Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 38

Nationalism

First published Thu Nov 29, 2001; substantive revision Wed Sep 2, 2020
The term “nationalism” is generally used to describe two phenomena:

1. the attitude that the members of a nation have when they care about their national
identity, and
2. the actions that the members of a nation take when seeking to achieve (or sustain)
self-determination.
(1) raises questions about the concept of a nation (or national identity), which is often
defined in terms of common origin, ethnicity, or cultural ties, and specifically about
whether an individual’s membership in a nation should be regarded as non-voluntary or
voluntary. (2) raises questions about whether self-determination must be understood as
involving having full statehood with complete authority over domestic and international
affairs, or whether something less is required.
Nationalism came into the focus of philosophical debate three decades ago, in the
nineties, partly in consequence of rather spectacular and troubling nationalist clashes.
Surges of nationalism tend to present a morally ambiguous, and for this reason often
fascinating, picture. “National awakening” and struggles for political independence are
often both heroic and cruel; the formation of a recognizably national state often responds
to deep popular sentiment but sometimes yields inhuman consequences, from violent
expulsion and “cleansing” of non-nationals to organized mass murder. The moral debate
on nationalism reflects a deep moral tension between solidarity with oppressed national
groups on the one hand and repulsion in the face of crimes perpetrated in the name of
nationalism on the other. Moreover, the issue of nationalism points to a wider domain of
problems related to the treatment of ethnic and cultural differences within democratic
polity, arguably among the most pressing problems of contemporary political theory.
In the last two decades, migration crisis and the populist reactions to migration and
domestic economic issues have been the defining traits of a new political constellation.
The traditional issue of the contrast between nationalism and cosmopolitanism has
changed its profile: the current drastic contrast is between populist aversion to the
foreigners-migrants and a more generous, or simply just, attitude of acceptance and
Samaritan help. The populist aversion inherits some features traditionally associated with
patriotism and nationalism, and the opposite attitude the main features of traditional
cosmopolitanism. One could expect that the work on nationalism will be moving further
on this new and challenging playground, addressing the new contrast and trying to locate
nationalism in relation to it.
In this entry, we shall first present conceptual issues of definition and classification
(Sections 1 and 2) and then the arguments put forward in the debate (Section 3),
dedicating more space to the arguments in favor of nationalism than to those against it in
order to give the philosophical nationalist a proper hearing. In the last part we shall turn
to the new constellation and sketch the new issues raised by nationalist and trans-
nationalist populisms and the migration crisis.

 1. What is a Nation?
o 1.1 The Basic Concept of Nationalism
o 1.2 The Concept of a Nation
 2. Varieties of Nationalism
o 2.1 Concepts of Nationalism: Classical and Liberal
o 2.2 Moral Claims, Classical Vs. Liberal: The Centrality of Nation
 3. The Moral Debate
o 3.1 Classical and liberal nationalisms
o 3.2 Arguments in favor of nationalism, classical vs. liberal: the deep need
for community
o 3.3 Arguments in favor of nationalism: issues of justice
o 3.4 Populism and a new face of nationalism
o 3.5 Nation-state in global context
 4. Conclusion
 Bibliography
o Introduction
o References
 Academic Tools
 Other Internet Resources
 Related Entries

1. What is a Nation?
1.1 The Basic Concept of Nationalism
Although the term “nationalism” has a variety of meanings, it centrally encompasses two
phenomena: (1) the attitude that the members of a nation have when they care about their
identity as members of that nation and (2) the actions that the members of a nation take in
seeking to achieve (or sustain) some form of political sovereignty (see for example,
Nielsen 1998–9: 9). Each of these aspects requires elaboration.

1. raises questions about the concept of a nation or national identity, about what it is
to belong to a nation, and about how much one ought to care about one’s nation.
Nations and national identity may be defined in terms of common origin, ethnicity,
or cultural ties, and while an individual’s membership in the nation is often
regarded as involuntary, it is sometimes regarded as voluntary. The degree of care
for one’s nation that nationalists require is often, but not always, taken to be very
high: according to such views, the claims of one’s nation take precedence over
rival contenders for authority and loyalty.[1]
2. raises questions about whether sovereignty requires the acquisition of full
statehood with complete authority over domestic and international affairs, or
whether something less than statehood suffices. Although sovereignty is often
taken to mean full statehood (Gellner 1983: ch. 1),[2] possible exceptions have been
recognized (Miller 1992: 87; Miller 2000). Some authors even defend an anarchist
version of patriotism-moderate nationalism foreshadowed by Bakunin (see
Sparrow 2007).
There is a terminological and conceptual question of distinguishing nationalism from
patriotism. A popular proposal is the contrast between attachment to one’s country as
defining patriotism and attachment to one’s people and its traditions as defining
nationalism (Kleinig 2014: 228, and Primoratz 2017: Section 1.2). One problem with this
proposal is that love for a country is not really just love of a piece of land but normally
involves attachment to the community of its inhabitants, and this introduces “nation” into
the conception of patriotism. Another contrast is the one between strong, and somewhat
aggressive attachment (nationalism) and a mild one (patriotism), dating back at least to
George Orwell (see his 1945 essay).[3]
Despite these definitional worries, there is a fair amount of agreement about the classical,
historically paradigmatic form of nationalism. It typically features the supremacy of the
nation’s claims over other claims to individual allegiance and full sovereignty as the
persistent aim of its political program. Territorial sovereignty has traditionally been seen
as a defining element of state power and essential for nationhood. It was extolled in
classic modern works by Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau and is returning to center stage in
the debate, though philosophers are now more skeptical (see below). Issues surrounding
the control of the movement of money and people (in particular immigration) and the
resource rights implied in territorial sovereignty make the topic politically central in the
age of globalization and philosophically interesting for nationalists and anti-nationalists
alike.
In recent times, the philosophical focus has moved more in the direction of “liberal
nationalism”, the view that mitigates the classical claims and tries to bring together the
pro-national attitude and the respect for traditional liberal values. For instance, the
territorial state as political unit is seen by classical nationalists as centrally “belonging” to
one ethnic-cultural group and as actively charged with protecting and promulgating its
traditions. The liberal variety allows for “sharing” of the territorial state with non-
dominant ethnic groups. Consequences are varied and quite interested (for more see
below, especially section 2.1).

1.2 The Concept of a Nation


In its general form, the issue of nationalism concerns the mapping between the ethno-
cultural domain (featuring ethno-cultural groups or “nations”) and the domain of political
organization. In breaking down the issue, we have mentioned the importance of the
attitude that the members of a nation have when they care about their national identity.
This point raises two sorts of questions. First, the descriptive ones:
(1a)
What is a nation and what is national identity?
(1b)
What is it to belong to a nation?
(1c)
What is the nature of pro-national attitude?
(1d)
Is membership in a nation voluntary or involuntary?
Second, the normative ones:
(1e)
Is the attitude of caring about national identity always appropriate?
(1f)
How much should one care?
This section discusses the descriptive questions, starting with (1a) and (1b);the normative
questions are addressed in Section 3 on the moral debate. If one wants to enjoin people to
struggle for their national interests, one must have some idea about what a nation is and
what it is to belong to a nation. So, in order to formulate and ground their evaluations,
claims, and directives for action, pro-nationalist thinkers have expounded theories of
ethnicity, culture, nation, and state. Their opponents have in turn challenged these
elaborations. Now, some presuppositions about ethnic groups and nations are essential for
the nationalist, while others are theoretical elaborations designed to support the essential
ones. The definition and status of the social group that benefits from the nationalist
program, variously called the “nation”, “ethno-nation”, or “ethnic group”, is essential.
Since nationalism is particularly prominent with groups that do not yet have a state, a
definition of nation and nationalism purely in terms of belonging to a state is a non-
starter.
Indeed, purely “civic” loyalties are often categorized separately under the title
“patriotism”, which we already mentioned, or “constitutional patriotism”. [4] This leaves
two extreme options and a number of intermediates. The first extreme option has been put
forward by a small but distinguished band of theorists.[5] According to their purely
voluntaristic definition, a nation is any group of people aspiring to a common political
state-like organization. If such a group of people succeeds in forming a state, the loyalties
of the group members become “civic” (as opposed to “ethnic”) in nature. At the other
extreme, and more typically, nationalist claims are focused upon the non-voluntary
community of common origin, language, tradition, and culture: the classic ethno-nation is
a community of origin and culture, including prominently a language and customs. The
distinction is related (although not identical) to that drawn by older schools of social and
political science between “civic” and “ethnic” nationalism, the former being allegedly
Western European and the latter more Central and Eastern European, originating in
Germany.[6] Philosophical discussions centered on nationalism tend to concern the ethnic-
cultural variants only, and this habit will be followed here. A group aspiring to
nationhood on this basis will be called an “ethno-nation” to underscore its ethno-cultural
rather than purely civic underpinnings. For the ethno-(cultural) nationalist it is one’s
ethnic-cultural background that determines one’s membership in the community. One
cannot choose to be a member; instead, membership depends on the accident of origin
and early socialization. However, commonality of origin has become mythical for most
contemporary candidate groups: ethnic groups have been mixing for millennia.
Sophisticated, liberal pro-nationalists therefore tend to stress cultural membership only
and speak of “nationality”, omitting the “ethno-” part (Miller 1992, 2000; Tamir
1993,2013; Gans 2003). Michel Seymour’s proposal of a “socio-cultural definition” adds
a political dimension to the purely cultural one: a nation is a cultural group, possibly but
not necessarily united by a common descent, endowed with civic ties (Seymour 2000).
This is the kind of definition that would be accepted by most parties in the debate today.
So defined, the nation is a somewhat mixed category, both ethno-cultural and civic, but
still closer to the purely ethno-cultural than to the purely civic extreme.
Let us now turn to the issue of the origin and “authenticity” of ethno-cultural groups or
ethno-nations. In social and political science one usually distinguishes two kinds of
views, but there is a third group, combining element from both. The first are modernist
views that see nationalism as born in modern times, together with nation-states. [7] In our
times the view was pioneered by Ernst Gellner (see his 1983).[8] Other modernist choose
similar starting points with century or two of variation.[9] The opposite view can be called,
following Edward Shils (1957) “primordialist”. According to it, actual ethno-cultural
nations have either existed “since time immemorial”.
The third, quite plausible kind of view, distinct from both primordialism-ethno-
symbolism and modernism, has been initiated by W. Connor (1994). [10] A nation is a
politicized and mobilized ethnic group rather than a state. So, the origins of nationalism
predate the modern state, and its emotional content remains up to our times (Conversi
2002: 270), but the actual statist organization is, indeed, modern. However, nation-state is
a nationalist dream and fiction, never really implemented, due to the inescapable plurality
of social groups. So much for the three dominant perspectives on the origin of
nationalism.
Indeed, the older authors—from great thinkers like Herder and Otto Bauer to the
propagandists who followed their footsteps—took great pains to ground normative claims
upon firm ontological realism about nations: nations are real, bona fide entities. However,
the contemporary moral debate has tried to diminish the importance of the imagined/real
divide. Prominent contemporary philosophers have claimed that normative-evaluative
nationalist claims are compatible with the “imagined” nature of a nation. [11] They point out
that common imaginings can tie people together, and that actual interaction resulting from
togetherness can engender important moral obligations.
Let us now turn to question (1c) about the nature of pro-national attitudes. The
explanatory issue that has interested political and social scientists concerns ethno-
nationalist sentiment, the paradigm case of a pro-national attitude. Is it as irrational,
romantic, and indifferent to self-interest as it might seem on the surface? The issue has
divided authors who see nationalism as basically irrational and those who try to explain it
as being in some sense rational. Authors who see it as irrational propose various
explanations of why people assent to irrational views. Some say, critically, that
nationalism is based on “false consciousness”. But where does such false consciousness
come from? The most simplistic view is that it is a result of direct manipulation of
“masses” by “elites”. On the opposite side, the famous critic of nationalism Elie Kedourie
(1960) thinks this irrationality is spontaneous. A decade and a half ago Liah Greenfeld
went as far as linking nationalism to mental illness in her provocative 2005 article (see
also her 2006 book). On the opposite side, Michael Walzer has offered a sympathetic
account of nationalist passion in his 2002. Authors relying upon the Marxist tradition
offer various deeper explanations. To mention one, the French structuralist Étienne
Balibar sees it as a result of the “production” of ideology effectuated by mechanisms
which have nothing to do with spontaneous credulity of individuals, but with impersonal,
structural social factors (Balibar & Wallerstein 1988 [1991]). [12]
Some authors claim that it is often rational for individuals to become nationalists (Hardin
1985). Can one rationally explain the extremes of ethno-national conflict? Authors like
Russell Hardin propose to do so in terms of a general view of when hostile behavior is
rational: most typically, if an individual has no reason to trust someone, it is reasonable
for that individual to take precautions against the other. If both sides take precautions,
however, each will tend to see the other as increasingly inimical. It then becomes rational
to start treating the other as an enemy. Mere suspicion can thus lead by small,
individually rational steps to a situation of conflict. (Such negative development is often
presented as a variant of the Prisoner’s Dilemma; see the entry on prisoner’s dilemma). It
is relatively easy to spot the circumstances in which this general pattern applies to
national solidarities and conflicts (see also Wimmer 2013).
Finally, as for question (1d), the nation is typically seen as an essentially non-voluntary
community to which one belongs by birth and early nurture and such that the belonging is
enhanced and made more complete by one’s additional conscious endorsement. Not
everyone agrees: liberal nationalists accept the idea of choice of one’s national belonging
and of possibility for immigrants to become nationals by choice and intentional
acculturation.

