Abductive Reasoning: 2 Deduction, Induction, and Ab-Duction

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

Abductive reasoning

“Abductive” redirects here. For other uses, see 2 Deduction, induction, and ab-
Abduction (disambiguation).
duction
Abductive reasoning (also called abduction,[1] abduc- Main article: Logical reasoning
tive inference[2] or retroduction[3] ) is a form of logical
inference which goes from an observation to a theory
which accounts for the observation, ideally seeking to find Deductive reasoning (deduction) allows deriving b
the simplest and most likely explanation. In abductive from a only where b is a formal logical consequence
reasoning, unlike in deductive reasoning, the premises do of a . In other words, deduction derives the con-
not guarantee the conclusion. One can understand abduc- sequences of the assumed. Given the truth of the
tive reasoning as “inference to the best explanation”.[4] assumptions, a valid deduction guarantees the truth
The fields of law,[5] computer science, and artificial in- of the conclusion. For example, given that 'Wikis
telligence research[6] renewed interest in the subject of can be edited by anyone' ( a 1) and 'Wikipedia is a
abduction. Diagnostic expert systems frequently employ wiki' ( a 2), it follows that 'Wikipedia can be edited
abduction. by anyone' ( b ).

Inductive reasoning (induction) allows inferring b


from a , where b does not follow necessarily from
a . a might give us very good reason to accept b ,
but it does not ensure b . For example, if all swans
that we have observed so far are white, we may
induce that the possibility that all swans are white
is reasonable. We have good reason to believe the
conclusion from the premise, but the truth of the
1 History conclusion is not guaranteed. (Indeed, it turns out
that some swans are black.)

The American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce Abductive reasoning (abduction) allows inferring a
(1839–1914) first introduced the term as “guessing”.[7] as an explanation of b . Because of this inference,
Peirce said that to abduce a hypothetical explanation a abduction allows the precondition a to be abduced
from an observed circumstance b is to surmise that a may from the consequence b . Deductive reasoning and
be true because then b would be a matter of course. [8] abductive reasoning thus differ in the direction in
Thus, to abduce a from b involves determining that a is which a rule like " a entails b " is used for inference.
sufficient, but not necessary, for b . As such, abduction is formally equivalent to the log-
ical fallacy of affirming the consequent (or Post hoc
For example, suppose we observe that the lawn is wet. If ergo propter hoc) because of multiple possible ex-
it rained last night, then it would be unsurprising that the planations for b . For example, in a billiard game,
lawn is wet. Therefore, by abductive reasoning, the pos- after glancing and seeing the eight ball moving to-
sibility that it rained last night is reasonable (but note that wards us, we may abduce that the cue ball struck
Peirce did not remain convinced that a single logical form the eight ball. The strike of the cue ball would ac-
covers all abduction);[9] however, some other process may count for the movement of the eight ball. It serves
have also resulted in a wet lawn, e.g. dew or lawn sprin- as a hypothesis that explains our observation. Given
klers. Moreover, abducing that it rained last night from the many possible explanations for the movement of
the observation of a wet lawn can lead to false conclu- the eight ball, our abduction does not leave us cer-
sion(s). tain that the cue ball in fact struck the eight ball, but
Peirce argues that good abductive reasoning from P to Q our abduction, still useful, can serve to orient us in
involves not simply a determination that Q is sufficient for our surroundings. Despite many possible explana-
P, but also that Q is among the most economical explana- tions for any physical process that we observe, we
tions for P. Simplification and economy both call for that tend to abduce a single explanation (or a few ex-
“leap” of abduction.[10] planations) for this process in the expectation that

1
2 3 FORMALIZATIONS OF ABDUCTION

we can better orient ourselves in our surroundings hypotheses. Formally, we are given a set of hypotheses
and disregard some possibilities. Properly used, ab- H and a set of manifestations M ; they are related by the
ductive reasoning can be a useful source of priors in domain knowledge, represented by a function e that takes
Bayesian statistics. as an argument a set of hypotheses and gives as a result
the corresponding set of manifestations. In other words,
for every subset of the hypotheses H ′ ⊆ H , their effects
3 Formalizations of abduction are known to be e(H ′ ) .
Abduction is performed by finding a set H ′ ⊆ H such
3.1 Logic-based abduction that M ⊆ e(H ′ ) . In other words, abduction is performed
by finding a set of hypotheses H ′ such that their effects

In logic, explanation is done from a logical theory T rep- e(H ) include all observations M .
resenting a domain and a set of observations O . Abduc- A common assumption is that the effects of the hypothe-
tion is the process of deriving a set of explanations of O ses are independent, that is, for every H ′ ⊆ H , it holds
according to T and picking out one of those explanations. that e(H ′ ) = ∪
h∈H ′ e({h}) . If this condition is met,
For E to be an explanation of O according to T , it should abduction can be seen as a form of set covering.
satisfy two conditions:

• O follows from E and T ;


