teacher summarizes after the students have completed their discussion, and any clarification on the queries raised by the students is entertained, These methods will give ample scope to the teacher to reach out to individual students, to identify their shortcomings, to supervise their overall performance and to effectively carry out continuous assessment of the performance by the students. To train and inculcate research skills among the students, project assignments shall be given to the students and the topics shall be allotted in advance during the vacation before the semester begins in order to allow the students to invest their time in research work. The students are also encouraged to develop publishable research papers on the project topics assigned to them, In the classroom, every student is required to present his/her topic and to have his/her doubt cleared through discussion. The teacher will be helping and guiding the students in their pursuits of legal learning, The overall teaching method shall enable to achieve the primary role of a teacher which is to coach and facilitate student learning and overall comprehension of the course material. Journals: ‘The study materials prescribed to the students for an in-depth readings in this course paper include inter alia articles published in reputed internal journals viz, The Cambridge Law Journal, Harvard Law Review, Mid-American Review of Sociology, Michigan Law Review, Chicago Journals, Sydney Law Review, The Yale Law Journal, ‘The Journal of Ethics, Canadian Journal of Political Science, Business & Professional Ethics Journal, The Philosophical Quarterly, The Modern Law Review, Stanford Law Review, The American Law Register, University of Pennsylvania Law Review, California Law Review, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Virginia Law Review, Journal of Law and Society, The American Political Science Review, Journal of Philosophy & Public Affairs, Hypatia - A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, University of Miami Law Review and Signs - Journal of Women in Culture and Society. Course Evaluation Method: ‘The Course is assessed for 100 Marks in total by a close book examination system. There shall be @ Mid-Semester Exam for 10 Marks and End Semester Exam for 40 Marks. 30 Marks are allotted for the Project work which includes 25 Marks for written research work (5 marks for rough draft and 20 marks for final draft) and 15 Marks for oral presentation of Project. Expected Outcomes of the Cours: On completion of the Course, the students are expected to develop a comprehensive understanding of the theoretical framework of the legal concepts that are used in legal statements, the conceptions without which law maker cannot make a law, interests which law protects and the methods to satisfy them. Further, the students are expected to acquire the skill of analytical in-depth research along with a publishable research work, The students are also expected to overcome the problem of lack of confidence during classroom presentation and to inculcate the habit of team work. COURSE CONTENTS: MODULE 1 [20 TEACHING HOURS] I: Feminist Jurisprudence and Critical Legal Studies Movement and Post-modernism: Feminist Jurisprudence: Background, Origin, Basic issues of Feminist Jurisprudence, Schools of Feminist Jurisprudence: Liberal, Radical, Cultural, Post-modern Feminism and Socialist Feminism, Critical Appraisal of Feminist Jurisprudence Critical Legal Studies (CLS): Background, Ground for CLS movement, essential targets for CLS movement Post-modernism: Understanding postmodernism, the subject-object dichotomy, a critique of “subject”, departure from grand-narratives, Deconstruction and Justice. Suggested Readings from Journals: Jean Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, University of Minnesota Press, 1984. John D. Caputo, Deconstruction in a Nutshell, Fordham University press, 1997 (Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice) Duncan Kennedy, The Critique of Rights in Critical Legal Studies, pp. 1-50. Denise Meyerson, Fundamental Contradictions in Critical Legal Studies, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 11, No. 3 (Autumn, 1991), Oxford University Press, pp. 439-451. Alan Hunt, The Theory of Gritical Lega! Studies, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 6, No. 1 (Spring, 1986), Oxford University Press, pp. 1-45. Peter Goodrich, Critical Legal Studies in England: Prospective Histories, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 12, No. 2 (Summer, 1992), Oxford University Press, pp. 195-236. ‘Ann C. Seales, The Emergence of Feminist Jurisprudence: An Essay, The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 95, No. 7 (Jun. 1986), pp. 1373-1403. Mark Tushnet, Critical Legal Studies: A Political History, The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 100, No. 5, Centennial Issue (Mar., 1991), pp. 1515-1544. Mary Anne C. Case, Disaggregating Gender from Sex and Sexual Orientation: The Effeminate Man in the Law and Feminist Jurisprudence, The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 105, No. 1 (Oct,, 1995), pp. 1-105. Jeffrey A. Standen, Critical Legal Studies as an Anti-Positivist Phenomenon, Virginia Law Review, Vol. 72, No. 5 (Aug., 1986), pp. 983-998, * Mark Tushnet, Critical Legal Studies and Constitutional Law: An Essay in Deconstruction, Stanford Law Review, Vol. 36, No. 1/2, Critical Legal Studies Symposium (Jan., 1984), pp. 623-647. * G. Edward White, The Inevitability of Critical Legal Studies, Stanford Law Review, Vol. 36, No. 1/2, Critical Legal Studies Symposium (Jan., 1984),pp. 649- 672. * Stephen M. Feldman, The Politics of Postmodern Jurisprudence, Michigan Law Review, Vol. 95, No. 1 (Oct., 1996), pp. 166-202. * Albert S. Thayer, Possession, Harvard Law Review, Vol. 18, No. 3 Jan., 1905), pp. 196-213, * Roberto Mangabeira Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement, Harvard Law Review, Vol. 96, No. 3 (Jan., 1983), pp. 561-675. * Emily Jackson, Catharine MacKinnon and Feminist Jurisprudence: A Critical Appraisal, Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 19, No. 2 (Summer, 1992), pp. 195-213. * Robin West, Jurisprudence and Gender, The University of Chicago Law Review, Vol. 55, No. 1 (Winter, 1988), pp. 1-72. * Andrew Altman, Legal Realism, Critical Legal Studies, and Dworkin, Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 15, No. 3 (Summer, 1986), pp. 205-2: * John P, McCormick, Three Ways of Thinking 'Critically" about the Law, The American Political Science Review, Vol. 93, No. 2 (Jun,, 1999), pp. 413-428. * Catharine A. MacKinnon, Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: Toward Feminist Jurisprudence, Signs, Vol. 8, No. 4 (Summer, 1983), pp. 635-658. +L. Ryan Musgrave, Liberal Feminism, from Law to Art: The Impact of Feminist Jurisprudence on Feminist Aesthetics, Hypatia, Vol. 18, No. 4, Women, Art, and Aesthetics (Autumn - Winter, 2003), pp.214-235. + Kathleen Daly, Reflections on Feminist Legal Thought, Social Justice, Vol. 17, No. 3 (41), Feminism and the Social Control of Gender (Fall 1990), pp. 7-24. * Gokulesh Sharma (ed.), Feminine Jurisprudence in India: Women’s Rights, New Delhi: Deep and Deep Publications, 2008. MODULE 2: [20 TEACHING HOURS] I: JURISTIG CONCEPTS OF LAW: RIGHTS, DUTIES AND OBLIGATIONS; PERSONS IN LAW ‘The Internal Structure of Legal Norms and the Basic Legal Conceptions: Building Blocks of Legal Norms Rights: Jurisprudence of Rights; Definitions of Right: (a) On the Basis of Formal Element (b) On the basis of Material Element (c) Right as an Interest (d) Right as a Claim (e) Right as a Capacity (f) Right as a Designation of Certain Conditions; Characteristics of a Legal Right: (a) Salmond’s View (b) Roscoe Pound’s View (¢) Other's Views; Hohfeld's Analysis of Legal Rights; Classification of Legal Rights; Modes of Acquisition of Rights; Theories of Rights: (a) The Will Theory (b) The Interests Theory; Juristic and Legal Creation of Rights; Modes of Extinction of Rights; Summarizing the