Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

Ratio Juris. Vol. 3 No.

1 bis March 1990 (130-47) Coherence and Discursive Rationality


copyright © Robert Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik 1990 131

Some influential theories of coherence assume that more general statements


create coherence in the less general ones they support. According to Neil Mac-
Cormick's conception of normative coherence in law, some principles support a
number of legal rules, and thus make them coherent (MacCormick 1984, 235ff.).1
On the other hand, some other theories assume that particular data-statements
make general theories coherent. According to Nicholas Rescher, a proposition
is true if, and only if, it follows from consistent data. However, the total set
The Concept of Coherence and of accessible data-statements will be inconsistent for at least two reasons.
Firstly, there is always the possibility of a mistake. Secondly, one may obtain
Its Significance for inconsistent data, depending on which of the competing theories of scientific
method one applies. Rescher thus determines various maximal consistent subsets
Discursive Rationality inherent in the (inconsistent) set of data. Some of those are to be preferred.
A proposition, p, maximally coheres with data, if it invariably follows from
all preferred maximal consistent subsets of data (Rescher 1973, 169ff.). One can
ROBERT AlEXY and ALEKSANDER PECZENIK thus say that the preferred subsets of data support this proposition.
Ronald Dworkin's theory of "integ...;ty" (that is, coherence) of law includes
MacCormick's idea that principles make rules coherent. But Dworkin's theory
seems to be more general. He compares a lawyer with a novelist, participating
Abstract. The main idea or the concept of coherence can be expressed in the following in writing a "chain llOvel" seriatim. Each novelist, and each lawyer, aims to
way: The more the statements belonging to a given theory approximate ~ perfect
supportive structure, the more coherent the theory. The degree of perfection of a make his additions fit not only general principles but all the material he has
supportive structure depends on the degree to which the following criteria of ~oherence been given, the predictions of what his successors will want or be able to add
are fulfilled: (1) the greatest possible number of supported statements belon~g to t~e to it, and his substantive value judgments (Dworkin 1986, 225ff.).
theory in question; (2) the greatest possible length of chains of reason~ belongmg to It;
(3) the greatest possible number of strongly sup~orted statements ?elongmg to ~he theo~;
(4) the greatest possible number of connectIons between vanous supp~rtlve chams I. The Concept and the Criteria of Coherence
belonging to the theory; (5) the greatest possible number of preference relatIons be~een
various principles belonging to it; (6) the greatest possible number ~nd complexity of A. The Concept
reciprocal supportive relations between various statements bel?ngmg to the theory;
(7) the greatest possible number of universal statements belongmg to the t~eory; the
We will analyse the concept of coherence in the follOWing manner: Firstly, we
greatest possible number of general concepts belonging to it; the highest. possible degree will state the main idea of coherence, although this concept remains a vague
of generality of concepts implemented within it; the greatest possl.ble. number of one. Secondly, we will formulate some criteria and principles which need to
resemblances between concepts used within it; (8) the greatest possible number of be weighed and balanced against each other to determine the coherence of a
conceptual cross-connections between various theories; (9) the greatest possi~le num~er theory.2 The main idea or the concept of coherence can be expressed as
of cases covered by the theory; and (10) the greatest possible number of fields of lIfe follows:
covered by the theory.

For a long time, the idea of coherence has been regarded as an attractive tool The more the statements belonging to a given theory approximate a perfect supportive
structure, the more coherent the theory.3
for solving epistemological problems (e.g., Hegel1970, 24). Many thinkers also
agree that coherence is more than logical consistency. They are right. To be
I Savigny (1814, 22) has already pointed out that "von ihnen [the leading principles] ausgehend
more precise, consistency is a necessary but not sufficient condition of coherence. den innern Zusammenhang und die Art der Verwandschaft aller juristischen Begriffe und Satze
Physics and chemistry, for example, are highly coherent with each other, zu erkennen, gehort eben zu den schwersten Aufgaben unsrer Wissenschaft, ja es ist eigentlich
whereas there is a lesser degree of mutual coherence between physics and religion dasjenige, was unsrer Arbeit den wissenschaftlichen Character giebt." "Recognition of the internal
connection and of the type of relationship linking all juristic concepts and propositions derived
although it cannot be said that they contradict each other. Philosophers face from them [the leading principles J is one of the most difficult tasks of our science, indeed the task
great difficulties when attempting to formulate the precise concept and crite~a which confers scientific character to our work" (English translation by M. La Torre).
2 As regards principles as commands to optimalize, cf. Alexy 1985a, 75ff.
of coherence. There is a tendency to avoid the term altogether, or to charactenze
3 As regards the connection between coherence and support, cf. Peczenik 1983, 88ff.; Aarnio 1987,
a coherent set of statements metaphorically as a "tightly knit unit," etc. 198ft
132 Robert Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik Coherence and Discursive Rationality 133

