Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

Provisionalism in the study of politics 351

to political theory and to the discipline of political science as a whole. In


focusing too narrowly on subdisciplinary methodological issues, political
16 Provisionalism in the study of politics scientists and political theorists alike have missed opportunities to address
political questions of broad, substantive interest (cf. Isaac 1995).
In this chapter I shall argue for a new practice in political theory: one
Elisabeth Ellis that takes a provisional, rather than a conclusive, perspective; and one
that operates in the historical, rational, and empirical modes. I illustrate
this practice with the extended example of a critique of contemporary
democratic theory. I claim that a provisional rather than a conclusive per-
spective allows political theorists to focus away from attempts to influ-
Introduction ence decisions emanating from the traditional but relatively undemo-
At a panel on the state of the discipline at the 2001 meeting of the cratic locations of authoritative judgment, and toward critical analysis
American Political Science Association, Professor David Laitin said that of the places where political actors may gain or lose capacities for sub-
Ill
political theory plays an indispensable role in contemporary political sci- stan tive self-rule. Furthermore, I argue that most generally interesting
ence, because it provides the foundational questions that the rest of the political questions cannot be addressed by historical analysis, contempo-
field tries to answer (Laitin 2001 a). For Lai tin, however, political theory's rary political philosophy, or empirical research alone. Take, for example,
continuing relevance is a sign of political science's immaturity (Laitin political analysis involving international human rights. First, ahistorical
2001 b: 24). Political theory's function of "accounting for and justifying inquiry would miss key points, such as the fact of institutions for the
different public outcomes" should be taken up by political science gen- defense of international human rights that precede the national state by
erally. Such investigators, he argues, may do better than theorists have hundreds of years, or the fact that claims for human rights have some-
been doing lately, as they may avoid getting mired in "diversionary tacks times followed a sequence from civil through political to social. Second,
inducing us to grapple with ontologies or epistemologies" (23). contemporary political philosophy has clarified the consequences for
Laitin's vision for a theory-free political science fails to account for the international human rights of reasoning from various premises, such
special nature of political science's object of inquiry: political actors are as the premise of individual rational agency or the premise of cultur-
historically constituted, limited rational beings in the process of maldng ally distinct group memberships. Finally, without empirical inquiry we
their collective worlds. What differentiates a political science that includes would have nothing but speculative responses to important questions,
theory from a "purified," "positive" political science is this: only the such as whether the concept of human right or the concept of human
former can account for its object of inquiry qua constructor of value. 1 dignity has more international currency, or the question of whether advo-
However, Laitin's point about diversionary tacks applies all too well, both cacy groups mobilized on the basis of commitment to human rights
have any advantages over or even dynamics different from other such
groups.
Early versions of some of the ideas in this chapter were presented at the 2002 meetings
of the Western Political Science Association, the Southern Political Science Association, Here I offer an example of provisional theory in the historical, rational,
and the American Political Science Association. I learned a great deal in discussion of and empirical modes with an analysis of deliberative democratic theory. I
those early ideas with Mika LaVaque-Manty, Sung Ho Park, and Doug Dow. Thanks to argue that deliberative theory offers distinct advantages over its com-
my colleagues Cary Nederman and Ed Portis for providing the forum in which these ideas
could be developed, and to visitors to the Texas A&M University Political Theory Convo- petitors, grouped roughly as participatory and minimalist democrats.
cation, especially Jim Johnson and Ian Shapiro, for their generous encouragement. Seyla However, deliberative theory is saddled with three basic implausibili-
Benhabib and Alan Ryan provided thoughtful and productive criticism of a draft of this ties - psychological, philosophical, and institutional - and thus requires
chapter, for which I am grateful. Part of the research that contributed to this chapter was
supported by a grant from the Texas A&M University Scholarly and Creative Enhance- modification if it is to be a useful guide to the norms of democratic poli-
ment Fund. tics. First, historical analysis reveals deliberative theory's weak psycholog-
1
Ian Shapiro's suggestion that political science fails to characterize its dependent variables
adequately is relevant here, although my complaint covers inadequate understanding of
ical basis, namely its reliance on individual-level rational enlightenment
variables on both sides of the equation (Shapiro, concluding remarks, Conference on under deliberative conditions. A less psychologically implausible model
Problems and Methods in the Study of Politics, Yale University, December 6- 8, 2002). of deliberative change, I argue, would focus on the longer-term historical
350
352 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 353

dynamics of the public sphere. 2 Second, deliberative theory's main philo- theory may, I argue, be applied with good results to current political
sophical weakness is its continued reliance on conclusive argument with problems.
regard not only to procedure but also to policy outcomes. However noble Some areas of research in contemporary political theory have already
the principles on which these policy conclusions are based, they undercut moved beyond stale distinctions by means of the concept of provisional
deliberative theory's bedrock democratic commitment to substantive self- right. For example, Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson argue that
rule by real citizenries (as opposed to formal self-rule by idealized citizen- a view of political principles as "morally provisional" allows us to avoid
ries), resulting in the kind of paternalism democratic theory is supposed static debates among "first-order" theories like communitarianism and
to deny. Finally, empirical research on actual instances of deliberative liberalism by focusing on a "second-order" theory for assessing the proce-
polling demonstrates the weakness of current deliberative theory's insti- dural justice of any deliberation (Gutmann and Thompson 2000). To take
tutional vision, while research on the concrete political power of widely a different example, Jane Mansbridge has argued that an essential element
held democratic ideals operating in the public sphere over the medium of any democratic polity must be the maintenance of a variety of sources
and long term provides a better alternative. of opposition. Rather than attending strictly to problems of"political obli-
These three modes of political theory are not arbitrary paths to under- gation and civil disobedience," democratic theory ought to recognize the
standing public life; they are rooted in the nature of our object of inquiry: "ongoing imperfection of democratic decision." She grounds this view
historically limited rational beings in the process of making their col- on the premise that the principles that regulate democratic procedures
lective worlds. Only a provisional theory attentive to historical, rational, must always remain "provisional" (Mansbridge 1996).
and empirical questions can do justice to the ineradicably normative and The provisional perspective allows political theory to address prob-
fundamentally provisional nature of politics. lems that have all too often been left to our colleagues in other subfields.
Provisionalism allows the theorist to focus on the midrange problem of
maintaining the possibility of progress, rather than on determining par-
Provisional theory ticular policy or even regime type outcomes and expecting the practical
Provisional theory takes its starting point from the Kantian notion that problems to be resolved separately. For example, traditional defenders of
the concept of provisional right applies to institutions which imperfectly liberal rights tend to focus on the courts and their decisions. A provisional
mirror their own normative principles, and thus that practical politics theory would focus instead on the institutions and processes that restrict
must follow a rule of provisional rather than conclusive right. A focus or promote citizens' capacities for self-rule. The appointed panels mak-
on provisional rather than conclusive right makes it possible to analyze ing decisions for international trade regimes, devices like base-closure
institutions that do not make absolute pronouncements on what counts commissions used to get around representational failure, governmental
as just. For example, in most people's experience of citizenship, what and non-governmental agencies devoted to ensuring inclusive access to
matters is their degree of access to the legal system rather than any one the levers of everyday power, electoral reforms designed to represent cit-
of the system's particular claims. A general formulation for provisional izens on the basis of participation rather than inheritance, stakeholder
right in specifically Kantian language is: "always leave open the possibil- schemes for resolving environmental disputes, micro-lending agencies
ity of entering into a rightful condition" (Kant VI:347). Kant identified that encourage citizen autonomy, and so forth; these locations ought to
the distinction between provisional and conclusive right at the end of the interest political theorists, because these are the places where citizens
eighteenth century, and applied it to various political topics, such as the either gain or lose the capacity to determine their fates themselves.
determination of which violations of international right were immedi-
ate threats to the possibility of world peace, and which might be pro- An example: deliberative democratic theory
visionally tolerated (Kant VIII:343-9). More importantly, provisional
James Bohman and William Rehg usefully define deliberative demo-
2
This criticism does not apply to deliberative theories of the public sphere (e.g., Haber- cratic theory as referring to "the idea that legitimate lawmaking issues
mas 1997, 1992, 1991; Benhabib 1996; Dryzek 1990). As I shall presently argue, the from the public deliberation of citizens" (Bohman and Rehg 1997: ix).
most defensible democratic theory would combine the provisionality of Gutmann and
For more than a decade now, under various headings such as "discur-
Thompson's theory and the historical perspective ofHabermas's view, while jettisonning
Gutmann and Thompson's historical naivite and Habermas' conclusivist ambitions. sive" and "deliberative," democratic theorists have been revising previous
Provisionalism in the study of politics 355
354 Elisabeth Ellis