3.3 Abductive validation
• E is consistent with T .
Abductive validation is the process of validating a given
In formal logic, O and E are assumed to be sets of liter- hypothesis through abductive reasoning. This can also be
als. The two conditions for E being an explanation of O called reasoning through successive approximation. Un-
according to theory T are formalized as: der this principle, an explanation is valid if it is the best
possible explanation of a set of known data. The best pos-
sible explanation is often defined in terms of simplicity
T ∪ E |= O and elegance (see Occam’s razor). Abductive validation
is common practice in hypothesis formation in science;
T ∪E
moreover, Peirce claims that it is a ubiquitous aspect of
Among the possible explanations E satisfying these two thought:
conditions, some other condition of minimality is usually
imposed to avoid irrelevant facts (not contributing to the
entailment of O ) being included in the explanations. Ab- Looking out my window this lovely spring
duction is then the process that picks out some member of morning, I see an azalea in full bloom. No,
E . Criteria for picking out a member representing “the no! I don't see that; though that is the only way
best” explanation include the simplicity, the prior proba- I can describe what I see. That is a proposi-
bility, or the explanatory power of the explanation. tion, a sentence, a fact; but what I perceive is
not proposition, sentence, fact, but only an im-
A proof theoretical abduction method for first order clas-
age, which I make intelligible in part by means
sical logic based on the sequent calculus and a dual one,
of a statement of fact. This statement is ab-
based on semantic tableaux (analytic tableaux) have been
stract; but what I see is concrete. I perform
proposed (Cialdea Mayer & Pirri 1993). The methods
an abduction when I so much as express in a
are sound and complete and work for full first order logic,
sentence anything I see. The truth is that the
without requiring any preliminary reduction of formulae
whole fabric of our knowledge is one matted
into normal forms. These methods have also been ex-
felt of pure hypothesis confirmed and refined
tended to modal logic.
by induction. Not the smallest advance can be
Abductive logic programming is a computational frame- made in knowledge beyond the stage of vacant
work that extends normal logic programming with abduc- staring, without making an abduction at every
tion. It separates the theory T into two components, one step.[11]
of which is a normal logic program, used to generate E by
means of backward reasoning, the other of which is a set
of integrity constraints, used to filter the set of candidate It was Peirce’s own maxim that “Facts cannot be ex-
explanations. plained by a hypothesis more extraordinary than these
facts themselves; and of various hypotheses the least ex-
traordinary must be adopted.”[12] After obtaining results
3.2 Set-cover abduction from an inference procedure, we may be left with mul-
tiple assumptions, some of which may be contradictory.
A different formalization of abduction is based on invert- Abductive validation is a method for identifying the as-
ing the function that calculates the visible effects of the sumptions that will lead to your goal.
3.5 Subjective logic abduction 3

3.4 Probabilistic abduction Probabilistic abduction can thus be described as a method


for inverting conditionals in order to apply probabilistic
Probabilistic abductive reasoning is a form of abductive deduction.
validation, and is used extensively in areas where conclu- A medical test result is typically considered positive or
sions about possible hypotheses need to be derived, such negative, so when applying the above equation it can be
as for making diagnoses from medical tests. For exam- assumed that either p(x) = 1 (positive) or p(x) = 1
ple, a pharmaceutical company that develops a test for a (negative). In case the patient tests positive, the above
particular infectious disease will typically determine the equation can be simplified to p(y∥x) = p(y|x) which
reliability of the test by hiring a group of infected and a will give the correct likelihood that the patient actually is
group of non-infected people to undergo the test. Assume infected.
the statements x : “Positive test”, x : “Negative test”, y :
The Base rate fallacy in medicine,[13] or the Prosecutor’s
“Infected”, and y : “Not infected”. The result of these tri-
fallacy[14] in legal reasoning, consists of making the er-
als will then determine the reliability of the test in terms
roneous assumption that p(y|x) = p(x|y) . While this
of its sensitivity p(x|y) and false positive rate p(x|y) .
reasoning error often can produce a relatively good ap-
The interpretations of the conditionals are: p(x|y) : “The
proximation of the correct hypothesis probability value,
probability of positive test given infection”, and p(x|y) :
it can lead to a completely wrong result and wrong con-
“The probability of positive test in the absence of infec-
clusion in case the base rate is very low and the reliability
tion”. The problem with applying these conditionals in a
of the test is not perfect. An extreme example of the base
practical setting is that they are expressed in the opposite
rate fallacy is to conclude that a male person is pregnant
direction to what the practitioner needs. The condition-
just because he tests positive in a pregnancy test. Obvi-
als needed for making the diagnosis are: p(y|x) : “The
ously, the base rate of male pregnancy is zero, and as-
probability of infection given positive test”, and p(y|x)
suming that the test is not perfect, it would be correct to
: “The probability of infection given negative test”. The
conclude that the male person is not pregnant.
probability of infection could then have been condition-
ally deduced as p(y∥x) = p(x)p(y|x) + p(x)p(y|x) , The expression for probabilistic abduction can be gener-
[15]
where " ∥ " denotes conditional deduction. Unfortunately alised to multinomial cases, i.e., with a state space X
the required conditionals are usually not directly available of multiple x i and a state space Y of multiple states yj .
to the medical practitioner, but they can be obtained if the
base rate of the infection in the population is known.
The required conditionals can be correctly derived by 3.5 Subjective logic abduction
inverting the available conditionals using Bayes rule.
The
{ inverted conditionals are obtained as follows: Subjective logic generalises probabilistic logic by includ-
p(x|y) = p(x∧y) ing parameters for uncertainty in the input arguments.
p(y)
⇒ p(y|x) = p(y)p(x|y) . Abduction in subjective logic is thus similar to probabilis-
p(y|x) = p(x∧y) p(x)
p(x)
tic abduction described above.[15] The input arguments in
The term p(y) on the right hand side of the equation ex-
subjective logic are composite functions called subjective
presses the base rate of the infection in the population.
opinions which can be binomial when the opinion applies
Similarly, the term p(x) expresses the default likelihood
to a single proposition or multinomial when it applies to a
of positive test on a random person in the population. In
set of propositions. A multinomial opinion thus applies to
the expressions below a(y) and a(y) = 1 − a(y) denote
a frame X (i.e. a state space of exhaustive and mutually
the base rates of y and its complement y respectively, so
disjoint propositions xi ), and is denoted by the compos-
that e.g. p(x) = a(y)p(x|y) + a(y)p(x|y) . The full ex-
ite function ωX = (⃗b, u, ⃗a) , where ⃗b is a vector of belief
pression for the required conditionals p(y|x) and p(y|x)
masses over the propositions of X , u is the uncertainty
are then
{ mass, and ⃗a is a vector of base rate values over
∑ the propo-
a(y)p(x|y)
p(y|x) = a(y)p(x|y)+a(y)p(x|y) sitions of X . These components satisfy u+ ⃗b(xi ) = 1

