Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 17

Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Cognition
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT

The Adams family


Igor Douven a,⇑, Sara Verbrugge b
a
Faculty of Philosophy, University of Groningen, The Netherlands
b
Department of Linguistics, University of Leuven, Belgium

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: According to Adams’s Thesis, the acceptability of an indicative conditional sentence goes by
Received 28 March 2009 the conditional probability of its consequent given its antecedent. We test, for the first
Revised 24 August 2010 time, whether this thesis is descriptively correct and show that it is not; in particular,
Accepted 26 August 2010
we show that it yields the wrong predictions for people’s judgments of the acceptability
of important subclasses of the class of inferential conditionals. Experimental results are
presented that reveal an interaction effect between, on the one hand, the type of inferential
Keywords:
connection between a conditional’s antecedent and its consequent and, on the other, the
Indicative conditionals
Adams’s Thesis
judged acceptability of the conditional in relation to the conditional probability of its con-
Acceptability sequent given its antecedent. Specifically, these results suggest a family of theses, each per-
Inferential conditionals taining to a different type of conditional, about how conditionals relate to the relevant
Conditional probability conditional probabilities.
! 2010 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

1. Introduction tion in this respect in that it is generally (even if not univer-


sally) believed to be at least descriptively correct. To a first
There is little that one can say about the semantics and approximation, the thesis asserts that the acceptability/
pragmatics of indicative conditional sentences that is not assertability of a conditional goes by the conditional proba-
highly controversial.1 Even such fundamental questions as bility of its consequent given its antecedent.
whether conditionals have truth conditions, and, if they Those who believe Adams’s Thesis to be descriptively
do, which is the right account of these conditions, are still correct cannot do so on the basis of any serious empirical
wide open today, despite their having been hotly debated research, for, surprisingly perhaps, the thesis has never
for several decades. Adams’s Thesis stands out as an excep- been subjected to experimental testing. In the present pa-
per, we address this lack and show that the thesis yields
⇑ Corresponding author. the wrong predictions of people’s judgments of the accept-
E-mail addresses: i.e.j.douven@rug.nl (I. Douven), sara.verbrugge@p- ability of important subclasses of the class of so-called
sy.kuleuven.be (S. Verbrugge). inferential conditionals. Experimental results, to be re-
1
Conditionals are sentences of the forms ‘‘If p, [then] q” and ‘‘q if p,” with ported below, reveal an interaction effect between, on
p called the antecedent and q, the consequent. The most general classifica-
the one hand, the type of inferential connection between
tion of such sentences distinguishes between indicative and subjunctive
conditionals. There is some debate about exactly what distinguishes these a conditional’s antecedent and its consequent and, on the
classes from one another. Some say that they differ in that the antecedents other hand, the judged acceptability of the conditional in
of subjunctive conditionals, but not those of indicative conditionals, are relation to the conditional probability of its consequent gi-
known or at least supposed to be false. Bennet (2003: p. 10) proposes a
ven its antecedent. Specifically, the results suggest a family
purely syntactic criterion, according to which the consequents of
subjunctive conditionals, but not those of indicative conditionals, have
of theses, each pertaining to a different type of conditional,
‘‘would” as the auxiliary of their main verb. Both claims may well be too about how conditionals relate to the relevant conditional
strong; see DeRose (2010). However this may be, in the present paper we probabilities; some of these theses are closely related to
shall only be concerned with clear cases of indicative conditionals. We use Adams’s original proposal, but others are at best remotely
‘‘conditional” (or ‘‘conditional sentence”) to refer to indicative conditionals
related.
throughout.

0010-0277/$ - see front matter ! 2010 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2010.08.015
I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318 303

We start, in Section 2, by introducing the typology of the joint truth of the second and third. Because the first
conditionals that will be deployed in our experiment. In deductive systems (logics) were aimed at formalizing the
Section 3, we state Adams’s Thesis more carefully and pro- notion of certain inference, certain inferences are also
vide some background to it by locating it within a broader called ‘‘deductive inferences”.4
approach to conditionals; there we also distinguish be- Since Peirce, the 19th-century pragmatist philosopher,
tween different versions of the thesis that may all have it is standard practice to group uncertain inferences into
their defenders. Section 4 describes some previous experi- inductive and abductive ones. Though this is presumably
mental work that is related to our own experiments, which not exactly how Peirce understood the notion, modern
are then presented in Sections 5–7. Finally, in Section 8, we authors typically mean by an abductive inference one in
draw some general conclusions from our empirical results. which the conclusion follows on the basis of explanatory
considerations, more particularly, because it is thought to
2. Classifying conditionals be the best explanation of something thought to be known.
An instance would be inferring that Kate has not had much
It has become customary for linguists to group condi- sleep lately from the known premise that she looks tired,
tionals into inferential and content conditionals.2 By the for- as the former would provide the best explanation of the
mer, they mean conditionals expressing a reasoning process, latter.5
or an inference, having the conditional’s antecedent as a pre- Inductive inferences form a more heterogeneous class.
mise and its consequent as the conclusion. Examples are: ‘‘If In this paper, by an inductive inference we shall mean
she looks tired, she has not had much sleep recently”; ‘‘If he one in which the conclusion follows with a certain statisti-
lives in Chelsea, he must be rich”; and ‘‘If the village is cal probability from the premises, but various other types
flooded, the dam must have broken.” The class of content of inductive inference have been described in the litera-
conditionals seems to be less well delineated. Its members ture.6 An example of what we mean by inductive inference
are sometimes loosely defined as describing relations be- is the inference of ‘‘Louise speaks at least two languages”
tween states of affairs or events as they happen in reality, from the premises ‘‘97 per cent of the Belgian college stu-
but examples adduced in the literature suggest a rather dents speak at least two languages” (or ‘‘Most Belgian col-
mixed bag, including such diverse conditionals as condi- lege students speak at least two languages”) and ‘‘Louise is
tional threats and promises as well as conditionals like ‘‘If a Belgian college student.”
you run fast, you’ll be out of breath” and ‘‘If she works hard, Corresponding to this typology, we shall say that q is a
she will pass the exam.” Whether the distinction between deductive/inductive/abductive consequence of p iff q can
inferential and content conditionals is well founded, and in be inferred deductively/inductively/abductively from p.
particular whether at least some of the conditionals classi- For later purposes, we notice that, whereas for deduc-
fied as content conditionals in the literature are not better tive inferences the conditional probability of the
thought of as reflecting an inference from antecedent to con- conclusion given the conjunction of the premises will
sequent, too, will not concern us here.3 What matters for our be high – even 1 – for inductive and abductive infer-
purposes is that many conditionals encountered in collo- ences this need not be the case. For inductive inferences,
quial speech fall into the class of inferential conditionals. this will be clear. For instance, one may infer ‘‘John is
For many authors, the distinction between inferential rich” from ‘‘John lives in Chelsea” and ‘‘60 per cent of
and content conditionals only serves as a starting point. the people living in Chelsea are rich,” but the probability
Various finer-grained typologies have been proposed, of the first sentence conditional on the conjunction of
especially of inferential conditionals. These typologies are the second and third is only .6. (This may be precisely
almost invariably based on grammatical distinctions. Here, the probability one ought attach to the conclusion of
we want to introduce a different typology of inferential the inference, but we leave these normative issues to
conditionals, one that classifies them according to the type one side here; see, for instance, Kyburg (1990) for a use-
of inference they embody. ful discussion.) As to abductive inferences, suppose you
Philosophers have traditionally distinguished between know that Tom and Hank have recently had a flaming
certain and uncertain inferences. In certain inferences, the row that ended their friendship. Now someone tells
truth of what is inferred is guaranteed by the truth of the you she thinks that she just saw Tom and Hank jogging
premises from which it is inferred. Not all inferences are together. It seems to you that the best explanation for
of this variety, as witness, for instance, the inference of
‘‘John is rich” from ‘‘John lives in Chelsea” and ‘‘Most peo- 4
Mostly this name is used for inferences in which the truth of the
ple living in Chelsea are rich.” The truth of the first sen- conclusion is guaranteed by the truth of the premises purely on the basis of
tence is clearly not guaranteed, but only made likely, by logical form. This guarantee can also come from meaning, however, as in
the inference of ‘‘a is not green all over” from ‘‘a is red all over.” We mean
deductive inference to be understood so as to include the latter type of
2
See, among others, Dancygier (1998, 2003), Dancygier and Sweetser inference as well.
5
(2005), Declerck and Reed (2001), and Haegeman (2003). For relevant See Fann (1970) and Hookway (1985, chap. 7) for some thorough
experimental results, see Verbrugge, Dieussaert, Schaeken, Smessaert, and discussions of Peirce’s notion of abduction. The notion of abduction as it is
Van Belle (2007). currently for the most part understood originates in Harman (1965). See
3
It is worth mentioning that, on our understanding, every conditional Douven (2010a) for a survey of the literature on abduction.
6
that may plausibly be thought of as reflecting a reasoning process will For an excellent overview of the distinct kinds of inductive inference,
qualify as an inferential conditional. Thus understood, the class of the reader is referred to Kyburg (1990, chap. 4). It should also be mentioned
inferential conditionals may well include conditionals that some linguists that some authors interpret inductive inference so widely that it even
would rather classify as content conditionals. encompasses abductive inference; see, e.g., Harman (1999: p. 29).
304 I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