We must explain what we mean by the terms "theory," "support," "supportive clarify this. Although they may differ in form, the criterion and the principle
structure," and "perfect supportive structure." are merely different expressions of the same requirement of coherence.
1) The word "theory" is used here in a broad sense, covering both descriptive,
for example empirical theories, and normative or evaluative theories (norm (1) Ceteris paribus, the more statements belonging to a theory are supported,
the more coherent the theory. S
systems or value systems).
2) The concept of support used above is a weak one. It can be characterized (1 *) One should justify as many statements as possible.
as follows:
The clause"ceteris paribus" and the expression "as many ... as possible" indicate
The statement pI supports the statement p2 if, and only if, pI belongs to a set of premises, the same thing here; no principle or criterion of coherence is independently
5, from which p2 follows logically.4 sufficient but must be weighed against others. For example, other principles
of coherence may explain the fact that relatively many statements belonging
In an extreme case, p2 follows from pI alone. A stronger concept of support to the theory in ~uestion are not justified but merely taken for granted.
will be introduced below. Moreover, the quality of coherence can be weighed and balanced against other
Certainly, any pI together with an arbitrarily added premise supports any values. For example, in a case of emergency, a fireman should obey orders rather
conclusion whatever. However, this weak concept o{ support may be used as than continually demand a time-consuming explanation.
a starting point of discussion. Inappropriate additional premises are to be
eliminated by the criteria of coherence, discussed below, and perhaps by further 2. Length of the Supportive Chains
means. Coherence depends also upon the length of the supportive chains belonging to
3) Supportive structure depends on supportive relations between statements the supportive structure. A statement pI thus supports p2, p2 supports p3, etc.
belonging to the theory in question. That is to say that the supportive structure Longer chains make the supportive structure more complex. In other words,
of a theory is the same as the class of formal properties of the supportive relations they make th~ theo~ ~ore structured. They can also make it more profound.
between statements belonging to it. The followmg CrIterIon and principle of coherence help to clarify this idea:
4) The degree of perfection of a supportive structure depends on the degree
(2) Ceteris paribus, the longer the chains of reasons belonging to a theory are,
to which the criteria of coherence are fulfilled. the more coherent the theory.
(2 *) When justifying a statement, one should support it with a chain of reasons
B. The Criteria as long as possible.
Criteria of coherence make the concept of coherence more precise. The criteria
are related to each other. The degree of coherence depends on weighing them Th~ ~~nciple 2* demands a long series of justifications. Together with the
up and balancing them against each other. The following discussion of these defmltIon o~ su~port, it assumes deductive correctness and they jointly imply
criteria constitutes one conception of coherence. Since the concept of coherence a co~plex cntenon of coherence. This comprises completeness of deductive trees,
obtamed as a result of a logical reconstruction of the supportive chain.
is vague and contested, it is possible to conceive coherence in different ways.
The criteria of coherence can be divided into three classes, namely, (0 the 3. Strong Support
properties of the supportive structure constituted by the theory, (ii) the properties
of concepts applied by it, and (iii) the properties of the scope covered by it. A premise may occupy a peculiar position. Lawyers often argue that a decision
should be supported by a statute. The same statute may support many decisions.
(i) PROPERTIES OF THE SUPPORTIVE STRUCTURE
To be sure, many other premises are also included in the supportive structure.
CONSTITIJTED BY THE THEORY Assume, e.g., that the conclusion that a certain part of a contract should be

1. The Number of Supportive Relations S Speaking about numbers, two questions occur. Firstly: What is a single statement1 Secondly:
The minimum condition of coherence is that a coherent theory contains state- How to tr~at numerous but trivial and perhaps redundant statements1 The first question may be
ments supported by reasons. The following criterion and principle of coherence answer~ ~ man~ ways depending, among other things, on the subject of the theory. One possible
~er IS this:. A ~ingle st~,tement sensu stricto is the smallest unit of a theory which can be confronted
WIth the ~uesti?n Why1, and, therefore, is capable of being justified. As regards the second problem
4 This is a semantical-syntactical concept of support. We leave out the pragmatic dimension of the cetens panbus clause in criterion 1 implies that it can and must be solved by the other criteri~
it, cf. Alexy 1987, 1. of coherence, and perhaps by other means.
134 Robert Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik Coherence and Discursive Rationality 13S