Concept of Legal Right (To be developed by the Student based upon the understanding of the above discussions) Duty: Meaning; Kinds of Duties: Universal, General and Particular Duties, Primary and Secondary Duties, Positive and Negative Duties, Relative and Absolute Duties, Positive and Negative Duties and Moral and Legal Duties Obligations: Meaning; Nature of Obligation; Kinds of Obligations: Moral and Legal Obligations, Contractual Obligations, Delictal Obligations, Quasi-Contractual Obligations, Innominate Obligations, Several Obligations, Joint Obligations, Joint and Several Obligations; Breach of Obligations; Relation between Obligations and Duties Persons in Law: Significance of the Topic; Meaning; Evolution of the Concept of Person; Kinds of Persons; Juristic Personality as A Centre for Jural Relations; Double Capacity and Double Personality; Status: Meaning and Nature, Status of Beasts, Status of Dead Men, Status of Unborn Persons, Status of Corporations, Theories of Corporate Personality: (a) The Fiction Theory (b) The Realist ‘Theory (c) The Purpose Theory (4) The Theory of Enterprise Entity (e) The Bracket Theory (f) The Concession Theory (g)The Theory of Procedural Forms Suggested Readings: 1. Autar Krishen Koul, A Textbook of Jurisprudence, New Delhi: Satyam Law International, 2009, pp. 299-314. 2, Salmond on Jurisprudence, Universal Law Publishing Co. Indian Rept., Twelfth Edn,, pp. 215 - 221. 3. Roscoe Pound, Jurisprudence, VI, pp. 80-81. 4, Biswas, Modern Jurisprudence, Calcutta: Kamal Law House, 1* edn,, 1998, pp. 495- 504, 515-537. 5. Biswas, Modern Jurisprudence, Calcutta: Kamal Law House, 1" edn., 1998, pp. 477- 494. 6, Autar Krishen Koul, A Textbook of Jurisprudence, New Delhi: Satyam Law International, 2009, pp. 330-397. 7. David Lyons, The Correlativity of Rights and Duties, Nots, Vol. 4, No. 1 (Feb, 1970), pp. 45-55. 8, David Andrew, Taking Rights Cynically: A Review of Critical Legal Studies, The Cambridge Law Journal, Vol. 48, No. 2 (Jul,, 1989), pp. 271-301. 1. A Javier Trevino, The Influence of Sociology on American Jurisprudence: From Oliver Wendell Holmes to Critical Legal Studies, Mid-American Review of Sociology, Vol. 18, No. 1/2 (WINTER, SPRING 1994), pp. 23-46. 2. Jeremy Waldron, The Role of Rights in Practical Reasoning: "Rights" versus "Needs’, The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 4, No. 1/2, Rights, Equality, and Liberty Universidad Torcuato Di Tella Law and Philosophy Lectures 1995-1997 (Jan. - Mar., 2000), pp. 115-135. 3. Phillip Montague, Two Concepts of Rights, Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 9, No, 4 (Summer, 1980), pp. 372-384. 4, Jed Rubenfeld, On the Legal Status of the Proposition That ‘Life Begins at Conception’, Stanford Law Review, Vol. 43, No. 3 (Feb., 1991), pp. 599-635. 5. L. H. Leigh, The Criminal Liability of Corporations and Other Groups: A Comparative View, Michigan Law Review, Vol. 80, No. 7, Articles on Corporate and Organizational Crime (Jun., 1982), pp. 1508-1528. 6 Mary Anne Warren, Life Before Birth: The Moral and Legal Status of Embryos and Fetuses by Bonnie Steinbock, Warren Ethics, Vol. 104, No. 2 (Jan, 1994), Chicago Journals, pp. 408-410. 7. E.T. Mitchell, A Theory of Corporate Will, Ethics, Vol. 56, No. 2 (Jan, 1946), Chicago Journals, pp. 96-105. 8 Thomas Carson, Friedman's Theory of Corporate Social Responsibility, Business & Professional Ethics Journal, Vol. 12, No. 1 (Spring, 1993), pp. 3-32. 9. John Dewey, The Historic Background of Corporate Legal Personality, The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 35, No. 6 (Apr., 1926), pp. 655-673. 10. Wesley N, Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository, 1917 11.J. M. Balkin, The Hohfeldian Approach to Law and Semiotics, University of Miami Law Review, 1990 12, Alan Gewirth, Rights and Duties, Mind, New Series, Vol. 97, July 1998 MODULE 3: [20 TEACHING HOURS] IM: THE CONCEPT OF PROPERTY, OWNERSHIP AND POSSESSION: Property: A jurisprudential understanding of the properties of property, Kinds of Property, Modes of Acquisition of Property, Theories of Property Ownership: Meaning and Implication of Ownership; Analysis of ownership: Single or Multiple Rights, Incidents and Subjectmatter; Kinds of Ownership; Model of Acquisition of Ownership Possession: Meaning and Implication of Possession; Physical Control v. Possession; Elements of Possession; the Acquisition of Possession Suggested Readings: * Howard Williams, Kane's Concept of Property, The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 27, No, 106 (Jan., 1977), pp. 32-40. + Edward Andrew, Jnalienable Right, Alienable Property and Freedom of Choice: Locke, Nozick and Marx on the Alienability of Labour, Canadian Journal of Political Science / Revue canadienne de science politique, Vol. 18,No. 3 (Sep, 1985), pp. 529-550. * G.P. Wilson, Jurisprudence and the Discussion of Ownership, The Cambridge Law Journal, Vol. 15, No. 2 (Nov, 1957), pp. 216-229. © Finders, Occupiers and Possession (Parkers v. British Airways Board (1982] 2 WLR. 503), Sydney Law Review, pp. 180-192, * Actual and Notorious Possession in Adverse Possession, The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 40, No. 4 (Feb, 1931), pp. 631-640. Stephen Jourdan, Current Issues Affecting Adverse Possession, Falcon Chamber, pp. 1-15. John Locke, The Works of John Locke, Vol. 4, Economic Writings and Two ‘Treatises of Government (1691) Richard A. Epstein, Possession as the Root of Title, 13 Georgia Law Review, University of Chicago Law school, Chicago Unbound, 1979, p. 1221. Carol M. Rose, Possession as the Origin of Property, Faculty Scolarship Series Paper, 1830 (1985), Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. Chhatrapati Singh, Common Property and Common Foverty, India's Forest Dwellers and the Law, New York: Oxford University Press, 1987. Gregory 8. Alexander, Ownership and Obligations: The Human Flourishing Theory of Property, Cornell Law School MODULE 4 [20 TEACHING HOURS] Iv: ACT, OMISSION AND NEGLIGENCE: Meaning of Act and Omission; Classification of Acts, Damnum Sine Injuria, Sine Damnum Injuria, Concept of negligence, Duty of Care, Standard of Care, Kinds of Negligence, Theories of Negligence: Subjective Theory and Objective Theory Suggested Readings from Journals: Mare Stauch, Risk and Remoteness of Damage in Negligence, The Modern Law Review, Vol. 64, No. 2 (Mar., 2001), pp. 191-214, Percy H. Winfield, Duty in Tortious Negligence, Columbia Law Review, Vol. 34, No. 1 (Jan., 1934), pp. 41-66. Gregory C. Keating, Reasonableness and Rationality in Negligence Theory, Stanford Law Review, Vol. 48, No. 2 (Jan., 1996), pp. 311-384. Emlin McClain, Contractual Limitation of Liability for Negligence, Harvard Law Review, Vol. 28, No. 6 (Apr., 1915), pp. 550-564. The Doctrine of Negligence, The American Law Register (1852-1891), Vol. 8, No. 7 (May, 1860), pp. 385-392. George P. Fletcher, The Theory of Criminal Negligence: A Comparative Analysis, University of Pennsylvania Law Review, Vol. 119, No. 3 (Jan., 1971), pp. 401-438. Albert A. Ehrenzweig, Negligence without Fault, California Law Review, Vol. 54, No. 4, A Tribute to Albert A. Ehrenzweig (Oct,, 1966),pp. 1422-1477. Christian Witting, Duty of Care: An Analytical Approach, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 25, No. 1 (Spring, 2005), pp. 33-63. * Douglas Payne, Foresight and Remoteness of Damage in Negligence, The Modern Law Review, Vol. 25, No. 1 Jan., 1962), pp. 1-24. MODULE FIVE: [10 TEACHING HOURS] V: Law as an Instrument of Social Change: An Introduction to the concept of social change/social transformation; relationship between law and social change; limitations of law in effecting social change; Judiciary and social change; identification of social problems and gauging the efficiency of relevant laws Suggested Readings: * Julius Stone, Law and Social Change © P.Ishwar Bhatt, Lav and Social Transformation * Sharyn L Roach Anleus, Law and Social Change, 2 edn., Sage Publication, 2000. Suggested Course Text Books for all Modules: Bodenheimer