this is that they are friends again. This does not neces- (3) If Tom and Hank are jogging together, then they are
sarily mean that you think it likely that they are friends friends again,
again conditional on the assumption that they are jog-
when the background knowledge about Tom and Hank gi-
ging together. What will be the case – we may suppose
ven a few paragraphs back is assumed. But in Bennet’s
– is that you find this explanation more likely than any
(2003: p. 340) example
of the alternative possible explanations for their jogging
again.7
Our proposal now is to group inferential conditionals (4) If the umbrella is not in the closet, my memory is
according to the type of inference that they reflect – deduc- failing,
tive, inductive, or abductive. So, p ? q is a deductive infer-
ential (or DI, for short)/inductive inferential (II)/abductive where the speaker has an apparent memory of putting his
inferential (AI) conditional iff q is a deductive/inductive/ umbrella in the closet and no memory of removing it, the
abductive consequence of p. (Throughout the paper, we best explanation for the apparent memory, at least if the
shall use ‘‘p ? q” to stand for the conditional with anteced- umbrella is not in the closet (as the antecedent says), is
ent p and consequent q.) that the speaker’s memory is failing. In other words, here
The three types of conditional have corresponding ‘‘con- the consequent is not the best explanation of the anteced-
textual” versions: ent, but rather of a background premise – though the con-
A sentence p ? q is a contextual DI/II/AI conditional iff q sequent is only the best explanation of that premise if the
is a deductive/inductive/abductive consequence of umbrella is not in the closet.
{p, p1, . . ., pn}, with p1, . . ., pn being background premises We have not been aiming for completeness here, and
salient in the context in which p ? q is asserted or want to leave open the possibility that there exist condition-
being evaluated. als that are plausibly regarded as expressing reasoning pro-
cesses but that do not fall into any of our categories. In
effect, this is already so because, as intimated, we are not
For instance, considering all forms of inductive inference that have been
distinguished in the literature. This being said, however, we
(1) If Chelsea wins the Champions League in 2011, then do believe that the aforementioned categories capture large
that will be a first in the club’s history classes of inferential conditionals, and important ones at that
is not a DI conditional in the strict sense: the consequent (as we aim to demonstrate experimentally). Furthermore, it
does not follow deductively from ‘‘Chelsea wins the Cham- may well be possible to refine the typology. For instance, a
pions League in 2011.” But it does follow deductively from natural refinement of the class of AI conditionals would con-
that sentence together with the (true) premise that so far sider the type of explanation involved. Often explaining is a
Chelsea has never been able to win the Champions League; matter of highlighting causal structure, but philosophers of
that makes (1) a contextual DI conditional, supposing that science have argued that this is not always so.9
the said premise is salient in the context in which the sen- 3. Epistemic theories of conditionals and Adams’s Thesis
tence is uttered or evaluated. Likewise,
(2) If John is a second-year psychology student, he has Epistemic theories of conditionals constitute a pres-
passed his statistics exam ently popular approach to theorizing about conditionals.
is not an II conditional taken by itself, but it is in a context The characteristic commonality of these theories is that
where, for instance, ‘‘Hardly any of the second-year psy- they make the acceptability/assertability of a conditional
chology students failed their statistics exam” is a salient dependent on the holding (or otherwise) of an epistemi-
background premise. In practice, we may more often cally significant relationship between the conditional’s
encounter contextual inferential conditionals than non- antecedent and its consequent.10 This relationship is typi-
contextual ones. This seems particularly true for II and AI cally one to the effect that a change in a person’s epistemic
conditionals.8 position vis-à-vis a conditional’s antecedent puts her, or
As to contextual AI conditionals, it should be noted that the
consequent need not refer to the best explanation of the 9
See, e.g., Kitcher (1981) and De Regt and Dieks (2005). To forestall
antecedent. It may, and presumably often will, do so, as in misunderstanding, it must be noted that what Over, Hadjichristidis, Evans,
Handley, and Sloman (2007) call ‘‘causal conditionals” are not necessarily
AI conditionals in which the explanatory connection between antecedent
7
There is an ongoing debate in the philosophy of science about the and consequent is at bottom a causal connection. Such conditionals need
relation between abductive and probabilistic reasoning; see, among many not be AI conditionals at all. For instance, their example ‘‘If the cost of petrol
others, van Fraassen (1989, chap. 7), Douven (1999, 2010a, Section 4), increases, then traffic congestion will improve” (p. 63), which they regard
Lipton (2004, chap. 7), Tregear (2004), and Weisberg (2009). as a causal conditional because there is evidence for the existence of a
8
However, it would be wrong to think that noncontextual II and AI causal relation between its antecedent and consequent, is presumably not
conditionals are impossible. For instance, ‘‘If most psychology students had an AI conditional – only given some rather unnatural assumptions about
at least a B for the statistics exam and John is a psychology student, then the context could an improvement of traffic congestion best explain an
John had at least a B for the statistics exam” could be an example of a increase of the cost of petrol – and is more plausibly read as being either a
noncontextual II conditional – ‘‘could be,” because this sentence might be DI or an II conditional, depending on the exact details of the context.
10
asserted in a context in which certain background premises are salient In the present context, ‘‘acceptability” is typically understood as
which are relevant to the interpretation of the sentence and which might, meaning justified (rational, reasonable) believability. There is currently
for instance, make it a DI conditional (like the premise that John is so smart no unanimity about how it relates to assertability; see Williamson (1996,
that his grades always place him in the top 10% of his peer group). 2000) and Douven (2006, 2009) for different views on this matter.
I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318 305

would put her, in a certain epistemic position vis-à-vis that tween the two proposals, also related to Adams’s non-propo-
conditional’s consequent, all else remaining equal.11,12 An sitional view on conditionals, is that, while in Adams’s Thesis
example of such a theory would be one according to which Pr(qjp) is to stand for a person’s subjective conditional proba-
p ? q is acceptable to/assertable for a person iff the person’s bility for q given p, Pr(p ? q) is not to be interpreted as the
coming to know p would place her in the position to know q probability that the conditional is true, but rather as the de-
(if she is not already in that position); or it could be held that gree of assertability or acceptability of the conditional.16 For
p ? q is acceptable/assertable iff, or to the extent that, what this reason, Jackson (1987: p. 11) states Adams’s Thesis as As(-
would justify the person in believing p would also justify her p ? q) = Pr(qjp). Because in our experiments we focus on
in believing q; or that it is acceptable/assertable iff the per- acceptability, we prefer to state it as
son’s subjective probability for q conditional on p, but not
Acðp ! qÞ ¼ PrðqjpÞ; ðATÞ
the unconditional probability of q, exceeds a given threshold
value. Many other epistemic connections could be, and have with p ? q being a simple conditional and with again the
been, considered; see, among others, Adams (1975), Lewis proviso that Pr(p) > 0.
(1976), Jackson (1979, 1987), Mellor (1993), Edgington We have five comments on this proposal. First, Adams
(1995), Bennett (2003), Rescher (2007), and Douven officially relates only assertability to conditional probabil-
(2008a). In the following, we focus on Adams’s theory, which ity, and not acceptability; see in particular his (1965).
is among the most popular epistemic theories. However, a reference to personal communication in Hájek
Stalnaker (1970) famously proposed that we identify and Hall (1994: p. 77) makes it clear that Adams does
the probability of a conditional with the probability of (also) conceive of Pr(qjp) as measuring the acceptability
the consequent, conditional on the antecedent, that is, of p ? q. This, at any rate, is how Adams is nowadays com-
monly interpreted.17,18
Prðp ! qÞ ¼ PrðqjpÞ; ðEqÞ
Second, we can speak about acceptability as well as
with the proviso that Pr(p) > 0.13 This proposal is often re- about assertability both in a categorical or qualitative
ferred to as ‘‘the Equation”.14 Just as famously, the proposal way and in a graded or quantitative way. It makes good
was shown to be untenable by a number of ‘‘triviality re- sense to say that a sentence is acceptable/assertable, but
sults” due to Lewis (1976, 1986), Hájek (1989, 1994), Döring it makes equally good sense to say that a sentence is highly
(1994), Hall (1994), and others. For instance, one of Lewis’s (or moderately, or hardly) acceptable/assertable, or that it
results shows that if (Eq) held, then it would also have to is acceptable/assertable to a certain degree, as well as that
hold that the conditional probability of q given p equals one sentence is more acceptable/assertable than a second.
the probability of q for all p and q. Surely this is absurd; it Clearly, (AT) has its natural home in the graded accounts of
is rather unlikely that Chelsea will do badly in next year’s acceptance and assertion. Indeed, as Lewis (1976: p. 133 f)
Premier League, but it is not quite so unlikely that they will points out, insofar as it pertains to assertion, (AT) is a nat-
do badly if they lose their six top players. ural extension to conditionals (which, as intimated, do not
Adams’s proposal – now commonly called ‘‘Adams’s The- express propositions according to Adams) of the idea that
sis” – looks, in his own presentations of it, very similar to the assertability of a proposition equals its probability. It
(Eq), the only obvious difference being that the former is re- merits remark that, by itself, a graded view of assertion is
stricted to ‘‘simple” conditionals, that is, unembedded con- not in conflict with the currently popular knowledge ac-
ditionals whose antecedent and consequent do not embed count of assertion, according to which a sentence is asser-
conditionals. The restriction is necessitated by the fact that, table only if one knows it (Williamson, 1996, 2000). If
for Adams, conditionals do not express propositions (they do
not possess classical truth conditions), which has as a conse- 16
It is to be noted that degrees of assertability or acceptability are not to
quence that, unlike (Eq), Adams’s Thesis does not succumb be conceived of as providing a different interpretation of the probability
to the said triviality results.15 A less obvious difference be- operator. They simply do not obey the probability calculus; see, e.g., McGee
(1987: p. 485) and Hájek and Hall (1994: p. 77).
17
See, e.g., McGee (1987: p. 485): ‘‘The numerical values [Adams assigns
11
Cf. Gärdenfors (1988: p. 147): ‘‘[C]onditional sentences in various forms to conditionals] accurately measure the assertability and acceptability of
are about changes of states of belief.” conditionals . . .” See also Mellor (1993: p. 233): ‘‘The Adams’s Thesis . . . is
12
The ceteris paribus clause is meant to take care of such conditionals as that my degree of acceptance of a conditional ‘If P, Q’ is equal to my
‘‘If Reagan worked for the KGB, no one will ever find out.” Here, an conditional credence in Q given P,” where by ‘‘conditional credence” Mellor
epistemic change vis-à-vis the antecedent might lead one to give up the means conditional subjective probability; Arló-Costa (2001, Section 3), who
conditional rather than to change one’s epistemic attitude vis-à-vis the likewise states Adams’s Thesis directly in terms of acceptance; and the
consequent; see van Fraassen (1980). quote from Bennett (2003) in the text below.
13 18
The proviso is unimportant, as conditionals are ‘‘zero-intolerant,” A reviewer remarked that it is odd to suppose that conditionals can be
meaning that ‘‘nobody has any use for p ? q when for him Pr(p) = 0” acceptable in the sense of being justifiedly credible if they do not have truth
(Bennet (2003: p. 55); notation altered for uniformity of reading). conditions, given that to believe is to believe to be true. This is in fact one of
14
Other names for it that one encounters in the literature are ‘‘Stalnaker’s the two main objections that have been levelled against Adams’s view, the
Thesis” (e.g., van Fraassen, 1976) and ‘‘Conditional Construal of Conditional other being Lewis’s (1976: p. 141f) objection that, on Adams’s view, it is
Probability” (e.g., Hájek & Hall, 1994). hard to make sense of Boolean combinations of conditionals and other
15
To escape Lewis’s triviality results, the restriction of (Eq) to simple sentences (conditional or non-conditional); see Douven (in press, Sec-
conditionals – leaving open the possibility that they express propositions – tion 1.2) for more on these objections. Adams (1998, chap. 8), and
would be enough. However, Hájek (1989)’s triviality result does not assume Edgington (2005) contain responses to the former objection. For present
embeddability of conditionals (it does assume that conditionals express purposes, it is immaterial whether or not these responses are fully
propositions). McGee (1989) is an attempt to extend Adams’s Thesis to satisfactory; our aim, after all, is not to defend Adams. To the contrary,
compounds of conditionals. Lance (1991) argues that the attempt fails; this the results to be presented show that his proposal is, at least in its original
also follows from results presented in Dietz and Douven (2010). formulation, descriptively inadequate.
306 I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