p(y|x) = a(y)p(x|y)
a(y)p(x|y)+a(y)p(x|y)
and ⃗a(xi ) = 1 as well as ⃗b(xi ), u, ⃗a(xi ) ∈ [0, 1] .
The full expression for the conditionally abduced proba- Assume the frames X and Y , the sets of conditional
bility of infection in a tested person, expressed as p(y∥x) opinions ωX|Y and ωX|Y , the opinion ωX on X , and
, given the outcome of the test, the base rate of the infec- the base rate function aY on Y . Based on these pa-
tion, as well as the test’s sensitivity and false positive rate, rameters, subjective logic provides a method for deriving
is then given by the set of inverted conditionals ωY |X and ωY |X . Using
( ) these inverted conditionals, subjective logic also provides
a(y)p(x|y)
p(y∥x) = p(x) a(y)p(x|y)+a(y)p(x|y) + a method for deduction. Abduction in subjective logic
( )
a(y)p(x|y)
p(x) a(y)p(x|y)+a(y)p(x|y) . consists of inverting the conditionals and then applying
deduction.
This further simplifies to The symbolic notation for conditional abduction is " ∥
p(y∥x) = a(y) (p(x|y) + p(x|y)) . ", and the operator itself is denoted as ⊚ . The expres-
4 4 HISTORY

sion for subjective logic abduction is then:[15] ωY ∥X = by rules of logic.[8] Even a well-prepared mind’s
ωX ⊚ (ωX|Y , ωX|Y , aY ) . individual guesses are more frequently wrong than
right.[18] But the success of our guesses far exceeds
The advantage of using subjective logic abduction com- that of random luck and seems born of attunement
pared to probabilistic abduction is that uncertainty about to nature by instinct[19] (some speak of intuition in
the probability values of the input arguments can be ex- such contexts[20] ).
plicitly expressed and taken into account during the analy-
sis. It is thus possible to perform abductive analysis in the • Abduction guesses a new or outside idea so as to ac-
presence of missing or incomplete input evidence, which count in a plausible, instinctive, economical way for
normally results in degrees of uncertainty in the output a surprising or very complicated phenomenon. That
conclusions. is its proximate aim.[19]
• Its longer aim is to economize inquiry itself. Its ra-
tionale is inductive: it works often enough, is the
4 History only source of new ideas, and has no substitute in
expediting the discovery of new truths.[21] Its ratio-
The philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce (/ˈpɜrs/; 1839– nale especially involves its role in coordination with
1914) introduced abduction into modern logic. Over the other modes of inference in inquiry. It is inference
years he called such inference hypothesis, abduction, pre- to explanatory hypotheses for selection of those best
sumption, and retroduction. He considered it a topic in worth trying.
logic as a normative field in philosophy, not in purely for-
mal or mathematical logic, and eventually as a topic also • Pragmatism is the logic of abduction. Upon the gen-
in economics of research. eration of an explanation (which he came to regard
as instinctively guided), the pragmatic maxim gives
As two stages of the development, extension, etc., of
the necessary and sufficient logical rule to abduction
a hypothesis in scientific inquiry, abduction and also
in general. The hypothesis, being insecure, needs to
induction are often collapsed into one overarching con-
have conceivable[22] implications for informed prac-
cept — the hypothesis. That is why, in the scientific
tice, so as to be testable[23][24] and, through its trials,
method pioneered by Galileo and Bacon, the abductive
to expedite and economize inquiry. The economy
stage of hypothesis formation is conceptualized simply
of research is what calls for abduction and governs
as induction. Thus, in the twentieth century this col-
its art.[10]
lapse was reinforced by Karl Popper's explication of the
hypothetico-deductive model, where the hypothesis is
considered to be just “a guess”[16] (in the spirit of Peirce). Writing in 1910, Peirce admits that “in almost everything
However, when the formation of a hypothesis is consid- I printed before the beginning of this century I more or
ered the result of a process it becomes clear that this less mixed up hypothesis and induction” and he traces
“guess” has already been tried and made more robust in the confusion of these two types of reasoning to logi-
thought as a necessary stage of its acquiring the status cians’ too “narrow and formalistic a conception of infer-
of hypothesis. Indeed, many abductions are rejected or ence, as necessarily having formulated judgments from
heavily modified by subsequent abductions before they its premises.”[25]
ever reach this stage. He started out in the 1860s treating hypothetical inference
Before 1900, Peirce treated abduction as the use of a in a number of ways which he eventually peeled away as
known rule to explain an observation, e.g., it is a known inessential or, in some cases, mistaken:
rule that if it rains the grass is wet; so, to explain the fact
that the grass is wet; one infers that it has rained. This • as inferring the occurrence of a character (a charac-
remains the common use of the term “abduction” in the teristic) from the observed combined occurrence of
social sciences and in artificial intelligence. multiple characters which its occurrence would nec-
Peirce consistently characterized it as the kind of infer- essarily involve;[26] for example, if any occurrence
ence that originates a hypothesis by concluding in an ex- of A is known to necessitate occurrence of B, C, D,
planation, though an unassured one, for some very cu- E, then the observation of B, C, D, E suggests by way
rious or surprising (anomalous) observation stated in a of explanation the occurrence of A. (But by 1878 he
premise. As early as 1865 he wrote that all conceptions no longer regarded such multiplicity as common to
of cause and force are reached through hypothetical infer- all hypothetical inference.[27] )
ence; in the 1900s he wrote that all explanatory content of • as aiming for a more or less probable hypothesis
theories is reached through abduction. In other respects (in 1867 and 1883 but not in 1878; anyway by
Peirce revised his view of abduction over the years.[17] 1900 the justification is not probability but the lack
In later years his view came to be: of alternatives to guessing and the fact that guess-
ing is fruitful;[28] by 1903 he speaks of the “likely”
• Abduction is guessing.[7] It is “very little hampered” in the sense of nearing the truth in an “indefinite
4.4 1902 and after 5