Jurisprudence, The Philosophy and Methods of Law, Delhi: Universal Publication, 1996. Jules Coleman, Scott Sharpiro, Kenneth Einar Himma (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, New York: Oxford University Press, 2002. Raymond Wacks, The Philosophy of Law: A Very Short Introduction, New York: Oxford University Press, 2006. Suri Ratnapala, Jurisprudence, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press, 2009. Salmond on Jurisprudence, Universal Law Publishing Co. Indian Rept, ‘Twelfth Edn. Fitzgerald, (ed.) Salmond on Jurisprudence (1999). W. Friedman, Legal Theory, Delhi: Universal Publishing House, 1944. V. D. Mahajan, Jurisprudence and Legal Theory, Lucknow: Eastern Books, Re. 1996. M.D.A. Freeman (ed.), Lloyd's Introduction to Jurisprudence, (1994), Sweet and Maxwell. Paton G. W., Jurisprudence, Oxford, ELBS, 1972, © HLA. Hart, The Concept of Law (1970), Oxford, ELBS. © Thomas Holland, The Elements of Jurisprudence, New Delhi: Universal Law Publishing Co. Ltd., 13" edn., 2010. © Roscoe Pound, Introduction to the Philosophy of Law (1998 Re-print), Universal Publication, Delhi. * Dias, Jurisprudence, New Delhi: Adithya Books, (1994). © Dhyani S. N., Jurisprudence: A Study of Indian Legal Theory, New Delhi: ‘Metropolitan, 1985. * MP. Tondon, Jurisprudence Legal Theory, Allahabad: Allahabad Law Agency. © Dr. Vijay Ghormade, Jurisprudence and Legal Theory, Hind Law House. © Nigel E Simmonds, Central Issues in Jurisprudence, London: Sweet and Maxwell Ltd,, 3 edn., 2008, 2010. NV. Pranjape, Studies in Jurisprudence and legal theory, Central Law Agency. Nv. Jayakumar, Lectures in Jurisprudence, 2nd Ed,, Lexis-Nexis. Dr. BN. Mani Tripathi, Jurisprudence Legal Theory, Allahabad Law Agency. PS. Atchthew Pillai, Jurisprudence and Legal Theory, Eastern Book Company. G.G. Venkata Subba Rao, Jurisprudence and Legal Theory, Eastern Book Comp * Autar Krishen Koul, A Textbook of Jurisprudence, New Delhi: Satyam Law International, 2009. * Biswas, Modern Jurisprudence, Calcutta: Kamal Law House, 1" edn,, 1998. * Gokulesh Sharma, An Introduction to Jurisprudence, New Delhi: Deep and Deep Publications, 2008. Reading Module Jean Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, University of Minnesota Press, 1984, John D. Caputo, Deconstruction in a Nutshell, Fordham University press, 1997 (Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice) Catharine A, MacKinnon, Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: Toward Feminist Jurisprudence, Signs, Vol. 8, No. 4 (Summer, 1983), pp. 635-658. Wesley N. Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Gonceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository, 1917 John Locke, The Works of John Locke, Vol. 4, Economic Writings and Two Treatises of Government (1691) Carol M. Rose, Possession as the Origin of Property, Faculty Scolarship Series Paper, 1830 (1985), Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. © Chhatrapati Singh, Common Property and Common Poverty, India’s Forest Dwellers and the Law, New York: Oxford University Press, 1987. CONTENTS x Name of the Topic Page 0. 1 | “Difference” 1 2. | The postmodern Condition 2 3. | Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: Toward 5 Feminist Jurisprudence 4 | Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial 29 Reasoning 5 | The Works of John Locke, vol. 4 Economic Writings and 91 Two Treatises of Government 6 | Possession as the Origin of Property it 7 | Property and Poverty 129 8 | The Theory of Criminal Negligence: A Comparative 137 Analysis The Role of Rights in Practical Reasoning: “Rights” versus | 175 “Needs” 10 | Toward a Theory of Property Rights 197 11 | The Criminal Liability of Corporations and Other Groups: 21 A Comparative View ~ VopsouH09 50 a10u S90 20 woueusuisisp Supyuodus RIP WOU; URED sy Sede ey 30 Suns wags oy opiasag sanboofe 1A UDA, ELL G a _Aoysesois, ue yams kg pases pou 30 omundeae ee ue pasiodsp ae ~ sung ou Jo Lon 24g 29 prom 3 Yosdusoy Yoox mupeu jo Lotsy a4 * “pa SSO “pyopan pasnpbas agra PucoRSyEANS TEST a ouyep of gpa we, ONO ABUTS aa pf pp pf fp oy et el al [Proje (pes GEER PavS\uon ‘wo os pus apid\nsap “Salidinasad“srTmousp om ang sanesrea= ious ade SARIED Jo SPROUT ' doit sy son ssi ny "oSurp seed Rey Hae nyssooany wououry-sapeuisu Sif“ wo PSST ised =i Ur youd WOPRITUY ASESA|UNS oe a smd seuss a jOSSeSSaoego pO], 1 soeoddnesad wan uy sudo 2exp ang souape ay ut ssasdoud jo Bnpesd fipsqnopun m Sypacu a "SAR NEUEN pute pout segpp | wom 4) Sud spn se em sums 2yp ut aantsiey puesd xp cy pousi Pang oF mysewiods a pur wea 2 od rone esas). ids onan voneagane Sono reo penning ce cope yp puts or usa sey 9 520 if pe bonus 9, "OR pons Apu at 2 od a ot se ouney Se SUI -poorsinpun pure paray 3 dso agoquuds ayn “ruKuout ado sin sou an w 93 pape jo woppueD a Spmbesiy jo goa, 2p Buypq ajgeseéwoous pur expe rip Bu es : pinoy] siosuvsg—uvaf uONIpUor UsBPOUISOg IY. ALT ESE pn pp uuneq axe YDHo=) Joe POUSTURLIP “HHL ‘ sais pas xp Sueno Jo sundae 250 wodipucar 0 (e032 a 9 RR PUSH JO 8H ip sume pyo ain anne Susuz “suo plo 24) 0 pappe se sabes ayy sung 9 ask wos aiojq of 2 OP semoy furut aoy, Suis opened sanuos pyo a7 62 25enSu, jo use, arwsnpoyy-ag pan *wontonateesegy “wnpeantmasss ig VIEWPOINT Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: Toward Feminist Jurisprudence Catharine A. MacKinnon I Feminism has no theory of the state. It has a theory of power: sexuality is, gendered as gender is sexualized. Male and female are created through the crotization of dominance and submission. ‘The man/woman dif- ference and the dominance/submission dynamic define each other. This is the social meaning of sex and the distinctively feminist account of gender inequality.’ Sexual objectification, the central process within this For A. D. and D. K. H. In addition to all those whose help is acknowledged in the first part of this article, “Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: An Agenda for Theory.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 7, no. 3 (Spring 1982): 515-44 (hereafter cited as part 1), my students and colleagues at Yale, Harvard, and Stanford contributed pro- foundly to the larger project of which both articles are parts. Among them, Sonia E Alvarez, Jeanne M. Barkey, Paul Brest, Ruth Colker, Karen E. Davis, Sharon Dyer, Tom Emerson, Daniel Gunther, Patricia Kliendienst Joplin, Mark Kelman, Duncan Kennedy, John Kaplan, Lyn Lemaire, Mira Marshall, Rebecca Mark, Martha Minow, Helen M. A. Neally, Lisa Rofel, Sharon Silverstein, Dean Spencer, Laurence Tribe, and Mary Whisner stand out vividly in retrospect. None of it would have happened without Lu Ann Carter and David Rayson. And thank you, Meg Baldwin, Annie McCombs, and Janet Spector Marxism appears in lower case, Black in upper ca ned in part 1. 1. Much has been made of the distinction between sex and gender. Sex is thought the more biological, gender the more social. The relation of each to sexuality varies. Since I believe sexuality is fundamental to gender and fundamentally social, and that biology is its social meaning in the system of sex inequality, which is a social and political system that does not rest independently on biological differences in any respect, the sex/gender dis- tinetion looks like a nature/culture distinction, I use sex and gender relatively inter- changeably for reasons ex; [Sign fwena of Women in Cutre ad Soriety 1988, v0. 8,0. 4} {©1985 by The Univer of Chicago. All rights reserved 002. 9TAN%3/0804.000301,00 635 5 “Tis conten donned on 4.139.215.1460 Fi, 23 7015 60603 AM. “Aes suc toJSTOR Teme ond Conte 636 MacKinnon Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State dynamic, is at once epistemological and political.