2. Varieties of Nationalism
2.1 Concepts of Nationalism: Classical and Liberal
We pointed out at the very beginning of the entry that nationalism focuses upon (1) the
attitude that the members of a nation have when they care about their national identity,
and (2) the actions that the members of a nation take when seeking to achieve (or sustain)
some form of political sovereignty. The politically central point is (2): the actions
enjoined by the nationalist. To these we now turn, beginning with sovereignty and
territory, the usual foci of a national struggle for independence. They raise an important
issue:
(2a)
Does political sovereignty within or over a territory require statehood or
something weaker?
The classical answer is that a state is required. A more liberal answer is that some form of
political autonomy suffices. Once this has been discussed, we can turn to the related
normative issues:
(2b)
What actions are morally permitted to achieve sovereignty and to maintain it?
(2c)
Under what conditions is it morally permitted to take actions of this kind?
Consider first the classical nationalist answer to (2a). Political sovereignty requires a state
“rightfully owned” by the ethno-nation (Oldenquist 1997). Developments of this line of
thought often state or imply specific answers to (2b), and (2c), i.e., that in a national
independence struggle the use of force against the threatening central power is almost
always a legitimate means for bringing about sovereignty. However, classical nationalism
is not only concerned with the creation of a state but also with its maintenance and
strengthening.
Classical nationalism is the political program that sees the creation and maintenance of a
fully sovereign state owned by a given ethno-national group (“people” or “nation”) as a
primary duty of each member of the group. Starting from the assumption that the
appropriate (or “natural”) unit of culture is an ethno-nation, it claims that a primary duty
of each member is to abide by one’s recognizably ethno-national culture in all cultural
matters.
Classical nationalists are usually vigilant about the kind of culture they protect and
promote and about the kind of attitude people have to their nation-state. This watchful
attitude carries some potential dangers: many elements of a given culture that are
universal or simply not recognizably national may fall prey to such nationalist
enthusiasms. Classical nationalism in everyday life puts various additional demands on
individuals, from buying more expensive home-produced goods in preference to cheaper
imported ones to procreating as many future members of the nation as one can manage
(see Yuval-Davies 1997, and Yack 2012).
Besides classical nationalism (and its more radical extremist cousins), various moderate
views are also now classified as nationalist. Indeed, the philosophical discussion has
shifted to these moderate or even ultra-moderate forms, and most philosophers who
describe themselves as nationalists propose very moderate nationalist programs.
Nationalism in this wider sense is any complex of attitudes, claims, and directives for
action ascribing a fundamental political, moral, and cultural value to nation and
nationality and deriving obligations (for individual members of the nation, and for any
involved third parties, individual or collective) from this ascribed value. The main
representative of this group of views is liberal nationalism, proposed by authors like
Miller, Tamir, and Gans (see below).
Nationalisms in this wider sense can vary somewhat in their conceptions of the nation
(which are often left implicit in their discourse), in the grounds for and degree of its
value, and in the scope of their prescribed obligations. Moderate nationalism is less
demanding than classical nationalism and sometimes goes under the name of
“patriotism.” (A different usage, again, reserves “patriotism” for valuing civic community
and loyalty to state, in contrast to nationalism, centered on ethnic-cultural communities).
Let us now turn to liberal nationalism, the most discussed kind of moderate nationalism.
Liberal nationalists see liberal-democratic principles and pro-national attitudes as
belonging together. One of the main proponents of the view, Yael Tamir, started the
debate in her 1993 book and in her recent book talks about the nation-state as “an ideal
meeting point between the two” (2019: 6). Of course, some things have to be sacrificed:
we must acknowledge that either the meaningfulness of a community or its openness
must be sacrificed to some extent as we cannot have them both. (2019: 57). How much of
each is to give way is left open, and of course, various liberal nationalists take different
views of what precisely the right answer is.
Tamir’s version of liberal nationalism is a kind of social liberalism, in this respect similar
to the views of David Miller who talks about “solidaristic communities” in his 1999
book Principles of Social Justice and also takes stance in his 1995 and 2008 books. They
both see the feeling of national identity as a feeling that promotes solidarity, and
solidarity as means for increased social justice (Tamir 2019, in particular ch.20; compare
Walzer 1983, Kymlicka 1995a, 2001, and Gans 2003, 2008).
Liberal nationalists diverge about the value of multiculturalism. Kymlicka takes it as
basic for his picture of liberalism while Tamir dismisses it without much ado:
multicultural, multiethnic democracies have a very poor track record, she claims (2019:
62). Tamir’s diagnosis of the present day political crisis, with politicians like Trump and
Le Pen coming to the forefront, is that “liberal democrats were paralyzed by their
assumed victory” whereas “nationalists felt defeated and obsolete” (2019: 7).
Tamir lists two kinds of reasons that guarantee special political status to nations. First
kind, that no other political entity “is more able than the state to promote ideas in the
public sphere” (2019: 52), and the second kind that nation needs continuous creative
effort to make it functional and attractive.
The historical development of liberalism turned it into a universalistic, anti-
communitarian principle; this has been a fatal mistake that can be and should be corrected
by the liberal nationalist synthesis. Can we revive the unifying narratives of our
nationality without sacrificing the liberal inheritance of freedom and rights? Liberal
nationalism answers in the affirmative. From its standpoint, national particularism has
primacy: “The love of humanity is a noble ideal, but real love is always particular…”
(2019: 68).
Interestingly, Tamir combines this high regard of nation with an extreme constructivist
view of its nature: nations are mental structures that exist in the minds of their members
(2019: 58).
Is liberal nationalism implemented anywhere in the present world, or is it more of an
ideal, probably end-state theory, that proposes a picture of a desirable society? Judging by
the writings of liberal nationalists, it is the latter, although presented as a relatively easily
reachable ideal, combining two traditions that are already well implemented in political
reality.
The variations of nationalism most relevant for philosophy are those that influence the
moral standing of claims and of recommended nationalist practices. The elaborate
philosophical views put forward in favor of nationalism will be referred to as “theoretical
nationalism”, the adjective serving to distinguish such views from less sophisticated and
more practical nationalist discourse. The central theoretical nationalist evaluative claims
can be charted on the map of possible positions within political theory in the following
useful but somewhat simplified and schematic way.
Nationalist claims featuring the nation as central to political action must answer two
crucial general questions. First, is there one kind of large social group that is of special
moral importance? The nationalist answer is that there certainly is one, namely, the
nation. Moreover, when an ultimate choice is to be made, say between ties of family, or
friendship, and the nation, the latter has priority. Liberal nationalists prefer a more
moderate stance, which ascribes value to national belonging, but don’t make it central in
this way. Second, what are the grounds for an individual’s obligations to the morally
central group? Are they based on voluntary or involuntary membership in the group? The
typical contemporary nationalist thinker opts for the latter, while admitting that voluntary
endorsement of one’s national identity is a morally important achievement. On the
philosophical map, pro-nationalist normative tastes fit nicely with the communitarian
stance in general: most pro-nationalist philosophers are communitarians who choose the
nation as the preferred community (in contrast to those of their fellow communitarians
who prefer more far-ranging communities, such as those defined by global religious
traditions).[13]
Before proceeding to moral claims, let us briefly sketch the issues and viewpoints
connected to territory and territorial rights that are essential for nationalist political
programs.[14] Why is territory important for ethno-national groups, and what are the extent
and grounds of territorial rights? Its primary importance resides in sovereignty and all the
associated possibilities for internal control and external exclusion. Add to this the
Rousseauian view that political attachments are essentially bounded and that love —or, to
put it more mildly, republican civil friendship—for one’s group requires exclusion of
some “other”, and the importance becomes quite obvious. What about the grounds for the
demand for territorial rights? Nationalist and pro-nationalist views mostly rely on the
attachment that members of a nation have to national territory and to the formative value
of territory for a nation to justify territorial claims (see Miller 2000 and Meisels 2009).
This is similar in some respects to the rationale given by proponents of indigenous
peoples’ rights (Tully 2004, but see also Hendrix 2008) and in other respects to Kolers’
2009 ethno-geographical non-nationalist theory, but differs in preferring ethno-national
groups as the sole carriers of the right. These attachment views stand in stark contrast to
more pragmatic views about territorial rights as means for conflict resolution (e.g., Levy
2000). Another quite popular alternative is the family of individualistic views grounding
territorial rights in rights and interests of individuals. [15] On the extreme end of anti-
nationalist views stands the idea of Pogge) that there are no specific territorial problems
for political philosophy—the “dissolution approach”, as Kolers calls it.