sense";[29] by 1908 he discusses plausibility as in- the hypothetical conclusion.[32] Like “Deduction, Induc-
stinctive appeal.[19] ) In a paper dated by editors tion, and Hypothesis” in 1878, it was widely read (see
as circa 1901, he discusses “instinct” and “natural- the historical books on statistics by Stephen Stigler), un-
ness”, along with the kind of considerations (low like his later amendments of his conception of abduction.
cost of testing, logical caution, breadth, and incom- Today abduction remains most commonly understood as
plexity) that he later calls methodeutical.[30] induction from characters and extension of a known rule
to cover unexplained circumstances.
• as induction from characters (but as early as 1900 he
characterized abduction as guessing[28] ) Sherlock Holmes uses this method of reasoning in the sto-
ries of Arthur Conan Doyle, although Holmes refers to it
• as citing a known rule in a premise rather than hy- as deductive reasoning.
pothesizing a rule in the conclusion (but by 1903 he
allowed either approach[8][31] )
4.4 1902 and after
• as basically a transformation of a deductive categor-
ical syllogism[27] (but in 1903 he offered a variation In 1902 Peirce wrote that he now regarded the syllogisti-
on modus ponens instead,[8] and by 1911 he was un- cal forms and the doctrine of extension and comprehen-
convinced that any one form covers all hypothetical sion (i.e., objects and characters as referenced by terms),
inference[9] ). as being less fundamental than he had earlier thought.[33]
In 1903 he offered the following form for abduction:[8]
4.1 1867 The surprising fact, C, is observed;
In 1867, in “The Natural Classification of But if A were true, C would be a
Arguments”,[26] hypothetical inference always deals matter of course,
with a cluster of characters (call them P′, P′′, P′′′, etc.) Hence, there is reason to suspect
known to occur at least whenever a certain character (M) that A is true.
occurs. Note that categorical syllogisms have elements
traditionally called middles, predicates, and subjects. The hypothesis is framed, but not asserted, in a premise,
For example: All men [middle] are mortal [predicate]; then asserted as rationally suspectable in the conclusion.
Socrates [subject] is a man [middle]; ergo Socrates Thus, as in the earlier categorical syllogistic form, the
[subject] is mortal [predicate]". Below, 'M' stands for a conclusion is formulated from some premise(s). But all
middle; 'P' for a predicate; 'S' for a subject. Note also the same the hypothesis consists more clearly than ever
that Peirce held that all deduction can be put into the in a new or outside idea beyond what is known or ob-
form of the categorical syllogism Barbara (AAA-1). served. Induction in a sense goes beyond observations
already reported in the premises, but it merely amplifies
ideas already known to represent occurrences, or tests an
idea supplied by hypothesis; either way it requires previ-
ous abductions in order to get such ideas in the first place.
4.2 1878 Induction seeks facts to test a hypothesis; abduction seeks
a hypothesis to account for facts.
In 1878, in “Deduction, Induction, and Hypothesis”,[27] Note that the hypothesis (“A”) could be of a rule. It need
there is no longer a need for multiple characters or pred- not even be a rule strictly necessitating the surprising ob-
icates in order for an inference to be hypothetical, al- servation (“C”), which needs to follow only as a “matter
though it is still helpful. Moreover, Peirce no longer poses of course"; or the “course” itself could amount to some
hypothetical inference as concluding in a probable hy- known rule, merely alluded to, and also not necessarily
pothesis. In the forms themselves, it is understood but a rule of strict necessity. In the same year, Peirce wrote
not explicit that induction involves random selection and that reaching a hypothesis may involve placing a surpris-
that hypothetical inference involves response to a “very ing observation under either a newly hypothesized rule or
curious circumstance”. The forms instead emphasize the a hypothesized combination of a known rule with a pecu-
modes of inference as rearrangements of one another’s liar state of facts, so that the phenomenon would be not
propositions (without the bracketed hints shown below). surprising but instead either necessarily implied or at least
likely.[31]
4.3 1883 Peirce did not remain quite convinced about any such
form as the categorical syllogistic form or the 1903 form.
Peirce long treated abduction in terms of induction from In 1911, he wrote, “I do not, at present, feel quite con-
characters or traits (weighed, not counted like objects), vinced that any logical form can be assigned that will
explicitly so in his influential 1883 “A Theory of Probable cover all 'Retroductions’. For what I mean by a Retroduc-
Inference”, in which he returns to involving probability in tion is simply a conjecture which arises in the mind.”[9]
6 4 HISTORY