disregarded as "unreasonable" follows from a set of premises containing sec. 36 In an extreme case, p2 follows from pI alone. In other cases, p2 follows from
of the Swedish Contracts Act, a description of the case, and some precedents. 6 pI together with some additional premises.
Any particular statement, belonging to this set, supports the conclusion in the The concept of strong support may play a role not only within legal reasoning
8
discussed manner. Within legal reasoning, however, such sources of law as a but also in other normative and causal contexts which include the question
statutory provision often have a special position. The same decision may follow ''Why7.'' Natural science, e.g., often states that x occurs because of y. The words
from another set of premises containing the same statutory provision, the "why" and "because" may indicate a causal relation. The logic of conditions
description of the case, and some quotations from travaux preparatoires (Govt. has no means to define causal necessity which seems to have an a priori quality
Bill 1975-76, 81, 118ff.). In this sense, neither the precedents nor the travaux (Kant 1983, B 233-35; Burks 1977, 619). Yet, laws of nature might serve as
preparatoires are necessary for the derivation. On the other hand, the decision criteria of causation (Peczenik 1979, 333ff.). One might perhaps construct a
might not follow from any set of premises belonging to legal reasoning and not reasonable interpretation of at least some laws of nature as expressing a relation
containing this statutory provision. If the statutory provision has such a special of strong support between a cause-statement and an effect-statement.
position, it strongly supports the decision. This kind of support exists when For reasons like these, the degree of coherence increases when not only weak
each member of the set of premises, S, belongs to a subset having the following but also strong support occurs. The following criterion and principle of coherence
properties: a) The decision follows logically from it; b) all members of the subset express this idea:
are necessary to infer the decision from this subset; and c) the decision does
(3) Ceteris paribus, the more statements belonging to a theory are strongly
not follow from any subset of S at all to which the provision does not belong.
supported by other statements, the mor~ coherent the theory.
Such a strong support can be characterized as follows:
(3*) One should formulate statements which strongly support as many state-
The statement pI strongly supports the statement p2 if, and only if, pI belongs to a ments as possible.
set of premises,S, having the following properties:
1) None of these premises is meaningless or falsified; The idea of strong support allows us to answer an important question. Let
2) at least one subset of 5 is such that us assume that a chain of reasons exists, that is, that pI supports p2, p2 supports
a) p2 follows logically from it, and p3, etc. To put it more precisely, this would imply that pI together with some
b) all members of the subset are necessary to infer p2 from this subset (that is, p2 other premises, say r1 and 51, logically entails p2; p2 together with another
does not follow, if any premise belonging to the subset is removed from it);
3) each member of 5 belongs to at least one such subset; and
set of premises, say, r2 and s2, logically entails p3, etc. But what if we omitted
4) pI is also necessary in the following stronger sense: p2 does not follow from any the intermediate step, p2, and simply stated that p3 follows from pI together
subset of 5 at all to which pI does not belong.7 with rI, 51, r2, and 527 This would effectively dissolve the chain of support.
What remained would be a conclusion and a set of premises, without inter-
6 Suppose, e.g., that an inexperienced businessman enters into a contract with a big company, mediate links.
entirely dominating the market. According to the contract, the company may unilaterally decide This would have the effect of invalidating a central point of our theory. In
whether future disputes are to be decided by a general court or arbitration. A dispute occurs. The
businessman sues the company before a general court, but the company claims that the case shall order to defend the idea of chains of support, one may refer to the progress
be referred to arbitration. Is the arbitration clause "unreasonable"7 The affirmative answer to this of thinking, in history of science as well as in the mind of an individual.
question follows from the case NJA 1979, 666. Knowledge evolves step by step. Longer and longer chains of support are
7 This definition of strong support constitutes an improvement of the definition of support
developed in Peczenik 1988a, 113 and 131-32; cf. Peczenik 1988b, 131: The statement p supports developed. However, historical and psychological insights are not sufficient to
the statement q if, and only if, jus~ a logical reconstruction of knowledge. Only logical or, at least, epistemo-
1) P belongs to a set of premises, 5, from which q logically follows; and lOgIcal reasons serve this purpose. The concept of strong support makes it
2) q does not follow from 5, if p is removed from it; and
3) 5 consists solely of reasonable premises. possible ~o develop such reasons. The concept of strong support thus matches
A reasonable premise is neither falsified nor arbitrary. More precisely, a premise is reasonable if, the fa~t that ~here are statements, as for instance norm-statements in legal
and only if, the following conditions are fulfilled: reasonmg, whIch play a special role in justification in a given context. 9 If there
1) The premise is not falsified.
2) The hypothesis is not to a sufficiently high degree corroborated that this premise does not
logically follow from a consistent and coherent set, solely consisting of certain premises, premises ~ The concept of st~~ng .support might perhaps be useful to explain the notOriously obscure distinc-
presupposed (taken for granted) within a particular practice, belonging to the culture under an betwee~ cond,tIO sine qua non and conditio per quam made by Kelsen (cf .• e.g., Kelsen 1960,
consideration, and/or proved premises. 197). One might perhaps construct a reasonable interpretation, according to which only the latter
This definition of support refers to coherence. Therefore, a logical circle would occur had we ~at the former, gives the conclusion strong support. '
used it in the present paper as the basis of a theory of coherence. Moreover, we make now a distinction As regards a gen~ral and informal account of the idea of propositions with privileged status within
between "weak support" and "strong support." a theory. cf. Quine 1961, xiiff.; Lakatas 1970, 132ff.
136 Robert Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik Coherence and Discursive Rationality 137