2.2 Moral Claims, Classical Vs. Liberal: The Centrality


of Nation
We now pass to the normative dimension of nationalism. We shall first describe the very
heart of the nationalist program, i.e., sketch and classify the typical normative and
evaluative nationalist claims. These claims can be seen as answers to the normative
subset of our initial questions about (1) pro-national attitudes and (2) actions.
We will see that these claims recommend various courses of action: centrally, those
meant to secure and sustain a political organization for the given ethno-cultural national
community (thereby making more specific the answers to our normative
questions (1e), (1f), (2b), and (2c)). Further, they enjoin the community’s members to
promulgate recognizable ethno-cultural contents as central features of the cultural life
within such a state. Finally, we shall discuss various lines of pro-nationalist thought that
have been put forward in defense of these claims. To begin, let us return to the claims
concerning the furthering of the national state and culture. These are proposed by the
nationalist as norms of conduct. The philosophically most important variations concern
three aspects of such normative claims:

i. The normative nature and strength of the claim: does it promote merely a right
(say, to have and maintain a form of political self-government, preferably and
typically a state, or have cultural life centered upon a recognizably ethno-national
culture), or a moral obligation (to get and maintain one), or a moral, legal, and
political obligation? The strongest claim is typical of classical nationalism; its
typical norms are both moral and, once the nation-state is in place, legally
enforceable obligations for all parties concerned, including for the individual
members of the ethno-nation. A weaker but still quite demanding version speaks
only of moral obligation (“sacred duty”).
ii. The strength of the nationalist claim in relation to various external interests and
rights: to give a real example, is the use of the domestic language so important that
even international conferences should be held in it, at the cost of losing the most
interesting participants from abroad? The force of the nationalist claim is here
being weighed against the force of other claims, including those of individual or
group interests or rights. Variations in comparative strength of nationalist claims
take place on a continuum between two extremes. At one rather unpalatable
extreme, nation-focused claims take precedence over any other claims, including
over human rights. Further towards the center is the classical nationalism that
gives nation-centered claims precedence over individual interests and many needs,
but not necessarily over general human rights (see, for example, MacIntyre 1994,
Oldenquist 1997). On the opposite end, which is mild, humane, and liberal, the
central classical nationalist claims are accorded prima facie status only (see Tamir
1993, Gans 2003, and Miller 2013; and for applications to Central Europe Stefan
Auer 2004).
iii. For which groups are the nationalist claims, classical or liberal, meant to be valid?
What is their scope? One approach claims that they are valid for every ethno-
nation and thereby universal. An example would be the claim “every ethno-nation
should have its own state”. To put it more officially
Universalizing nationalism is the political program that claims that every ethno-
nation should have a state that it should rightfully own and the interests of which it
should promote.
Alternatively, a claim may be particularistic, such as the claim “Group X ought to
have a state”, where this implies nothing about any other group:
Particularistic nationalism is the political program claiming that some ethno-
nation should have its state, without extending the claim to all ethno-nations. It
claims thus either

A. by omission (unreflective particularistic nationalism), or


B. by explicitly specifying who is excluded: “Group X ought to have a state,
but group Y should not” (invidious nationalism).
The most difficult and indeed chauvinistic sub-case of particularism, i.e., (B), has
been called “invidious” since it explicitly denies the privilege of having a state to
some peoples. Serious theoretical nationalists usually defend only the universalist
variety, whereas the nationalist-in-the-street most often defends the egoistic
indeterminate one.
The nationalist picture of morality traditionally has been quite close to the dominant view
in the theory of international relations called “realism”. Put starkly, the view is that
morality ends at the boundaries of the nation-state; beyond there is nothing but anarchy.
[16]
 It nicely complements the main classical nationalist claim about the nation-state, i.e.,
that each ethno-nation or people should have a state of its own, and suggests what
happens next: nation-states enter into competition in the name of their constitutive
peoples.

3. The Moral Debate


3.1 Classical and liberal nationalisms
Recall the initial normative question centered around (1) attitudes and (2) actions. Is
national partiality justified, and to what extent? What actions are appropriate to bring
about sovereignty? In particular, are ethno-national states and institutionally protected
(ethno-) national cultures goods independent from the individual will of their members,
and how far may one go in protecting them? The philosophical debate for and against
nationalism is a debate about the moral validity of its central claims. In particular, the
ultimate moral issue is the following: is any form of nationalism morally permissible or
justified, and, if not, how bad are particular forms of it?[17] Why do nationalist claims
require a defense? In some situations they seem plausible: for instance, the plight of some
stateless national groups—the history of Jews and Armenians, the historical and
contemporary misfortunes of Kurds—lends credence to the idea that having their own
state would have solved the worst problems. Still, there are good reasons to examine
nationalist claims more carefully. The most general reason is that it should first be shown
that the political form of the nation-state has some value as such, that a national
community has a particular, or even central, moral and political value, and that claims in
its favor have normative validity. Once this is established, a further defense is needed.
Some classical nationalist claims appear to clash—at least under normal circumstances of
contemporary life—with various values that people tend to accept. Some of these values
are considered essential to liberal-democratic societies, while others are important
specifically for the flourishing of creativity and culture. The main values in the first set
are individual autonomy and benevolent impartiality (most prominently towards members
of groups culturally different from one’s own). The alleged special duties towards one’s
ethno-national culture can and often do interfere with individuals’ right to autonomy.
Liberal nationalists are aware of the difficulties of the classical approach, and soften the
classical claims, giving them only a prima facie status. They usually speak of “various
accretions that have given nationalism a bad name”, and they are eager to “separate the
idea of nationality itself from these excesses” (Miller 1992, 2000). Such thoughtful pro-
nationalist writers have participated in an ongoing philosophical dialogue between
proponents and opponents of the claim.[18] In order to help the reader find their through
this involved debate, we shall briefly summarize the considerations which are open to the
ethno-nationalist to defend their case (compare the useful overview in Lichtenberg 1997).
Further lines of thought built upon these considerations can be used to defend very
different varieties of nationalism, from radical to very moderate ones.
For brevity, each line of thought will be reduced to a brief argument; the actual debate is
more involved than one can represent in a sketch. Some prominent lines of criticism that
have been put forward in the debate will be indicated in brackets (see Miscevic 2001).
The main arguments in favor of nationalism will be divided into two sets. The first set of
arguments defends the claim that national communities have a high value, sometime seen
as coming from the interests of their individual member (e.g., by Kymlicka, Miller, and
Raz) and sometimes as non-instrumental and independent of the wishes and choices of
their individual members, and argues that they should therefore be protected by means of
state and official statist policies. The second set is less deeply “comprehensive”, and
encompasses arguments from the requirements of justice, independent from substantial
assumptions about culture and cultural values.
The first set will be presented in more detail since it has formed the core of the debate. It
depicts the community as the source of value or as the transmission device connecting its
members to some important values. For the classical nationalist, the arguments from this
set are communitarian in a particularly “deep” sense since they are grounded in basic
features of the human condition.
The general form of deep communitarian arguments is as follows. First, the
communitarian premise: there is some uncontroversial good (e.g., a person’s identity),
and some kind of community is essential for acquisition and preservation of it. Then
comes the claim that the ethno-cultural nation is the kind of community ideally suited for
this task. Then follows the statist conclusion: in order for such a community to preserve
its own identity and support the identity of its members, it has to assume (always or at
least normally) the political form of a state. The conclusion of this type of argument is
that the ethno-national community has the right to an ethno-national state and the citizens
of the state have the right and obligation to favor their own ethnic culture in relation to
any other.
Although the deeper philosophical assumptions in the arguments stem from the
communitarian tradition, weakened forms have also been proposed by more liberal
philosophers. The original communitarian lines of thought in favor of nationalism suggest
that there is some value in preserving ethno-national cultural traditions, in feelings of
belonging to a common nation, and in solidarity between a nation’s members. A liberal
nationalist might claim that these are not the central values of political life but are values
nevertheless. Moreover, the diametrically opposing views, pure individualism and
cosmopolitanism, do seem arid, abstract, and unmotivated by comparison. By
cosmopolitanism we refer to moral and political doctrines claiming that

a. one’s primary moral obligations are directed to all human beings (regardless of
geographical or cultural distance), and
b. political arrangements should faithfully reflect this universal moral obligation (in
the form of supra-statist arrangements that take precedence over nation-states).
Confronted with opposing forces of nationalism and cosmopolitanism, many philosophers
opt for a mixture of liberalism-cosmopolitanism and patriotism-nationalism. In his
writings, B. Barber glorifies “a remarkable mixture of cosmopolitanism and
parochialism” that in his view characterizes American national identity (Barber 1996:
31). Charles Taylor claims that “we have no choice but to be cosmopolitan and patriots”
(Taylor 1996: 121). Hilary Putnam proposes loyalty to what is best in the multiple
traditions in which each of us participates, apparently a middle way between a narrow-
minded patriotism and an overly abstract cosmopolitanism (Putnam 1996: 114). The
compromise has been foreshadowed by Berlin (1979) and Taylor (1989, 1993), [19] and in
the last two decades it has occupied center stage in the debate and even provoked re-
readings of historical nationalism in its light.[20] Most liberal nationalist authors accept
various weakened versions of the arguments we list below, taking them to support
moderate or ultra-moderate nationalist claims.
Here are then the main weakenings of classical ethno-nationalism that liberal, limited-
liberal, and cosmopolitan nationalists propose. First, ethno-national claims have
only prima facie strength and cannot trump individual rights. Second, legitimate ethno-
national claims do not in themselves automatically amount to the right to a state, but
rather to the right to a certain level of cultural autonomy. The main models of autonomy
are either territorial or non-territorial: the first involves territorial devolution; the second,
cultural autonomy granted to individuals regardless of their domicile within the state.
[21]
 Third, ethno-nationalism is subordinate to civic patriotism, which has little or nothing
to do with ethnic criteria. Fourth, ethno-national mythologies and similar “important
falsehoods” are to be tolerated only if benign and inoffensive, in which case they are
morally permissible despite their falsity. Finally, any legitimacy that ethno-national
claims may have is to be derived from choices the concerned individuals are free to make.

3.2 Arguments in favor of nationalism, classical vs.


liberal: the deep need for community
Consider now the particular pro-nationalist arguments from the first set. The first
argument depends on assumptions that also appear in the subsequent ones, but it further
ascribes to the community an intrinsic value. The later arguments point more towards an
instrumental value of nation, derived from the value of individual flourishing, moral
understanding, firm identity and the like.
1. The Argument From Intrinsic Value. Each ethno-national community is valuable
in and of itself since it is only within the natural encompassing framework of
various cultural traditions that important meanings and values are produced and
transmitted. The members of such communities share a special cultural proximity
to each other. By speaking the same language and sharing customs and traditions,
the members of these communities are typically closer to one another in various
ways than they are to the outsiders.
2. The Argument from Flourishing. The ethno-national community is essential for
each of its members to flourish. In particular, it is only within such a community
that an individual can acquire concepts and values crucial for understanding the
community’s cultural life in general and the individual’s own life in particular.
There has been much debate on the pro-nationalist side about whether divergence
of values is essential for separateness of national groups.
The Canadian liberal nationalists Seymour (1999), Taylor, and Kymlicka pointed out that
“divergences of value between different regions of Canada” that aspire to separate
nationhood are “minimal”. Taylor (1993: 155) concluded that it is not separateness of
value that matters.