categorical assertability is identified with assertability to Lastly, we note that, as it stands, (AT) is very strict in
the highest degree, and a sentence is held to be assertable that it requires the acceptability or assertability of a condi-
to the highest degree iff it has probability 1, then the tional to equal the corresponding conditional probability.
knowledge account of assertion is even a limiting case of But clearly, one can acknowledge that acceptability/asser-
the graded account of assertion if it is also held – as for in- tability is a matter of degree, and also subscribe to the
stance Williamson does – that one should assign probabil- thought that, at least in general, the acceptability/asserta-
ity 1 to a sentence iff one knows the sentence. The same bility of a conditional ‘‘goes by” its conditional probability
goes, mutatis mutandis, for a graded account of (as Lewis (1976: p. 133) puts it), without having to sub-
acceptability. scribe to a strict equality between Ac(p ? q) and Pr(qj p),
Third, (AT) is supposed to hold generally, not unexcep- as (AT) postulates, or even to this slightly weaker version
tionally. Adherents of the thesis will readily admit that a of the thesis:22
conditional whose corresponding conditional probability
is high may, for Gricean or more broadly social reasons, Acðp ! qÞ # PrðqjpÞ: ðWAT1Þ
still have a low degree of assertability. However, these rea- What are apparently meant as paraphrases of (AT) in
sons only pertain to assertability, not to acceptability. (Be- the literature suggest that various authors also conceive
lief is, for instance, not subject to social norms of of the relevant connection in a looser way. Purportedly
politeness.) They may thus be ignored for the purposes of stating Adams’s view – with which he proclaims to agree
our studies, which focused on the acceptability, and not – Bennet (2003: p. 46) writes: ‘‘[T]he assertability or
the assertability, of conditionals. acceptability of p ? q for a person at a time is governed
Fourth, what is the status of (AT)? Is it meant as a nor- by the probability the person then assigns to q on the sup-
mative thesis, or is it supposed to be descriptively correct, position of p” (notation altered for uniformity of reading;
or both? Adams and others have pointed to various advan- italics ours). This can be interpreted in a number of ways.
tages for philosophical theorizing that adopting (AT) would For instance, Bennett might have in mind something like
have.19 Clearly, however, that is not enough to make the
thesis normatively compelling, and we are unaware of any Acðp ! qÞ is high=middling=low iff PrðqjpÞ is high=middling=low:
explicit claims that the thesis is thus compelling. By con- ðWAT2Þ
trast, as already noted at the outset, several authors have
explicitly claimed that (AT) is descriptively correct (or at This, in any event, is the version of Adams’s Thesis that
least that some thesis in its vicinity is correct; see below). McGee (1989: p. 487 f) aims to defend; he thinks that, thus
For instance, according to McGee (1989: p. 485) ‘‘[Adams’s] interpreted, Adams’s Thesis ‘‘displays uncanny accuracy”
theory describes what English speakers assert and accept (p. 488).23 Alternatively, Bennett’s assertion that Ac(p ? q)
with unfailing accuracy . . .”20 Equally, Jackson (1987: p. is governed by Pr(qjp) could be taken to mean that
17) states that ‘‘Adams’s Thesis is massively supported by
Acðp ! qÞ highly correlates with PrðqjpÞ; ðWAT3Þ
the empirical evidence relating to our actual use of indica-
tive conditionals”.21 In fact, as Evans, Handley, and Over or perhaps even just that
(2003: p. 323) also observe, Ramsey (1931: p. 247n), in the
footnote which is generally taken to have inspired (AT), Acðp ! qÞ at least moderately correlates with PrðqjpÞ:
was clearly trying to give a phenomenologically plausible
ðWAT4Þ
account of the kind of process people go through to deter-
mine the probability of a conditional (as well as the corre- (Presumably on no plausible reading of ‘‘being governed
sponding conditional probability). So a descriptive reading by” could Ac(p ? q) be said to be governed by Pr(qjp) if
of (AT) is, in any case, appropriate (next to a normative there is but a weak correlation between them.)
one, perhaps). Note, however, that experimental findings, We thus seem to have a family of Adams’s Theses. Nat-
whether confirming or disconfirming (AT), are relevant urally, if (AT) holds, then so do (WAT1)–(WAT4). But any of
either way. Even if (AT) were only, or primarily, meant to these latter theses might hold without (AT) holding. There
be normatively compelling, it would still be valuable to is also the possibility that different theses hold for different
know whether and, if so, to what extent ordinary people restricted domains. For instance, one thesis might hold for
comply with it, just as psychologists have found it valuable DI conditionals, a second for II conditionals, and a third for
to investigate whether people comply with the laws of logic AI conditionals. A key objective of our experiments was to
or probability theory. investigate whether this possibility obtains. Before going
into the experiments, we briefly discuss some recent re-
19
lated work.
See, e.g., Adams (1965, 1975, 1998) and Hájek and Hall (1994).
20
See also the citation from the same paper in note 17.
21 22
See also Jackson (19787: p. 12): ‘‘There is a great deal of evidence for We take it to be understood that in (WAT1), and also in the further
[(AT)]. There is head-counting evidence. Very many philosophers of variants of (AT) to be stated below in the text, p ? q stands for a simple
otherwise differing opinions have found [(AT)] highly intuitive. There is conditional.
23
case-by-case evidence. Take a conditional which is highly assertible . . . ; it Hájek and Hall (1994: p. 101) think that, while (WAT2) may be
will invariably be one whose consequent is highly probable given its plausible, it is not very interesting, given that ‘‘it seems unlikely that it
antecedent.” Edgington, who shares Adams’s view on conditionals, is, as a could play a very useful role in the development of probability logic, or in
noteworthy exception, much more cautious on this point. She says: ‘‘It is an other philosophical projects.” Clearlly, insofar as one’s interest is in the
empirical question how well [(AT)] fits our practice of assessing condition- descriptive adequacy of (AT) or any of its variants, such considerations are
als . . .” (1995: p. 280). beside the point.
I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318 307

4. Related experimental work than their probability of truth. That is what we set out to do
in our own experiments.
Contrary to what Bradley’s and McGee’s earlier-cited The different focus of our work raises a noteworthy
claims would seem to suggest, neither (AT) nor any of the methodological issue. The notion of acceptability as it fig-
mentioned variants have yet been investigated experimen- ures in Adams’s work is clearly meant as an epistemic no-
tally. Still, in the past decade Jonathan Evans and David Over, tion: a statement is acceptable in Adams’s sense if and to
together with various collaborators, have been doing the extent that it is reasonable to believe. However, it can-
impressive experimental work on the related (Eq); see for not be ruled out that, when asked to grade the acceptabil-
instance, Hadjichristidis et al. (2001), Evans, Handley, and ity of a statement, one might take the question to pertain
Over (2003), Over and Evans (2003), Evans and Over to the social acceptability of the statement. For instance,
(2004), Evans, Handley, Neilens, and Over (2007), Over a statement, even if deemed acceptable epistemically
et al. (2007), Over and Evans (2010), Politzer, Over, and Bar- speaking, might be socially unacceptable in that it would
atgin (in press).24 In all their studies, they found a high corre- be an impolite or irrelevant or otherwise inappropriate
lation between the probabilities that participants assigned to thing to say in a conversation. Our second experiment
a set of conditionals and the corresponding conditional prob- had the specific purpose of verifying that the participants
abilities, thereby providing strong support for (Eq).25 had understood the question about the acceptability of
In none of the aforementioned studies were the partic- conditionals in the intended – epistemic – sense.
ipants asked to grade the acceptability of the conditionals; As mentioned, considerations deriving from the Lottery
the question each time was how probable it is that the con- Paradox do not conclusively exclude that acceptability goes
ditional is true. Of course, this might ipso facto have elic- by probability. It might thus be that, as a matter of fact, par-
ited the participants’ acceptability judgments, in which ticipants’ judgments of the acceptability of a given condi-
case the said studies would have provided empirical sup- tional coincide with their judgments of the probability of
port for (AT) as well. However, the past three decades have truth of that conditional. To see whether this is the case,
witnessed a surge of interest in the relation between we conducted a third experiment in which we asked partic-
acceptability and subjective probability, and philosophers ipants to grade conditionals according to their probability of
have offered various reasons for doubting that they are truth and compared the results with those of our main
as closely related as was once assumed. The best known experiment, which pertained to acceptability. The differ-
reason derives from the so-called Lottery Paradox (Kyburg, ences in the outcomes lend further support to the thesis that
1961). Suppose you own a ticket – say, ticket # 14 – in acceptability is not (fully) determined by probability.
what you know to be a fair lottery consisting of There are two further ways that deserve mentioning in
1,000,000 tickets, only one of which is going to win. Then which our experiments differed from those of Evans, Over,
while, prior to the drawing, ‘‘Ticket # 14 won’t win” is and their collaborators. First, the latter almost invariably
highly probable, it cannot be highly acceptable. For if it presented contexts in which probabilities were specified
were, then presumably each element of the set {‘‘Ticket # for all logical possibilities; participants were then asked
i won’t win”j i=1, . . . ,1,000,000} would be highly accept- to judge the probabilities of conditionals relevantly related
able, these sentences being equiprobable. Patently, though, to these contexts and were also asked to judge the corre-
if you were to actually accept all of them, your resulting sponding conditional probabilities. However, the mental
belief state would be inconsistent, given that you know arithmetic these participants had thereby to complete
that the lottery has a winner. Hence, acceptability does was later feared to have created artifacts in the data; see
not go by probability – or so a majority of philosophers Evans and Over (2004: p. 140). To prevent this kind of
who have considered the issue hold.26 Admittedly, the Lot- problem, we used context descriptions that did not involve
tery Paradox involves a rather peculiar type of sentences. any numerical information but instead used what logicians
Still, the foregoing argument does give grounds to not sim- call ‘‘generalized quantifiers” – terms such as ‘‘all,” ‘‘most,”
ply assuming the truth of (AT) on the basis of Evans and ‘‘almost all,” ‘‘practically never,” and so on – to provide sta-
Over’s work on (Eq) and to test (AT) on its own, by asking tistical information whenever that was required by the
participants to grade the acceptability of conditionals, rather purpose of the studies. Second, we tested Adams’s theory
of conditionals specifically in connection with the typology
of inferential conditionals introduced earlier. Therefore,
24
our test items were selected so as to make our tests consist
For related work by other researchers, see Oaksford and Chater (2003),
Oberauer and Wilhelm (2003), Weidenfeld, Oberauer, and Horning (2005), of equal numbers of DI, II, and AI conditionals.
Oberauer, Weidenfeld, and Fischer (2007), and Pfeifer and Kleiter (2010).
25
In view of the triviality arguments mentioned earlier, Evans and Over’s 5. Experiment 1
results may appear puzzling. After all, the triviality arguments show
precisely that (Eq) cannot hold if Pr(p ? q) is interpreted as the probability
One objective of our first experiment was to investigate
that p ? q is true. It would thus seem that even if the participants’
subjective probabilities appear to obey (Eq), they cannot really do so. For the relationship between the acceptability of inferential
responses to this puzzle, arguing (though along different lines) that there is conditionals and the corresponding conditional probabili-
no real tension between the triviality arguments and the said experimental ties. In particular, we were interested in whether Adams’s
results, see Edgington (2003) and Evans and Over (2004: p. 28 ff); but see proposal is descriptively correct, as several philosophers
also Dietz and Douven (in press).
26
See, e.g., Lehrer (1974, 1986, 1990), Kaplan (1981a, 1981b, 1996),
have claimed. Another objective was to investigate whether
Pollock (1987, 1990), Ryan (1996), Evnine (1999), Nelkin (2000), Adler there are significant differences between acceptability and
(2002), Douven and Williamson (2006), and Douven (2008b). probability ratings for the three types of conditionals.
308 I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