paradigms in what John S. Dryzek calls "a strong deliberative turn" deliberative conditions must be met. Deliberative theorists use provi-
(Dryzek 2000: 1). sional principles in the name of making good on the bedrock promises of
Roughly speaking, deliberative democratic theory falls between the democratic self-rule.
neo-Rousseauian politics of public good and the neo-Lockean politics It follows that deliberative democratic theory may not foreclose any
of liberal individualism; participatory democracy, communitarians, and topic from the domain of public choice unless the choice might under-
civic republicans would fall into the former camp, while Schumpeterian mine democracy itself. As I have just mentioned, deliberative democ-
minimalists, liberals of many stripes, and aggregative theories of democ- racy's liberal constitutionalist competitors traditionally protect the private
racy belong to the latter. 3 No matter what the image of theoretical ter- sphere from collective interference by categorically limiting the legitimate
rain employed by a particular deliberative democrat, deliberative theory scope of state activity, while their more participatory counterparts com-
always seeks to provide an account of democratic politics that preserves plain that the resulting polity is too thin to satisfy the demands of pos-
the best of both ends of the spectrum, while avoiding the conundra asso- itive freedom. Thus a significant advantage of deliberative theory over
ciated with each. For example, a standardized debate between, say, a its alternatives is that it can broaden the scope of legitimate state activ-
civic republican and a liberal individualist would result in a less-than- ity to address the moral reality of political life without sacrificing liberal
satisfactory set of alternatives on the divide between public and private. freedoms. "Moral argument already pervades democratic politics, and
Many liberals would defend a broad concept of the private sphere in the although it often fails to produce moral agreement, citizens evidently
name of non-tyranny. For them, the state exists to defend private inter- hope it will, or they would not engage in it" (Gutmann and Thompson
est. Civic republicans would point out that the narrow public sphere that 1996: 346). Indeed, much of the criticism of deliberative democratic the-
remains in the liberal vision is arbitrarily beholden to a private status quo, ory has in fact run along the same lines as the classic modernist critique of
and limits political freedoms to mere public formalities. Nearly all advo- the Old Regime's conflation of moral and temporal power. Such a mod-
cates of deliberative theory, on the other hand, regard some distinction ernist might argue, for example, that it took devastating wars and theorists
between public and private as necessary to protect civil freedom, while of the caliber of Hobbes and Locke to free modern politics from religion
insisting that protection of substantive (not merely formal) political lib- as a permanent source of debilitating conflict. Along these lines, William
erties entails some blurring of the public/private divide. Gutmann and Galston complains that deliberative theory underrates the achievements
Thompson, for example, argue that no "matter how earnestly citizens of "mere toleration" in the areas of peace and stability: "In most times
carry on deliberation in the spirit of reciprocity, publicity, and account- and places, the avoidance of repression and bloody conflict is in itself
ability, they can realize these ideals only to the extent that each citizen a morally significant achievement ... " (Galston 1999: 45). Gutmann's
has sufficient social and economic standing to meet his or her fellows on and Thompson's constitutionalist democratic foils make a similar point:
terms of equal respect" (1996: 349). the democratic state must be limited in scope - and excluded from enforc-
Most theorists of deliberative democracy argue that not only public pol- ing moral or religious judgments - in order to keep the more fundamental
icy, but also procedural standards themselves are included among poten- promise of providing basic security to its citizens.
tial items for public deliberation; they have provisional status (Gutmann Given the force of these arguments, why bring morality back in?
and Thompson 1996: 351-354). Gutmann and Thompson, for example, Because a system of political legitimacy that would exclude moral ques-
explicitly identify deliberative theory as having "a provisional status" and tions entirely from the activity of the state makes three fundamental
say that it "expresses a dynamic conception of politics" (1999: 276). They errors. First, denial of the state's right to action in a particular realm
add: "this provisional status does not merely express some general sense does not make the state value-neutral; rather, such a denial privileges
of fallibility: it is specific to resolutions of deliberative disagreements in the status quo by throwing moral issues to non-state (and therefore non-
politics and carries implications for political practices and institutions" accountable) actors to decide. 4 Whether the determining players are spe-
(1999a: 277). The logic of deliberative democracy is hypothetical rather cific private sector interests or the more diffuse forces of culture and
than categorical; if a system is to be legitimately democratic, then certain history, such a point of view arbitrarily limits the scope of democratic

3
Not all neo-Schumpeterian democrats accept Lockean premises about the priority of
4 For an interesting argument about the myth of state neutrality from a different point of
society over the state. See, for example, Ian Shapiro's Democratic Justice (1999b). view, see Kymlicka 2000.
356 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 357

self-rule. Gutmann and Thompson argue similarly that denying moral up to this moral fact of political life. They assume that it is simply the
reason a place in politics amounts to excluding all considerations but result of misunderstanding, which could be overcome if citizens would
power and interest from the public sphere. "Why," they ask, "assume only adopt the correct philosophical view or cultivate the proper moral
that a power-based conception of democracy is the default position? ... character" (1996: 360). Deliberative theory does not seek to do justice to
At the foundational level, no one has yet provided a justification of a the moral element in political life by selecting the correct moral point of
power-based conception that is any more adequate than a justification of view and arguing for its universal adoption. Nor does deliberative theory
a conception based on moral reason" (Gutmann and Thompson 1996: throw up its hands with a culturally relativist stance, accepting either sep-
353). aratism or a severely limited scope for public action as the natural result of
Second, democratic politics cannot legitimately be limited by theory moral pluralism. By treating political settlements as provisional, the fact of
in advance to a few supposedly neutral values, such as "security" or moral disagreement as permanent, but individual moral disagreement on
"economic prosperity." The very selection of these few values distorts particular issues as at least provisionally amenable to democratic accom-
the institution itself. To take a contemporary example: as currently con- modation, deliberative theory improves on both its liberal neutralist and
stituted, the World Trade Organization (WTO) may legitimately sanction its participatory, not to mention its cultural relativist, predecessors.
member nations only for actions deemed to be illegitimate restraints on While deliberative theory envisions a more expansive thematic scope
free trade. This limited scope provides the WTO with much of its legiti- for democratic decisionmaking than mainstream liberal theory, it restricts
macy, and ensures that member nations tolerate its very real interference the sphere of theoretical prejudgment to the preconditions of substantive
with their national sovereignty. However, such narrow limits on the scope deliberation. By contrast, with a set of absolute normative standards such
and basis ofWTO judgments have led to policy decisions that run counter as mainstream liberal theory seeks to provide, a theorist might derive spe-
to local and even world public opinion. The individuals affected by WTO cific policy outcomes that follow from those standards. For example, since
rulings are unlikely to prefer the narrow standards of trade expansion the United States Supreme Court handed down its decision in Wisconsin
to broader standards addressing the environment, employment, human vs. Yoder (406 US 205 [1972]), theorists have been second-guessing the
rights, and other areas affected by trade policy. The WTO has been outcome, each by means of his or her preferred set of standards of politi-
criticized, with reason, for its undemocratic character; not only are its cal right. In an interesting example of what Cass R. Sunstein (1999) calls
unelected panels of decisionmakers only very indirectly accountable, but "incompletely theorized agreement," while most academic critics dis-
the rules under which they operate forbid them to consider many of the agree with the court's ruling, which allowed an exception to the schooling
most salient elements of the public will regardless of the formal structure requirement for Amish teenagers, these critical opinions are based on the-
of accountability. oretical standpoints as divergent as utilitarianism and Kantian liberalism.
The third and final argument that moral considerations ought not to Thus, over the past few decades, the reading public for political theory,
be excluded ex ante from political deliberation lies in the empirical asso- such as it is, has enjoyed significant clarification of what sorts of policy
ciation between moral and political reasoning in practice. Though there outcomes may be justified by what sorts of philosophical premises. How-
is relatively little consensus on the moral content of political ideals, there ever, and, I would add, fortunately, political theorists have not reached
is overwhelming consensus that political ideals have some moral con- even provisional consensus on which set of philosophical premises might
tent. This is of course an empirical statement, a fact which could be be most authoritative, even for a particular time and place, much less
disproved at any moment. But while it is possible to imagine a politics universally. More problematically, the theoretical focus on correct policy
devoid of moral content, the fact remains that the overwhelming major- outcomes has come at the expense of some very fundamental political
ity of people, across differences of time and space, conceive of politics problems, including the whole complex of questions around how legiti-
in moral terms such as "justice," "right," "respect," "human dignity," mate liberal-democratic contemporary regimes in fact are. The theorist
and so forth. 5 On the presence of moral reason in politics, Gutmann interested in reaching, say, the populist-utilitarian answer to the ques-
and Thompson write that "many theorists of democracy refuse to face tion addressed in Wisconsin vs. Yoder only complains about the outcome
reached by the court, not the fact that the court itself as it currently
5
For an insightful discussion of the implications of this Wittgensteinian point for the operates constitutes an affront to most relatively strong conceptions of
concept of justice, see Pitkin 1972. democratic value (but see Ginsburg 2001; and Shapiro 1999a).
358 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 359