3. The Argument from Identity. Communitarian philosophers emphasize nurture over


nature as the principal force determining our identity as people—we come to be
who we are because of the social settings and contexts in which we mature. This
claim certainly has some plausibility. The very identity of each person depends
upon his/her participation in communal life (see MacIntyre 1994, Nielsen, 1998,
and Lagerspetz 2000). Given that an individual’s morality depends upon their
having a mature and stable personal identity, the communal conditions that foster
the development of personal identity must be preserved and encouraged.
Therefore, communal life should be organized around particular national cultures.
4. The Argument from Moral Understanding. A particularly important variety of
value is moral value. Some values are universal, e.g., freedom and equality, but
these are too abstract and “thin”. The rich, “thick” moral values are discernible
only within particular traditions; as Charles Taylor puts it, “the language we have
come to accept articulates the issues of the good for us” (1989: 35). The nation
offers a natural framework for moral traditions, and thereby for moral
understanding; it is the primary school of morals.
5. The Argument from Diversity. Each national culture contributes uniquely to the
diversity of human cultures. The most famous twentieth century proponent of the
idea, Isaiah Berlin (interpreting Herder), writes:
The ‘physiognomies’ of cultures are unique: each presents a wonderful exfoliation
of human potentialities in its own time and place and environment. We are
forbidden to make judgments of comparative value, for that is measuring the
incommensurable. (1976: 206)
Assuming that the (ethno-)nation is the natural unit of culture, the preservation of cultural
diversity amounts to institutionally protecting the purity of (ethno-)national culture. The
plurality of cultural styles can be preserved and enhanced by tying them to ethno-national
“forms of life”.
David Miller has developed an interesting and sophisticated liberal pro-national stance
over the course of decades from his work in 1990 to the most recent work in 2013. He
accepts multicultural diversity within a society but stresses an overarching national
identity, taking as his prime example British national identity, which encompasses the
English, Scottish, and other ethnic identities. He demands an “inclusive identity,
accessible to members of all cultural groups” (2013: 91). miller claims such identity is
necessary for basic social solidarity, and it goes far beyond simple constitutional
patriotism. A skeptic could note the following. The problem with multicultural society is
that national identity has historically been a matter of ethno-national ties and has required
sameness in the weighted majority of cultural traits (common language, common
“history-as-remembered”, customs, religion and so on). However, multi-cultural states
typically bring together groups with very different histories, languages, religions, and
even quite contrasting appearances. Now, how is the overarching “national identity” to be
achieved starting from the very thin identity of common belonging to a state? One seems
to have a dilemma. Grounding social solidarity in national identity requires the latter to be
rather thin and seems likely to end up as full-on, unitary cultural identity. Thick
constitutional patriotism may be one interesting possible attitude that can ground such
solidarity while preserving the original cultural diversity.

3.3 Arguments in favor of nationalism: issues of justice


The arguments in the second set concern political justice and do not rely on metaphysical
claims about identity, flourishing, and cultural values. They appeal to (actual or alleged)
circumstances that would make nationalist policies reasonable (or permissible or even
mandatory), such as (a) the fact that a large part of the world is organized into nation-
states (so that each new group aspiring to create a nation-state just follows an established
pattern), or (b) the circumstances of group self-defense or of redressing past injustice that
might justify nationalist policies (to take a special case). Some of the arguments also
present nationhood as conducive to important political goods, such as equality.

1. The Argument from the Right to Collective Self-determination. A group of people


of a sufficient size has a prima facie right to govern itself and decide its future
membership, if the members of the group so wish. It is fundamentally the
democratic will of the members themselves that grounds the right to an ethno-
national state and to ethno-centric cultural institutions and practices. This
argument presents the justification of (ethno-)national claims as deriving from the
will of the members of the nation. It is therefore highly suitable for liberal
nationalism but not appealing to a deep communitarian who sees the demands of
the nation as independent from, and prior to, the choices of particular individuals.
[22]

2. The Argument from the Right to Self-defense and to Redress Past Injustices.
Oppression and injustice give the victimized group a just cause and the right to
secede. If a minority group is oppressed by the majority to the extent that almost
every minority member is worse off than most members of the majority simply in
virtue of belonging to the minority, then nationalist claims on behalf of the
minority are morally plausible and potentially compelling. The argument
establishes a typical remedial right, acceptable from a liberal standpoint (see the
discussion in Kukathas and Poole 2000, also Buchanan 1991; for past injustices
see Waldron 1992).
3. The Argument from Equality. Members of a minority group are often
disadvantaged in relation to the dominant culture because they have to rely on
those with the same language and culture to conduct the affairs of daily life.
Therefore, liberal neutrality itself requires that the majority provide certain basic
cultural goods, i.e., granting differential rights (see Kymlicka 1995b, 2001, and
2003b). Institutional protections and the right to the minority group’s own
institutional structure are remedies that restore equality and turn the resulting
nation-state into a more moderate multicultural one.
4. The Argument from Success. The nationstate has in the past succeeded in
promoting equality and democracy. Ethno-national solidarity is a powerful motive
for a more egalitarian distribution of goods (Miller 1995; Canovan 1996, 2000).
The nation-state also seems to be essential to safeguard the moral life of
communities in the future, since it is the only form of political institution capable
of protecting communities from the threats of globalization and assimilationism
(for a detailed critical discussion of this argument see Mason 1999).
Andreas Wimmer (2018) presents an interesting discussion of the historical success of
nation-state (discussed in Knott, Tolz, Green, & Wimmer 2019).
These political arguments can be combined with deep communitarian ones. However,
taken in isolation, their perspectives offer a “liberal culturalism” that is more suitable for
ethno-culturally plural societies. More remote from classical nationalism than the liberal
one of Tamir and Nielsen, it eschews any communitarian philosophical underpinning.
[23]
 The idea of moderate nation-building points to an open multi-culturalism in which
every group receives its share of remedial rights but, instead of walling itself off from
others, participates in a common, overlapping civic culture in open communication with
other sub-communities. Given the variety of pluralistic societies and intensity of trans-
national interactions, such openness seems to many to be the only guarantee of stable
social and political life (see the debate in Shapiro and Kymlicka 1997).
In general, the liberal nationalist stance is mild and civil, and there is much to be said in
favor of it. It tries to reconcile our intuitions in favor of some sort of political protection
of cultural communities with a liberal political morality. Of course, this raises issues of
compatibility between liberal universal principles and the particular attachments to one’s
ethno-cultural nation. Very liberal nationalists such as Tamir divorce ethno-cultural
nationhood from statehood. Also, the kind of love for country they suggest is tempered by
all kinds of universalist considerations, which in the last instance trump national interest
(Tamir 1993: 115; 2019: passim, see also Moore 2001 and Gans 2003). There is an
ongoing debate among philosophical nationalists about how much weakening and
compromising is still compatible with a stance’s being nationalist at all. [24] There is also a
streak of cosmopolitan interest present in the work of some liberal nationalists (Nielsen
1998–99).[25]
In the last two decades, the issues of nationalism have been increasingly integrated into
the debate about the international order (see the entries
on globalization and cosmopolitanism). The main conceptual link is the claim that nation-
states are natural, stable, and suitable units of the international order. A related debate
concerns the role of minorities in the processes of globalization (see Kaldor 2004).
Moreover, the two approaches might ultimately converge: a multiculturalist liberal
nationalism and a moderate, difference-respecting cosmopolitanism have a lot in
common.[26]

3.4 Populism and a new face of nationalism


“Populism” is an umbrella term, covering both right-wing and left-wing varieties. This
section will pay attention to right-wing populist movements, very close to their traditional
nationalist predecessors. This corresponds to the situation in the biggest part of Europe,
and in the US, where nationalist topics are being put forward by the right-wing populist. [27]
However, it has become quite clear that nationalism is only one of the political “isms”
attracting the right-wing populists. The migration crisis has brought to the forefront
populist self-identification with linguistic-cultural communities (“we, French speaking
people” for the former, “we Christians” for the later) that goes beyond nationalism.
Jan-Werner Müller (2016) and Cas Mudde (2007) note that the form common to all sorts
of populism is quite simple and describe it as “thin”. Mudde explains: “Populism is
understood as a thin-centered ideology that considers society to be ultimately separated
into two homogeneous and antagonistic groups, ‘the pure people’ versus ‘the corrupt
elite’, and which argues that politics should be an expression of the volonté
générale (general will) of the People” (2007: 23). Populism, so defined, has two
opposites: elitism and pluralism. First, there is the elite vs. people (“underdog”) contrast.
Second, it is possible to distinguish two ways of characterizing “the people”: either in
terms of social status (class, income-level, etc.) or in terms of ethnic and/or cultural
belonging (see also de Cleen 2017).
Elite

Social (class) ← People → ethnic, cultural
The second, horizontal dimension distinguishes the predominantly left-wing from the
predominantly right-wing populisms and leaves a place for a centrist populist option.
Take classical strong ethnic nationalism. The relation between right-wing populism and
such a nationalism is very tight. This has led some theoreticians (Taguieff 2015) to
present “nationalist populism” as the only kind of populism. The term captures exactly
the synthesis of populism and the strong ethnic nationalism or nativism. From populism,
it takes the general schema of anti-elitism: the leader is addressing directly the people and
is allegedly following the people’s interest. From nationalism, it takes the characterization
of the people: it is the ethnic community, in most cases the state-owing ethnic
community, or the ethno-nation. In his work, Mudde documents the claim that purely
right-wing populists claim to represent the true people who form the true nation and
whose purity is being muddied by new entrants. In the United States, one can talk about
populist and reactionary movements, like the Tea Party, that have emerged through the
recent experience of immigration, terrorist attacks, and growing economic polarization.
We have to set aside here, for reasons of space, the main populist alternative (or quasi-
alternative) to national populism. In some countries, like Germany, some populist groups-
parties (e.g., German AfD party (Alternative for Germany)), appeal to properties much
wider in their reach than ethno-national belonging, typically to religious affiliations.
Others combine this appeal with the ethno-national one. This yields what Riva
Kastoryano (2006) calls “transnational nationalism”.
Interestingly, liberal nationalism is not very attractive to the populists. On the theoretical
side one can note that Tamir (2019) sees her liberal nationalism as a good recipe against
the threat of demagogues like Trump and Boris Johnson (she avoids the use of the label
“populist”, e.g., 2019: 31).
The rise of populism is changing the political playfield one must work with. The tolerant
(liberal nationalist or anti-nationalist) views are confronting new problems in the populist
age marked by migration crisis, etc. The dangers traditionally associated with military
presence are gone; the national populists have to invent and construct a presumed danger
that comes into the country together with foreign families, including those with children.
In short, if these conjectures hold, the politicians and theoreticians are faced with a
change. The traditional issue of the contrast between patriotism/nationalism and
cosmopolitanism has changed its profile: the current drastic contrast is between the
populist aversion to the foreigners-migrants and a more generous attitude of acceptance
and Samaritan help. Finally, the populist understanding of “our people” (“we-
community”) encompasses not only nationalist options but also goes way beyond it. The
important element is the promiscuous character of the populist choices. It is probable that
the future scholarship on nationalism will mainly focus on this new and challenging
playfield, with an aim to address the new contrast and locate kinds of nationalism in
relation to it.[28]