is such a statement, it can be used to establish a certain step of reasoning, which (4.2*) When justifying a statement, one should formulate as many independent
can be distinguished from other steps. First, one indicates that p2 strongly. sets of premises supporting it as possible.
supports p3 and then, perhaps within another theory, one states that a deeper·
premise, pI, strongly supports p2. In this way, one organizes the totality of· 5. Priority Orders Between Reasons
knowledge into different.1evels, such as, e.g., biology and physics, each charac_ Moreover, coherence of some theories depends on priority orders between
terized by its own core of premises which strongly support conclusions. If the reasons. Everybody who works with normative systems knows that different
levels were eliminated, one would lose important insights into the structure of chains of reasons may support incompatible conclusions. This fact may have
our knowledge. A supportive structure which expresses such knowledge is better· very different causes. For example, two logically incompatible rules may be
than one which does not. This is the reason for introducing the concept of • chosen as starting points of reasoning. Collisions of principles have another
supportive chains instead of simply talking about classes of premises. character. One may regard principles as commands to perform the optimal
By the way, this is confirmed by the practice of judicial reasoning. For' weighing and balancing. According to this theory, a principle is a norm which
example, when sentencing Charlie for a petty larceny, it would be manifestly demands that a given ideal should be carried into effect to a degree as high as
absurd for a judge to embark on a philosophical discussion of the validity of factually and legally possible (Alexy 1985a, 75ff.). The range of legal possibilities
the penal provision applied, the problem of legal validity in general, the ultimate depends, among other things, on colliding principles. When principles collide,
justification of practical reasoning, and so on. e.g., when an individual right collides with the demand to protect the environ-
ment, the relevant question is not: "What principle is to be eliminated from
4. Connection Between Supportive Chains the system?," but: "How to optimalize both principles within the system?" This
Coherence also depends upon the connection between various supportive chains is a question of creating coherence. The only possible answer is to establish
belonging to the supportive structure. We will discuss two kinds of connections: conditional, more or less general, definitive priority relations and prima facie
Firstly, the same premise may support different conclusions. Secondly, the same priority orders (Alexy 1985a, 516ff.; Alexy 1985b, 25ff.). This is the only way
conclusion may follow from different sets of premises. to avoid the risk that the system will be used to justify incoherent decisions.
A connection of the first kind occurs, e.g., when the same principle supports Incoherence would consist in the fact that though the decisions are logically
a number of legal rules, and thus makes them coherent. The following criterion compatible, their relation to each other is arbitrary. The following criterion
and principle of coherence correspond to this idea: and principle of coherence express this idea:
(4.1) Ceteris paribus, the greater the number of conclusions which are sup- ,: (5) If the theory in question contains principles, then, ceteris paribus, the
ported by the same premise belonging to the theory in question, the more greater the number of priority relations between the principles, the more
coherent the theory. coherent the theory.
(4.1 *) When justifying a statement, one should formulate premises supporting (5*) When using principles belonging to a theory as premises which justify
as many different conclusions as possible. a statement, one should formulate as many priority relations between
the principles as possible.
Cumulation of reasons within the supportive structure is also a criterion of
coherence. It is well known that in judicial practice the decision is often justified
6. Reciprocal Justification
by a cluster of reasons, which are not sufficient in themselves, but provide fairly
Reciprocal justification constitutes another criterion of coherence. One of the
good evidence when taken along with others. In other cases, the same conclusion
most fascinating and, at the same time, most controversial ideas connected with
follows from a number of independent reasons, each one sufficient. For example,
coherence is that of a system in which any statement supports each other. It
the Bundesverfassungsgericht supported a conclusion concerning the require-
is easy to see the problem. The idea would be untenable, if one had defined
ment of a statute in the German legal order by three independent reasons: the
support as logical entailment between pI and p2 alone. Mutual support would
rule of law (Rechts. staatsprinzip), the principle of parliamentary democracy,
then mean that p2 follows from pI and pI follows from p2. This is the case
and the basic rights (BVerfGE 49, 89, 126£.).
only when pI and p2 are equivalent. The idea of a system in which each state-
The following criterion and principle of coherence express this idea:
ment supports each other would thus lead to the conclusion that the system
(4.2) Ceteris paribus, the greater the number of independent sets of premises contains only logically equivalent statements, that is, it contains only one single
within the theory in question, so that the same conclusion follows from statement. This is one of the reasons why we have chosen another definition
each one of these sets, the more coherent the theory. of support, ~ccording to which pI might support p2 even if p2 does not follow
138 Robert Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik Coherence and Discursive Rationality 139