Deliberative theory at its best focuses on institutions rather than out- developments associated with globalization have run up against delib-
comes. Gutmann and Thompson, for example, make a compelling argu- erative principles, of course. As Margaret Keck and Kathryn Sikkink
ment for the progressive power of state-sanctioned norms of transparency (1998) point out, for example, new transnational networks of advocacy
and publicity, rather than direct regulation or privatization, with the case groups in areas such as human rights and the environment have enjoyed
of environmental impact statements. The "practice of requiring agencies occasionally surprising success in the global public sphere. However, the
and companies to issue environmental impact statements before proceed- implications for global and local citizenship of deliberative theory have
ing with major development projects is often more effective, according to not yet been adequately explored by political theorists (for an exception

I! one study, than other methods of enforcement .... Agencies and com-
panies pay closer attention to environmental matters when they know
they will have to defend their actions in detail in public" (1996: 98).
outside deliberative theory, see Kymlicka 2000).
Political inclusion within the national state, however, is a topic that
deliberative theorists have made a central part of their reconstruction
Provisional theorists of deliberative democracy, with their focus on insti- of democratic theory. While standard liberal democratic theory has suc-
tutions and empowerment rather tha_n on directing policy outcomes, are cessfully championed formal political inclusion over a long series of pro-
thus able to avoid the shortcomings of both the liberal and the partici- gressively more inclusive policies, deliberative theorists point to a "reality
patory poles of alternative democratic theories. On the one hand, they gap" between merely formal and substantive political inclusion. Accord-
avoid the neo-Lockean pitfall of overreliance on the private sector and ing to Iris Marion Young, for example, both passive and active exclusions
the concomitant loss of democratic self-rule; on the other, they dodge are unjust: "In principle, inclusion ensures that every potentially affected
the neo-Rousseauian specter of total government, with its twin dangers agent has the opportunity to influence deliberative processes and out-
of tyranny and ineffectiveness. comes" (Young 1999: 155). The state has an obligation to ensure formal
Deliberative theory values democratic self-rule in a strong sense: access inclusiveness (via policies such as voting rights - in light of the experi-
to and accountability from the policy structure for those affected by its ence of exclusion by large numbers of Black Floridians in the 2000 US
policies. Such a principle raises interesting questions about membership presidential elections, this is clearly an ongoing project). But according
and citizenship which I cannot address here. It does improve upon mod- to provisional deliberative theory, the state must also ensure "effective
ernist democratic theory based on the national state by providing for opportunity" to participate, a standard that reaches well beyond formal
substantive rather than merely formal empowerment. Classic social con- rights (Young 1999: 157).
tract theory limits positive rights to an arbitrary group of empowered Thus deliberative theory improves substantially on its neo-Lockean
citizens, chosen by a combination of morally arbitrary qualities (geogra- and neo-Rousseauian competitors. It avoids the charge of insufficient
phy, wealth, blood ties, and so forth) (Rawls 1996). Recent changes in the attention to liberty by means of provisional defense of the rights neces-
global political environment only make more urgent what was already a sary to the deliberative process, and by restricting would-be paternalist
difficult democratic conundrum: why should control over policies affect- prejudgment of policy outcomes. It avoids the opposite charge of being
ing a large group be limited to some subset of that group? insufficiently critical by removing some liberal restrictions on the scope of
Most deliberative democrats do not in fact draw this strong con- democratic decisionmaking and by its attention to the institutional pre-
clusion about the limited legitimacy of national citizenship from their conditions of substantive deliberation. For all its substantive advantages
premises about self-rule. There are certainly good reasons for cleaving to over previous democratic theories, however, deliberative theory remains
the national state in the absence of more promising institutional alter- saddled with some of the traditional shortcomings of standard liberal
natives. Historically, the national state has at some times and places theory: an implausible model of political change that relies on unlikely
been the instrument of progressively more inclusive citizen empowerment accounts both of individual psychology and of the time-frame of shifts
(Marshall 1964) . As the substantive scope of narrowly national policy in social mentalities; a neo-paternalist commitment to the "right" policy
contracts, new transnational actors are acquiring policy discretion, often outcomes based on noble but ultimately arbitrary absolute principles;
without even the formal accountability that constrained national govern- and a too-thin conception of the reasoning subject that excludes the
ments. Small wonder, then, that anti-globalization protests attract not vast majority of potentially empowered democratic citizens, especially
only those opposed to expanded trade and its downstream effects, but those with strong religious views. Gutmann and Thompson are certainly
also activists concerned with democracy's promise of self-rule. Not all right to reject cultural relativism. Even as committed a communitarian as
360 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 361