3.5 Nation-state in global context


The migration crisis has made the nation-state in global context the central political topic
concerning nationality. Before moving on to current events, the state of art before the
crisis should be summarized. First, consider the debates on territory and nation and issues
of global justice.
Liberal nationalists try to preserve the traditional nationalist link between ethnic
“ownership” of the state and sovereignty and territorial control, but in a much more
flexible and sophisticated setting. Tamar Meisels thus argues in favor of “taking existing
national settlements into account as a central factor in demarcating territorial boundaries”
since this line “has both liberal foundations” (i.e., in the work of John Locke) and liberal-
national appeal (2009: 159) grounded in its affinity with the liberal doctrine of national
self-determination. She combines it with Chaim Gans’ (2003: Ch. 4) interpretation of
“historical right” claims as “the right to formative territories”. She thus combines
“historical arguments, understood as claims to formative territories”, with her argument
from settlement and insists on their interplay and mutual reinforcement, presenting them
as being “most closely related to, and based on, liberal nationalist assumptions and
underlying ideas” (Meisels 2009: 160). She nevertheless stresses that more than one
ethnic group can have formative ties to a given territory, and that there might be
competing claims based on settlement.[29] But, given the ethno-national conflicts of the
twentieth century, one can safely assume that culturally plural states divided into isolated
and closed sub-communities glued together merely by arrangements of modus vivendi are
inherently unstable. Stability might therefore require that the pluralist society envisioned
by liberal culturalists promote quite intense intra-state interaction between cultural groups
in order to forestall mistrust, reduce prejudice, and create a solid basis for cohabitation.
But where should one stop? The question arises since there are many geographically
open, interacting territories of various sizes. Consider first the geographical openness of
big continental planes, then add the modern ease of interaction (“No island is an island
any more”, one could say), and, finally and dramatically, the substantial ecological
interconnectedness of land and climate. Here, the tough nationalistic line is no longer
proposed seriously in ethical debates, so the furthest pro-national extreme is in fact a
relatively moderate stance, exemplified by Miller in the works listed. Here is a typical
proposal of his concerning global justice based on nation-states: it might become a matter
of national pride to have set aside a certain percentage of GDP for developmental goals—
perhaps for projects in one particular country or group of countries (2013: 182).
This brings us to the topic of migrations, and the heated debate on the present scene. [30] In
Europe immigration is probably the main topic of the present day populist uproar, and in
the United States it is one of the main topics. So, immigration plus the nationalist-populist
reactions to it are in the current decade the main testing ground for nationalist and
cosmopolitan views.
Let’s look at the pro-national side in the debate. Liberal nationalists, in particular Miller,
have put forward some thoughtful pro-nationalist proposal concerning immigration.
Miller’s proposal allows refugees to seek asylum temporarily until the situation in their
country of origin improves; it also limits economic migration. Miller argues against the
defensibility of a global standard for equality, opportunity, welfare, etc., because
measures of just equality are context-bound. People do have the right to a minimum
standard of living, but the right to migrate only activates as a last resort after all other
measures within a candidate-migrant’s country of origin have been tried. However, he
also (particularly in his book on “Strangers in our midst”, 2016), claims that national
responsibility to accept immigrant refugees is balanced by considerations of the interest
of would-be immigrants and the interests that national communities have in maintaining
control over their own composition and character.
If we agree with the liberal nationalists on the positive side, we can ask about the
dynamics of the help required for the immigrants. Distinguish at least three stages, first,
the immediate emergency (starvation, freezing, urgent medical problems) and catering to
it, second, settlement and learning (on the host and the immigrant newcomer side), and
third, the stage of (some kind of) citizenship, of relatively stable life in the host country.
In the first phase, the immediate help comes first, both normatively and causally: just
accept the would-be refugees (indeed, the would-be refugees should be helped in leaving
their countries and travelling to the host country). In longer term, staying should involve
opportunity for work and training.
But there is more. The Samaritan obligation can and should function as a preparation for
wider global activity.[31] So, we have two theoretical steps, first, accepting Samaritanism
and second, agreeing with deeper trans-national measure of blocking distant causes, like
poverty and wars in the Third world. Let us call this “Samaritan-to-deeper-measures
model”. The model is geared to the dramatically changed playground in which the
nationalism issues are played out in the context of populism and refugee crisis, raising
issues that were not around two decades ago.

4. Conclusion
In presenting the claims that the pro-nationalists defend, we have proceeded from the
more radical towards more liberal nationalist alternatives. In examining the arguments for
these claims, we have presented metaphysically demanding communitarian arguments
resting upon deep communitarian assumptions about culture, such as the premise that the
ethno-cultural nation is the most important community for all individuals. This is an
interesting and respectable claim, but its plausibility has not been established. The moral
debate about nationalism has resulted in various weakenings of culture-based arguments,
typically proposed by liberal nationalists, which render the arguments less ambitious but
much more plausible. Having abandoned the old nationalist ideal of a state owned by a
single dominant ethno-cultural group, liberal nationalists have become receptive to the
idea that identification with a plurality of cultures and communities is important for a
person’s social identity. They have equally become sensitive to trans-national issues and
more willing to embrace a partly cosmopolitan perspective. Liberal nationalism has also
brought to the fore more modest, less philosophically or metaphysically charged
arguments grounded in concerns about justice. These stress the practical importance of
ethno-cultural membership, ethno-cultural groups’ rights to have injustices redressed,
democratic rights of political association, and the role that ethno-cultural ties and
associations can play in promoting just social arrangements.
The events in the current decade, the refugee crisis and the rise of right-wing populism,
have dramatically changed the relevant practical and theoretical playground. The
traditional nationalism is still relevant, but populist nationalism attracts much more
attention: new theories are being produced and debated, coming to occupy the center
stage. On the other hand, migration crisis has replaced the typical cosmopolitan issue of
solidarity-with-distant-strangers with burning issues of helping refugees present at our
doors. Of course, the causes of the crisis are still the same ones that cosmopolitans have
been worrying about much earlier: wars and dramatically unequal global distribution of
goods, and of threats, like illnesses and climate disasters. The task of the theory is now to
connect these deeper issues with the new problems occupying the center-stage of the new
playground; it is a challenge now formulated in somewhat different vocabulary and
within different political conceptual frameworks than before.

Bibliography
Introduction
This is a short list of books on nationalism that are readable and useful introductions to
the literature. First, two contemporary classics of social science with opposing views are:

 Gellner, Ernest, 1983, Nations and Nationalism, Oxford: Blackwell.


 Smith, Anthony D., 1991, National Identity, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Three presentations of liberal nationalism, two of them by the same author, Yael Tamir,
offer the best introduction to the approach:

 Miller, David, 1995, On Nationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.


doi:10.1093/0198293569.001.0001
 Tamir, Yael, 1993, Liberal Nationalism, Press, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
 –––, 2019, Why Nationalism, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Two short and readable introductions are:

 Özkirimli, Umut, 2010, Theories of Nationalism: A Critical Introduction, second


edition, London: Palgrave Macmillan. First edition is 2000; third edition is 2017.
 Spencer, Philip and Howard Wollman, 2002, Nationalism, A Critical Introduction,
London: Sage.
The two best anthologies of high-quality philosophical papers on the morality of
nationalism are:

 McKim, Robert and Jeff McMahan (eds), 1997, The Morality of Nationalism,


Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Couture, Jocelyne, Kai Nielsen, and Michel Seymour (eds.), 1998, Rethinking
Nationalism, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplement Volume 22, Calgary,
AB: University of Calgary Press.
The debate continues in:

 Miscevic, Nenad (ed), 2000, Nationalism and Ethnic Conflict: Philosophical


Perspectives, La Salle and Chicago: Open Court.
 Dieckoff, Alain (ed.), 2004, The Politics of Belonging: Nationalism, Liberalism,
and Pluralism, Lanham: Lexington.
 Primoratz, Igor and Aleksandar Pavković (eds), 2007, Patriotism, Philosophical
and Political Perspectives, London: Ashgate.
 Breen, Keith and Shane O’Neill (eds.), 2010, After the Nation? Critical
Reflections on Nationalism and Postnationalism, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
doi:10.1057/9780230293175
A good brief sociological introduction to nationalism in general is:

 Grosby, Steven, 2005, Nationalism: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford: Oxford


University Press.
and to the gender-inspired criticism of nationalism is:

 Yuval-Davis, Nira, 1997, Gender & Nation, London: Sage Publications.


and also:
 Heuer, Jennifer, 2008, “Gender and Nationalism”, in Herb and Kaplan 2008: vol.
1, 43–58.
 Hogan, Jackie, 2009, Gender, Race and National Identity: Nations of Flesh and
Blood, London: Routledge.
The best general introduction to the communitarian-individualist debate is still:

 Avineri, Shlomo and Avner de-Shalit (eds.), 1992, Communitarianism and


Individualism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
For a non-nationalist defense of culturalist claims see:

 Kymlicka, Will (ed.), 1995a, The Rights of Minority Cultures, Oxford: Oxford


University Press.
A very readable philosophical defense of very moderate liberal nationalism is:

 Gans, Chaim, 2003, The Limits of Nationalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University


Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511490231
And for application to Central Europe see:

 Auer, Stefan, 2004, Liberal Nationalism in Central Europe, London: Routledge.


A polemical, witty and thoughtful critique is offered in:

 Barry, Brian, 2001, Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of


Multiculturalism, Cambridge, MA: Polity Press.
And a more recent one in

 Kelly, Paul, 2015, “Liberalism and Nationalism”, in The Cambridge Companion


to Liberalism, Steven Wall (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 329–
352. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139942478.018
Interesting critical analyses of group solidarity in general and nationalism in particular,
written in the traditions of rational choice theory and motivation analysis, are:

 Hardin, Russell, 1985, One for All, The Logic of Group Conflict, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
 Yack, Bernard, 2012, Nationalism and the Moral Psychology of Community,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
There is a wide offering of interesting sociological and political science work on
nationalism, which is beginning to be summarized in:

 Motyl, Alexander (ed.), 2001, Encyclopedia of Nationalism, Volumes I and II,


New York: Academic Press.
A fine encyclopedic overview is:
 Herb, Guntram H. and David H. Kaplan, 2008, Nations and Nationalism: a
Global Historical Overview, four volumes, Santa Barbara, CA: ABC Clio.
A detailed sociological study of life under nationalist rule is:

 Billig, Michael, 1995, Banal Nationalism, London: Sage Publications.


The most readable short anthology of brief papers for and against cosmopolitanism (and
nationalism) by leading authors in the field is:

 Cohen, Joshua (ed.), 1996, For Love of Country: Debating the Limits of


Patriotism, Martha Nussbaum and respondents, Boston, MA: Beacon Press

References
 Anderson, Benedict, 1983 [2006], Imagined Communities, London: Verso; revised
edition, 2006.
 Aron, Raymond, 1962, Paix et guerre entre les nations, Paris: Calmann-Levy.
Translated as Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, Richard Howard and
Annette Baker Fox (trans), Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1965.
 Auer, Stefan, 2004, Liberal Nationalism in Central Europe, London: Routledge.
 Avineri, Shlomo and Avner de-Shalit (eds.), 1992, Communitarianism and
Individualism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Balibar, Etienne and Immanuel Wallerstein, 1988 [1991], Race, nation, classe: les
identités ambiguës, Paris: Editiones La Découverte; translated as Race, Nation, Class:
Ambiguous Identities, Chris Turner (trans.), London-New York: Verso.
 Barber, Benjamin R., 1996, “Constitutional Faith”, in J. Cohen (ed.) 1996: 30–37.
 –––, 1996, Jihad Vs. McWorld: How Globalism and Tribalism are Reshaping the
World, New York: Ballantine Books.
 Barry, Brian, 1999, “Statism and Nationalism: a Cosmopolitan Critique”, in
Shapiro and Brilmayer 1999: 12–66.
 –––, 2001, Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of Multiculturalism,
Cambridge, MA: Polity Press.
 Bauböck, Reiner, 2004, “Territorial or Cultural Autonomy for National
Minorities?”, in Dieckoff 2004: 221–258.
 Bechhofer, Frank and David McCrone (eds.), 2009, National Identity, Nationalism
and Constitutional Change, London: Palgrave Macmillan. doi:10.1057/9780230234147
 Bell, Duncan (ed.), 2008, Political Thought and International Relations:
Variations on a Realist Theme, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Berlin, Isaiah, 1976, Vico and Herder: Two Studies in the History of Ideas,
London: The Hogarth Press.
 –––, 1979, “Nationalism: Past Neglect and Present Power”, in Against the
Current: Essays in the History of Ideas, London: Hogarth Press, 333–355.
 Betts, Alexander and Paul Collier, 2017, Refuge: Transforming a Broken Refugee
System, London: Penguin.
 Billig, Michael, 1995, Banal Nationalism, London: Sage Publications.
 –––, 2017, “Banal Nationalism and the Imagining of Politics”, in Everyday
Nationhood: Theorising Culture, Identity and Belonging after Banal Nationalism,
Michael Skey and Marco Antonsich (eds.), London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 307–321.
doi:10.1057/978-1-137-57098-7_15
 Blake, Michael, 2013, Justice and Foreign Policy, Oxford: Oxford University
Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199552009.001.0001
 Breuilly, John, 2001, “The State”, in Motyl (ed.) 2001: Volume 1.
 –––, 2011, “On the Principle of Nationality”, in The Cambridge History of
Nineteenth-Century Political Thought, Gareth Stedman Jones and Gregory Claeys (eds.),
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 77–109.
doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521430562.005
 Breuilly, John, John Hutchinson, and Eric Kaufmann (eds), 2019, special issue on
populism and nationalism in Nations and Nationalism, 25(1): 1–400.
 Brubaker, Rogers, 2004, “In the Name of the Nation: Reflections on Nationalism
and Patriotism1”, Citizenship Studies, 8(2): 115–127.
doi:10.1080/1362102042000214705
 –––, 2013, “Language, Religion and the Politics of Difference”, Nations and
Nationalism, 19(1): 1–20. doi:10.1111/j.1469-8129.2012.00562.x
 –––, 2015, Grounds for Difference, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
 Buchanan, Allen, 1991, Secession: The Morality of Political Divorce from Fort
Sumter to Lithuania and Quebec, Boulder: Westview Press.
 –––, 2004, Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for
International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198295359.001.0001
 Buchanan, Allen and Margaret Moore (eds.), 2003, States, Nations and Borders:
The Ethics of Making Boundaries, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511613937
 Butt, Daniel, Sarah Jane Fine, & Zofia Stemplowska (eds), 2018, Political
Philosophy, Here and Now: Essays in Honour of David Miller, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
 Calhoun, Craig, 2007, Nations Matter. Culture, History, and the Cosmopolitan
Dream, London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203960899
 Canovan, Margaret, 1996, Nationhood and Political Theory, Cheltenham: Edward
Elgar.
 –––, 2000, “Patriotism Is Not Enough”, British Journal of Political Science, 30(3):
413–432. doi:10.1017/S000712340000017X
 –––, 2001, “Sleeping Dogs, Prowling Cats and Soaring Doves: Three Paradoxes in
the Political Theory of Nationhood”, Political Studies, 49(2): 203–215.
doi:10.1111/1467-9248.00309
 Carens, Joseph H., 2013, The Ethics of Immigration, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
 Casertano, Stefano, 2013, Our Land, Our Oil! Natural Resources, Local
Nationalism, and Violent Secession, Wiesbaden: Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden.
doi:10.1007/978-3-531-19443-1
 Chatterjee, Deen K. and B. Smith (eds.), 2003, Moral Distance, special issue
of The Monist, 86(3): 327–515.
 Christiano, Thomas, 2008, “Immigration, Community and Cosmopolitanism”,
in San Diego Law Review, 933(Nov–Dec): 938–962.
 –––, 2012, “The Legitimacy of International Institutions”, in The Routledge
Companion to Philosophy of Law, Andrei Marmor (ed.), London: Routledge, pp. 380–
394.
 Christiano, Thomas and John Christman (eds.), 2009, Contemporary Debates in
Political Philosophy, Oxford: Wiley Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9781444310399
 Cohen, Joshua (ed.), 1996, For Love of Country? (Martha C. Nussbaum with
respondents), Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
 Colm Hogan, Patrick, 2009, Understanding Nationalism: On Narrative, Cognitive
Science and Identity, Ohio: Ohio State University Press.
 Connor, Walker, 1994, Ethnonationalism: The Quest for Understanding,
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
 Conversi, Daniele, 2002, Ethnonationalism in the Contemporary World: Walker
Connor and the Study of Nationalism, London: Routledge.
 –––, 2018, “Introduction: Why a State Is Not a Nation – and Whether Economics
Really Matters. Walker Connor 50 Years On”, Nations and Nationalism, 24(3): 497–505.
doi:10.1111/nana.12441
 Couture, Jocelyne, Kai Nielsen, and Michel Seymour (eds.), 1998, Rethinking
Nationalism, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplement Volume 22, Calgary, AB:
University of Calgary Press.
 Crowley, Brian Lee, 1987, The Self, the Individual and the Community, Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
 Dagger, Richard, 2009, “Individualism and the Claims of Community”, in
Christiano and Christman 2009: 303–332. doi:10.1002/9781444310399.ch17
 de Cleen, Benjamin, 2017, “Populism and Nationalism”, in Cristóbal Rovira
Kaltwasser, Paul Taggart, Paulina Ochoa Espejo, and Pierre Ostiguy (eds.), The Oxford
Handbook of Populism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 de Lange, Deborah E., 2010, Power and Influence: The Embeddedness of Nations,
New York: Palgrave Macmillan US. doi:10.1057/9780230115545
 De Schutter, Helder and Ronald Tinnevelt (eds.), 2011, Nationalism and Global
Justice: David Miller and His Critics, London: Routledge.
 Delanty, Gerard, John Hutchinson, Eric Kaufmann, Umut Özkirimli, and Andreas
Wimmer, 2008, “Debate on John Hutchinson’s Nations as Zones of Conflict”, Nations
and Nationalism, 14(1): 1–28. doi:10.1111/j.1469-8129.2008.00306.x
 Delanty, Gerard and Krishan Kumar (eds.), 2006, The SAGE Handbook of Nations
and Nationalism, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
 Derks, Tom and Nico Roymans (eds.), 2009, Ethnic Constructs in Antiquity: The
Role of Power and Tradition, Amsterdam: University of Amsterdam Press.
 Dieckoff, Alain (ed.), 2004, The Politics of Belonging: Nationalism, Liberalism,
and Pluralism, Lanham: Lexington.
 –––, 2017, Nationalism and the Multination State, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
 Edensor, T., 2002, National Identity, Popular Culture and Everyday Life, Oxford:
Berg.
 Eisenberg, Avigail and Jeff Spinner-Halev (eds.), 2005, Minorities within
Minorities: Equality, Rights and Diversity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511490224
 Farris, Sara R., 2017, In the Name of Women’s Rights: The Rise of
Femonationalism, Durham: Duke University Press.
 Feltham, Brian and John Cottingham (eds), 2010, Partiality and Impartiality:
Morality, Special Relationships, and the Wider World, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199579952.001.0001
 Fine, Sarah and Lea Ypi (eds.), 2016, Migration in Political Theory: The Ethics of
Movement and Membership, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199676606.001.0001
 Fox, Jon E., 2017, “The Edges of the Nation: A Research Agenda for Uncovering
the Taken-for-Granted Foundations of Everyday Nationhood”, Nations and Nationalism,
23(1): 26–47. doi:10.1111/nana.12269
 Frost, Catharine, 2006, Morality and Nationalism, London: Routledge.
 Gans, Chaim, 2003, The Limits of Nationalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511490231
 –––, ,2017, “Citizenship and Nationhood”, in Rainer Baubock et al. (eds.), The
Oxford Handbook of Citizenship, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Gat, Azar and Alexander Yakobson, 2013, Nations: The Long History and Deep
Roots of Political Ethnicity and Nationalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9781139047654
 Giddens, Anthony, 1985, The Nation-state and Violence (Volume 2), Berkeley:
University of California Press.
 Glenn, John, 1997, “Nations and Nationalism: Marxist Approaches to the
Subject”, Nationalism and Ethnic Politics, 3(2): 79–100.
doi:10.1080/13537119708428503
 Gellner, Ernest, 1983, Nations and Nationalism, Oxford: Blackwell.
 Goetze, David, 2001, “Evolutionary Theory”, in Motyl (ed.) 2001: Volume 1.
 Goodin, Robert E., 2006, “Liberal Multiculturalism: Protective and
Polyglot”, Political Theory, 34(3): 289–303. doi:10.1177/0090591705284131
 Greenfeld, Liah, 2001, The Spirit of Capitalism: Nationalism and Economic
Growth, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
 –––, 2005, “Nationalism and the Mind”, Nations and Nationalism, 11(3): 325–
341. doi:10.1111/j.1354-5078.2005.00207.x
 –––, 2006, Nationalism and the Mind: Essays Modern Culture. London:
Oneworld.
 Grosby, Steven, 2005, Nationalism: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
 Habermas, Jürgen, 1992 [1996], Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur
Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats, Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp. Translated as Between Facts and Norms: Contribution to a Discourse Theory
of Law and Democracy, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1996.
 –––, 1996 [1998], Die Einbeziehung des Anderen: Studien zur politischen Theorie,
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Translated as The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in
Political Theory, Ciaran Cronin and Pablo De Greiff (eds), Cambridge, MA: The MIT
Press, 1998.
 Haidt, Jonathan, 2016, “When and Why Nationalism Beats Globalism”, The
American Interest, 12(1): 10 July 2016. URL = <available online>.
 Hale, Henry E., 2008, The Foundations of Ethnic Politics: Separatism of States
and Nations in Eurasia and the World, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511790669
 Hardin, Russell, 1985, One for All, The Logic of Group Conflict, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
 Harris, Erika, 2016, “Why Has Nationalism Not Run Its Course?”, Nations and
Nationalism, 22(2): 243–247. doi:10.1111/nana.12185
 Hastings, Adrian, 1997, The Construction of Nationhood: Ethnicity, Religion and
Nationalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511612107
 Hazony, Yoram, 2018, The Virtue of Nationalism, New York: Basic Books.
 Hearn, Jonathan, 2018, “Power, Culture, Identity, and the Work of Anthony
Smith”, Nations and Nationalism, 24(2): 286–291. doi:10.1111/nana.12407
 Hearn, Jonathan, Chandran Kukathas, David Miller, and Bernard Yack, 2014,
“Debate on Bernard Yack’s Book Nationalism and the Moral Psychology of
Community”, Nations and Nationalism, 20(3): 395–414. doi:10.1111/nana.12074