Adams’s own theory predicts that this will not be so. After Very unlikely 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Very likely
all, his theory makes no reference to the types of inference
that may be involved in the reasoning process expressed The following are instances of the first schema, of one of our
by a conditional. Thus, Adams and his followers must be tac- DI items, one of our II items, and one of our AI items, respec-
itly assuming, or in any event are committed to the view, tively; the corresponding examples of the questions asking for
that either our typology is irrelevant to matters having to the conditional probability can be read from the second schema
do with the acceptability/assertability of conditionals or above. (For the full materials, see Appendix A.)
any influence the type which an inferential conditional be-
longs to may have on its acceptability/assertability is al- (DI) Context: All students in class 6C have at least a B for
ready accounted for by whatever factors go into the their math test paper.
determination of the corresponding conditional probability. Conditional: If Ben is in class 6C, then he has at least
Either assumption would be proven wrong if we found sig- a B for his math test paper.
nificant differences between, say, how acceptability ratings Indicate how acceptable you find this conditional in
of DI conditionals relate to probability ratings of such condi- the given context:
tionals and, on the other hand, how these different ratings Highly unacceptable 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Highly acceptable
relate to one another in the case of AI or II conditionals. (II) Context: According to a recent report written on the
authority of the Dutch government, many primary
5.1. Method
school students in the province of Friesland (where
many people still mainly speak Frisian) have difficulty
5.1.1. Participants
with spelling. Jitske is a student of a primary school
Sixty-seven students of the University of Leuven partic-
somewhere in the Netherlands.
ipated in the experiment as part of a course requirement.
Conditional: If Jitske goes to a Frisian primary
5.1.2. Design school, then she has difficulty with spelling.
The question concerning probability and the question
concerning acceptability were manipulated between sub- Etc.
jects. The type of inferential conditional was manipulated (AI) Context: You strongly doubt that Hank will have
within subjects. passed the first-year examination. You suspect that
his parents will buy him a car only if he passed that
5.1.3. Materials and procedure examination. You suddenly see Hank driving a new car.
All materials were in Dutch, the participants’ mother Conditional: If the car Hank is driving is his, then he
tongue. Thirty items consisting of context–sentence pairs passed the first-year examination.
were presented in a booklet. Ten of the sentences were
DI conditionals, ten were AI conditionals, and ten were II Etc.
conditionals. Each participant had to evaluate all items.
Items were randomized per booklet and the booklets were In determining conditional probabilities in the above
randomly distributed in the lecture hall. way, we followed Hadjichristidis et al. (2001). Another
The participants were divided into two groups. We method, suggested by the ratio definition of conditional
asked one group to judge the acceptability of conditionals probability, would be to determine Pr(qj p) by determining
and another to judge the corresponding conditional proba- Pr(p ^ q) and Pr(p) and dividing the former by the latter (cf.
bilities. To be more precise, one group (N = 30) was given Over et al. (2007: p. 67)). For reasons given in Edgington
30 questions of the following form (i 2 {1, . . . , 30}): (1995: p. 266 f) and (1997: p. 108 f), it would be wrong
to think that the latter way of determining conditional
Context Ci probabilities is mandatory, or in any case, to be preferred
pi ? qi to the former. In fact, the former way is clearly much closer
How acceptable is this statement in context Ci? to Ramsey’s proposal for determining conditional probabil-
ities, hinted at earlier, according to which we determine
Highly unacceptable 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Highly acceptable27 Pr(qjp) by adding, hypothetically, p to our current stock
of beliefs and determining how probable we deem q in that
The other group (N = 37) got 30 matching questions, hypothetical situation. (This proposal now commonly goes
which had this form: by the name ‘‘the Ramsey test.”)28 Moreover, evidence pre-
sented in Zhao, Shah, and Osherson (2009) suggests that
Context C !i (=Context Ci + ‘‘Suppose pi”) Ramsey’s proposal offers the more accurate way of deter-
mining conditional probabilities.29

qi
28
Bennett (2005: p. 53) even goes so far as to say that ‘‘[t]he best
definition [of conditional probability] we have is the one provided by the
How likely is this statement in context C !i ? Ramsey test” and not by the ratio definition. Oaksford and Chater (2007: p.
109) agree. On this issue see also Hájek (2003).
29
While Zhao, Shah, and Osherson (2009) do not refer to Ramsey’s work,
27
The numbers 2–6 were also labelled, in the obvious way (2 = unac- their ‘‘direct” conditional probabilities judgments are in effect judgments of
ceptable, 3 = somewhat unacceptable, and so on). conditional probabilities determined via Ramsey’s proposal.
I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318 309

5.2. Results As for the interaction effect between type of conditional


and acceptability/probability, planned comparisons re-
Firstly, we investigated Adams’s Thesis in its strictest vealed that acceptability and probability differed signifi-
form (AT) and its approximate form (WAT1). To that end, cantly for the abductive sentences (F(1, 65) = 10.32; p
we conducted an ANOVA analysis with acceptability/prob- < .01). Acceptability and probability differed significantly
ability as between subjects variable and type of conditional for the inductive sentences (F(1, 65) = 52.33; p < .0001). No
as within subjects variable. The analysis of question type significant difference was revealed between acceptability
revealed a main effect of acceptability/probability and probability for the deductive sentences.
(F(1, 65) = 34.51; p < .00001; mean probability = 5.44; Thirdly, we investigated whether acceptability and
mean acceptability = 4.76) and a main effect of type of con- probability were highly correlated, as predicted by
ditional (F(2, 130) = 350.13; p < .00001; mean deductive = (WAT3). Since the probability and acceptability were
6.08; mean inductive = 4.6; mean abductive = 4.63) and tested between subjects, it was not possible to compute di-
an interaction effect between both (F(2, 130) = 28.36; rect correlations between both. In order to overcome this
p < .00001). For all these tests, power > 0.99.30 The main ef- difficulty, we computed the mean per sentence (ten abduc-
fect between acceptability and probability disproves (AT) tive sentences, ten inductive sentences, and ten deductive
and (WAT1). sentences) over the participants (for a similar approach see
As for the effect of type of conditional, planned compar- Hadjichristidis et al. (2001)). In this way, we obtained a
isons revealed that the abductive sentences did not differ mean for each of the 30 sentences. Then we computed
from the inductive sentences.31 The abductive sentences the correlations per type of conditional between probabil-
differed significantly from the deductive sentences ity and acceptability. We do realize that averaging across
(F(1, 65) = 449.89; p < .01). Inductive and deductive sen- participants may conceal individual differences. However,
tences also differed significantly (F(1, 65) = 474.6; p < .01). by manipulating probability and acceptability between
As for the interaction effect between type of conditional subjects, we can be absolutely sure that participants were
and acceptability/probability, planned comparisons re- not influenced by the other variable. For the 30 sentences
vealed that acceptability and probability differed signifi- in the experiment, probability and acceptability were
cantly for the abductive sentences (F(1, 65) = 18.18; highly correlated: N = 30, R = .83, p < .05. Per type of condi-
p < .0001; mean acceptability = 4.34; mean probabil- tional, we found the following: for the abductive sen-
ity = 4.92). Acceptability and probability differed signifi- tences, probability and acceptability were highly
cantly for the inductive sentences (F(1, 65) = 72.55; correlated: N = 10, R = .81, p < .05; for the inductive sen-
p < .0001; mean acceptability = 3.99; mean probabil- tences, probability and acceptability were correlated:
ity = 5.19). No significant difference was revealed between N = 10, R = .65, p < .05; for the deductive sentences, proba-
acceptability (mean = 5.96) and probability (mean = 6.20) bility and acceptability were highly correlated: N = 10,
for the deductive sentences. R = .88, p < .05.33
Secondly, we tested whether (WAT2) holds. To that end,
we recoded the scale into three levels, 1–2 complying with 5.3. Discussion
low probability/acceptability, 3–4–5 with medium proba-
bility/acceptability, 6–7 with high probability/acceptabil- The significant effect over all sentences between
ity. Low was given score 1, medium 2, and high 3. We acceptability and probability shows that the acceptability
then conducted an ANOVA analysis with acceptability/ of a conditional does not equal the conditional probability,
probability as between subjects variable and type of condi- nor do the two approximately equal one another (on any
tional as within subjects variable. The analysis revealed a plausible reading of ‘‘approximately”). We have thus been
main effect of acceptability/probability (F(1, 65) = 27.03; able to disprove Adams’s Thesis, both in its strict form (AT)
p < .00001) and a main effect of type of conditional and in its approximate form (WAT1). We have further
(F(2, 130) = 270.99; p < .00001) and an interaction effect demonstrated that (WAT2) does not hold either. On the
between both (F(2, 130) = 23.18; p < .00001). For all these other hand, our results do support (WAT3): the acceptabil-
tests, power >0.99. The main effect between acceptability ity of a conditional highly correlates with the correspond-
and probability disproves (WAT2). ing conditional probability.
As for the effect of type of conditional, planned compar- The most interesting results were obtained by compar-
isons revealed that the abductive sentences did not differ ing the separate results for the three types of conditionals.
from the inductive sentences.32 The abductive sentences These comparisons suggest a family of Adams’s Theses. Our
differed significantly from deductive sentences data support the hypothesis that (AT), or at least (WAT1),
(F(1, 65) = 370.73; p < .01). Inductive and deductive sen- holds for DI conditionals, but not for either of the other
tences also differed significantly (F(1, 65) = 371.78; p < .01).
33
An anonymous reviewer worried that the materials of Experiment 1 are
30
Determined according to BWPower, Version 1.6, September 2002 rather one-sided as far as DI conditionals are concerned, given that in all
(1997–2002 Roger Bakeman). See also Bakeman and McArthur (1999). our DI items, the consequent follows deductively from the antecedent or
31
However, when we look at probability and acceptability separately, from the antecedent plus background premises. This reviewer suggested
abductive and inductive sentences differ. Acceptability: F(1, 65) = 17.28; that we also consider items in which this is not the case and even in which
p < .0001. Probability: F(1, 65) = 13.58; p < .001. the intuitively correct verdict about the given conditional is ‘‘highly
32
Here, too, abductive and inductive sentences differ when we look at unacceptable.” A control experiment which takes up this suggestion is
probability and acceptability separately. Acceptability: F(1, 65) = 16.15; presented in Appendix B. The results of that additional experiment are in
p < .001. Probability: F(1, 65) = 10.10; p < .01. line with the results reported here.
310 I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