Michael Sandel agrees that to "make justice the creature of convention is methods of inquiry' .... The Gutmann/Thompson model works only for
to deprive it of its critical character" (1998: xi). Gutmann and Thompson those fundamentalists who also count themselves fallibilist democrats.
criticize Robert P. George's argument that one day permissive abortion That, I fear, is an empty class ... " (1999a: 30-1).
laws will be viewed in the same light as permissive slavery laws are today Deliberative theory's case for short-term individual enlightenment
with the Kantian point that privileging any particular historical stand- would be strengthened by examples of the phenomenon in action, but
point cannot be justified: "Imagining the time in the future when one's these are unfortunately in very short supply. Perhaps the strongest case
argument might win the day does not add anything to the strength of in the Gutmann and Thompson volume, a study of deliberation around
one's argument in the present" (Gutmann and Thompson 1999: 270). the Oregon health-care rationing debate, is also the most deeply flawed, in
This is certainly a valid point, and one that draws strength from the very that very few of those actually affected by the policy (those dependent on
reasonable assumption that changes in public morality do not always hap- the state for health care) actually participated in the public deliberation
pen in a positive direction. However, Gutmann and Thompson entirely on the policies that affected them. Even James Fishkin, whose deliber-
miss the force of historical and cultural arguments like George's. Instead, ative polling mechanism is the most promising of proposed deliberative
they expect that, given the right institutional background, public reason institutions, admits that we "do not know to what degree deliberative
will trump social context and historical prejudice, and over the short opinion polls would contribute to thoughtful, self-reflective opinion for-
run at that. A focus on an idealized individual reasoner produces such mation" ( 1991: 83). Deliberative enlightenment seems unlikely to occur
conclusions: why shouldn't a person, confronted with the shortcomings of on the time-scale contemplated by most of its contemporary advocates.
a long-held view in the process of public debate, simply change her mind? Theorists interested in the mechanism by which it might occur ought to
But this is the wrong question. Rather than ask how individual reasoners turn their attention away from individual rational choice and toward the
of good will might form excellent political judgments, we should ask how dynamics of argument in the public sphere.
the discursive environment changes over time such that some arguments There are a number of such literatures available, though I will restrict
become more or less possible to make. 6 my discussion to a few examples here (Reinhart Koselleck and the
Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe school; J. G. A. Pocock and those studying the
"languages of political thought"; and Jane Mansbridge's "everyday talk"
Deliberative theory's psychological implausibility and its historically
model). None of these schools of thought offer a model for deliberative
informed solution: the historical public sphere
theory to embrace and apply without significant revision. The histori-
Deliberative theory's model of political change rests on an underlying cal schools are, of course, much more interested in describing changes
psychological implausibility: under deliberative conditions, rational indi- in political mentality than in relating those changes to the degree of sub-
viduals are supposed to achieve immediate enlightenment. While reason- stantive political freedom enjoyed by a discourse's participants. However,
ing in the public sphere can make profound differences in general public these alternate models of a dynamic public sphere offer deliberative the-
opinion, these changes are effective at the level of a public more than at ory a way out of its psychological implausibility without sacrificing its
the level of the individual, and over the medium and long term, rather advantages.
than immediately. 7 Ian Shapiro illustrates the model's implausibility in
the case of Gutmann's and Thompson's work with the point that, alluring Reinhart Koselleck and the history of political concepts. Reinhart
"as this reasoning might be to you and me, I find it hard to imagine a fun- Koselleck and his fellow contributors to the enormous and very use-
damentalist being much impressed by it, particularly when she learns that ful encyclopedia of modern political concepts, Geschichtliche Grundbe-
any empirical claims she makes must be consistent with 'relatively reliable grijfe, have traced the development of some important political ideas and
their legitimating arguments, concentrating especially on the key period
6
Such a move, by the way, is a shift from inquiry guided by Kantian absolutist ethics (what between 1750 and 1820 in Europe. By showing how various concepts shift
must a reasoner of good will conclude?) toward inquiry guided by Kantian provisional their meanings over time, Koselleck illustrates the dynamics of differing
political theory (what are the institutional preconditions of a healthy public sphere, and styles of political argument. In fact, as certain terms acquire new polit-
how can it contribute to political progress?).
7
A similar point is made by Kant in "An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?" ical meaning, old strategies of legitimation become, as it were, linguis-
(VIII: 35-6). tically impossible. For example, discussing the establishment of French
362 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 363

revolutionary political language, Koselleck argues, "In France, the plat- investigators into the "languages of political thought" are concerned with
form of revolutionary language, victorious after 1789, rapidly and effec- the dynamics of political ideas. Rather than create histories of political
tively rendered the privileges of the estates incapable of legitimation" thought, Pocock argues, we should consider ideas as events, and political
(1989: 659). history as the history of political discourse (Pocock 1987). Changes in
Koselleck and his colleagues include philological information from well political language shut out possibilities that used to exist, while opening
before the modern period. However, a basic premise of their research is up new ones heretofore unimaginable. While Pocock puts equal empha-
that the history of concepts has operated according to a different dynamic sis on investigating the effects of linguistic change on political possibility,
since the Enlightenment; now, concepts are not merely collected from on the one hand, and the "learning" of "political languages" to facili-
reality, but expected to drive and respond to a constantly changing polit- tate historical insight, on the other, deliberative democrats are of course
ical environment. New political terms create expectations about change relatively uninterested in the latter pursuit (except insofar as it allows us
rather than describe current politics (2002: 128-9). In fact, "the lower to understand independently interesting sources better). As Pocock and
their content in terms of experience, the greater the expectations they his colleagues establish their case for context-based readings of political
created - this would be a short formula for the new type of political ideas, then, they also provide deliberative theory with support for a model
and historical contexts" (2002: 129). Koselleck concludes: "Political and of a dynamic and potentially empowering public sphere. Pocock himself
social concepts become the navigational instruments of the changing makes reference to this dual result of context-sensitive research in the
movement of history. They do not only indicate or record given facts. history of political ideas; even as the historian is interested in old patterns
They themselves become factors in the formation of consciousness and and the ways they constrain change, "there is a process in the contrary
the control of behavior" (2002: 129). Though the language Koselleck direction; the new circumstances generate tensions in the old conven-
himself uses encourages the reader to think of linguistic phenomena tions, language finds itself being used in new ways, changes occur in the
as somehow autonomous historical forces, this is misleading. Koselleck language being used, and it is possible to imagine this process leading to
is describing something very like the Kantian and neo-Kantian public the creation and diffusion of new languages ... " (Pocock 1987: 32).
sphere, in which concrete political actors participate in the creation of The study of the languages of political thought provides an interest-
new modes of political thought. Koselleck illustrates this dynamic with ing model for a mechanism of the public sphere, but only a model. As
the concept of emancipation. Pocock notes, most material thus far studied by himself and his col-
leagues predates industrial society. Democratization, the information rev-
The following thesis may be ventured: with the introduction of the reflexive verb olution, mass literacy, and mass media all contribute to new contexts for
'to emancipate oneself (sich emanzipieren), a profound shift of mentality was, the same basic mechanism driving change. The question remains: what
for the first time, foreshadowed and then brought about. While initially it was a
arguments are possible to make under what conditions? But the speed,
word used by the cognoscenti, the poets and philosophers, who sought to liberate
themselves from all pregivens and dependency, the new active word usage was medium, and scale of change should be fairly different in a postindustrial
expanded to increasingly refer to groups, institutions, and entire peoples .... context.
Contained within the reflexive word usage was eo ipso a thrust against the estates
system. (2002: 252) Jane Mansbridge on "everyday talk". Mansbridge's model of
the dynamics of public speech bears some resemblance to Koselleck's
These concepts do not change according to any internal, independent and Pocock's, but unlike the historical models, Mansbridge is focused
dynamic of their own. Instead, a received new concept is the result of a on the contemporary world. The underlying mechanism of change in
political battle fought by linguistic means in the public sphere, subject to Mansbridge's account is composed of social activists and their inno-
standards of rationality to be sure, but also to forces of political mobi- vations, but serious change occurs only as the activists and their ideas
lization, temporary strategic advantages, extrapolitical cultural shifts, and interact with the general public. She writes, "In social movements, new
plain dumb luck. ideas - and new terms, such as 'male chauvinism' or 'homophobia' -
enter everyday talk through an interaction between political activists and
J G. A. Pocock and the languages ofpolitical thought. Like Kosel- non-activists. Activists craft, from ideals or ideas solidly based in the exist-
leek and the Geschichtliche Grundbegrijfe group, Pocock and his fellow ing culture, ideals or ideas that begin to stretch that base" (1999: 219).
364 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 365