from pI alone. Thus, pI supports p2 if, and only if, pI belongs to a set of elucidates this concept. During a long period, the Bundesverfassungsgericht
premises, S, from which p2 follows logically. At the same time, p2 might sup. interpreted the constitutional guarantee of human dignity as follows: "It contra-
port pI, that is, p2 might belong to another set of premises, S', from which dicts human dignity to make a person a mere object" (BVerfGE 27, 1, 6) of
pI follows logically. the activity of the state authorities. In spite of its vagueness, this formula
An important distinction is the one between three different kinds of mutual supported the solution of many cases, and the cases were regarded as a support
support: empirical, analytic, and normative. for the formula. However, in a case concerning the interception df telephone
An empirical reciprocal support exists, e.g., when institutional enforcement conversations, the Court found that human dignity is contradicted first when
of basic rights constitutes a factual condition of democratic procedure of legisla-· the action of the authorities not only makes a person a mere object but also
tion and the latter constitutes a factual condition of the former. Such empirical constitutes a contempt (BVerfGE 30,1,26). The new formula helped to justify
connections are normatively relevant. A normative theory which contains them the change of the law, according to which a person whose conversation was
is richer and connects its elements in a better way. The following criterion and intercepted no longer could appeal to a court, only to a special parliamentary
principle of coherence express this idea: body. Yet, one may find this change to be wrong and regard this evaluation
as a reason against the new formula. Moreover, one may imagine a series of
(6.1) Ceteris paribus, the greater the number of reciprocal empirical relations cases where an activity of the authorities violates human dignity in spite of the
between statements belonging to a theory, the more coherent the theory. fact that it does not constitute a contempt. Thus, the old formula seems to be
(6.1 *) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the better than the new one. Consequently, the Court returned to it in later decisions
theory covers as many reciprocal empirical relations between statements (BVerfGE 45, 187, 228).
belonging to it as PQssible. A creation of reciprocal normative relations, that is, a reflective equilibrium of
the type described above, is not a perfect justificatory procedure, since it leaves
As an example for ~ mutual analytic support, one can employ the relation open the priority order between general and special statements. Sometimes, a
between basic rights and the well-known institution called "Rechtsstaat" (the more special statement is easier to give up; sometimes it is easier to stick to
state based on the rule of law) in the Continental political philosophy. Many it and change a more general one. Yet, one can hardly deny that this procedure
reasons support the conclusion that legal validity of basic rights constitutes a is rational and contributes to the creation of a coherent system. The following
conceptually necessary condition of a fully developed Rechtsstaat and, at the criterion and principle of coherence correspond to this insight:
same time, if no Rechtsstaat at all exists, one cannot, for conceptual reasons,
speak about the validity of the basic rights. A system which contains such (6.3) Ceteris paribus, the greater the number of reciprocal normative relations
conceptual relations connects its elements in a better way than one which does between statements belonging to a theory, the more coherent the theory.
not. The following criterion and principle of coherence express this idea: (6.3*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the
(6.2) Ceteris paribus, the greater the number of reciprocal analytic relations theory covers as many reciprocal normative relations between statements
between statements belonging to a theory, the more coherent the theory. belonging to it as possible.

(6.2*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the A slightly more complex reciprocal justification has the following structure:
theory covers as many reciprocal analytic relations between statements a. pI
belonging to it as possible. 51 &pl-p2
51
A normative reciprocal support exists when a relatively general statement
supports a number of relatively special ones and the latter support the former. Conclusion: p2
A connection of the first kind occurs, e.g., when a general legal norm supports b. p2
52 &p2-p3
a number of legal rules (see the criterion 4.1. supra). It is often called "deductive."
52
A connection of the second kind, often called "inductive," may be made deduc-
tively complete by the addition of some premises. The relatively general Conclusion: p3
conclusion follows logically from the relatively less general statements together c. p3
53 & p 3 - p l
with the added premises therein.
53
The cumulation of both kinds of support is interesting because it leads to what
Rawls calls "reflective equilibrium" (Rawls 1971, 48). The following example Conclusion: pI
140 Robert Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik Coherence and Discursive Rationality 141