 Hechter, Michael, 2001, Containing Nationalism, Oxford: Oxford University
Press. doi:10.1093/019924751X.001.0001
 Helbling, Marc, Tim Reeskens, and Matthew Wright, 2016, “The Mobilisation of
Identities: A Study on the Relationship between Elite Rhetoric and Public Opinion on
National Identity in Developed Democracies”, Nations and Nationalism, 22(4): 744–767.
doi:10.1111/nana.12235
 Held, David, 2003, “Cosmopolitanism: Globalisation Tamed?”, Review of
International Studies, 29(4): 465–480. doi:10.1017/S0260210503004650
 Hendrix, Burke A., 2008, Ownership, Authority, and Self-Determination: Moral
Principles and Indigenous Rights Claims, University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State
University Press.
 Hobsbawm, E. J., 1990, Nations and Nationalism since 1780: Programme, Myth,
Reality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Second edition 2012.
doi:10.1017/CBO9781107295582
 Hutchinson, John, 2005, Nations as Zones of Conflict, London: Sage; see also the
debate on this book in Delanty et al. 2008.
 –––, 2017, Nationalism and War, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198798453.001.0001
 –––, 2018, “Bringing the Study of Warfare into Theories of Nationalism”, Nations
and Nationalism, 24(1): 6–21. doi:10.1111/nana.12364
 Ichijo, Atsuko and Ronald Ranta, 2016, Food, National Identity and Nationalism:
From Everyday to Global Politics, London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.
doi:10.1057/9781137483133
 Ichijo, Atsuko, Jon E. Fox, Arthur Aughey, David McCrone, and Frank
Bechhofer, 2017, “Debate on Understanding National Identity by David McCrone and
Frank Bechhofer”, Nations and Nationalism, 23(3): 441–462. doi:10.1111/nana.12314
 Ingram, James D., 2017, “Populism and Cosmopolitanism”, in Oxford Handbook
of Populism, Cristóbal Rovira Kaltwasser, Paul Taggart, Paulina Ochoa Espejo,and Pierre
Ostiguy (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 644–660.
 Iyall Smith, Keri E. and Patricia Leavy (eds.), 2008, Hybrid Identities: Theoretical
and Empirical Examinations, Leiden: Brill.
 Jaramillo Torres, Angel and Marc Benjamin Sable (eds.), 2018, Trump and
Political Philosophy: Leadership, Statesmanship, and Tyranny, Cham: Springer
International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-74445-2
 Joppke, Christian and Steven Lukes (eds.), 1999, Multicultural Questions, Oxford:
Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019829610X.001.0001
 Kaldor, Mary, 2004, “Nationalism and Globalisation”, Nations and Nationalism,
10(1–2): 161–177. doi:10.1111/j.1354-5078.2004.00161.x
 Kastoryano, Riva, 2006, “Vers un Nationalisme Transnational. Redéfinir la
Nation, le Nationalisme et le Territoire”, Revue Française de Science Politique, 56: 533–
553.
 Kaufmann, Eric, 2019, “Ethno‐traditional Nationalism and the Challenge of
Immigration”, Nations and Nationalism, 25(2): 435–448. doi:10.1111/nana.12516
 Kedourie, Elie, 1960, Nationalism, London: Hutchison.
 Kim, Sung Ho, 2002, “Max Weber’s Liberal Nationalism”, History of Political
Thought, 23(3): 432–457.
 Kleinig, John, 2014, On Loyalty and Loyalties: The Contours of a Problematic
Virtue, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Knott, Eleanor, Vera Tolz, Elliott Green, and Andreas Wimmer, 2019, “Debate on
Andreas Wimmer’s Nation Building: Why Some Countries Come Together While Other
Fall Apart” Nation and Nationalism, 25(1): 82–103.
 Kohen, Marcelo G. (ed.), 2006, Secession: International Law Perspectives,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511494215
 Kohn, Hans, 1965, Nationalism: Its Meaning and History, revised edition, New
York: Van Nostrand Reinhold Company.
 Kolers, Avery, 2009, Land, Conflict, and Justice: A Political Theory of Territory,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511575709
 Kostagiannis, Konstantinos, 2018, Realist Thought and the Nation-State: Power
Politics in the Age of Nationalism, (The Palgrave Macmillan History of International
Thought), Cham: Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-59629-7
 Kukathas, Chandran, 2003, The Liberal Archipelago: A Theory of Diversity and
Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019925754X.001.0001
 Kukathas, Chandran and R. Poole, Ross, (eds.), 2000, Australasian Journal of
Philosophy (Special Issue on Indigenous Rights), Volume 78, Issue 3.
 Kuran Burcoglu, Nedret (ed.), 1997, Multiculturalism: Identity and Otherness,
Istanbul: Bogazici University Press.
 Kymlicka, Will (ed.), 1995a, The Rights of Minority Cultures, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
 –––, 1995b, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights,
Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198290918.001.0001
 –––, 2001, Politics in the Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism, and
Citizenship, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199240981.001.0001
 –––, 2003a, “Conclusion: The Futures of Nationalism”, in Nationalism and Its
Futures, Umut Özkırımlı (ed.), London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 145–151.
doi:10.1057/9780230524187_8
 –––, 2003b, “Liberal Theories of Multiculturalism”, in Rights, Culture and the
Law: Themes from the Legal and Political Philosophy of Joseph Raz, Lukas H. Meyer,
Stanley L. Paulson, and Thomas W. Pogge (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 229–
252.
 –––, 2004, “Justice and Security in the Accommodation of Minority Nationalism”,
in Dieckoff 2004: 127–154.
 –––, 2007a, “Community and Multiculturalism”, in A Companion to
Contemporary Political Philosophy (Volume 2), second edition, Robert E. Goodin, Philip
Pettit, and Thomas Pogge (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell, 463–477.
 –––, 2007b, Multicultural Odysseys: Navigating the New International Politics of
Diversity, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 –––, 2016 “Defending Diversity in an Era of Populism: Multiculturalism and
Interculturalism Compared” in Multiculturalism and Interculturalism: Debating the
Dividing Lines, Nasar Meer, Tariq Modood and Ricard Zapata-Barrero (eds.), Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 158–177.
 Kymlicka, Will and Alan Patten (eds.), 2004, Language Rights and Political
Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Lægaard, Sune, 2007, “Liberal Nationalism and the Nationalisation of Liberal
Values”, Nations and Nationalism, 13(1): 37–55. doi:10.1111/j.1469-8129.2007.00269.x
 Lagerspetz, Olli, 2000, “On National Belonging” in Miscevic 2000: 57–74.
 Laitin, David, 2001, “Political Science and Nationalism”, in Motyl (ed.) 2001:
Volume 1.
 –––, 2007, Nations, States, and Violence, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Laitin, David D. and Rob Reich, 2004, “A Liberal Democratic Approach to
Language Justice”, in Kymlicka and Patten 2004: 80–104.
 Laitin, David D., James T. Watkins IV, and Elise V. Watkins, 1998, Identity in
Formation: The Russian-Speaking Populations in the Near Abroad, Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
 Lecours, André and Luis Moreno (eds.), 2010, Nationalism and Democracy:
Dichotomies, Complementarities, Oppositions, London: Routledge.
 Leoussi, Athena S. and Steven Grossby (eds.), 2007, Nationalism and
Ethnosymbolism: History, Culture and Ethnicity in the Formation of Nations, Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press.
 Levy, Jacob T., 2000, Multiculturalism of Fear, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/0198297122.001.0001
 –––, 2004, “National Minorities without Nationalism”, in Dieckoff 2004: 155–
174.
 Lichtenberg, Judith, 1997, “Nationalism, For and (Mainly) Against”, in McKim &
McMahan 1997: 158–175.
 MacCormick, Neil, 1982, Legal Right and Social Democracy: Essays in Legal
and Political Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
 MacIntyre, Alasdair, 1984“Is Patriotism a Virtue?”, The Lindley Lecture,
Lawrence: The University of Kansas, available online.
 Malešević, Siniša, 2011, “The Chimera of National Identity”, Nations and
Nationalism, 17(2): 272–290. doi:10.1111/j.1469-8129.2010.00479.x
 –––, 2013, Nation-States and Nationalisms: Organization, Ideology and
Solidarity, Cambridge: Polity.
 –––, 2018, “The Rise and Rise of Grounded Nationalisms”, Ethnopolitics, 17(5):
553–557. doi:10.1080/17449057.2018.1532636
 Malešević, Siniša and Mark Haugaard (eds.), 2007, Ernest Gellner and
Contemporary Social Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511488795
 Malešević, Siniša, 2017, The Rise of Organized Brutality, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
 Margalit, Avishai, 1997, “The Moral Psychology of Nationalism”, in McKim and
McMahan 1997: 74–88.
 Margalit, Avishai and Joseph Raz, 1990, “National Self-Determination”, Journal
of Philosophy, 87(9): 439–461. doi:10.2307/2026968
 Markell, Patchen, 2000, “Making Affect Safe for Democracy?: On ‘Constitutional
Patriotism’”, Political Theory, 28(1): 38–63. doi:10.1177/0090591700028001003
 Mason, Andrew, 1999, “Political Community, Liberal‐Nationalism, and the Ethics
of Assimilation”, Ethics, 109(2): 261–286. doi:10.1086/233896
 McCabe, David, 1997, “Patriotic Gore, Again”, The Southern Journal of
Philosophy, 35(2): 203–223. doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.1997.tb00834.x
 McKim, Robert and Jeff McMahan (eds), 1997, The Morality of Nationalism,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Meadwell, Hudson, 2012, “Nationalism Chez Gellner”, Nations and Nationalism,
18(4): 563–582. doi:10.1111/j.1469-8129.2012.00544.x
 –––, 2014, “Gellner Redux?”, Nations and Nationalism, 20(1): 18–36.
doi:10.1111/nana.12029
 Meinecke, Friedrich, 1924 [1965], Die Idee der Staatsräson in der neueren
Geschichte, Munich and Berlin: R. Oldenbourg. Translated as Machiavellism, Douglas
Scott (trans.), New York: Praeger, 1965.
 Meisels, Tamar, 2009, Territorial Rights, second edition, (Law and Philosophy
Library 72), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-9262-6
 Miller, David, 1990, “The Resurgence of Political Theory”, Political Studies,
38(3): 421–437.
 –––, 1992, “Community and Citizenship”, in Avineri and de Shalit 1992: 85–100.
 –––, 1995, On Nationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/0198293569.001.0001
 –––, 1999, Principles of Social Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
 –––, 2000, Citizenship and National Identity, Oxford: Blackwell.
 –––, 2005a, “Crooked Timber or Bent Twig? Isaiah Berlin’s
Nationalism”, Political Studies, 53(1): 100–123. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2005.00519.x
 –––, 2005b, “Immigration: The Case for Limits”, in Contemporary Debates in
Applied Ethics, Andrew I. Cohen and Christopher Heath Wellman (eds.), Oxford;
Blackwell, 193–206.
 –––, 2007, National Responsibility and Global Justice, Oxford: Oxford University
Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199235056.001.0001
 –––, 2008, “Immigrants, Nations, and Citizenship”, Philosophy, Politics &
Society (Special Issue), 4 (December): 371–390.
 –––, 2013, Justice for Earthlings: Essays in Political Philosophy, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139236898
 –––, 2016, Strangers in Our Midst: The Political Philosophy of Immigration,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
 Miller, David Lee and Sohail H. Hashmi (eds.), 2001, Boundaries and Justice:
Diverse Ethical Perspectives, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
 Miscevic, Nenad (ed.), 2000, Nationalism and Ethnic Conflict. Philosophical
Perspectives, La Salle and Chicago: Open Court.
 –––, 2001, Nationalism and Beyond, Budapest, New York: Central European
University Press.
 –––, 2019, “Populism and nationalism”, in New Politics of Decisionism, Violeta
Besirevic (ed.), The Hague: Eleven International Publishing.
 Moore, Margaret (ed.), 1998, National Self-Determination and Secession, Oxford:
Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198293844.001.0001
 –––, 2001, “Normative Justifications for Liberal Nationalism: Justice, Democracy
and National Identity”, Nations and Nationalism, 7(1): 1–20. doi:10.1111/1469-
8219.00001
 –––, 2009, “Liberalism, Communitarianism and the Politics of Identity”, in
Christiano and Christman 2009: 322–342. doi:10.1002/9781444310399.ch18
 Morgenthau, Hans, 1946, Scientific Man versus Power Politics, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