Political possibilities change as vocabularies shift. For example, a world deliberate and inform themselves on a topic and come up with what the
without a word for homophobia is a world in which the public may not public "would think about the issue if it focused on it in a more substan-
have been encouraged to consider the moral status of prevailing anti-gay tial way" 8 (Fishkin 1995: 2, Fishkin's emphasis). Fishkin's deliberative
attitudes. democratic institutions do not seek consensus, but only to reveal the pub-
Like the other models, everyday talk is not perfect for deliberative pur- lic will in all its diversity without the distortions of poor information, false
poses. Mansbridge is more interested in the political aspects of social attitudes, and other survey research shortcomings.
life, such as the empowerment of women in oppressive family situations John S. Dryzek's early Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political
via the incorporation of new ideas into their moral vocabularies. She Science (1990) is also partly inspired by dissatisfaction with contemporary
also does not address the drastically unidimensional motives of the big reliance on public opinion polls, and also offers an alternative aimed at
corporate media organizations which offer the most opportunities for reaching some more genuine public will ("Q methodology," an inter-
idea transmission in the advanced industrial societies. But her model of subjective, non-hierarchical survey technique) (Dryzek 1990: l 73ff.).
the mechanism of change is compelling: "If parts of new ideals begin Dryzek's critique, however, goes beyond unsatisfactory levels of public
to win more general acceptance, many people, including non-activists, debate in contemporary democracies to the dysfunctions of instrumen-
begin changing their lives in order to live up to those ideals in a better tal reason itself; unlike Fishkin, Dryzek works in the tradition of the
way." Mansbridge recognizes that powerful representatives of interested Frankfurt School critics of modern society, including among others Max
parties will try to promote or denigrate ideals that provide material advan- Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, and Jurgen Habermas. Like Horkheimer
tages and disadvantages, but argues that "material loss and gain do not and Adorno, Dryzek attributes many contemporary social problems to
fully explain adherence to or rejection of an idea. People are governed the nature of liberal democracy itself (rather than its incomplete real-
in part by their ideals, and they often want to act consistently" (1999: ization), particularly insofar as liberal democracy conceives of the pub-
220). lic good as the aggregate of many individual preferences (Dryzek 1990:
Unlike most deliberative theorists, who focus on rational choice at the 125). However, unlike Horkheimer and Adorno, and like Habermas,
individual level, Jane Mansbridge offers a model for a dynamic public Dryzek sees the potential for democratic, maybe even liberal-democratic,
sphere based on interaction between social activists and non-activists. redemption in the expansion of the public sphere. For Habermas and
She does not restrict contributions to public discourse on the basis of for Dryzek, both critical theorists of a deliberative democratic bent, the
their emotional content, but instead allows the full panoply of politi- alternative to (unavailable) universal standards ofliberal rights is not free-
cal language to count as contributions in the public sphere. As Marcus, wheeling pluralism or cultural relativism, but recourse to the normative
Neuman, and MacKuen have also argued, the current scholarly atten- standards inherent in the deliberative procedures of the public sphere
tion directed exclusively toward instrumentally rational public opinion (Dryzek 1990; Habermas 1992).
fails to comprehend the human political animal as it in fact operates in Critical theory's commitment to absolute standards of political right,
the world: emotional systems, they demonstrate, can promote ultimately whether rooted in the ideal speech situation (Habermas 1973) or in a
rational political behavior (Marcus et al. 2000). theory that posits the occlusion of genuine public right by an irrational
or hyperrational system, does provide the basis for a grounded critique
of contemporary society. However, societal criticism made on this kind
Deliberative theory's philosophical implausibility and its rationally
of basis only has as much weight as its underlying principles. Thus far,
informed solution: provisionalism
no consensus has emerged on which set of basic principles democratic
Some of the earliest calls for more deliberation in democratic practice theorists ought to embrace (Rawlsian or Habermasian? neo-Marxist or
arose out of critique of the state of really existing liberal democracy in neo-liberal? Post-Nietzschean orneo-Aristotelean? ... ). Ian Shapiro com-
the advanced industrial nations. For example, James S. Fishkin's long- ments on the situation: "If there were an answer to [the question of which
running effort to incorporate citizen deliberation into the practice of political institutions would be chosen by truly neutral reasoners], it might
public decisionmaking in Texas, the United States, and Great Britain
8 This is, of course, a classically Kantian formulation for approximating the general will.
arose at least partly from dissatisfaction with the institution of opinion
All existing states being imperfect (and right, therefore, being provisional rather than
polling. In place of public opinion surveys, with all their well-known flaws, conclusive), the head of state must strive to make the decisions that would be made by the
Fishkin calls for opportunities for representative samples of the public to united will of the people (Kant VI: 328).
366 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 367
arguably provide a yardstick for political evaluation. . . . If, however, Conclusivist (i.e., non-provisional) theorists of deliberative democracy
there is no compelling answer to the motivating question, as the exis- do not, therefore, present interesting alternatives to liberal or participa-
tence of multiple pretenders to the neo-Kantian throne suggests is the tory democratic theory. In other words, without provisionalism and the
case, then the enterprise is forlorn" (Shapiro 1996: 6). status/scope limitations such a perspective implies, deliberative demo-
The question is not whether standards are necessary (for critique, they cratic theory does not improve substantially on its predecessors. Cass R.
are), but what status and scope apply to them. Provisional, as opposed Sunstein argues similarly for what he calls "incompletely theorized agree-
to conclusivist, theorists of deliberative democracy recognize that the ments" in the name of respect for historical persons: such agreements
standards themselves are included among potential items for public "are valuable when we seek moral evolution over time," since a rigid set
deliberation (Gutmann and Thompson 1996: 351-4) . Gutmann and of absolute principles "would disserve posterity" (Sunstein 1999: 132). 11
Thompson, for example, explicitly identify deliberative theory as having To respect the bedrock democratic principle of substantive self-rule, the-
"a provisional status" and say that it "expresses a dynamic conception of ories must remain provisional rather than conclusivist, leaving most issues
politics" (Gutmann and Thompson 1999: 276). They add: "this provi- to the active decisionmaking of citizens themselves.
sional status does not merely express some general sense of fallibility: it Any democratic theory that prejudges the outcome of a particular pol-
is specific to resolutions of deliberative disagreements in politics and car- icy area beyond those directly involved in guaranteeing self-rule violates
ries implications for political practices and institutions" (Gutmann and the bedrock democratic principle of respect for what Frederick Schauer
Thompson 1999: 277). calls the "people's right to be wrong" (1999: 24). Anticipations of the
Some deliberative theorists would also limit the scope of application correct outcomes for substantive policymaking respond to the under-
of normative standards of public reason to procedural questions, rather standable demand for justice as soon as possible. However, attempts to
than both deliberative procedures and policy outcomes. 9 I shall include prejudge policy outcomes beyond those required for substantive self-
among provisional theorists those who recognize at least the status if not rule end up foreclosing the most important elements of self-rule from
the scope limitation on universal deliberative norms. Most in this group citizens' purview. Provisional deliberative theory, then, ought to insist
insist on the value of leaving people to determine their own policy out- on the preconditions of citizen empowerment and maximum institu-
comes. But even the most prominent 10 advocates of provisionalism in tional democracy in the name of the bedrock democratic commitment to
deliberative theory, Gutmann and Thompson, waver on this point. As I substantive self-rule.
discuss below, Gutmann and Thompson make contradictory statements This does not boil down to what Gutmann and Thompson call pro-
about scope limitations, insisting rightly on the wrongness of theoreti- ceduralist democratic theory. Mere formal proceduralism has proved too
cally prejudged policy outcomes, but also insisting wrongly on the uni- weak to support the equally bedrock democratic commitment to jus-
versal rightness of some very specific policies. I shall argue below that tice (Shapiro 1999b). Again, from a provisional perspective, then, what
universal deliberative standards do apply to that very limited subset of matters most for democratic theory are the preconditions of substantive
policy outcomes which affect substantive self-rule on the part of individ- self-rule. For example, in a discussion of the Clinton health care plan, Ian
uals, and thus that Gutmann and Thompson are right to include slavery Shapiro argues that its failure is due, "more than any other single factor,
among legitimately forbiddable policy outcomes, right to exclude abor- to the blank check the United States Supreme Court has given those who
tion rights from the narrow circle of universalist policies, but wrong to have large amounts of money, or the capacity to raise it, to shape the terms
include medical rationing in that domain. of public debate. It creates a reality in which, rather than compete in the
realm of ideas, politicians actually must compete for campaign contribu-
9
tions" (1999a: 35). Similarly, Douglas Rae argues that attention to very
See Knight 1999, which distinguishes among three types of deliberative theory: con- specific local conditions of citizen empowerment is necessary to convert
straints on arguments themselves according to public reason (Rawls); substantive con-
straints on policy outcomes (such as Gutmann and Thompson's use of the ideals of "intangible" into "tangible" freedoms (1999: 169). Norman Daniels's
liberty and opportunity); and Knight's favored version: derivations of substantive con-
straints from procedural norms (Knight, Knight and Johnson, Habermas, Bohman, inter II A rarely recognized Kantian point. Though in the sphere of ethics Kant is indeed some-
alia). Note that Knight includes both provisional and conclusive theorists of deliberative thing of an absolutist, in politics Kant denied any single generation the right to settle ques-
democracy in his favored group. tions, including moral ones. See "An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?"
IO As measured by the Social Science Citation Index, as of February 2003 . (VIII: 33- 42).
368 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 369