types. For AI conditionals, acceptability can still be said to as part of Experiment 1. The items presented to the second
go strictly by conditional probability: there is a high corre- group differed from those only in that instead of ‘‘How
lation between acceptability and conditional probability. acceptable is this statement in the present context?,” the
For II conditionals, not even this is true. At best, the accept- participants were asked the question, ‘‘How reasonable is
ability of these conditionals could be said to go loosely by it to believe this statement in the present context?” After
conditional probability: the correlation between accept- they had completed the experiment, the participants in
ability and conditional probability is only moderately high. the first group were also asked how they had understood
In short, our data suggest that (AT) or (WAT1) holds for DI the notion of acceptability.
conditionals, that (WAT3) holds for AI conditionals, and
that only the exceedingly weak (WAT4) holds for II
conditionals. 6.2. Results

6. Experiment 2 An ANOVA analysis with type of question as between


subjects variable and type of conditional as within subjects
As mentioned in Section 4, acceptability, as the notion variable revealed no effect of type of question and no inter-
occurs in the standard interpretation of Adams’s Thesis, action effect between type of question and type of condi-
is meant in an epistemic sense, as indicating reasonable- tional; see Fig. 1. As expected, there was an effect of type
ness to believe. However, one cannot automatically as- of conditional (F(2, 322) = 95,46; p < .0001).
sume that this is how the participants of Experiment 1 The following is a representative sample of the qualita-
understood the notion. For instance, they might have mis- tive feedback we received in response to the question of
understood the questions about acceptability as asking how the notion of acceptability was interpreted:
whether it would be appropriate to contribute the given
conditional to a conversation taking place in the relevant ! Acceptable is that the sentence relates logically to the
context. To determine whether any such misunderstanding story.
was involved, we conducted a control experiment in ! As something that one can take to be true.
which, first, we compared responses to questions about ! When the sentence logically fits the context.
acceptability with responses to questions directly about ! I have interpreted ‘‘acceptable” as meaning that the
reasonableness to believe; and second, we asked the par- sentence flows from the situation described in the story.
ticipants who had been presented the questions about ! That it seemed logical to me that the represented event
acceptability how they had interpreted this notion. would be true.
! As in: it would be a logical explanation.
! Something that one can assume or suppose.
6.1. Method
! As something that seems reasonable and sensible.
! What seems logical, self-evident.
6.1.1. Participants
! Something that can be expected to be true given the
One hundred and sixty-three students of the University
story.
of Leuven participated in the experiment as part of a course
requirement.

6.1.2. Design
The question concerning type of question (acceptable/ 6
reasonable to believe) was manipulated between subjects.
The type of conditional (abductive/inductive/deductive) 5.5
was manipulated within subjects.
Answer on 7-point scale

6.1.3. Materials and procedure 5


All materials were in Dutch, the participants’ mother
tongue. Fifteen items were presented to each participant 4.5
in a computer experiment. Items consisted of context–sen-
tence pairs. Every participant had to evaluate five abduc-
tive, five inductive, and five deductive items. Those five 4
items per type of conditional were, each time, randomly
chosen out of the list of ten items per type of conditional
3.5
of Experiment 1. The Fifteen items per test were presented
in a randomized order.
The participants were divided into two groups. We 3
abductive inductive deductive
asked the participants in the first group to judge the
acceptability of conditionals and those in the second group acceptability reasonable believability
to judge how reasonable it is to believe the conditionals.
Thus, the items presented to the first group were identical Fig. 1. Comparison of acceptability and reasonable believability of
to the items concerning acceptability that were presented conditionals.
I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318 311

6.5 then compared both with the acceptability judgments


and with the conditional probability judgments that
6 were obtained in Experiment 1.
Answer on 7-point scale

5.5 7.1. Method

5 Twenty-five students of the University of Leuven partic-


ipated as part of a course requirement. The participants
were asked to grade the probability of truth of the same
4.5
conditional sentences that were used in Experiment 1.
Materials were similar to the ones presented in Experi-
4
ment 1, the only difference being that the question of
how acceptable the given conditional is was replaced by
3.5 the question of how probable it is that the conditional is
true. So, here too, every participant had to evaluate ten
3 abductive, ten inductive, and ten deductive context–sen-
abductive inductive deductive
tence pairs.
probability of truth acceptability The condition of probability of truth was added to the
conditional probability two conditions of Experiment 1. So, in total the experiment
consisted of 92 participants: 25 new participants who
Fig. 2. Conditional probability compared with acceptability and proba- were asked about probability of truth and 67 participants
bility of truth of conditionals: for all types of conditionals, conditional who in Experiment 1 were asked about acceptability (30)
probability and probability of truth judgments match each other closely; and conditional probability (37).
neither type of judgments matches acceptability judgments very closely.

7.2. Results

Although it is not equally easy to make sense of each of An ANOVA analysis with type of question (acceptability/
these answers, and although none of the participants di- probability of truth/conditional probability) as between
rectly stated that they had interpreted ‘‘acceptable” as subjects variable and type of conditional (abductive/induc-
meaning ‘‘reasonable to believe,” the answers do suggest tive/deductive) as within subjects variable revealed an ef-
that the notion of acceptability was interpreted in an epi- fect of type of question (F(2, 89) = 18.64; p < .00001) and an
stemic sense rather than in some other sense; things that interaction effect between type of question and type of con-
seem logical, or self-evident, or that can be taken to be ditional (F(4, 178) = 12.7; p < .0001). There was also an effect
true, are probably things that are reasonable to believe, of type of conditional (F(2, 178) = 388.08; p < .0001).
though not obviously also things that it would be appropri- As for the main effect of type of question, planned com-
ate to contribute to a conversation. Indeed, there was no parisons revealed that probability of truth and conditional
indication that any of the participants had understood probability did not differ from one another. Acceptability
‘‘acceptable” as meaning something like ‘‘conforming to differed from probability of truth (F(1, 89) = 21.36;
broadly social norms governing good conversational p < .0001) and from conditional probability (F(1, 89) =
practice.” 33.27; p < .0001) (see Fig. 2).34
In sum, given that the participants did not respond in As for the main effect of type of conditional, planned
fundamentally different ways to the type of question, given comparisons revealed that the abductive sentences did
also the qualitative feedback that we received, the conclu- not differ from the inductive sentences. The deductive sen-
sion is warranted that the notion of acceptability as it fig- tences differed from the abductive sentences
ured in our first experiment was understood as we (F(1, 89) = 524.27; p < .01) and also from the inductive sen-
intended it to be. tences (F(1, 89) = 510.77; p < .01).
As for the interaction effect, planned comparisons re-
vealed that there was no significant difference between
7. Experiment 3 conditional probability and probability of truth for the
abductive sentences. The same held for the inductive
That the participants of our first experiment under- and deductive sentences. There was a significant differ-
stood the notion of acceptability in an epistemic sense ence between conditional probability and acceptability
is consistent with the supposition that they interpreted for the abductive sentences (F(1, 89) = 18.14; p < .0001)
degree of acceptability as subjective probability. If they and for the inductive sentences (F(1, 89) = 62.38;
did, then the results of Experiment 1 would conflict with p < .0001) but not for the deductive sentences.35 There
the findings of Evans, Over, and others cited in Section 4. was also a significant difference between probability of
To see whether this was how the participants had inter-
preted the notion of acceptability, we conducted a fur- 34
This was already stated in Section 5; we restate the result here for the
ther experiment in which we asked the participants to sake of completeness.
grade the probability of truth of the various conditionals 35
As was discussed in Section 5; the result is restated here for the sake of
from Experiment 1. These probability judgments were completeness.
312 I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