4.5 Pragmatism 4.6.1 Classification of signs

In 1901 Peirce wrote, “There would be no logic in impos- As early as 1866,[37] Peirce held that:
ing rules, and saying that they ought to be followed, un-
1. Hypothesis (abductive inference) is inference through
til it is made out that the purpose of hypothesis requires
an icon (also called a likeness).
them.”[34] In 1903 Peirce called pragmatism “the logic
2. Induction is inference through an index (a sign by fac-
of abduction” and said that the pragmatic maxim gives
tual connection); a sample is an index of the totality from
the necessary and sufficient logical rule to abduction in
which it is drawn.
general.[24] The pragmatic maxim is: “Consider what ef-
3. Deduction is inference through a symbol (a sign by in-
fects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we
terpretive habit irrespective of resemblance or connection
conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our
to its object).
conception of these effects is the whole of our conception
of the object.” It is a method for fruitful clarification of In 1902, Peirce wrote that, in abduction: “It is recognized
conceptions by equating the meaning of a conception with that the phenomena are like, i.e. constitute an Icon of, a
the conceivable practical implications of its object’s con- replica of a general conception, or Symbol.”[38]
ceived effects. Peirce held that that is precisely tailored
to abduction’s purpose in inquiry, the forming of an idea
that could conceivably shape informed conduct. In vari- 4.6.2 Critique of arguments
ous writings in the 1900s[10][35] he said that the conduct of
abduction (or retroduction) is governed by considerations At the critical level Peirce examined the forms of ab-
of economy, belonging in particular to the economics of ductive arguments (as discussed above), and came to
research. He regarded economics as a normative science hold that the hypothesis should economize explanation
whose analytic portion might be part of logical methodeu- for plausibility in terms of the feasible and natural. In
tic (that is, theory of inquiry).[36] 1908 Peirce described this plausibility in some detail.[19]
It involves not likeliness based on observations (which is
instead the inductive evaluation of a hypothesis), but in-
4.6 Three levels of logic about abduction stead optimal simplicity in the sense of the “facile and
natural”, as by Galileo’s natural light of reason and as
Peirce came over the years to divide (philosophical) logic distinct from “logical simplicity” (Peirce does not dismiss
into three departments: logical simplicity entirely but sees it in a subordinate role;
taken to its logical extreme it would favor adding no ex-
1. Stechiology, or speculative grammar, on the con- planation to the observation at all). Even a well-prepared
ditions for meaningfulness. Classification of signs mind guesses oftener wrong than right, but our guesses
(semblances, symptoms, symbols, etc.) and succeed better than random luck at reaching the truth or
their combinations (as well as their objects and at least advancing the inquiry, and that indicates to Peirce
interpretants). that they are based in instinctive attunement to nature, an
affinity between the mind’s processes and the processes of
2. Logical critic, or logic proper, on validity or justifia-
the real, which would account for why appealingly “nat-
bility of inference, the conditions for true represen-
ural” guesses are the ones that oftenest (or least seldom)
tation. Critique of arguments in their various modes
succeed; to which Peirce added the argument that such
(deduction, induction, abduction).
guesses are to be preferred since, without “a natural bent
3. Methodeutic, or speculative rhetoric, on the condi- like nature’s”, people would have no hope of understand-
tions for determination of interpretations. Method- ing nature. In 1910 Peirce made a three-way distinction
ology of inquiry in its interplay of modes. between probability, verisimilitude, and plausibility, and
defined plausibility with a normative “ought": “By plau-
Peirce had, from the start, seen the modes of inference sibility, I mean the degree to which a theory ought to rec-
as being coordinated together in scientific inquiry and, ommend itself to our belief independently of any kind
by the 1900s, held that hypothetical inference in par- of evidence other than our instinct urging us to regard
ticular is inadequately treated at the level of critique of it favorably.”[39] For Peirce, plausibility does not depend
arguments.[23][24] To increase the assurance of a hypo- on observed frequencies or probabilities, or on verisimil-
thetical conclusion, one needs to deduce implications itude, or even on testability, which is not a question of
about evidence to be found, predictions which induction the critique of the hypothetical inference as an inference,
can test through observation so as to evaluate the hypoth- but rather a question of the hypothesis’s relation to the
esis. That is Peirce’s outline of the scientific method of inquiry process.
inquiry, as covered in his inquiry methodology, which in- The phrase “inference to the best explanation” (not used
cludes pragmatism or, as he later called it, pragmaticism, by Peirce but often applied to hypothetical inference) is
the clarification of ideas in terms of their conceivable im- not always understood as referring to the most simple
plications regarding informed practice. and natural. However, in other senses of “best”, such as
7

“standing up best to tests”, it is hard to know which is the 5 Applications


best explanation to form, since one has not tested it yet.
Still, for Peirce, any justification of an abductive infer-
ence as good is not completed upon its formation as an Applications in artificial intelligence include fault diag-
argument (unlike with induction and deduction) and in- nosis, belief revision, and automated planning. The most
stead depends also on its methodological role and promise direct application of abduction is that of automatically
(such as its testability) in advancing inquiry.[23][24][40] detecting faults in systems: given a theory relating faults
with their effects and a set of observed effects, abduction
can be used to derive sets of faults that are likely to be the
cause of the problem.
4.6.3 Methodology of inquiry
In medicine, abduction can be seen as a component of
[43][44]
At the methodeutical level Peirce held that a hypothesis clinical evaluation and judgment.
is judged and selected[23] for testing because it offers, via Abduction can also be used to model automated plan-
its trial, to expedite and economize the inquiry process ning.[45] Given a logical theory relating action occur-
itself toward new truths, first of all by being testable and rences with their effects (for example, a formula of the
also by further economies,[10] in terms of cost, value, and event calculus), the problem of finding a plan for reach-
relationships among guesses (hypotheses). Here, consid- ing a state can be modeled as the problem of abducting a
erations such as probability, absent from the treatment of set of literals implying that the final state is the goal state.
abduction at the critical level, come into play. For exam-
In intelligence analysis, Analysis of Competing Hypothe-
ples:
ses and Bayesian networks, probabilistic abductive rea-
soning is used extensively. Similarly in medical diagno-
• Cost: A simple but low-odds guess, if low in cost sis and legal reasoning, the same methods are being used,
to test for falsity, may belong first in line for testing, although there have been many examples of errors, espe-
to get it out of the way. If surprisingly it stands up cially caused by the base rate fallacy and the prosecutor’s
to tests, that is worth knowing early in the inquiry, fallacy.
which otherwise might have stayed long on a wrong Belief revision, the process of adapting beliefs in view
though seemingly likelier track. of new information, is another field in which abduction
has been applied. The main problem of belief revision
• Value: A guess is intrinsically worth testing if it has is that the new information may be inconsistent with the
instinctual plausibility or reasoned objective proba- corpus of beliefs, while the result of the incorporation
bility, while subjective likelihood, though reasoned, cannot be inconsistent. This process can be done by the
can be treacherous. use of abduction: once an explanation for the observation
has been found, integrating it does not generate inconsis-
• Interrelationships: Guesses can be chosen for trial tency. This use of abduction is not straightforward, as
strategically for their adding propositional formulae to other propositional for-
mulae can only make inconsistencies worse. Instead, ab-
• caution, for which Peirce gave as example the duction is done at the level of the ordering of preference
game of Twenty Questions, of the possible worlds. Preference models use fuzzy logic
or utility models.
• breadth of applicability to explain various phe-
nomena, and In the philosophy of science, abduction has been the
key inference method to support scientific realism, and
• incomplexity, that of a hypothesis that seems much of the debate about scientific realism is focused on
too simple but whose trial “may give a good whether abduction is an acceptable method of inference.
'leave,' as the billiard-players say”, and be in-
In historical linguistics, abduction during language acqui-
structive for the pursuit of various and conflict-
sition is often taken to be an essential part of processes
ing hypotheses that are less simple.[41]
of language change such as reanalysis and analogy.[46]
In anthropology, Alfred Gell in his influential book Art
and Agency defined abduction (after Eco[47] ) as “a case
4.7 Other writers
of synthetic inference 'where we find some very curious
circumstances, which would be explained by the suppo-
Norwood Russell Hanson, a philosopher of science, sition that it was a case of some general rule, and there-
wanted to grasp a logic explaining how scientific discov- upon adopt that supposition”.[48] Gell criticizes existing
eries take place. He used Peirce’s notion of abduction for 'anthropological' studies of art, for being too preoccupied
this.[42] with aesthetic value and not preoccupied enough with the
Further development of the concept can be found in Peter central anthropological concern of uncovering 'social re-
Lipton's Inference to the Best Explanation (Lipton, 1991). lationships,' specifically the social contexts in which art-
8 7 REFERENCES