(ii) PROPERTIES OF CONCEPTS APPLIED BY THE THEORY and general justification, in others it is enough that such a justification is
possible.
There are intrinsic connections between the properties of supportive structure
Therefore, the following criteria and principles of coherence hold good.
and the properties of concepts. All supportive structures presuppose some logical
concepts such as "if ... , then," etc. Besides, many supportive structures are (7.1) Ceteris paribus, the more statements without individual names a theory
possible only because of relations between some other, e.g., moral or legal, uses, the more coherent the theory.
concepts. In the history of philosophy, there are examples of thinkers who (7.1*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the
emphasize concepts, e.g., Hegel, and those who emphasize statements, e.g., theory is expressed in as many statements without individual names as
many logicians of the first half of the 20th century. The classical German Begriffs- possible.
jurisprudenz (Conceptual Jurisprudence) emphasized concepts, though many
of its theses could be reconstructed as concerning support between statements. (7.2) Ceteris paribus, the greater the number of general concepts belonging
In this context, let us discuss the following criteria and principles of coherence. to a theory, and the higher their degree of generality, the more coherent
the theory.
7. Generality
(7.2*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the
A criterion of coherence is what could be described as generality in the broad sense,
theory is expressed in as many general concepts as possible and in as
generality of concepts, and, consequently, arguments. In this context, one may
highly general concepts as possible.
refer to (a) universality, (b) generalfty in the strict sense, and (c) resemblances.
a. Universality consists in the fact that one uses concepts designating all things (7.3) Ceteris paribus, the more resemblances between concepts are used within
belonging to a certain class, not merely names of individual objects. Universality, a theory, the more coherent the theory.
that is, the use of concepts, is a necessary condition of all coherence. Therefore, (7.3*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should make a list as
the criterion 7.1, formulated below, only declares what the criteria discussed complete as possible of the resemblances between the concepts belonging
above already imply. to the theory.
b. Generality, on the other hand, can be graded. The more general the concept
in question, the greater the number of objects it covers (cf. Hare 1972-73, 2ff.). 8. Conceptual Cross-Connections
In the law, this form of coherence manifests itself, inter alia, in the so-called Conceptual cros5-Connections between parts of the structure constitute a further
general parts of criminal codes of many countries, dealing generally with criterion of coherence. Ceteris paribus, two theories are thus coherent to the
negligence, intent, self-defence, and so on. Civil codes, such as the German BGB, extent that they use the same or analogous concepts, structures, rules, etc.
also have a general part. Moreover, in legal reasoning, one often uses general For example, due to such structural similarity, modal logic, which deals with
arguments, rooted in moral philosophy, e.g., when the defendant pleads not the concepts of necessity and possibility, is highly coherent with deontic logic,
guilty on the grounds that he was not negligent, and argues that responsibility which deals with the concepts of obligation and permission. This fact helped
without negligence would be unjust. logicians to solve many ancient problems connected with the relations between
c. A conceptual family exists when the concept in question refers to a cluster such concepts as obligation, prohibition, and permission, on the analogy of
of phenomena, one similar to another, this to a third one, etc. relations between necessity, impossibility, and possibility (cf. the fundamental
In legal reasoning, this kind of generality and thus coherence, shows itself. paper, von Wright 1957). Another example is the fact that conceptual t~ols
when one argues ex analogja. Amongst these forms of argumentation is the so- elaborated in economics, such as Pareto-optimality and indifference curves, can
called analogia intra legem, that is, the argument that a certain case is so similar be used to analyse the weighing and balancing in legal and moral reasoning
to the cases the statute typically covers that it must itself be counted as covered (Alexy 1985a, 100ff., 145ff.).
by the linguistic meaning of it. Another form of argument is the so-called The ciiteria and principles of coherence which emerge from this idea are as
statutory analogy, which useS various similarities to extend the area of applica- follows:
tion of a statutory norm beyond its purely linguistic limits. Last but not least,
there is reasoning by analogy, which applies a precedent to a subsequent case (8.1) Ceteris paribus, the more concepts a given theory, TI, has in common with
which is similar to the prior one. another theory, T2, the more coherent these theories are with each other.
The criteria of generality in the broad sense apply both to general theories (8.1*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the
and particular decisions. The latter m4,st also be supported by coherent theories theory is expressed in as many concepts belonging to other theories as
which use general concepts. In some cases, the court must formulate an explicit possible.
142 Roberl Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik Coherence and Discursive Rationality 143