truth and acceptability for the abductive sentences Lowe took this fact to refute (AT).36 That might seem
(F(1, 89) = 11.60; p < .001) as well as for the inductive sen- rash, for (5) could have been an exception, a linguistic
tences (F(1, 89) = 34.2; p < .0001) but not for the deductive curiosity, and therefore of little significance, given that
sentences. few (if any) theses about natural language (such as
Thus, this experiment warrants the conclusion that, Adams’s Thesis pretends to be) can be expected to hold
while participants understood the notion of acceptability unexceptionably. Arguably, however, Lowe’s conditional
in an epistemic sense (as Experiment 2 made it reason- is not an isolated counterexample at all. For note that
able to assume), their acceptability judgments were not while not all II conditionals are about lottery tickets, they
simply their subjective probability judgments. Moreover, are like (5) in an important and relevant respect. Inferring
given that we found a close match between judgments of about Jim that he had at least a B for his statistics exam
probability of truth of conditionals and corresponding on the supposition that he is a second-year psychology
conditional probabilities, the experiment is in line with student and given the background knowledge that 95%
Evans and Over’s findings and gives further support to of the second-year psychology students have at least a B
(Eq). In fact, it is shown here for the first time that for their statistics exam (without further relevant back-
(Eq) holds for DI, II, and AI conditionals alike. ground knowledge) is structurally no different from infer-
ring that you will lose, on the supposition that you bought
a ticket and given the background knowledge that the
8. General discussion ticket is one of a great number of tickets all belonging
to a fair lottery with only one winner (and no further rel-
Our experiments showed that neither is it generally evant background knowledge): in both cases it is inferred
true that Ac(p ? q) = Pr(qjp), nor that Ac(p ? q) ! Pr(qjp), that a particular individual has a given property from the
nor that Ac(p ? q) is high (middling/low) whenever Pr(qjp) premise that the individual belongs to a certain class, and
is high (middling/low). On the positive side, the experi- the background statistical information that a certain high
ments showed that the acceptability of inferential condi- percentage of the individuals in the class have the given
tionals highly correlates with their corresponding property. Accordingly, ‘‘If Jim is a second-year psychology
conditional probabilities, at least when taken over all such student, he has at least a B for his statistics exam”
conditionals, though the experiments also showed that this expresses a reasoning process of the same type as is
does not hold for the different types of inferential condi- expressed by (5). And we only need to imagine a suffi-
tionals considered separately. ciently high number of second-year psychology students
One major lesson to be learned from these results is to make the former conditional as intuitively compelling
that a popular strand of philosophical theorizing about as a counterexample against (AT) as Lowe’s (5).
conditionals needs substantial rethinking. While many To be sure, this does little to explain why acceptability
philosophers assume explicitly – though presumably and probability ratings match so poorly for II condition-
merely on the basis of casual introspection – that (AT), als, much less why there are the kind of differences
or at least some attenuated version thereof, is descrip- among the three types of conditionals that our experi-
tively correct, this assumption is not warranted by the ment uncovered. That there are these sort of differences
above findings. These suggest, in the best possible sce- at all may simply reflect the fact that, as philosophers
nario, a more nuanced picture, to wit, that in general unanimously agree, and as would seem obvious anyway,
only the ‘‘high correlation thesis” (WAT3) can be main- the types of inference that underlie our typology differ
tained, but that when different types of conditionals from an epistemological viewpoint in that they may
are considered separately, different versions of Adams’s put us in different epistemic positions vis-à-vis the con-
Thesis hold for them. This is the best possible scenario, clusions we reach by them on the basis of known or ac-
inasmuch as we have limited our attention to inferential cepted premises. For instance, if q is an inductive
conditionals. The picture might become still more frag- consequence of p, then coming to know the latter may
mented when content conditionals are taken into ac- result in one’s coming to have a different – stronger,
count as well. weaker, or perhaps incomparably different – epistemic
Perhaps not all of the results should have come as a position vis-à-vis q than if q were an abductive or deduc-
surprise. Lowe (1996: p. 611 ff) had already pointed to tive consequence of p instead. In principle, such differ-
a problem regarding Adams’s view on conditionals. The ences could correspond to probabilistic differences, in
problem is closely related to the Lottery Paradox that that the value of Pr(qjp) might lie within a certain inter-
was briefly discussed in Section 4. Suppose we know that val, depending on whether q is a deductive, inductive, or
a lottery is to be held, and know that the lottery is fair
and consists of 1,000,000 tickets, only one of which will 36
Kaufmann (2004) also argues, though along very different lines, that
win. Then consider (given the present context) the II
Adams’s proposal sometimes deviates starkly from intuition. However, as is
conditional argued in Douven (2008c), our intuitive verdicts about the cases Kaufmann
depicts are highly dependent on how the probabilistic information relevant
(5) If we buy ticket # 14, we won’t win. to them is presented to us, and the kind of verdict that appears to militate
against Adams’s proposal may only follow because in Kaufmann’s examples
that information is presented in a way that psychologists have long known
While the conditional probability of ‘‘We won’t win” to confuse people’s intuitions in predictable ways. Douven thus concludes
given ‘‘We buy ticket # 14” is close to 1, (5) appears that the intuitions to which Kaufmann appeals are to be explained away
to be neither highly acceptable nor highly assertable. rather than explained.
I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318 313

abductive consequence of p, and where there is no over- areas of ongoing research on or involving conditionals38 –
lap between the intervals. But this suggestion is already such as research on the learning of conditionals and on rea-
a priori implausible, and the data we obtained make it soning tasks with conditionals – the results from Experi-
appear even more so. Hence, if the acceptability condi- ments 1 and 2 do make it reasonable to check for possible
tions of conditionals are to be understood in terms of effects of type of conditional, and to guard against a one-
an epistemic relationship between antecedent and conse- sided use of test items involving a particular type of
quent, and if this relationship depends (whether wholly conditional.
or partly) on the kind of consequence relation that holds Finally, it should be of some interest to linguists that
between them, then that makes it understandable why our typology of DI, II, and AI conditionals is not just simple
we found an interaction between the type to which a gi- and grounded in a time-tested distinction between types of
ven conditional belongs and its perceived acceptability. inference, but also has considerable explanatory force. At a
Even if this is so, it still only provides a rather shallow minimum, it seems a valuable addition to the typologies
and unspecific explanation of our findings. We may be able already to be found in the literature.
to dig a bit deeper by turning to the psychological litera-
ture on human reasoning. There is ample experimental evi-
dence indicating that the various types of inference differ Acknowledgements
psychologically in important respects. For instance, there
is much evidence suggesting that deductive and nondeduc- We are greatly indebted to three anonymous reviewers
tive inference are processed differently from one another for extremely detailed and valuable comments on a previ-
(see, e.g., Evans & Over, 1996, Sloman, 1996, Stanovich, ous version of this paper and to Steven Sloman for useful
1999, Rips, 2001). Parsons and Osherson (2001) even pres- editorial advice. We are further grateful to Jean-François
ent neuropsychological evidence to the effect that deduc- Bonnefon, Richard Dietz, Kristien Dieussaert, Shira Elqa-
tive and probabilistic reasoning are processed in different yam, Janneke Huitink, David Over, Niki Pfeifer, Walter
brain hemispheres (see also Osherson et al., 1995; for a re- Schaeken, William Van Belle, and Christopher von Bülow
lated study, see Goel & Dolan, 2004). And from the heuris- for helpful comments and discussion. Earlier versions of
tics-and-biases literature, we know that statistical this paper were presented at the First Formal Epistemology
inference has a somewhat special, even problematic, sta- Festival in Constance (July 2008), at the 31st Wittgenstein
tus. (See the papers in Kahneman, Slovic, & Tversky, Symposium in Kirchberg am Wechsel (August 2008), and
1982, Gilovich et al., 2002; see also De Neys, 2006 & De at the Fourth London Reasoning Workshop (July 2009).
Neys & Verschueren, 2006.) Furthermore, it is known that We thank the audiences on those occasions for stimulating
explanation is of special value with respect to memory, questions and comments. For financial support, we would
and also that memory plays a key role in conditional rea- like to thank the Government of the Flemish Community
soning (see Bransford & Johnson (1972) on the former (project ‘‘Formal Epistemology: Foundations and Applica-
and Toms, Morris, & Ward (1993) on the latter). Finally, tions”) and the Research Foundation Flanders (FWO).
Brem and Rips (2000) present studies showing that when
people are able to think of an explanation for some event,
they come to regard the occurrence of this event as being Appendix A
more likely, and even tend to overrate its likelihood, at
least when they possess scarce evidence relevant to the This appendix presents the contexts and conditionals
likelihood of that occurrence. But while these studies that were used in Experiments 1–3.
may go some way towards explaining the kind of differ-
ences we found, we surmise that a specific explanation of DI Items:
the results of our experiments will have to await a more Context: All students in class 6C have at least a B for
systematic investigation of the differences between deduc- their math test paper.
tive, inductive, and abductive reasoning – in terms of speed Conditional: If Ben is in class 6C, then he has at least
of processing, proneness to error, use of working memory, a B for his math test paper.
and similar apparently obvious parameters – than has
hitherto been carried out by psychologists.37
Context: In the football competition, a won match
This brings us to another general lesson to be learned
yields three points.
from our studies, one that should be of particular interest
Conditional: If Anderlecht is seven points ahead of
to psychologists working on conditionals. While it does
Club Brugge, and there are only two matches to go
not follow from our results that important differences will
in this year’s competition, then Club Brugge cannot
be found for the different types of conditionals in other
become champion this year.

Context: All white cats possess a gene that predis-


37
In his (1991), Evans complained about the fragmented state of
poses them to develop blindness late in their lives.
psychological theorizing concerning human reasoning, and by that he
meant only deductive reasoning. While since 1991, the situation certainly
seems to have improved as far as our knowledge of deductive reasoning
goes, we still seem to be far removed from a systematic and integrated
38
theory of reasoning in general (that is, also including inductive and Indeed, as shown in Section 7, (Eq) holds for each of the three types of
abductive reasoning). conditionals that we defined.
314 I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

Conditional: If Paul’s kitten is white, then it possesses Conditionals: If Harriet regularly exercises, she is at a
a gene that predisposes it to develop blindness late decreased risk of developing osteoporosis.
in its life.
II Items:

Context: Two friends are wondering whether Cynthia


passed the exam. They know that it was an absolute Context: According to a recent report written on the
requirement for the exam to hand in a thesis before authority of the Dutch government, many primary
the end of the semester. school students in the province of Friesland (where
Conditional: If Cynthia did not hand in her thesis many people still mainly speak Frisian) have diffi-
before the end of the semester, she failed. culty with spelling. Jitske is a student of a primary
school somewhere in the Netherlands.
Conditional: If Jitske goes to a Frisian primary school,
Context: It is generally known that the bank is
then she has difficulty with spelling.
always open on Fridays, except when the employees
go on an outing. It’s Friday, and Kathy is on her way
to the bank. She thinks: Context: Most miners develop silicosis, a disease
Conditional: If the bank is closed, then the employees caused by inhaling fine dust for a prolonged period
are on an outing.39 of one’s life.
Conditional: If Rudolph has worked in the mines for
all his life, then he has developed silicosis.
Context: Every student that has less than a C for the
exam is required to retake the exam.
Conditional: If my classmate Joan has less than a C Context: A group of friends like to go shopping. Each
for her exam, she is required to retake the exam. month they jointly visit some interesting shoe
shops. Most members of the group own at least 20
pairs of shoes.
Context: Students who belong to the top 10% of their
Conditional: If Aline is a member of that group, she
class each year will be able to write a good doctoral
has at least 20 pairs of shoes.
thesis. Persons who are able to write a good doctoral
thesis are eligible for an externally funded PhD
Context: Today is Saturday and you want to return a
position.
book to the library. The library is hardly ever closed
Conditional: If your fellow-student Stan belongs to
on Saturdays. If it is, then that is mostly because
the top 10% of his class each year, he will be eligible
Luke, the librarian, is sick.
for an externally funded PhD position.
Conditional: If the library is closed today, then Luke
is sick.
Context: Matt reads about a case of arson in the
newspaper. The police have a suspect in custody.
Arson is punished by imprisonment. He thinks: Context: According to the local bus company, none of
Conditional: If the suspect is found guilty, he or she their buses has been more than 5 min late in the past
will go to prison. 2 years.
Conditional: If our bus is not exactly on time, it will
at most be a few minutes late.
Context: Rational numbers are numbers that can be
written as a ratio of two natural numbers. Ellen
has written down a number on a slip of paper and Context: A pharmaceutical company unexpectedly
asks Carl to guess which number it is. Carl thinks: got into financial trouble. They had to cut many jobs
Conditional: If Ellen has written down a rational and decided to fire most employees above fifty.
number, then the number on the slip of paper can Mark is an employee of this company.
be written as a ratio of two natural numbers. Conditional: If Mark is above 50, he has been fired.