works are produced, circulated, and received.[49] Abduc- • Practopoiesis


tion is used as the mechanism for getting from art to
agency. That is, abduction can explain how works of • Logic
art inspire a sensus communis: the commonly-held views • Subjective logic
shared by members that characterize a given society.[50]
The question Gell asks in the book is, 'how does it ini- • Logical reasoning
tially 'speak' to people?' He answers by saying that “No
• Maximum likelihood
reasonable person could suppose that art-like relations be-
tween people and things do not involve at least some form • Scientific method
of semiosis.”[48] However, he rejects any intimation that
semiosis can be thought of as a language because then he • Sherlock Holmes
would have to admit to some pre-established existence of
• Sign relation
the sensus communis that he wants to claim only emerges
afterwards out of art. Abduction is the answer to this
conundrum because the tentative nature of the abduc-
tion concept (Peirce likened it to guessing) means that 7 References
not only can it operate outside of any pre-existing frame-
work, but moreover, it can actually intimate the existence • This article is based on material taken from the Free
of a framework. As Gell reasons in his analysis, the phys- On-line Dictionary of Computing prior to 1 Novem-
ical existence of the artwork prompts the viewer to per- ber 2008 and incorporated under the “relicensing”
form an abduction that imbues the artwork with inten- terms of the GFDL, version 1.3 or later.
tionality. A statue of a goddess, for example, in some
• Awbrey, Jon, and Awbrey, Susan (1995), “Inter-
senses actually becomes the goddess in the mind of the
pretation as Action: The Risk of Inquiry”, Inquiry:
beholder; and represents not only the form of the deity
Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines, 15, 40-52.
but also her intentions (which are adduced from the feel-
Eprint
ing of her very presence). Therefore, through abduction,
Gell claims that art can have the kind of agency that plants • Cialdea Mayer, Marta and Pirri, Fiora (1993)
the seeds that grow into cultural myths. The power of “First order abduction via tableau and sequent
agency is the power to motivate actions and inspire ul- calculi” Logic Jnl IGPL 1993 1: 99-117;
timately the shared understanding that characterizes any doi:10.1093/jigpal/1.1.99. Oxford Journals
given society.[50]
• Cialdea Mayer, Marta and Pirri, Fiora
(1995) “Propositional Abduction in Modal
Logic”, Logic Jnl IGPL 1995 3: 907-919;
6 See also doi:10.1093/jigpal/3.6.907 Oxford Journals

• Abductive logic programming • Edwards, Paul (1967, eds.), “The Encyclopedia of


Philosophy,” Macmillan Publishing Co, Inc. & The
• Analogy Free Press, New York. Collier Macmillan Publish-
ers, London.
• Analysis of Competing Hypotheses
• Eiter, T., and Gottlob, G. (1995), “The Complex-
• Charles Sanders Peirce
ity of Logic-Based Abduction, Journal of the ACM,
• Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography 42.1, 3-42.

• Deductive reasoning • Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of Discovery: An


Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science,
• Defeasible reasoning Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN
978-0-521-09261-6.
• Doug Walton
• Harman, Gilbert (1965). “The Inference to the Best
• Gregory Bateson Explanation”. The Philosophical Review 74 (1): 88–
95. doi:10.2307/2183532.
• Inductive inference
• Josephson, John R., and Josephson, Susan G. (1995,
• Inductive probability
eds.), Abductive Inference: Computation, Philoso-
• Inductive reasoning phy, Technology, Cambridge University Press, Cam-
bridge, UK.
• Inquiry
• Lipton, Peter. (2001). Inference to the Best Expla-
• List of thinking-related topics nation, London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-24202-9.
9

• McKaughan, Daniel J. (2008), “From Ugly Duck- [5] See, e.g. Analysis of Evidence, 2d ed. by Terence Ander-
ling to Swan: C. S. Peirce, Abduction, and the son (Cambridge University Press, 2005)
Pursuit of Scientific Theories”, Transactions of the
[6] For examples, see "Abductive Inference in Reasoning
Charles S. Peirce Society, v. 44, no. 3 (summer),
and Perception", John R. Josephson, Laboratory for Ar-
446–468. Abstract. tificial Intelligence Research, Ohio State University, and
Abduction, Reason, and Science. Processes of Discov-
• Menzies, T (1996). “Applications of Abduction:
ery and Explanation by Lorenzo Magnani (Kluwer Aca-
Knowledge-Level Modeling” (PDF). International
demic/Plenum Publishers, New York, 2001).
Journal of Human-Computer Studies 45 (3): 305–
335. doi:10.1006/ijhc.1996.0054. [7] Peirce, C. S.