work on deliberative theory and managed health care is also of inter- institutions of deliberative democracy are more likely to reach the "right
est here, as Daniels confesses himself a lapsed Rawlsian who no longer answers" to policy questions than current minimalist institutions allow.
believes that absolute principles can guide institutions making moral deci- However, in the first place, this is an empirical question. One could come
sions in the health-care area (1999: 199-200). Middle-level moral policy up with an arbitrary list of "correct" liberal democratic policy outcomes,
problems, such as health-care rationing, respond better to a provisional measure their prevalence along with the level of institutional "deliber-
approach modeled on case law, with important decisions reached in a ativeness" in a large-N cross-national study, and see whether the two
public forum. Rather than handing down correct moral policy answers variables are significantly related. Presuming consensus among theorists
from a position of ethical expertise, Daniels argues, health-care policy- on at least some basic policy outcomes, large-scale investigation into the
makers ought to be required to give reasons in public for their decisions. usefulness of deliberative institutions might proceed on the model of,
"Case law does not imply past infallibility.... It involves a form of insti- say, Robert Putnam's ongoing study of the relation between social cap-
tutional reflective equilibrium, a commitment to both transparency and ital and general measures of societal well-being (2000). The results of
coherence in the giving of reasons" (1999: 205). For these theorists, the such a study would certainly be interesting, but they would tell us noth-
problem illustrated by health-care policy in the United States is less its ing about the normative status of deliberative democratic institutions.
(very real) failure to build an acceptable system than that system's failure In the second place, prejudging the outcomes of deliberation violates a
to make good on democratic principles of inclusiveness. bedrock precept of democratic theory in the deliberative mode, namely
The issue of health care illustrates a contradictory tendency in main- respect for persons as concrete historical individuals able to engage in
stream deliberative theory. Despite a laudable commitment to provision- substantial self-rule. As Iris Marion Young writes, "a theory of democ-
alism, most deliberative theorists are still too willing to prejudge the racy in itself should have little to say about the substance of welfare pol-
outcome of what should be democratically and dynamically determined icy, but should have a great deal to say about the institutions, practices,
policy choices. Gutmann and Thompson, for example, argue that med- and procedures for deliberating about and deciding on a welfare policy"
ical rationing can contradict the deliberative principles of inclusiveness, (1999: 156-7).
reciprocity, and basic opportunity, since someone denied a chance at life However, exceptions may be made for policies that relate to the pre-
will not be able to participate politically. Their main case study on this conditions of deliberation itself. On the issue of slavery, for example,
point is that of Dianna Brown, an Arizona resident denied an organ trans- Gutmann and Thompson plausibly object to Robert P. George's view
plant because she could not afford one herself, and the state had decided that proslavery viewpoints have not always deserved moral disrespect
to fund other medical needs instead (Gutmann and Thompson 1996). (Gutmann and Thompson 1999: 270). The difference between the issue
Compelling as Brown's need is, by prejudging the outcome of this case, of slavery, for which there can be no moral respect for the pro side, and
Gutmann and Thompson narrow the scope of democratic deliberation the issue of abortion, for which Gutmann and Thompson argue moral
intolerably. They do not recognize that a focus on substantive rather than respect must be accorded all reciprocity-respecting viewpoints, is this: the
merely formal freedoms entails the recognition that innumerable pub- institution of slavery contradicts the basic principles underlying delibera-
lic decisions, and not only those explicitly and directly dealing with life tive democracy itself by excluding adults affected by public policies from
and death, can result in the death of a potentially empowered individual. deliberation over them (that is, from self-rule).
Substantively speaking, there is little difference between state policy on The line between provisional and conclusivist theories is admittedly
organ transplants, and state policy on automobile safety, environmental a fine one: why exclude Habermasian conditions of ideal speech from
toxicity, junk food in the public schools, and thousands of other issues the ranks of the provisional theorists while including Gutmann's and
with demonstrable connections to individual life chances. Thompson's conditions of deliberation? The answer is twofold. First,
Between a formal proceduralism that privileges the status quo, and a Habermas and other theorists of conclusive right make universalist claims
neo-paternalism that privileges the views of the theorist above those of for their principles, while Gutmann and Thompson and other theorists of
the polity, lies the sort of "thick proceduralism" recommended by a pro- their type make only contingent claims for theirs. "If you want the legit-
visional rather than a conclusivist approach to political thought. Some imacy accorded to the deliberative policymaking process, then you must
conclusive theorists may plausibly argue that people acting through the respect these principles inherent in deliberativeness per se," a provisional