Context: Women who regularly exercise are at a 30% Context: The police received an anonymous tip that a
decreased risk of developing osteoporosis. known terror group has planned an attack. They are
trying to determine when the attack might take
39 place. They know that large-scale attacks mostly
One of the reviewers was concerned about the use of ‘‘except” in the
description of the context of this item. We therefore included the same take place during morning rush hours.
item without ‘‘except” in another experiment, specifying the context as Conditional: If the group wants to kill a great many
follows: ‘‘It is generally known that the local bank is closed on Fridays people, the attack will take place during morning
whenever the employees go on an outing. Otherwise, the bank is open on
rush hours.
Fridays. It’s Friday, and Kathy is on her way to the bank.” For acceptability,
an analysis revealed no difference between the item with and without
‘‘except” occurring in the context description. Similarly, no difference was Context: You are employed at the incident room of a
found for the question concerning probability between the item with and company that guards all banks and other financial
without ‘‘except.”
I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318 315

institutions in the neighborhood. You were told that then the most likely cause of the flooding is the
false alarms are not rare, and that the local bank has breaking of the dam.
a particularly bad reputation in this respect: the Conditional: If the village has been flooded, the dam
majority of their alarms are false. Suddenly there is is broken.
an alarm. You say to your colleague:
Conditional: If this alarm is from the local bank, it is
Context: Judy is waiting for the train. She is looking
false.flase
for her iPod to listen to some music while she waits.
It is not in her coat. Yet she is sure that she took it
Context: Dick is a bit of an irregular student: some-
this morning. Perhaps it is in her bag. Then she sees
times he works hard, but he can also be lazy. So far
that the zipper of her bag is open. She cannot
he had excellent grades for most courses for which
remember that she opened it. At that moment there
he had worked hard.
is an announcement that pickpockets are active in
Conditional: If Dick works hard for the linguistics
the train station.
course, then he will get an excellent grade for it.
Conditional: If Judy’s iPod is not in her bag, then
someone has stolen it.
Context: You know that today Jessica, the girl next door,
will hear whether she passed her finals. As far as you
Context: The police are investigating a homicide. The
know, Jessica has always been a serious student. Your
body was found in a morass. The police have a prime
neighbors (her parents) are normally quiet people but
suspect. At the suspect’s home, they are looking for
they like to celebrate joyful events in a somewhat noisy
his shoes. One of the detectives says:
fashion. For instance, when Jessica’s elder brothers and
Conditional: If we find muddy shoes, then he was at
sisters passed their finals, the stereo each time went on
the crime scene.
maximal loudness. In the afternoon you suddenly hear
loud music. You cannot immediately determine from
Context: Pete had to play the finals of a tennis tour-
which direction it is coming. But:
nament earlier today. Two friends of his, who do not
Conditional: If this music comes from the neighbors,
yet know the result of the match, are walking to
then Jessica has passed her finals.
Pete’s house. From a distance, it seems to them that
there is a party going on in Pete’s garden. One of
AI Items: them says:
Conditional: If Pete is partying, he has won the match.
Context: You strongly doubt that Hank will have
passed the first-year examination. You suspect that
Context: In an archive, letters have been found that
his parents will buy him a car only if he passed that
may have been written by Ludwig van Beethoven.
examination. You suddenly see Hank driving a new
The author of these letters has put some symbols
car.
in the margins whose meaning is unclear. According
Conditional: If the car Hank is driving is his, then he
to the historians studying the letters, the best expla-
passed the first-year examination.
nation for the presence of these symbols is that the
author was a freemason.
Context: Nelly lives on the sixth floor of an apart- Conditional: If these letters are van Beethoven’s
ment building. The elevator has been broken since indeed, then he was a freemason.
earlier this morning. A good friend of Nelly’s who
lives on the third floor of the same building hears Context: Mary invited archenemies Betty and Chris
someone rushing down the stairs. She knows that to her party tonight. She does not expect Chris to
Nelly is not very sports-loving. She therefore thinks: come; he does not seem to be very fond of parties.
Conditional: If that’s Nelly rushing down the stairs, On the other hand, she knows that Chris likes to irri-
then she is in a hurry. tate Betty.
Conditional: If Chris comes to the party, then he
wants to irritate Betty tonight.
Context: You know that Tom and Hank recently had
a flaming row which, you think, ended their friend-
ship for good. Now a friend tells you that she thinks Context: The government has taken measures
she just saw Tom and Hank jogging together. She against the increasing pollution of the soil. It is not
may well be mistaken, but you think: certain that these will be effective. There is also a
Conditional: If Tom and Hank are jogging together chance that, through natural causes, soil pollution
again, they are friends again. will be halted. Yet experts agree that a decrease in
soil pollution in the coming years would be most
reasonably explained by the effectiveness of the
Context: Someone tells you that a nearby village has
measures taken.
been flooded. You doubt that this is true, but if it is,
316 I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

Conditional: If we shall witness a decrease in soil pol- in a booklet. Items were randomized per booklet and the
lution in the next years, then the measures taken by booklets were randomly distributed in the lecture hall.
the government are effective. The participants were divided into two groups. We asked
one group to judge acceptability of the conditionals and
Appendix B another group to judge the corresponding conditional
probabilities.
In response to the reviewer’s concern mentioned in
note 33 about the DI items used in our experiments, we Results
conducted an experiment that included five items in which
the conditional’s consequent followed deductively from its An ANOVA analysis with follows/does not follow as within
antecedent, or from its antecedent together with back- subjects variable and acceptability/probability as between
ground premises provided by the context, and five items subjects variable showed that there was no effect of
in which this was not the case. In fact, to accommodate acceptability/probability and no interaction effect. Unsur-
the reviewer’s suggestion that we consider items for which prisingly, there was an effect of follows/does not follow
the intuitive verdict about the given conditional is ‘‘highly (F(1, 67) = 1208.2; p < 0001). Moreover, correlations
unacceptable,” we took five items in which the negation of showed that there was a high correlation between accept-
the conditional’s consequent followed deductively from ability and probability for the 10 items (N = 10; Spearman
the conditional’s antecedent, or from the antecedent to- R = 0.95; p < .0001).
gether with background premises. Specifically, for the
present experiment we reused the first five context–condi-
tional pairs of the DI items listed in Appendix A and com- References
bined them with the following items:
Adler, J. (2002). Belief’s own ethics. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Adams, E. W. (1965). The logic of conditionals. Inquiry, 8, 166–197.
Context: This winter, all people older than 65 will be Adams, E. W. (1975). The logic of conditionals. Dordrecht: Reidel.
vaccinated for the Mexican flu. Adams, E. W. (1998). A primer of probability logic. Stanford: CSLI
Publications.
Conditional: If Mrs. Van Damme is older than 65, she
Arló-Costa, H. (2001). Bayesian epistemology and epistemic conditionals:
won’t be vaccinated for the Mexican flu this winter. On the status of the export–import law. Journal of Philosophy, 98,
555–593.
Bakeman, R., & McArthur, D. (1999). Determining the power of multiple
Context: The freshmen recently had a statistics exam. regression analyses both with and without repeated measures.
Behavior Research Methods Instruments and Computers, 31, 150–154.
Only those who scored at least 8/20 are allowed to resit.
Bennett, J. (2003). A philosophical guide to conditionals. Oxford: Clarendon
Conditional: If Paul (a freshman) scored 6/20 for the sta- Press.
tistics exam, he is allowed to resit. Bradley, R. (2007). A defence of the Ramsey test. Mind, 116, 1–21.
Bransford, J. D., & Johnson, M. K. (1972). Contextual prerequisites for
understanding: Some investigations of comprehension and recall.
Context: A pharmaceutical is testing a new drug to help Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11, 717–726.
people who want to quit smoking. Only people who Brem, S., & Rips, L. J. (2000). Explanation and evidence in informal
have been smoking for 2 years or longer are eligible as argument. Cognitive Science, 24, 573–604.
Dancygier, B. (1998). Conditionals and predictions: Time, knowledge and
test persons. Renée started smoking a year ago. causation in conditional constructions. Cambridge: Cambridge
Conditional: If Renée wants to participate in this test, University Press.
then she will be admitted. Dancygier, B. (2003). Classifying conditionals: Form and function. English
Language and Linguistics, 7, 309–323.
Dancygier, B., & Sweetser, E. (2005). Mental spaces in grammar: Conditional
constructions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Context: All Indian elephants have small ears. Declerck, R., & Reed, S. (2001). Conditionals: A comprehensive empirical
Conditional: If the elephant Babou has big ears, then analysis. Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Babou is an Indian elephant. De Neys, W. (2006). Automatic-heuristic and executive-analytic
processing in reasoning: Chronometric and dual task considerations.
Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 59, 1070–1100.
De Neys, W., & Verschueren, N. (2006). Working memory capacity and a
Context: According to the Belgian constitution, only Bel- notorious brain teaser: The case of the Monty Hall Dilemma.
gian citizens are eligible for a seat in the Belgian Experimental Psychology, 53, 123–131.
parliament. De Regt, H., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific
understanding. Synthese, 144, 137–170.
Conditional: If Günther has only German nationality, DeRose, K. (2010). The Conditionals of Deliberation. Mind, 119, 1–42.
then he is eligible for a seat in the Belgian parliament. Dietz, R., & Douven, I. (2010). Ramsey’s Test, Adams’ Thesis, and left-
nested conditionals. Review of Symbolic Logic, 3, 467–484.
Dietz, R. & Douven, I. (in press). A Puzzle about Stalnaker’s Hypothesis.
Method
Topoi.
Döring, F. (1994). On the probabilities of conditionals. Philosophical
Sixty-nine students of the University of Leuven partici- Review, 103, 689–699.
Douven, I. (1999). Inference to the best explanation made coherent.
pated in the experiment as part of a course requirement.
Philosophy of Science (Proceedings), 66, S424–S435.
The question concerning probability/acceptability was Douven, I. (2006). Assertion, knowledge, and rational credibility.
manipulated between subjects. The type of conditional Philosophical Review, 115, 449–485.
(follows/does not follow) was manipulated within sub- Douven, I. (2008a). The evidential support theory of conditionals.
Synthese, 164, 19–44.
jects. The participants were asked to evaluate the 10 Douven, I. (2008b). The lottery paradox and our epistemic goal. Pacific
above-mentioned items, which were presented to them Philosophical Quarterly, 89, 204–225.
I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318 317