• Queiroz, Joao & Merrell, Floyd (guest eds.). (2005). • “On the Logic of drawing History from Ancient
“Abduction - between subjectivity and objectivity”. Documents especially from Testimonies” (1901),
(special issue on abductive inference) Semiotica 153 Collected Papers v. 7, paragraph 219.
(1/4). . • “PAP” ["Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragma-
tism"], MS 293 c. 1906, New Elements of Mathe-
• Santaella, Lucia (1997) “The Development of matics v. 4, pp. 319-320.
Peirce’s Three Types of Reasoning: Abduction, De-
• A Letter to F. A. Woods (1913), Collected Papers
duction, and Induction”, 6th Congress of the IASS.
v. 8, paragraphs 385-388.
Eprint.
(See under "Abduction" and "Retroduction" at Commens
• Sebeok, T. (1981) “You Know My Method”. In Se- Dictionary of Peirce’s Terms.)
beok, T. “The Play of Musement”. Indiana. Bloom-
ington, IA. [8] Peirce, C. S. (1903), Harvard lectures on pragmatism,
Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 188–189.
• Yu, Chong Ho (1994), “Is There a Logic of Ex-
ploratory Data Analysis?", Annual Meeting of Amer- [9] A Letter to J. H. Kehler (1911), New Elements of Mathe-
ican Educational Research Association, New Or- matics v. 3, pp. 203–4, see under "Retroduction" at Com-
mens Dictionary of Peirce’s Terms.
leans, LA, April, 1994. Website of Dr. Chong Ho
(Alex) Yu [10] Peirce, C.S. (1902), application to the Carnegie Institu-
tion, see MS L75.329-330, from Draft D of Memoir 27:

Consequently, to discover is simply to


8 Notes expedite an event that would occur sooner
or later, if we had not troubled ourselves to
[1] • Magnani, L. “Abduction, Reason, and Science: make the discovery. Consequently, the art of
Processes of Discovery and Explanation”. Kluwer discovery is purely a question of economics.
Academic Plenum Publishers, New York, 2001. xvii. The economics of research is, so far as logic
205 pages. Hard cover, ISBN 0-306-46514-0. is concerned, the leading doctrine with refer-
• R. Josephson, J. & G. Josephson, S. “Abductive ence to the art of discovery. Consequently,
Inference: Computation, Philosophy, Technology” the conduct of abduction, which is chiefly a
Cambridge University Press, New York & Cam- question of heuristic and is the first question
bridge (U.K.). viii. 306 pages. Hard cover (1994), of heuristic, is to be governed by economical
ISBN 0-521-43461-0, Paperback (1996), ISBN 0- considerations.
521-57545-1.
[11] Peirce MS. 692, quoted in Sebeok, T. (1981) "You Know
• Bunt, H. & Black, W. “Abduction, Belief and Con- My Method" in Sebeok, T., The Play of Musement,
text in Dialogue: Studies in Computational Prag- Bloomington, IA: Indiana, page 24.
matics” (Natural Language Processing, 1.) John
Benjamins, Amsterdam & Philadelphia, 2000. vi. [12] Peirce MS. 696, quoted in Sebeok, T. (1981) "You Know
471 pages. Hard cover, ISBN 90-272-4983-0 (Eu- My Method" in Sebeok, T., The Play of Musement,
rope), 1-58619-794-2 (U.S.) Bloomington, IA: Indiana, page 31.

[2] R. Josephson, J. & G. Josephson, S. “Abductive Inference: [13] Jonathan Koehler. The Base Rate Fallacy Reconsidered:
Computation, Philosophy, Technology” Cambridge Uni- Descriptive, Normative and Methodological Challenges.
versity Press, New York & Cambridge (U.K.). viii. 306 Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 19, 1996.
pages. Hard cover (1994), ISBN 0-521-43461-0, Paper-
back (1996), ISBN 0-521-57545-1. [14] Robertson, B., & Vignaux, G. A. (1995). Interpreting
evidence: Evaluating forensic evidence in the courtroom.
[3] “Retroduction | Dictionary | Commens”. Commens – Dig- Chichester: John Wiley and Sons.
ital Companion to C. S. Peirce. Mats Bergman, Sami
Paavola & João Queiroz. Retrieved 2014-08-24. [15] A. Jøsang. Conditional Reasoning with Subjective Logic.
Journal of multiple valued logic and soft computing. 15(1),
[4] Sober, Elliot. Core Questions in Philosophy,5th edition. pp.5-38, 2008.PDF
10 8 NOTES