~-
370 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 371

deliberative theorist might argue. 12 Second, Gutmann and Thompson fellow investigators have paid a great deal of attention to the problem
argue that even bedrock principles such as reciprocity are open to revi- of representativeness, and may well be able to resolve that problem with
sion in the deliberative sphere: "Citizens learn more about the nature of adjustments to the incentive structure and the like. The second problem
reciprocity, as they reason according to its requirements. Because they is more serious : the very short term (in deliberative polling, a matter of a
regard the requirements of reciprocal reasoning, like its results, as provi- few hours or at most a few weeks) may not be the right place to look for
sional, their understanding of reciprocity has the capacity to correct itself the kind of dynamic shift in public reason that deliberative theory leads
over time" (Gutmann and Thompson 1996: 351) . us to expect. Denver et al. found no significant change in participants'
views after the Grenada 500 deliberative poll; what's worse, they found a
decrease in political knowledge and no increase in political sophistication
Deliberative theory's institutional implausibility and its empirically
(Denver et al. 1995 : 152-3). I shall add that even a very well-established
informed solution: the global public sphere
deliberative institution like the deliberative poll faces enormous obstacles
Despite their continued interest, expressed in case studies such as that in moving from a few trial runs to becoming part of the national political
of Dianna Brown, in achieving moral justice in the very short term, culture. Compare Fishkin's deliberative polling institution with some of
Gutmann and Thompson do make some interesting longer-term insti- the other suggestions offered by deliberative theorists (such as increasing
tutional suggestions. I have already mentioned their call to broaden the access to the public sphere, campaign finance reform, or requiring pub-
policy tool of the environmental impact statement to require many more lic consultation on most public business); for the price of sequestering,
decisionmakers to give public reasons for their major development activi- compensating, and publicizing deliberative polling groups as a regular
ties. They decry the emphasis in the United States on the courts as moral national political institution, might we not enact more direct political
arbiters oflast resort, and call for moral politics to break out of its judicial reforms aimed not at short-term, potentially paternalistic enlightenment
cage and into the general public sphere. But as many of their defenders, but at the long-term empowerment of the citizenry to enlighten, in fact,
not to mention their detractors, have noted, Gutmann's and Thompson's to rule, itself?
book makes relatively few positive institutional suggestions; in fact, the The empirical record for deliberative institutions modeled on an indi-
whole book seems at times to be a demonstrative exercise in deliberative vidual level is not encouraging. 13 However, for institutions seeking delib-
reasoning itself. eration at the level of a historical public sphere, there are some promising
One reason Gutmann and Thompson may have shied away from mak- new findings. A recent and fine example of this sort of political science is
ing concrete institutional suggestions for improving the deliberative cli- the work by Margaret Keck and Kathryn Sikkink on transnational advo-
mate is the sheer implausibility of some of the proposals already on the cacy groups (1998). They argue that a new, important, and poorly under-
table. The least implausible, most well-researched and well-documented stood entity has emerged in international politics: transnational advocacy
innovation in deliberative institution-making is James Fishkin's project networks. These networks, linking activists in different countries inter-
of deliberative polling, which has been tried in the state of Texas, and ested in moral causes such as human rights and environmental protection,
nationally in the US and UK. While deliberative polling has produced can be shown to have concrete political effects under certain conditions.
some very interesting findings, such as the finding that ordinary citizens Keck and Sikkink identify, for example, a set of conditions leading to a
of the state of Texas are quite willing to trade higher energy prices for "boomerang effect," in which domestic activists faced with an unrespon-
more environmentally friendly and sustainable energy policies, it has also sive government are able to work with international activists who put
been criticized as ineffective. Studying the "Grenada 500" deliberative pressure on their more responsive home governments, which in turn are
poll during the 1992 general election in Great Britain, David Denver and able effectively to pressure the originally unresponsive state (13) . What
his colleagues (1995) conclude that two problems plagued the effort: sets transnational advocacy networks apart from more traditional political
a persistent problem with unrepresentative samples, and the failure of agents is primarily their commitment to "principled ideas," which they
the deliberative experience to deliver on its promises. Fishkin and his
13 Not only are the empirical prospects grim, but even the theoretical prospects for deliber-
12
This is why Mansbridge bases her version of provisionalism on the Kantian notion of a ative institutions on the time scale contemplated are not at all encouraging. For a nicely
"regulative principle." reasoned effort in that direction, see Ferejohn (2000) .
372 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 373

use to attempt to change perceptions of interest among more powerful included. Provisional theory in all three modes - historical, rational, and
actors (30). Keck and Sikkink use classic comparative methodology to empirical - is therefore needed to address the questions raised by the
examine their object of inquiry, setting up structured comparisons, for political world as it really exists.
example, between failed and successful campaigns by advocacy groups
(202 and passim). The logic of transnational advocacy groups' activity,
however, was set out years ago by Kant in his theory of the concrete polit- REFERENCES
ical effects of speech in the public sphere (Habermas 1989; Ellis forth- Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago
coming). Keck and Sikkink's empirical findings on the effectiveness of Press.
transnational advocacy groups complements recent work in neo-Kantian Benhabib, Seyla (ed.). 1996. Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries
of the Political. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
political philosophy on the norm of reciprocity and its political function
Bohman, James. 1997. "Deliberative Democracy and Effective Social Freedom:
(Rawls 1996; Gutmann and Thompson 1996). Keck and Sikkink's empir- Capabilities, Resources, and Opportunities," in Bohman and Rehg (eds.),
ical findings about the transcultural value of the concept of human dignity pp. 321-48.
(as opposed to human rights) has interesting implications for liberal theo- Bohman, James and William Rehg (eds.). 1997. Deliberative Democracy: Essays on
ries of overlapping consensus. In fact, Keck and Sikkink themselves draw Reason and Politics. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press.
!I I some broad and interesting theoretical conclusions from their empirical Brunner, Otto, Werner Conze, and Reinhart Koselleck (eds.). 1972-.
findings: "liberalism carries within it not the seeds of its destruction, but Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe: historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache
in Deutschland. 8 vols. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.
the seeds of its expansion. Liberalism, with all its historical shortcom-
Burns, Nancy, Kay Lehman Schlozman, and Sidney Verba. 2001. The Private
ings, contains a subversive element that plays into the hands of activists" Roots of Public Action: Gender, Equality, and Political Participation. Cambridge,
(1998: 205). MA: Harvard University Press.
Attention to the empirical literature on the dynamics of the public Cohen, Joshua. 1997. "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in Bohman
sphere should, therefore, provide encouragement for deliberative theory and Rehg (eds.), pp. 67-92.
modeled on the longer term, while the paucity of evidence of short-term Daniels, Norman. 1999. "Enabling Democratic Deliberation: How Managed
individual-level opinion change under deliberative conditions should lead Care Organizations Ought to Make Decisions about Coverage for New Tech-
nologies," in Macedo (ed.), pp. 198-210.
traditional deliberative theorists to seek alternative mechanisms of politi-
iI Denver, David, Gordon Hands, and Bill Jones. 1995. "Fishkin and the Delib-
cal change. The long-run shifts in which arguments are politically possible
II!i'i
erative Opinion Poll: Lessons from a Study of the Granada 500 Television
to make in the public sphere are a far more promising avenue of inquiry Program." Political Communication 12: 147-56.
for provisional deliberative theory than the hoped-for short-run shifts in Dryzek, John S. 1990. Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science.
public opinion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
2000. Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations. Oxford
and New York: Oxford University Press.
Conclusion Ellis, Elisabeth. Forthcoming. Kant's Politics: Provisional Theory for an Uncertain
World. New Haven: Yale University Press.
As Hannah Arendt once wrote of an earlier debate in political science, Bister, Jon. 1997. "The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political
"The trouble with modern theories of behaviorism is not that they are Theory," in Bohman and Rehg (eds.), pp. 3-34.
wrong but that they could become true" (1958: 322). Lai tin's prediction Ferejohn, John. 2000. "Instituting Deliberative Democracy," in Designing Demo-
of a theory-free political science is not impossible, but for the science to cratic Institutions: Nomos XLII. New York: New York University Press. 75-
conform to its own standards, political life itself would have to change. It 104 .
is certainly possible to imagine historical contexts that are more and less Fiorina, Morris. 1999. "Extreme Voices: The Dark Side of Civic Engagement,"
in Civic Engagement and American Democracy. Skocpol and Fiorina (eds.).
"theory-friendly," so perhaps a world in which conflicts over constructed
Washington, DC: Brookings.
political ideals do not occur is not unthinkable. Thus far, however, politi- Fishkin, James S. 1991. Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic
cal science has not found such a world. In fact, as has been argued well by Reform. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
others (Green and Shapiro 1994; Kuhn 1970), particular and contestable 1995. The voice of the People: Public Opinion and Democracy. New Haven and
theoretical perspectives inform every school of research, political science London: Yale University Press.
374 Elisabeth Ellis Provisionalism in the study of politics 375