 Motyl, Alexander (ed.), 2001, Encyclopedia of Nationalism: Volume 1:
Fundamental Themes, New York: Academic Press.
 Mudde, Cas, 2007, Populist Radical Right Parties in Europe, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511492037
 Müller, Jan-Werner, 2016, What is Populism, Philadelphia, PA: University of
Pennsylvania Press.
 Nation and Nationalism, 2019, thematic issue on migration, 25(2): 401–751.
 Nielsen, Kai, 1998, “Liberal Nationalism, Liberal Democracies and
Secession”, University of Toronto Law Journal, 48(2): 253–295. doi:10.2307/825982
 –––, 1998–99, “Cosmopolitanism, Universalism and Particularism in the age of
Nationalism and Multiculturalism”, Philosophical Exchange, 29(1): art. 2 (3–34).
[Nielsen 1998–99 available online]
 O’Neill, Onora, 2000, Bounds of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511605734
 Okin, Susan Moller, 1999, “Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?” and
“Response”, in Boston Review, 1997; reprinted with some revisions in Is
Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Joshua Cohen, Matthew Howard, and M. Nussbaum
(eds.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
 –––, 2002, “‘Mistresses of Their Own Destiny’: Group Rights, Gender, and
Realistic Rights of Exit”, Ethics, 112(2): 205–230. doi:10.1086/324645
 –––, 2005, “Multiculturalism and Feminism: No Simple Question, No Simple
Answers”, in Eisenberg and Spinner-Halev 2005: 67–89.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511490224.004.
 Oldenquist, Andrew, 2002, “Ethnicity and Sovereignty”, Studies in East European
Thought, 54(4): 271–284.
 Orgad, Liav, 2015, The Cultural Defense of Nations: A Liberal Theory of Majority
Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199668687.001.0001
 Orwell, George, 1945 [2000], “Notes on Nationalism”, first published: Polemic.
May 1945, London; reprinted in his Essays, Bernard Crick (ed.), London: Penguin, 2000.
 Özkirimli, Umut, 2003, “The Nation as an Artichoke? A Critique of
Ethnosymbolist Interpretations of Nationalism”, Nations and Nationalism, 9(3): 339–355.
doi:10.1111/1469-8219.00100
 –––, 2010, Theories of Nationalism: A Critical Introduction, second revised
edition, London: Palgrave Macmillan. First edition is 2000; third edition is 2017.
 Patten, Alan, 2003, “Liberal Neutrality and Language Policy”, Philosophy &
Public Affairs, 31(4): 356–386. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2003.00356.x
 Pavković, Aleksandar and Peter Radan (eds.), 2007, Creating New States: Theory
and Practice of Secession, London: Ashgate.
 Pogge, Thomas W., 1997, “Group Rights and Ethnicity”, in Shapiro and Kymlicka
1997: 187–221.
 –––, 2001, “Rawls on International Justice”, The Philosophical Quarterly,
51(203): 246–253. doi:10.1111/j.0031-8094.2001.00228.x
 –––, 2002, World Poverty and Human Rights, Cambridge: Polity Press.
 Primoratz, Igor, 2017, “Patriotism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/patriotism/>.
 Primoratz, Igor and Aleksandar Pavković (eds), 2007, Patriotism, Philosophical
and Political Perspectives, London: Ashgate.
 Putnam, Hilary, 1996, “Must We Choose Between Patriotism and Universal
Reason?”, in Cohen 1996: 91–97.
 Rawls, John, 1999, The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
 Renan, Ernest, 1882, “Qu’est-ce qu’une nation?”, lecture delivered at the
Sorbonne, 11 March 1882. Translated by Martin Thom as “What is a nation?”, in Nation
and Narration, Homi K. Bhabha (ed.), London: Routledge, 1990, 8–22; reprinted in part
in Nationalism, John Hutchinson and Anthony D. Smith (eds.), Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1994, 17–18.
 Risse, Mathias, 2012a, “Global Justice” in The Oxford Handbook of Political
Philosophy, David Estlund (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 457–489
 –––, 2012b, On Global Justice, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
 Roshwald, Aviel, 2006. The Endurance of Nationalism: Ancient Roots and
Modern Dilemmas, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
 Sardoč, Mitja (ed.), 2017–, Handbook of Patriotism, Springer International
Publishing AG (some chapters available on the web from 2017 on). doi:10.1007/978-3-
319-30534-9
 Satz, Debra and Rob Reich (eds.), 2009, Toward a Humanist Justice: The
Political Philosophy of Susan Moller Okin, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/Acprof:Oso/9780195337396.001.0001
 Scruton, Roger, 2004, England and the Need for Nations, London: Civitas:
Institute for the Study of Civil Society.
 Searle-White, Joshua, 2001, The Psychology of Nationalism, New York: Palgrave
Macmillan US. doi:10.1057/9780312299057
 Seymour, Michel, 1999, La nation en question, Montreal: L’Hexagone.
 –––, 2000, “On Redefining the Nation”, in Miscevic 2000: 25–56.
 Shapiro, Ian and Lea Brilmayer (eds.), 1999, Global Justice, (Nomos, Volume
XLI), New York: New York University Press.
 Shapiro, Ian and Will Kymlicka (eds.), 1997, Ethnicity and Group Rights,
(Nomos, Volume XXXIX), New York: New York University Press.
 Simmons, A. John, 2001, “On The Territorial Rights of States”, Philosophical
Issues, 11: 300 –326. doi:10.1111/0029-4624.35.s1.12
 –––, 2016, Boundaries of Authority, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190603489.001.0001
 Shils, Edward, 1957, “On The Territorial Rights of StatesPrimordial, Personal,
Sacred and Civil Ties: Some Particular Observations on the Relationships of Sociological
Research and Theory”, The British Journal of Sociology, 8(2): 130– 145.
 Smith, Anthony D., 1991, National Identity, Penguin, Harmondsworth.
 –––, 2001, Nationalism, Cambridge: Polity Press.
 –––, 2003, “The Poverty of Anti-Nationalist Modernism”, Nations and
Nationalism, 9(3): 357–370. doi:10.1111/1469-8219.00101
 –––, 2008a. The Cultural Foundations of Nations: Hierarchy, Covenant and
Republic, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing
 –––, 2008, “Opening Remarkts to the Debate on Aviel Roshwald’s The Endurance
of Nationalism”, Nations and Nationalism, 14(4): 637–663. doi:10.1111/j.1469-
8129.2008.00355.x
 –––, 2009, Ethno-Symbolism and Nationalism: a Cultural Approach, London:
Routledge.
 –––, 2011, “National Identity and Vernacular Mobilisation in Europe”, Nations
and Nationalism, 17(2): 223–256. doi:10.1111/j.1469-8129.2011.00491.x
 Sober, Elliott, and David Sloan Wilson, 1998, Unto Others: The Evolution and
Psychology of Unselfish Behavior, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
 Sparrow, Robert, 2007, “For the Union Makes Us Strong: Anarchism and
Patriotism”, in Primoratz and Pavkovic 2007: 201–218.
 Spinner-Halev, Jeff, 2008, “Democracy, Solidarity and Post-
Nationalism”, Political Studies, 56(3): 604–628. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2007.00708.x
 Steiner, Hillel, 1999, “Just Taxation and International Redistribution”, in Shapiro
and Brilmayer 1999: 171–191.
 Stiltz, Anna, 2016, “The Value of Self-Determination”, Oxford Studies in Political
Philosophy 2, David Sobel, Peter Vallentyne, and Steven Wall (eds), Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 98–127. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198759621.003.0005
 Stone, John and Ioanna Christodoulaki, 2018, “Nebulous Nationalism: Walker
Connor in an Era of Rising Populism”, Nations and Nationalism, 24(3): 513–518.
doi:10.1111/nana.12443
 Storm, Eric, 2018, “A New Dawn in Nationalism Studies? Some Fresh Incentives
to Overcome Historiographical Nationalism”, European History Quarterly, 48(1): 113–
129. doi:10.1177/0265691417741830
 Tan, Kok-Chor, 2004, Justice without Borders: Cosmopolitanism, Nationalism,
and Patriotism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511490385
 –––, 2011, “Nationalism and Global Justice: A Survey of Some Challenges”,
in Sovereign Justice: Global Justice in a World of Nations, Diogo P. Aurélio, Gabriele De
Angelis, and Regina Queiroz (eds.), Berlin, New York: de Gruyter, 9–24.
doi:10.1515/9783110245745.1.9
 –––, 2012, Justice, Institutions, and Luck: The Site, Ground, and Scope of
Equality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199588855.001.0001
 Taguieff, Pierre-André, 2015, La revanche du nationalisme: Néopopulistes et
xénophobes ? l’assaut de l’Europe, Paris: Presses Universitaires De France.
 Tajfel, Henri, 1981, Human Groups and Social Categories, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
 Tamir, Yael, 1993, Liberal Nationalism, Press, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
 –––, 2019, Why Nationalism, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
 Taylor, Charles, 1989, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
 –––, 1993, Reconciling the Solitudes, Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
 –––, 1996, “Why Democracy Needs Patriotism”, in Cohen 1996: 119–121.
 Tilly, Charles (ed.), 1975, The Formation of National States in Western Europe,
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
 Tonkiss, Katherine, 2013, Migration and Identity in a Post-National World,
London: Palgrave Macmillan UK. doi:10.1057/9781137309082
 Tully, James, 1994, An Approach to Political Philosophy: Locke in Contexts,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511607882
 –––, 2004, “Recognition and dialogue: the emergence of a new field”, Critical
Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 7(3): 84–106.
 Twining, William (ed.), 1991, Issues of Self-determination, Aberdeen: Aberdeen
University Press.
 Vick, Brian, 2007, “Of Basques, Greeks, and Germans: Liberalism, Nationalism,
and the Ancient Republican Tradition in the Thought of Wilhelm von
Humboldt”, Central European History, 40(4): 653–681.
doi:10.1017/S0008938907001070
 Vincent, Andrew, 2001, “Political Theory”, in Motyl (ed.) 2001: Volume 1, 589–
599.
 Waldron, Jeremy, 1992, “Superseding Historic Injustice”, Ethics, 103(1): 4–28.
doi:10.1086/293468
 Walker, R.B.J., 2001, “Postmodernism”, in Motyl (ed.) 2001: Volume 1, 611–630.
 Walzer, Michael, 1983, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality,
New York: Basic Boooks.
 –––, 2002, “Passion and Politics”, Philosophy & Social Criticism, 28(6): 617–633.
doi:10.1177/019145370202800602
 –––, 2004, Arguing about War, New Haven & London: Yale University Press.
 Weber, Max, 1924, “Diskussionsrede zum Vortrag von P. Barth ‘Die Nationalitit
in ihrer soziologischer (1912) Bedeutung’ auf dem zweiten Deutschen Soziologentag in
Berlin 1912”, in Max Weber, Gesammelte Aufsatze zur Soziologie und Sozialpolitik,
Tubingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), S. pp. 484–486.
 Wellman, Christopher Heath, 2005, A Theory of Secession: The Case for Self-
Determination, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511499265
 Williams, Michael C., 2007, “Morgenthau Now: Neoconservatism, National
Greatness, and Realism”, in Realism Reconsidered: The Legacy of Hans Morgenthau in
International Relations, Michael C. Williams (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press,
216–240.
 Wimmer, Andreas, 2013, Waves of War: Nationalism, State Formation, and
Ethnic Exclusion in the Modern World, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
doi:10.1017/CBO9781139198318
 –––, 2018, Nation Building: Why Some Countries Come Together While Others
Fall Apart, Princeton: Princeton University Press
 Wright, Sue, 2016, Language Policy and Language Planning: From Nationalism
to Globalisation, second revised edition, London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.
doi:10.1007/978-1-137-57647-7
 Yack, Bernard, 2012, Nationalism and the Moral Psychology of Community,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
 –––, 2018, “Nationalism’s Grip on Democracy: Good News and Bad”,
in Reimagining Nation and Nationalism in Multicultural East Asia, Sungmoon Kim and
Hsin-Wen Lee (eds.), London: Routledge, chapter 1.
 Ypi, Lea, 2011, Global Justice and Avant-Garde Political Agency, Oxford: Oxford
University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199593873.001.0001
 Yuval-Davis, Nira, 1997, Gender and Nation, New York: Sage Publications.
 Žižek, Slavoj, 2015, “In the Wake of Paris Attacks the Left Must Embrace Its
Radical Western Roots”, In These Times, 16 November 2015, available online.
 –––, 2017, The Incontinence of the Void, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

You might also like