Douven, I. (2008c). Kaufmann on the probabilities of conditionals. Journal Kyburg, H. Jr., (1961). Probability and the logic of rational belief.
of Philosophical Logic, 37, 259–266. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.
Douven, I. (2009). Assertion, Moore, and Bayes. Philosophical Studies, 144, Kyburg, H. Jr., (1990). Science and reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
361–375. Lance, M. (1991). Probabilistic dependence among conditionals.
Douven, I. (2010a) Abduction. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophical Review, 100, 269–276.
Philosophy. <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/>. Lehrer, K. (1974). Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Douven, I. (in press). Indicative Conditionals. In L. Horsten & R. Pettigrew Lehrer, K. (1986). The coherence theory of knowledge. Philosophical Topics,
(Eds.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic. London: Continuum Press. 14, 5–25.
Douven, I., & Williamson, T. (2006). Generalizing the lottery paradox. Lehrer, K. (1990). Theory of knowledge. London: Routledge.
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 755–779. Lewis, D. K. (1976) Probabilities of conditionals and conditional
Edgington, D. (1995). On conditionals. Mind, 104, 235–329. probabilities. Philosophical Review 85: 297–315. (Reprinted with a
Edgington, D. (1997). Commentary. In M. Woods (Ed.), Conditionals (pp. new postscript in his Philosophical Papers (Vol. II), Oxford:
95–137). Oxford: Clarendon Press (edited by D. Wiggins). Oxford University Press, pp. 133–156; the page reference is to
Edgington, D. (2003). What if? Questions about conditionals. Mind and the reprint.)
Language, 18, 380–401. Lewis, D. K. (1986). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional
Edgington, D. (2005). Ramsey’s legacies on conditionals and truth. In H. probabilities II. Philosophical Review, 95, 581–589.
Lillehammer & D. H. Mellor (Eds.), Ramsey’s legacy (pp. 37–52). Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd edn.). London:
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Routledge.
Evans, J. St. B. T. (1991). Theories of human reasoning: The fragmented Lowe, E. J. (1996). Conditional probability and conditional beliefs. Mind,
state of the art. Theory and Psychology, 1, 83–105. 105, 603–615.
Evans, J. St. B. T., Handley, S. J., Neilens, H., & Over, D. E. (2007). Thinking McGee, V. (1989). Conditional probabilities and compounds of
about conditionals: A study of individual differences. Memory and conditionals. Philosophical Review, 98, 485–541.
Cognition, 35, 1759–1771. Mellor, D. H. (1993). How to believe a conditional. Journal of Philosophy,
Evans, J. St. B. T., Handley, S. J., & Over, D. E. (2003). Conditionals and 90, 233–248.
conditional probability. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Nelkin, D. (2000). The lottery paradox, knowledge, and rationality.
Memory and Cognition, 29, 321–355. Philosophical Review, 109, 373–409.
Evans, J. St. B. T., & Over, D. E. (1996). Rationality and reasoning. Hove: Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (2003). Conditional probability and the
Psychology Press. cognitive science of conditional reasoning. Mind and Language, 18,
Evans, J. St. B. T., & Over, D. E. (2004). If. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 359–379.
Evnine, S. (1999). Believing conjunctions. Synthese, 118, 201–227. Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (2007). Bayesian rationality. Oxford: Oxford
Fann, K. T. (1970). Peirce’s theory of abduction. The Hague: Martinus University Press.
Nijhoff. Oberauer, K., Weidenfeld, A., & Fischer, K. (2007). What makes us believe a
Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. conditional? The roles of covariation and causality. Thinking and
Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (Eds.). (2002). Heuristics and Reasoning, 13, 340–369.
biases: The psychology of intuitive judgement. Cambridge: Cambridge Oberauer, K., & Wilhelm, O. (2003). The meaning(s) of conditionals:
University Press. Conditional probabilities, mental models and personal utilities.
Goel, V., & Dolan, R. J. (2004). Differential involvement of left prefrontal Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition,
cortex in inductive and deductive reasoning. Cognition, 93, 29, 688–693.
B109–B121. Osherson, D., Perani, D., Cappa, S., Schnur, T., Grassi, F., & Fazio, F. (1995).
Hadjichristidis, C., Stevenson, R. J., Over, D. E., Sloman, S. A., Evans, J. St. B. Distinct brain loci in deductive versus probabilistic reasoning.
T., & Feeney, A. (2001). On the evaluation of ‘if p then q’ conditionals. Neuropsychologia, 36, 369–376.
In J.D. Moore & K. Stenning (Eds.) Proceedings of the 23rd annual Over, D. E., & Evans, J. St. B. T. (2003). The probability of
meeting of the cognitive science society, Edinburgh (pp. 381–386). conditionals: The psychological evidence. Mind and Language, 18,
Haegeman, L. (2003). Conditional clauses: External and internal syntax. 340–358.
Mind and Language, 18, 317–339. Over, D. E., & Evans, J. St. B. T. (2010). Conditionals and non-constructive
Hájek, A. (1989). Probabilities of conditionals – revisited. Journal of reasoning. In M. Oaksford & N. Chater (Eds.), Cognition and
Philosophical Logic, 18, 423–428. conditionals (pp. 135–151). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hájek, A. (1994). Triviality on the cheap? In E. Eells & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Over, D. E., Hadjichristidis, C., Evans, J. St. B. T., Handley, S. J., & Sloman, S.
Probability and conditionals (pp. 113–140). Cambridge: Cambridge A. (2007). The probability of causal conditionals. Cognitive Psychology,
University Press. 54, 62–97.
Hájek, A. (2003). What conditional probability could not be. Synthese, 137, Parsons, L. M., & Osherson, D. (2001). New evidence for distinct right and
273–323. left brain systems for deductive versus probabilistic reasoning.
Hájek, A., & Hall, N. (1994). The hypothesis of the conditional construal of Cerebral Cortex, 11, 954–965.
conditional probability. In E. Eells & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Probability and Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2010). The conditional in mental probability
conditionals (pp. 75–111). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. logic. In M. Oaksford & N. Chater (Eds.), Cognition and conditionals
Hall, N. (1994). Back in the CCCP. In E. Eells & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Probability (pp. 153–173). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
and conditionals (pp. 141–160). Cambridge: Cambridge University Politzer, G., Over, D. E., & Baratgin, J. (in press) Betting on Conditionals.
Press. Thinking and Reasoning.
Harman, G. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Pollock, J. (1987). Defeasible reasoning. Cognitive Science, 11, 481–518.
Review, 74, 88–95. Pollock, J. (1990). Nomic probability and the foundations of induction.
Harman, G. (1999). Rationality, in his reasoning, meaning, and mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Oxford: Oxford University Press (pp. 9–45). Ramsey, F. P. (1931). The foundations of mathematics and other logical
Hookway, C. (1985). Peirce. London: Routledge. essays. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Jackson, F. (1979). On assertion and indicative conditionals. Philosophical Ryan, S. (1996). The epistemic virtues of consistency. Synthese, 109,
Review, 88, 565–589. 121–141.
Jackson, F. (1987). Conditionals. Oxford: Blackwell. Rescher, N. (2007). Conditionals. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment under Rips, L. J. (2001). Two kinds of reasoning. Psychological Science, 12,
uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University 129–134.
Press. Sloman, S. A. (1996). The empirical case for two systems of reasoning.
Kaplan, M. (1981a). Rational acceptance. Philosophical Studies, 40, Psychological Bulletin, 119, 3–22.
129–145. Stalnaker, R. (1970). Probability and conditionals. Philosophy of Science, 37,
Kaplan, M. (1981b). A Bayesian theory of rational acceptance. Journal of 64–80.
Philosophy, 78, 305–330. Stanovich, K. E. (1999). Who is rational? Studies of individual differences in
Kaplan, M. (1996). Decision theory as philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
University Press. Toms, M., Morris, N., & Ward, D. (1993). Working memory and
Kaufmann, S. (2004). Conditioning against the grain. Journal of conditional reasoning. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology,
Philosophical Logic, 33, 583–606. 46A, 679–699.
Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48, Tregear, M. (2004). Utilising explanatory factors in induction? British
507–531. Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 505–519.
318 I. Douven, S. Verbrugge / Cognition 117 (2010) 302–318

van Fraassen, B. C. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals. In W. L. Harper & Weidenfeld, A., Oberauer, K., & Horning, R. (2005). Causal and non-causal
C. A. Hooker (Eds.). Foundations of probability theory, statistical conditionals: An integrated model of interpretation and reasoning.
inference, and statistical theories of science (Vol. I, pp. 261–301). Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 58, 1479–1513.
Dordrecht: Reidel. Weisberg, J. (2009). Locating IBE in the Bayesian framework. Synthese,
van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). Review of B. Ellis, Rational belief systems. 167, 125–143.
Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10, 497–511. Williamson, T. (1996). Knowing and asserting. Philosophical Review, 105,
van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University 489–523.
Press. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University
Verbrugge, S., Dieussaert, K., Schaeken, W., Smessaert, H., & Van Belle, W. Press.
(2007). Pronounced inferences: A study on inferential conditionals. Zhao, J., Shah, A., & Osherson, D. (2009). On the provenance of judgments
Thinking and Reasoning, 13, 105–133. of conditional probability. Cognition, 113, 26–36.

You might also like