Fishkin, James S., Robert C. Luskin, and Roger Jowell. 2000. "Deliberative Sprache in Deutschland, 0. Brunner, W Conze, and R. Koselleck (eds.).
Polling and Public Consultation." Parliamentary Affairs 53: 657-66. Stuttgart: Ernst K.lett Verlag.
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Language, Counter-Memory, Practice. Ithaca, New York: 1985. Futures Past. Keith Tribe (trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cornell University Press. 1988. Critique and Crisis: Enlightenment and the Pathogenesis of Modern Society.
Galston, William A. 1999. "Diversity, Toleration, and Deliberative Oxford: Berg.
Democracy: Religious Minorities and Public Schooling," in Macedo (ed.), 1989. "Linguistic change and the History of Events." Journal ofModern History
pp. 39-48. 61: 649-66.
George, Robert P. 1999. "Law, Democracy, and Moral Disagreement: Reci- 2002. The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts. Todd
procity, Slavery, and Abortion," in Macedo (ed.), pp. 184-97. Samuel Presner et al. (trans). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Ginsburg, Ruth Bader. 2001. "In Pursuit of the Public Good: Access to Justice Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (2nd edn.) Chicago:
in the United States." Washington University Journal of Law and Policy 7: University of Chicago Press.
1-15. Kymlicka, Will. 1996. "Three Forms of Differentiated Citizenship in Canada,"
Green, Donald P. and Ian Shapiro. 1994. Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: in Benhabib (ed.), pp. 153-70.
A Critique of Application in Political Science. New Haven and London: Yale 2000. Politics in the U?rnacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism and Citizenship.
University Press. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. 1996. Democracy and Disagreement: W'hy Laitin, David D. 1998. "Toward a Political Science Discipline: Authority Patterns
Moral Conflict Cannot be Avoided in Politics, and W'hat Should be Done About Revisited." Comparative Political Studies 31(4): 423-43.
It. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. 2001a. "The Political Science Discipline." Remarks accompanying a paper
1999. "Democratic Disagreement," in Macedo (ed.), pp. 243-80. (Laitin 2001 b) delivered at the annual meeting of the American Political
2000. "Why Deliberative Democracy is Different." Social Philosophy and Policy Science Association, San Francisco, CA, September.
17(1) (Winter): 161-80. 2001 b. "The Political Science Discipline." Paper delivered at the annual
Habermas, Jurgen. 1973. "Wahrheitstheorien." In Wirklichkeit and Reflexion: Wal- meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco, CA,
ter Schultz zum 60. Geburtstag. Helmut Farhenbach (ed.). Pfiillingen: Neske. September.
1989. The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Cate- Macedo, Stephen (ed.). 1999. Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and
gory of Bourgeois Society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Disagreement. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
1992. Faktizitat und Geltung: Beitrage zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des Mansbridge, Jane. 1996. "Using Power/Fighting Power: the Polity," in Benhabib
demokratischen Rechtsstaats. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. (ed.), pp. 46-66.
1996. "Three Normative Models of Democracy," in Benhabib (ed.), pp. 21- 1999. "Everyday Talk in the Deliberative System," in Macedo (ed.), pp. 211-
30. 42.
1997. "Popular Sovereignty as Procedure," in Bohman and Rehg (eds.), Marcus, George E., W. Russell Neuman, and Michael MacKuen. 2000. Affec-
pp. 35-66. tive Intelligence and Political Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago
Isaac, Jeffrey C. 1995. "The Strange Silence of Political Theory." Political Theory Press.
23(4): 636-52. Marshall, T. H. 1964. Class, Citizenship, and Social Development: Essays. Garden
Kant, I. 1902-. Kants gesammelte Schriften. Preussischen Akademie der Wis- City, NY: Doubleday & Co.
senschaften. Berlin and Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter & Co. Pagden, Anthony. 1987. "Introduction," in The Languages of Political Theory in
Keck, Margaret E. and Kathryn Sikkink. 1998. Activists Beyond Borders: Advo- Early-Modern Europe. A. Pagden (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University
cacy Networks in International Politics. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.
Press. Phillipson, Nicholas and Quentin Skinner (eds.). 1993. Political Discourse in Early
Knight, Jack. 1999. "Constitutionalism and Deliberative Democracy," in Macedo Modern Britain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(ed.), pp. 159-69. Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel. 1972. Wittgenstein and Justice: On the Significance of
Knight, Jack, and James Johnson. 1994. "Aggregation and Deliberation: On Ludwig Wittgenstein for Social and Political Thought. Berkeley: University of
the Possibility of Democratic Legitimacy." Political Theory 22(2) (May): 277- California Press.
96. Pocock, J. G. A. 1987. "The Concept of a Language and the metier d'historien:
1997. "What Sort of Equality Does Deliberative Democracy Require?" in Some Considerations on Practice," in Pagden (ed.).
Bohman and Rehg (eds.), pp. 279-320. 1989. Politics, Language, and Time. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Koselleck, Reinhart. 1972-89. Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe and Introduc- Putnam, Robert D. 1993. "The Prosperous Community." The American Prospect
tion, in Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe: Historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen 4(13), March 21.
3 76 Elisabeth Ellis

1996. "Unsolved Mystery, the Tocqueville Files." The American Prospect 7 (25),
March 1 and April 1.
2000. Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community. New
York: Simon & Schuster.
17 What have we learned?
Putnam, Robert D., with Robert Leonardi, and Rafaella Y. Nanetti. 1993. Mak-
ing Democracy U:vrk: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy. Princeton: Princeton
University Press. Responses by Robert A. Dahl, Truman E Bewley,
Rae, Douglas. 1999. "Democratic Liberty and the Tyrannies of Place." in Shapiro Susanne Haeber Rudolph, and John Mearsheimer
and Hacker-Cordon (eds.), pp. 165-92.
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
1980. "Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory." The Journal of Philosophy
77(9): 515-73. Robert A. Dahl: Complexity, change, and contingency
1985. "Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical." Philosophy and Public I am simply going to set out, perhaps somewhat more dogmatically than
Affairs 14(3): 223-51.
is appropriate, a set of observations. I think some of you will disagree
1996. Political Liberalism (2nd edn). New York: Columbia University Press.
1997. "The Idea of Public Reason" and "Postscript," in Bohman and Rehg with some of them. Some of you may disagree with all of them. If it turns
(eds.), pp. 93-141. out that most or all of you agree with all of them, then I am wasting your
Richter, Melvin. 1989. "Understanding Begriffsgeschichte." Political Theory time and my own by being here.
17(2): 296-301. I begin with a question and observation: What is our subject? What is
1995. The History of Political and Social Concepts: A Critical Introduction. New political science? For those of you who have read some of my work over
York: Oxford University Press. the years it won't come as a surprise that my answer to the question is
Romer, Paul M. 1993. "Two Strategies for Economic Development: Using Ideas
this: political science is the systematic study of relations of power and
and Producing Ideas." Proceedings of the World Bank Annual Conference
on Development Economics 1992. 63-91. influence among human beings. My observation is: if you define political
Sandel, Michael J. 1998. Liberalism and the Limits ofJustice (2nd edn.) Cambridge: science in this way, then the study of politics is perhaps a subject of
Cambridge University Press. greater complexity than any other area of scholarly research, writing, and
Schauer, Frederick. 1999. "Talking as a Decision Procedure," in Macedo (ed.), teaching.
pp. 17-27. There are, I believe, at least three reasons why the study of politics is a
Shapiro, Ian. 1999a. "Enough of Deliberation: Politics is about Interests and subject of exceptional complexity.
Power," in Macedo (ed.), pp. 28-38.
First, consider the number of possible relations of power and influence
1999b. Democratic Justice. New Haven: Yale University Press.
1996. Democracy's Place. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press. among relevant units. Perform a simple-minded thought experiment:
Shapiro, Ian and Casiano Hacker-Cordon (eds.). 1999. Democracy's Edges. identify some of the possible relations of power and influence among
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. two people. You'd come up pretty quickly with a list of five possible rela-
Sunstein, Cass R. 1999. "Agreement without Theory," in Macedo (ed.), tions, maybe ten, maybe more; but let's be modest and settle for ten.
pp. 123-50. Now imagine ten people and once again assume, say, ten possible rela-
Young, Iris Marion. 1999. "Justice, Inclusion, and Deliberative Democracy," in tions of power and influence among them. Then go up to 100 people,
Macedo (ed.), pp. 151-58.
and the possible number of relationships. Perhaps you might now move
to 400 or 500 persons, which perhaps approaches the limit with which
we can interact with individual people. Now let's add relations between
individual persons and associations. Then proceed to relations among
groups and associations; now proceed to relations among individuals,
associations, and the special kind of association we call a state. Now
add international organizations. If you aren't already totally exhausted,

377

You might also like