* The feminist theory of knowledge is inextricable from the feminist critique of power because the male point of view forces itself upon the world as its way of ap- prehending it. ‘The perspective from the male standpoint? enforces woman's defi- nition, encircles her body, circumlocutes her speech, and describes her life. ‘The male perspective is systemic and hegemonic. The content of the signification “woman” is the content of women’s lives. Each sex has its role, but their stakes and power are not equal. If the sexes are unequal, and perspective participates in situation, there is no ungendered reality or ungendered perspective. And they are connected. In this context, objectivity—the nonsituated, universal standpoint, whether claimed or aspired to—is a denial of the existence or potency of sex inequality that tacitly participates in constructing reality from the dominant point of view. Objectivity, as the epistemological stance of which objectification is the social process, creates the reality it apprehends by defining as know! edge the reality it creates through its way of apprehending it, Sexual metaphors for knowing are no coincidence.* The solipsism of this ap- 2. This analysis is developed in part 1. 1 assume here your acquaintance with the arguments there. ‘3 Male is a social and political concept, not a biological attribute. As T use it, it has nothing whatever to do with inhereney, preexistence, nature, inevitability, or body a8 such. ft enor epistemological than ontological, unctercutting the distinction itself, given male power to conform being with perspective. (See part 1, pp: 588-89, n, 56.) The perspective poet he imale standpoint is not always each man’s opinion, alihough most men adhere (o in nonconseiously and without considering it a point of view, as much because itm ease of their experience (the male experience) as because itis in their interest, Isr for them, A few men reject it; they pay. Because itis the dominant point of view and tlefines rationality, women are pushed to see reality in is terms, although this denies their Vantage point as women in that it contradicts (at least some of) thet lived experience Women who adopt the male standpoint are passing, epistemologicaly speaking, This is not veomunon and is rewarded. The intractability of maleness asa form of dominance Suggests that social constructs, although they flow from human agency, can be less plastic than nature has proven to be. If experience trying to do sois any guide, it may be easier to change biology than society. Fe athe Bible, to know a woman is to have sex with her. You acquire carnal knowl: edge. Many scholarly metaphors elaborate the theme of violating bounties o appropri et om inside to carry off in usable form: “a penetrating observation,” “an incisive analysis: “piereing the veil.” Mary Ellman writes, “The male mind . . is assumed to function primarily ike a penis. ls fundamental character is seen to be aggression, and this {ait is held essential to the highest or best working of dhe intellect” (Thinking abut vVomen [New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich, 1968), p. 29). Feminists are beginning tounderstand that to know has meant to fuck. See Evelyn Fox Keller, "Gender and Scien Paychoanabyis and Contemporary Thought 1,10. (1978): 409-83, esp. 13; and Helen Robe ted Dovug Poninist Research (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981). The term “to tiniguely eapuures my meaning because i refers to sexual activity without distingyi eens inom intercourse. Atleast since Plato's cave, vistal metaphors for knowing have been aval to Western theories of knowledge, the visual sense prioritized as a mode of verifica cen The relationship between visual appropriation and objectification is now only begin- t 8 “this cone downoad fm 14129213146 oF, 23 an 2015 0606418 AM “asset to STOR Terns an Conan Signs Summer 1983 637 proach does not undercut its sincerity, but it is interest that precedes method. Feminism criticizes this male totality without an account of our ca- pacity to do so or to imagine or realize a more whole truth. Feminism affirms women’s point of view by revealing, criticizing, and explaining its impossibility. This is not a dialectical paradox. It is a methodological expression of women’s situation, in which the struggle for consciousness is a struggle for world: for a sexuality, a history, a culture, a community, a form of power, an experience of the sacred. If women had conscious ness or world, sex inequality would be harmless, or all women would be feminist. Yet we have something of both, or there would be no such thing as feminism, Why can women know that this—life as we have known it—is not all, not enough, not ours, not just? Now, why don’t all women?® ning to be explored. “The knowledge gained through still photographs will always be... a semblance of knowledge, a semblance of wisdom, as the act of taking pictures is a sem- blance of wisdom, a semblance of rape. The very muteness of what is, hypothetically, com prehensible in photographs is what constitutes their attraction and provocativeness” (Susan Sontag, On Photography [New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1980], p. 24). See part 1, pp. 539-40, n. 59 5, Feminism aspires to represent the experience of all women as women see it, yet, criticizes antifeminism and misogyny, including when it appears in female form. This tension is compressed in the epistemic term of art “the standpoint of all women.” We are barely beginning to unpack it. Not all women agree with the feminist account of women’s situation, nor do all feminists agree with any single rendition of feminism. Authority of interpretation—the claim to speak as a woman—thus becomes methodologically complex and politically crucial for the same reasons. Consider the accounts of their own experience given by right-wing women and lesbian sadomasochists. How can patriarchy be diminishing, to women when women embrace and defend their place in it? How can dominance and submission be violating to women when women eroticize it? Now what is the point of view of the experience of all women? Most responses in the name of feminism, stau terms of method, either (1) simply regard some women’s views as “false consciousness,” (2) embrace any version of women's experience that a biological female claims as her own. The first approach treats some women’s views as unconscious conditioned reflections of their oppression, complicitous in it. Just as science devalues experience in the process of uncovering its roots, this approach criticizes the substance of a view because it can be accounted for by its determinants. But if both feminism and antifeminism are responses to the condition of women, how is feminism exempt from devalidation by the same account? “That feminism is critical, and antifeminism is nor, is not enough, because the question is the basis on which we know something is one or the other when women, all of whom share the condition of women, disagree. The false consciousness approach begs this question by taking women’s self-reflections as evidence of their stake in their own oppression, when the women whose self-reflections are at issue question whether their condition is oppressed at all. The second response proceeds as if women are free. Or, at least, as if we have consider- able latitude to make, or to choose, the meanings if not the determinants of our situation. (Or, that the least feminism can do, since it claims to see the world through women’s eyes, is to validate the interpretations women choose. Both responses arise because of the un- willingness, central to feminism, to dismiss some women as simply deluded while granting other women the ability to see the truth. These two resolutions echo the object/subject split 7 This cote: demos Gun 1413921314608 Fi, 25 Jan 2015 040608 AM “ie ibe to STOR Tenn anu Conan’ 638 MacKinnon Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State ‘The practice of a politics of all women in the face of its theoretical impossibility is creating a new process of theorizing and a new form of theory. Although feminism emerges from women's particular experi- ence, it is not subjective or partial, for no interior ground and few if any aspects of life are free of male power. Nor is feminism objective, abstract, or universal.