(8.2) Ceteris paribus, the more concepts a given theory, Tl, contains which (10) Ceteris paribus, the more fields of life a theory covers, the more coherent
resemble concepts used in another theory, T2, the more coherent these the theory.
theories are with each other.
(10*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the
(8.2*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the theory covers as many fields of life as possible.
theory is expressed in as many concepts similar to those used in other To be sure, the connections between sciences and, on the other hand, social
theories as possible. institutions, history, etc. are not sufficient to conclude that, for example, physics
and history jointly constitute one coherent whole. Yet, our institutions and
(iii) PROPERTIES OF THE SCOPE COVERED BY THE THEORY history have some connections with, e.g., physics and biology. At the very least,
they exist in a universe following the laws of physics, and they must fit the
9. Number of Cases biological limitations of human beings. Social institutions which aim at the
A further criterion of coherence is the number of cases a theory covers. For_ achievement of the physically or biologically impossible are, of course, doomed.
example, coherence increases when a theory covers an increased number of On the other hand, some science fiction stories, or even political ideologies,
alleged data, that is, "data candidates." We do not assume here any strong theory may fulfil other criteria of coherence to a high degree, yet they lack connection
of data. Instead, we think that the criteria of coherence may contribute to with many fields of life. If such a story covered our life so well that, among
establish the required difference between proper candidates to the data status, other things, a person performing his everyday actions had to pay attention
e.g., physical experiment, and improper candidates, such as dreams and spiritual to it in a similar manner as to his physical, chemical, and biological charac-
revelations. teristics and conditions, it would no longer be a science fiction but a coherent,
The following criterion and principle of coherence correspond to this idea: and probably true, theory.
(9) Ceteris paribus, the greater number of individual cases a theory covers,
the more coherent the theory. C. Weighing and Balancing
(9*) When using a theory to justify a statement, one should see to it that the The degree of coherence is determined by weighing and balancing the discussed
theory covers as many indtvidual cases as possible. criteria. One should not follow any of the principles of coherence in isolation
from others. In some cases, the higher the degree of fulfilment of one criterion,
To some extent, the number of cases a theory covers depends both on the the lower that of another. For example, the supportive chain of reasons may be
dimensions of the supportive structure in question and the generality of the • particularly long when one uses less general concepts, and shrink substantially
applied concepts. To this extent, the criterion 9 is a corollary of the criteria - when the concepts applied become more general. In such a case, one must
1-8 discussed above. "perform a complicated act of weighing in order to answer the question which
theory is more coherent, the more general one, or the one containing the longer
10. Diversity of Fields of Life chain of reasons.
From another point of view, however, a theory has a greater scope, if the cases_
to which it applies are more diversified, that is, belong to more different areas
11. Coherence and Practical Rationality
of knowledge. A particular logical calculus is thus especially important if-
applicable to very different areas, e.g., to modal and deontic logic. A theory What is the importance and the full impact of coherence7 In the present context
of weighing and balancing is particularly important if applicable to such different we cannot discuss this complex problem in a comprehensive manner. We will
fields as economics, law, and practical philosophy. limit ourselves to a few brief remarks on the coherence of practical statements.
The theory or the cluster of theories in question should be as wide-ranging as To clarify the contribution of coherence to practical rationality, one can
possible. Indeed, the most important theories formulated in physics, chemistry, discuss the difference between a legal justification which is supported by a fairly
biology, etc., are supportively and conceptually linked together in such a manner coherent system and a justification which has no such support. A legal justifica-
that they jointly constitute a coherent set of propositions covering a great number tion which neither explicitly nor implicitly refers to a system is an ad hoc
of fields of life and showing some supportive and conceptual connections with justification. Neither universal nor general, it would not fulfil elementary
many fields of life. , demands of justice (MacCormick 1984: 243). Justice requires that legal justifica-
The following criterion and prin~iple of coherence are thus justifiable. tion is embedded in a fairly coherent system. Moreover, the connection with a
144 Robert Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik Coherence and Discursive Rationality 145