® It claims no external ground or unsexed sphere of gener- alization or abstraction beyond male power, nor transcendence of the specificity of each of its manifestations. How is it possible to have an engaged truth that does not simply reiterate its determinations? Dis- engaged truth only reiterates ifs determinations. Choice of method is choice of determinants—a choice which, for women as such, has been unavailable because of the subordination of women. Feminism does not begin with the premise that it is unpremised. It does not aspire to per suade an unpremised audience because there is no such audience. Its project is to uncover and claim as valid the experience of women, the major content of which is the devalidation of women’s experience. This defines our task not only because male dominance is perhaps the most pervasive and tenacious system of power in history, but because it is metaphysically nearly perfect.” Its point of view is the standard for objectivity (my consciousness is true, yours false, never mind why) or subjectivity (1 know | ie right because it feels right tome, never mind why). Thusis determinism answered with vrnseandence, traditional marxism with traditional liberalism, dogmatism with tolerance. The first approach claims authority on the basis o its lack of involvement, asserting its view independent of whether the described concurs sometimes because it does not Ut also vonn count, ther thai its alleged lack of involvement, of its own ability to provide such 3 seouint, How can some women sce the truth and other women no? The second approach Tsing authority on the basis of its involvement. Tt has no account for different inter- pretations of the sume experience or any way of choosing among conficting ones, includ Ing those between women and men. It tends to assume that women, as we are, have power arin tree in exactly the ways feminism, substantively, has found we are not. Thus, the first approach is one-sidedly outside when there is no outside, the second one-sidedly inside when someone (probably a woman) is inside everything, including every facet of sexism, racism, and so on. So our problem is this: the false consciousness approach cannot explii experience asit is experienced by those who experience it. The alternative ean only vente the terms of that experience. This is only one way in which the objecusubject split is fatal to the feminist enterprise To stress! the Feminist evitcism is not that the objective stance fails to be truly objective because it as social content, all the better to exorcise that content inthe pursuit oP the more truly poincof-viewless viewpoint. The criticism is that objectivity is largely vecurate to itvthela world, which world is criticized; and that it becomes more accurate as the poner it represents aud estends becomes more total, Analogous evtciys have arisen in the natural sciences, without being seen as threatening to the" project projects an berween natural and social objects of tnowledge, What if we estend Heisenberg’ uncertainty principle to social theory? (Wemer Heisenberg, The Physical Prneiples of the Quantan Theary (Chicago: University of Chicayo Press, 1931, pp. 4,20, 62-65). What of the axiomatic method alter Gedel's proofe {See Feat Nagel and fumes R. Newsman, Gide’ Proof [New York: New York University Press, 1958) 7 Andrea Davorkin helped me express this. oy calling into question thy cit equa ‘his oe! dows am 1439213146 09 23 Jn 2015 040508 AM site subj to JSTOR Tes nt Cnns Signs Summer 1983 639 point-of-viewlessness, its particularity the meaning of universality. Its force is exercised as consent, its authority as participation, its supremacy as the paradigm of order, its control as the definition of legitimacy. Feminism claims the voice of women's silence, the sexuality of our eroticized desexualization, the fullness of “lack,” the centrality of our marginality and exclusion, the public nature of privacy, the presence of our absence. This approach is more complex than transgression, more transformative than transvaluation, deeper than mirror-imaged resis- tance, more affirmative than the negation of our negativity. It is neither materialist nor idealist; it is feminist, Neither the transcendence of liberalism nor the determination of materialism works for us. Idealism is too unreal; women’s inequality is enforced, so it cannot simply be thought out of existence, certainly not by us. Materialism is too real; women’s inequality has never not existed, so women’s equality never has. That is, the equality of women to men will not be scientifically provable until it is no longer necessary to do so. Women’s situation offers no outside to stand on or gaze at, no inside to escape to, too much urgency to wait, no place else to go, and nothing to use but the wwisted tools that have been shoved down our throats. If feminism is revolutionary, this is why. Feminism has been widely thought to contain tendencies of liberal feminism, radical feminism, and socialist feminism. But just as socialist feminism has often amounted to marxism applied to women, liberal feminism has often amounted to liberalism applied to women. Radical feminism is feminism. Radical feminism—after this, feminism unmodified—is methodologically post-marxist.* It moves to resolve the 8. 1 mean to imply that contemporary feminism that is not methodologically post marxist is not radical, hence not feminist on this level. For example, to the extent Mary Daly's Gynicology: The Metaethies of Radical Frminism (Boston: Beacon Press, 1978) is idealist in method —meaning that the subordination of women isan idea such that to think it differently is to ehange it—it is formally liberal no matter how extreme or insightful. To the extent Shulamith Firestone's analysis (The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revolution. [New York: William Morrow & Co., 1972) rests on a naturalist definition of gender, holding that women are oppressed by our bodies rather than their social meaning, her radicalism, hence her feminism, is qualified. Susan Griffin's Pornography and Silence: Cul- ture’s Revolt against Nature (San Francisco: Harper & Row Publishers, 1982) is classically liberal in all formal respects including, for in he treatment of pornography and eros asa distinetion that is fundamentally psychological rather than interested, more deeply a matter of good and bad (morality) than of power and powerlessness (politic). Andrea Dworkin’s work, esp. Pornvgraphy: Men Passessing Women (New York: Perigee Books, 1981). and Adrienne Rich's poetry and essays, exemplify feminism as a methodological de parture. This feminism seeks co define and pursue women’s interest as the fate of alll women bound together. It seeks lo extract the truth of women’s commonalities out of the lie that all women are the same, If whatever a given society defines as sexual defines gender, and if gender means the subordination of women to men, “woman” means—is not qualified or unclereut by—the uniqueness of each woman and the specificity of race, class, time, and place, In this sense, lesbian feminism, the feminism of women of color, and socialist feminism are converging in a feminist polities of sexuality, rac left to right spectrum of its own. This politics is struggling fo and class, with a of unity that does ‘his comet dowloaded fm 14139213 16 a0 Fi, 23 Ja 2015 0806405 AM Mites sabre STOR Tem ond Conicns 640 MacKinnon Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State marxist-feminist problematic on the level of method. Because its method emerges from the concrete conditions of all women as a sex, it dissolves the individualist, naturalist, idealist, moralist structure of liberalism, the politics of which science is the epistemology. Where liberal feminism sees sexism primarily as an illusion or myth to be dispelled, an inaccuracy to be corrected, true feminism sees the male point of view as fundamental to the male power to create the world in its own image, the image of its desires, not just as its delusory end product. Feminism distinctively as such comprehends that what counts as truth is produced in the interest of those with power to shape reality, and that this process is as pervasive as it is necessary as it is changeable. Unlike the scientific strain in marx- ism or the Kantian imperative in liberalism, which in this context share most salient features, feminism neither claims universality nor, failing that, reduces to relativity. It does not seek a generality that subsumes its particulars or an abstract theory or a science of sexism. It rejects the approach of control over nature (including us) analogized to control over society (also including us) which has grounded the “science of soci- ety” project as the paradigm for political knowledge since (at least) Des- cartes. Both liberalism and marxism have been subversive on women’s behalf, Neither is enough. To grasp the inadequacies for women of liberalism on one side and marxism on the other is to begin to com- prehend the role of the liberal state and liberal legalism’ within a post- marxist feminism of social transformation. As feminism has a theory of power but lacks a theory of the state, so marxism has a theory of value which (through the organization of work in production) becomes class analysis, but a problematic theory of the state, Marx did not address the state much more explicitly than he did women. Women were substratum, the state epiphenomenon.’ Engels, not depend upon saineness without dissolving into empty tolerance, including tolerance of all it exists to change whenever that appears embodied in one of us. A new community begins here. As critique, women’s communality describes a fact of male supremacy, of sex “in itself": no woman escapes the meaning of being a woman within a gendered social system, and sex inequality is not only pervasive but may be universal (in the sense of never having not been in some form) although “intelligible only in ... locally specific forms” (M. Z. Rosaldo, “The Use and Abuse of Anthropology: Reflections on Feminism and Cross- cultural Understanding,” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Soviety §, no. 8 (Spring 1980}: 389-417, 417), For women to become a sex "for ourselves” moves community to the level of vision. 9, See Karl Klare, “Law-Making as Praxis,” Telos 12, no, 2 (Summer 1979): 123-35; Judith Shklar, Legalivm (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1964). ‘To examine law as state is not to decide that all relevant state behavior occurs in legal texts. 1 do think that legal decisions expose power on the level of legitimizing rationale, and that lav, as words in power, is central in the social erection of the liberal state. 10. Karl Marx, Capital, Selected Works, 3 vols. (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1969), 20120, 139-40; The German Ideology (New York: International Publishers, 1972), pp. 48-52; Trtvauction to Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right, ed. Joseph O'Malley, trans. Annete Jolin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), p. 139; Marx to P. V. Annenkov, 1846, in The Poverty of Philosophy (New York: International Publishers, 1968), pp. 179-98, 181 ‘his sonst downloaded fom 14139215146 on Fi, 23 San 2015 04:06:03 AM Tifusesbjet fo STOR Terme ond Cn Signs Summer 1983 641 who frontally analyzed both, and together, presumed the subordination of women in every attempt to reveal its roots, just as he presupposed something like the state, or state-like social conditions, in every attempt to expose its origins.!" Marx tended to use the term “political” narrowly to refer to the state or its laws, criticizing as exclusively political inter- pretations of the state’s organization or behavior which took them as sui generis. Accordingly, until recently, most marxism has tended to con- sider political that which occurs between classes, that is, to interpret as “the political” instances of the marxist concept of inequality. In this broad sense, the marxist theory of social inequality has been its theory of poli- tics. This has not so much collapsed the state into society (although it goes far in that direction) as conceived the state as determined by the totality of social relations of which the state is one determined and de- termining part—without specifying which, or how much, is which. In this context, recent marxist work has tried to grasp the specificity of the institutional state: how it wields class power, or transforms class society, or responds to approach by a left aspiring to rulership or other changes. While liberal theory has seen the state as emanating power, and traditional marxism has seen the state as expressing power constituted elsewhere, recent marxism, much of it structuralist, has tried to analyze state power as specific to the state as a form, yet integral to a determinate social whole understood in class terms. This state is found “relatively autonomous.” This means that the state, expressed through its functionaries, has a definite class character, is definitely capitalist or socialist, but also has its own interests which are to some degree in- dependent of those of the ruling class and even of the class structure." The state as such, in this view, has a specific power and interest, termed “the political,” such that class power, class interest expressed by and in the state, and state behavior, although inconceivable in isolation from one another, are nevertheless not linearly or causally linked or strictly coextensive. Such work locates “the specificity of the political” in a 11, 1 am criticizing Engels's assumptions about sexuality and women’s place, and his empiricist method, and suggesting that the two are linked. Friedrich Engels, Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State (New York: International Publishers, 1942). 12. Representative works include Fred Block, “The Ruling Class Does Not Rule Notes on the Marxist Theory of the State,” Socialist Revolution 33 (May-June 1977): 6-28; Ralph Miliband, The State in Capitalist Society (New York: Basic Books, 1969); Nicos Poulantzas, Classes in Contemporary Capitalism (London: New Left Books, 1975), and Political Power and Social Classes (London: New Left Books, 1975); Goran Therborn, What Does the Ruling Class Do When It Rules? (London: New Left Books, 1978); Norberto Bobbio, “Is There Marxist Theory of the State?" Telos 35 (Spring 1978): 5-16. Theda Skocpol, States and Social Revolution: A Comparative Analysis of France, Russia and China (Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press, 1979), pp. 24-38, ably reviews much of this literature. Applica: tions to law include Isaac Balbus, "Commodity Form and Legal Form: An Essay on the “Relative Autonomy’ of the Law,” Law and Society Review 11, no. 3 (Winter 1977): 571-88: Mark Tushnet, “A Marxist Analysis of American Law," Marxist Perspectives 1, no. 1 (Spring 1978): 96-116; and Klare (n. 9 above), dat “This cone dows 1413921546 on Fi, 23 Jan 2015 DOGS AM ‘lfasesujesto STOR Tem nd Conn 642 MacKinnon Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State mediate “region” between the state as its own ground of power (which alone, as in the liberal conception, would set the state above or apart from class) and the state as possessing no special supremacy or priority in terms of power, as in the more orthodox marxist view. The idea that the state is relatively autonomous, a kind of first among equals of social institutions, has the genius of appearing to take a stand on the issue of reciprocal constitution of state and society while straddling it. Is the state essentially autonomous of class but partly de- termined by it, or is it essentially determined by class but not exclusively so? Is it relatively constrained within a context of freedom or relatively free within a context of constraint? As to who or what fundamentally moves and shapes the realities and instrumentalities of domination, and where to go to do something about it, what qualifies what is as ambiguous as it is crucial. Whatever it has not accomplished, however, this literature has at least relieved the compulsion to find