system has a number of further results to be positively evaluated from the point cross-connections between various theories; (9) the greatest possible number
of view of practical rationality (Alexy 1989, 266f£.): Legal dogmatics creates of cases covered by the theory; and (10) the greatest possible number of fields
a system of concepts and statements which enables one to collect, test, and of life covered by the theory.
improve opinions expressed by many generations of jurists. In this way, it Thus, it seems to be sufficiently clear that we can have not only feelings and
contributes to stability and progress. Within such a system, statements are tested emotions concerning practical matters but also more or less well-grounded
in a much more efficient way than within an unsystematic ad hoc justification. judgements. Certainly, a judgement based exclusively on feelings and emotions
Moreover, construction of the system results in new insights, which persons may have some advantages. For example, it may be better than a well-grounded
solely engaged in an ad hoc justification would hardly gain. Finally, the system judgement insofar as it is easier to obtain. But it is difficult to doubt that a
makes the work of the decision-maker easier. He can rely upon statements which judgement which is supported by argument is better in what concerns rationality
have already been tested many times, and has no need to return to the hopeless and correctness than a judgement which has no such support. Then the question
task of justifying everything at once in each case. occurs: Should we deal with problems of our times in a rational way or not7
Generally, it can be said that the concept of justification is related to that
of support. Justification in a strong sense includes support and additional require-
Ill. Coherence and Consensus
ments. A central one is that of coherence. Moreover, such concepts as rationality
and correctness are related to that of justification and thus coherence. Therefore The advantages of a coherent system are limited by three necessary disadvantages.
one can say that coherence is a central element of a fully-fledged concept of The first one follows from the concept of coherence. Coherence is a matter
justification, rationality, and correctness. This relation can be expressed as of degree. It also depends on the weighing and balancing of partly incompatible
follows: demands. The criteria of coherence do not always lead to a unique answer to
the question of whether one system is more coherent than another. In some
If the norm- or value-system in question is more coherent than any competing system, cases, they only decide that one system is more coherent in one respect, another
then it is prima facie better justified and more rational than any competing system. If
system in another respect. The choice between the systems requires then an
the norm- or value-system in question is more coherent than any competing system,
then there exists a prima facie reason that it is correct. evaluation which cannot be based solely on criteria of coherence.
The second limitation follows from the formal character of coherence. The
These analytical connections between coherence, justification, rationality, and criteria of coherence do not say anything about the content of normative
correctness might, however, not convince a sceptic. He might say that all this systems. Certainly, the criteria comprise generality and universality. Moreover,
talk about justification, rationality, and correctness is an illusion while the plain a fully elaborated justification is apt to contribute to rationality and justice rather
fact is that practical statements merely express our arbitrary feelings. than to irrationality and injustice. Thus, fulfilment of the criteria restricts
However, one can advance the following arguments against this kind of irrationality and contributes to justice. Yet, it cannot entirely eliminate unjust
scepticism. The fact that one can arrange one's opinions concerning practical and unreasonable contents of a normative system.
problems into a coherent whole means that one can rationally think about these The third limitation is the most important in practice. It results from the
problems. One could try to explicate the very concept of rational thinking as. necessary incompleteness ("open texture") of all normative systems, regardless
an effort to obtain a balance between the following criteria of coherence: (1) of their degree of coherence. A creation as well as an application of a normative
the greatest possible number of supported statements belonging to the theory system makes it necessary to formulate some new norm-statements and value-
in question; (2) the greatest possible length of chains of reasons belonging to statements. This fact is particularly important when the following steps are
it; (3) the greatest possible number of strongly supported statements belonging concerned: the step from relatively general to relatively special norms (4.1),
to the theory; (4) the greatest possible number of connections between various the weighing and balancing of principles (5.), and the creation of a reflective
supportive chains belonging to the theory; (5) the greatest possible number of equilibrium (6.3). .
preference relations between various principles belonging to it; (6) the greatest These limitations do not destroy the idea of a coherent system of statements.
possible number and complexity of reciprocal supportive relations between However, they show that another level is also important. that is, the procedural
various statements belonging to the theory; (7) the greatest possible number level. in which persons and their acts of reasoning play the decisive role. The
of universal statements belonging to the theory; the greatest possible number idea of justification connects these levels with each other. Justification requires
of general concepts belonging to it; the highest possible degree of generality two things. Firstly, it requires the creation of a system of statements as coherent
of concepts implemented within it; the gfeatest possible number of resemblances as possible. Therefore, it is true, perhaps even analytically true, that if a norm-
between concepts used within it; (8) the ~eatest possible number of conceptual or value-system in question is more coherent than any competing system, then
146 Robert Alexy and Aleksander Peczenik Coherence and Discursive Rationality 147
consensus about it would be prima facie rational. Secondly, justification requires 1814. Vom Beruf
a procedure of argumentation as rational as possible, which aims at a reasonable von SaVI' gny
, Friedrich Carl.
. d . unsrer Zeit fur Gesetzgebung und
Rechtswissenschaft. Heldelberg: Mo~r un . Zlmmer. . . .
consensus. A theory of rational discourse deals with this requirement (Alexy von Wright, Georg Henrik. 1957. DeontIc LogIC. In G. H. v~n Wnght, LogIcal StudieS,
1989, 188ff., 221ff.). However, this is another topic. 58-74. London: RoutIedge and Kegan Paul. (1st ed. Mlrld, 1951.)

Christian Albrechts University


Faculty of Law
Olshausenstraj3e 40
0-2300 Kie1 1
West Germany

University of Lund
Box 207
5-22100 Lund
Sweden

References
Aamio, Aulis. 1987. The Rational as Reasonable. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Alexy, Robert. 1985a. Theorie der Grundrechte. Baden-Baden: Nomos (Frankfurt 1986:
Suhrkamp).
---.1985b. Rechtsregeln und Rechtsprinzipien. Archiv fUr Rechts- und Sozial-
philosophie, Beiheft 25: 13-29.
---.1987. Argumentation, Argumentationstheorie. In Ergiinzbares Lexikon des
Rechts. Neuwied: Luchterhand.
---.1989. A Theory of Legal Argumentation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Burks, Arthur W. 1977. Chance, Cause, Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law's Empire. London: Fontana.
Hare, R. M. 1972-73. Principles. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73: 1-18.
Hegel, Georg W. F. 1970. Phiinomenologie des Geistes. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Kant, Immanuel. 1983. Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche
BuchgeseIlschaft.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960. Reine Rechtslehre. 2nd ed. Vienna: Deuticke.
Lakatos, Imre. 1970. Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Pro-
grammes. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave,
91-196. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
MacCormick, Neil. 1984. Coherence in Legal Justification. In Theory of Legal Science.
Ed. A. Peczenik et aI., 235-51. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Peczenik, Aleksander. 1979. Causes and Damages. Lund: Juridiska fiireningen.
- - - . 1983. The Basis of Legal Justification. Lund: Lund University Press.
- - - . 1988a. Ratten och fornuftet. 2nd ed. Stockholm: Norstedt.
- - - . 1988b. Legal Reasoning as a Special Case of Moral Reasoning. Ratio Juris 1:
123-36.
Quine, WilIard Van Orman. 1961. Methods of Logic. Revised ed. New York: Holt,
Rinehart, and Winston.
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rescher, Nicholas. 1973. The Coherence'Theory of Truth. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.

You might also like