all law—directly or con- volutedly, nakedly or clothed in unconscious or devious rationalia—to be simply bourgeois, without undercutting the notion that it is de- terminately driven by interest. ‘A methodologically post-marxist feminism must confront, on our own terms, the issue of the relation between the state and society, within a theory of social determination adequate to the specificity of sex. Lack ing even a tacit theory of the state of its own, feminist practice has instead oscillated between a liberal theory of the state on the one hand and a left theory of the state on the other. Both treat law as the mind of society: disembodied reason in liberal theory, reflection of material interest in left theory. In liberal moments the state is accepted on its own terms as a neutral arbiter among conflicting interests. The law is actually or potentially principled, meaning predisposed to no substantive out- come, thus available as a tool that is not fatally wwisted. Women implicitly become an interest group within pluralism, with specific problems of mobilization and representation, exit and voice, sustaining incremental gains and losses. In left moments, the state becomes a tool of dominance and repression, the law legitimizing ideology, use of the legal system a form of utopian idealism or gradualist reform, each apparent gain de- ceptive or cooptive, and each loss inevitable. Applied to women, liberalism has supported state intervention on behalf of women as abstract persons with abstract rights, without scrutinizing the content of these notions in gendered terms. Marxism 13. Poulantzas’s formulation follows Althusser. Louis Althusser and Etienne Balibar, Reading Capital, trans. Ben Brewster (London: New Left Books, 1968). For Poulantzas, the “specific autonomy whieh is characteristic of the function of the state _ . . isthe basis of the specificity of the political” (Political Power and Social Classes (n. 12 above}, pp. 14, 46). Whatever that means. On structural causality between class and state, see p. 14. 14. See Ernesto Lackiu's similar criticism of Miliband in Politirs and Ideology in Marxist Theory (London: New Left Books, 1977), p. 65. \e "his comet downland fr 14.139.213.146 09 Fi 23 Jn 2015 060 AM. Tas abject to JSTOR Teams and Conds Signs Summer 1983 643 applied to women is always on the edge of counseling abdication of the state as an arena altogether—and with it those women whom the state does not ignore or who are, as yet, in no position to ignore it. Feminism has so far accepted these constraints upon its alternatives: either the state, as primary tool of women’s betterment and status transformation, without analysis (hence strategy) for it as male; or civil society, which for women has more closely resembled a state of nature. The state, with it the law, has been either omnipotent or impotent: everything or nothing. ‘The feminist posture toward the state has therefore been schizoid on issues central to women’s survival: rape, battery, pornography, pros- titution, sexual harassment, sex discrimination, abortion, the Equal Rights Amendment, to name a few. Atiempts to reform and enforce rape laws, for example, have tended to build on the model of the deviant perpetrator and the violent act, as if the fact that rape is a crime means that the society is against it, so law enforcement would reduce or de- legitimize it, Initiatives are accordingly directed toward making the police more sensitive, prosecutors more responsive, judges more re- ceptive, and the law, in words, less sexist. This may be progressive in the liberal or the left senses, but how is it empowering in the feminist sense? Even if it were effective in jailing men who do litle different from what nondeviant men do regularly, how would such an approach alter wom- en’s rapability? Unconfronted are why women are raped and the role of the state in that. Similarly, applying laws against battery to husbands, although it can mean life itself, has largely failed to address, as part of the strategy for state intervention, the conditions that produce men who systematically express themselves violently toward women, women whose resistance is disabled, and the role of the state in this dynamic Criminal enforcement in these areas, while suggesting that rape and battery are deviant, punishes men for expressing the images of mascu- linity that mean their identity, for which they are otherwise trained, elevated, venerated, and paid. These men must be stopped. But how does that change them or reduce the chances that there will be more like them? Liberal strategies entrust women to the state. Left theory aban- dons us to the rapists and batterers. The question for feminism is not only whether there is a meaningful difference between the two, but whether either is adequate to the feminist critique of rape and battery as systemic and to the role of the state and the law within that system. Feminism has descriptions of the state's weatment of the gender difference, but no analysis of the state as gender hierarchy. We need to know. What, in gender terms, are the state's norms of accountability, sources of power, real constituency? Is the state to some degree autono- mous of the interests of men or an integral expression of them? Does the state embody and serve male interests in its form, dynamics, relation to society, and specific policies? Is the state constructed upon the sub- ordination of women? If so, how does male power become state power? IS Ts ctr dnd or 4129213. 2 9 2015 040503 AM 644 MacKinnon Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State Gan such a state be made to serve the interests of those upon whose powerlessness its power is erected? Would a different relation between state and society, such as may pertain under socialism, make a dif- ference? If not, is masculinity inherent in the state form as such, or is some other form of state, or some other way of governing, distinguish- able or imaginable? In the absence of answers to such questions, feminism has been caught between giving more power to the state in each attempt to claim it for women and leaving unchecked power in the society to men. Undisturbed, meanwhile, like the assumption that women generally consent to sex, is the assumption that we consent to this government. The question for feminism, for the first time on its own terms, is: what is this state, from women’s point of view? ‘As a beginning, 1 propose that the state is male in the feminist sense.'® The law sees and treats women the way men see and treat women. The liberal state coercively and authoritatively constitutes the social order in the interest of men as a gender, through its legitimizing norms, relation to society, and substantive policies. It achieves this through embodying and ensuring male control over women’s sexuality at every level, occasionally cushioning, qualifying, or de jure prohibiting its excesses when necessary to its normalization. Substantively, the way the male point of view frames an experience is the way it is framed by state policy. To the extent possession is the point of sex, rape is sex with a woman who is not yours, unless the act is so as to make her yours. If part of the kick of pornography involves eroticizing the putatively prohibited, obscenity law will putatively prohibit pornography enough to maintain its desirability without ever making it unavailable or truly illegitimate The same with prostitution, As male is the implicit reference for human, maleness will be the measure of equality in sex discrimination law. To the extent that the point of abortion is to control the reproductive sequelae of intercourse, so as to facilitate male sexual access to women, access to abortion will be controlled by “a man or The Man.”!® Gender, elaborated and sustained by behavioral patterns of application and ad- ministration, is maintained as a division of power. Formally, the state is male in that objectivity is its norm. Objectivity is liberal legalism’s conception of itself. It legitimizes itself by reflecting its view of existing society, a society it made and makes by so seeing i 15. Sce Susan Rae Peterson, “Coercion and Rape: The State as a Male Protection Racket,” in Feminism and Philosophy, ed. Mary Vetterling-Braggin, Frederick A. Elliston, and Jane English (Totowa, N.J.: Littlefield, Adams & Co., 1977), pp. 360-71; Janet Rifkin, “Toward a Theory of Law Patriarchy,” Harvard Women's Law Journal 3 (Spring 1980): 83-92, 16. Johnnie Tillmon, “Welfare Is a Women's Issue,” Liberation News Service (February 26, 1972), in America's Working Women: A Documentary History, 1600 to the Present, ed. Rosa lyn Baxandall, Linda Gordon, and Susan Reverby (New York: Vintage Books, 1976), pp. 357-58. 4 This cet donno 4.138213. 146 00 Fi, 23 Jn 2015 04.0503 AM Mie saben to STOR Teme nd Condon Signs Summer 1983 645 and calling that view, and that relation, practical rationality. If rationality is measured by point-of-viewlessness, what counts as reason will be that which corresponds to the way things are. Practical will mean that which can be done without changing anything. In this framework, the task of legal interpretation becomes “to perfect the state as mirror of the soci- ety."!7 Objectivist epistemology is the law of law. It ensures that the law will most reinforce existing distributions of power when it most closely adheres to its own highest ideal of fairness. Like the science it emulates, this epistemological stance can not see the social specificity of reflection as method or its choice to embrace that which it reflects. Such law not only reflects a society in which men rule women; it rules in a male way: “The phallus means everything that sets itself up as a mirror." The rule form, which unites scientific knowledge with state control in its concep- tion of what law is, institutionalizes the objective stance as jurisprudence. A closer look at the substantive law of rape’ in light of such an argu- ment suggests that the relation between objectification (understood as the primary process of the subordination of women) and the power of the state is the relation between the personal and the political at the level of government. This is not because the state is presumptively the sphere of politics. It is because the state, in part through law, institutionalizes male power. If male power is systemic, it is the regime 17, Laurence Tribe, “Constitution as Point of View” (Harvard Law School, Cam- bridge, Mass., 1982, mimeographed), p. 13. 18. Madeleine Gagnon, “Body I,” in New French Feminisms, ed. Elaine Marks and Isabelle de Courtivron (Amherst, Mass.: University of Massachusetts Press, 1980), p. 180. Turns on the mirroring trope, which T see as metaphoric analyses of the epistemological’ political dimension of objectification, are ubiquitous in feminist writing: “Into the room of the dressing where the walls are covered with mirrors, Where mirrors are like eyes of men, and the women reflect the judgments of mirrors” (Susan Griffin, Woman and Nature: The Roaring Insile Her (New York: Harper & Row Publishers, 1979], p. 155). See also Mary Daly, Beyond God the Father: Toward a Philosophy of Women's Liberation (Boston: Beacon Press, 1975), pp. 195, 197; Sheila Rowbotham, Women's Consciousness, Man's World (H. worth: Pelican Books, 1973), pp. 26-29. "She did suffer, the witch/ trying to peer round the looking/ glass, she forgot/ someone was in the way" (Michelene, “Reffexion,” quoted in Rowbotham, p. 2). Virginia Woolf wrote the figure around ("So I reflected . .."), noticing “the necessity that women so often are to men” of serving as a looking glass in which a man can “sce himself at breakfast and at dinner at least twice the size he really is.” Notice the doubled sexwal/ gender meaning: "Whatever may be their use in civilized societies, mirrors are essential to all violent and heroic action. That is why Napoleon and Mussolini both. insist so emphatically upon the inferiority of women, for if they were not inferior, they would cease to enlarge” (4 Room of One’s Own [New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1969}, p. 36), 19, Space limitations made it necessary to eliminate sections on pornography, sex discrimination, and abortion, For the sate reason, most supporting references, including, those to case law, have been cut. The final section accordingly states the systemic im; plications of the analysis more tentatively than I think them, but as strongly as I felt I could, ‘on the basis of the single substantive examination that appears here. pp 1s coon Sond oy 143921345 on 23 2015080509 AM “ia ue BTOK Tatas ow 646 MacKinnon Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State i Feminists have reconceived rape as central to women’s condition in two ways. Some see rape as an act of violence, not sexuality, the threat of which intimidates all women.° Others see rape, including its violence, as an expression of male sexuality, the social imperatives of which define all women.?! The first, formally in the liberal tradition, comprehends rape as a displacement of power based on physical force onto sexuality, a pre- existing natural sphere to which domination is alien. ‘Thus, Susan Brownmiller examines rape in riots, wars, pogroms, and revolutions; rape by police, parents, prison guards; and rape motivated by racism— seldom rape in normal circumstances, in everyday life, in ordinary re- lationships, by men as men.*® Women are raped by guns, age, white supremacy, the state—only derivatively by the penis. The more feminist view to me, one which derives from victims’ experiences, sees sexuality as a social sphere of male power of which forced sex is paradigmatic, Rape is not less sexual for being violent; to the extent that coercion has become integral to male sexuality, rape may be sexual to the degree that, and because, it is violent The point of defining rape as “violence not sex” or “violence against women" has been to separate sexuality from gender in order to affirm sex (heterosexuality) while rejecting violence (rape). The problem re- mains what it has always been: telling the difference. The convergence of sexuality with violence, long used at law to deny the reality of women’s violation, is recognized by rape survivors, with a difference: where the legal system has scen the intercourse in rape, victims see the rape in intercourse. The uncoerced context for sexual expression becomes as elusive as the physical acts come to feel indistinguishable.** Instead of 20. Susan Brownmiller, Agains! Our Will: Men, Women aud Rape (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1976), p. 15. 21. Diana E. H, Russell, The Polities of Rape: The Victim's Perspective (New York: Stein & Day, 1977); Andrea Medea and Kathleen Thompson, -(gainst Rape (New York: Farrat Straus & Giroux, 1974}; Lorenne M. G. Clark and Debra Lewis, Rape: The Price of Coercive Sexuality (Toronto; ‘The Women's Press, 1977}; Susan Griffin, “Rape: ‘The All-American Crime,” Ramparts (September 1971), pp. 26-35; Ti-Grace Atkinson connects rape with “the institution of sexual intercourse” (mason Oryssey: The First Collection of Writings by the Political Pioneer of the Women’s Movement (New York: Links Books, 1974], pp. 13-23). Kakanu ya Salaam, "Rape: A Radical Analysis from the African-American Perspective,” in Our Women Keep Our Skies from Falling (New Orleans: Nkombo, 1980), pp. 25-40. 22. Racism, clearly, is everyday life, Racisin in the United States, by singling out Black men for allegations of rape of white women, has helped obscure the fact that it is men who. rape women, disproportionately women of color 23. “Like other victims, I had problems with sex, after the rape. There was no way that Arthur could touch me that it didn’t remind me of having been raped by this guy 1 never saw” (Carolyn Craven, “No More Victims: Carolyn Craven Talks about Rape, and about What Women and Men Can Do to Stop It," ed. Alison Wells (Berkeley, Calif., 1978, ‘mimeographed]), p. 2 16 ‘is eet donload eo 141392156 on Fj 23 Jun 205 080605 AM fade ebjecto STOR fens and Condon

You might also like