[16] Popper, Karl (2002), Conjectures and Refutations: The .... What is good abduction? What should
Growth of Scientific Knowledge, London, UK: Routledge. an explanatory hypothesis be to be worthy
p 536 to rank as a hypothesis? Of course, it must
explain the facts. But what other conditions
[17] See Santaella, Lucia (1997) “The Development of Peirce’s ought it to fulfill to be good? .... Any hypoth-
Three Types of Reasoning: Abduction, Deduction, and esis, therefore, may be admissible, in the ab-
Induction”, 6th Congress of the IASS. Eprint. sence of any special reasons to the contrary,
provided it be capable of experimental ver-
[18] Peirce, C. S. (1908), "A Neglected Argument for the Re- ification, and only insofar as it is capable of
ality of God", Hibbert Journal v. 7, pp. 90–112, see §4. such verification. This is approximately the
In Collected Papers v. 6, see paragraph 476. In The Es- doctrine of pragmatism.
sential Peirce v. 2, see p. 444.
[25] Peirce, A Letter to Paul Carus circa 1910, Collected Pa-
[19] Peirce, C. S. (1908), "A Neglected Argument for the Re- pers v. 8, paragraphs 227–228. See under "Hypothesis"
ality of God", Hibbert Journal v. 7, pp. 90–112. See at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce’s Terms.
both part III and part IV. Reprinted, including originally
unpublished portion, in Collected Papers v. 6, paragraphs [26] (1867), “On the Natural Classification of Arguments”,
452–85, Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 434–50, and elsewhere. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sci-
ences v. 7, pp. 261–287. Presented April 9, 1867. See
[20] Peirce used the term “intuition” not in the sense of an in- especially starting at p. 284 in Part III §1. Reprinted in
stinctive or anyway half-conscious inference as people of- Collected Papers v. 2, paragraphs 461–516 and Writings
ten do currently. Instead he used “intuition” usually in the v. 2, pp. 23–49.
sense of a cognition devoid of logical determination by
[27] Peirce, C. S. (1878), “Deduction, Induction, and Hypoth-
previous cognitions. He said, “We have no power of Intu-
esis”, Popular Science Monthly, v. 13, pp. 470–82, see
ition” in that sense. See his “Some Consequences of Four
472. Collected Papers 2.619–44, see 623.
Incapacities” (1868), Eprint.
[28] A letter to Langley, 1900, published in Historical Per-
[21] For a relevant discussion of Peirce and the aims of abduc- spectives on Peirce’s Logic of Science. See excerpts under
tive inference, see McKaughan, Daniel J. (2008), “From "Abduction" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce’s Terms.
Ugly Duckling to Swan: C. S. Peirce, Abduction, and
the Pursuit of Scientific Theories”, Transactions of the [29] “A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic'" (1903
Charles S. Peirce Society, v. 44, no. 3 (summer), 446– manuscript), Essential Peirce v. 2, see p. 287. See
468. under "Abduction" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce’s
Terms.
[22] Peirce means “conceivable” very broadly. See Collected
Papers v. 5, paragraph 196, or Essential Peirce v. 2, p. [30] Peirce, C. S., “On the Logic of Drawing History from An-
235, “Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction” (Lecture cient Documents”, dated as circa 1901 both by the editors
VII of the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism): of Collected Papers (see CP v. 7, bk 2, ch. 3, footnote
1) and by those of the Essential Peirce (EP) (Eprint. The
It allows any flight of imagination, pro- article’s discussion of abduction is in CP v. 7, paragraphs
vided this imagination ultimately alights upon 218–31 and in EP v. 2, pp. 107–14.
a possible practical effect; and thus many hy-
potheses may seem at first glance to be ex- [31] Peirce, C. S., “A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic”
cluded by the pragmatical maxim that are not (1903), Essential Peirce v. 2, p. 287:
really so excluded. The mind seeks to bring the facts, as
modified by the new discovery, into order;
[23] Peirce, C. S., Carnegie Application (L75, 1902, New El-
that is, to form a general conception embrac-
ements of Mathematics v. 4, pp. 37–38. See under
ing them. In some cases, it does this by an
"Abduction" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce’s Terms:
act of generalization. In other cases, no new
law is suggested, but only a peculiar state of
Methodeutic has a special interest in Ab-
facts that will “explain” the surprising phe-
duction, or the inference which starts a scien-
nomenon; and a law already known is recog-
tific hypothesis. For it is not sufficient that a
nized as applicable to the suggested hypoth-
hypothesis should be a justifiable one. Any
esis, so that the phenomenon, under that as-
hypothesis which explains the facts is jus-
sumption, would not be surprising, but quite
tified critically. But among justifiable hy-
likely, or even would be a necessary result.
potheses we have to select that one which is
This synthesis suggesting a new conception or
suitable for being tested by experiment.
hypothesis, is the Abduction.
[24] Peirce, “Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction” (Lec- [32] Peirce, C. S. (1883), “A Theory of Probable Inference” in
ture VII of the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism), see Studies in Logic).
parts III and IV. Published in part in Collected Papers v.
5, paragraphs 180–212 (see 196–200, Eprint and in full [33] In Peirce, C. S., 'Minute Logic' circa 1902, Collected Pa-
in Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 226–241 (see sections III and pers v. 2, paragraph 102. See under "Abduction" at Com-
IV). mens Dictionary of Peirce’s Terms.
11

[34] Peirce, “On the Logic of drawing History from Ancient [45] Kave Eshghi. Abductive planning with the event calcu-
Documents”, 1901 manuscript, Collected Papers v. 7, lus. In Robert A. Kowalski, Kenneth A. Bowen editors:
paragraphs 164–231, see 202, reprinted in Essential Peirce Logic Programming, Proceedings of the Fifth Interna-
v. 2, pp. 75–114, see 95. See under "Abduction" at Com- tional Conference and Symposium, Seattle, Washington,
mens Dictionary of Peirce’s Terms. August 15–19, 1988. MIT Press 1988, ISBN 0-262-
61056-6
[35] Peirce, “On the Logic of Drawing Ancient History from
Documents”, Essential Peirce v. 2, see pp. 107–9. [46] April M. S. McMahon (1994): Understanding language
change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN
[36] Peirce, Carnegie application, L75 (1902), Memoir 28: 0-521-44665-1
“On the Economics of Research”, scroll down to Draft
E. Eprint. [47] Eco, U. (1976). “A theory of Semiotics”. Bloomington,
IA: Indiana. p 131
[37] Peirce, C. S., the 1866 Lowell Lectures on the Logic
of Science, Writings of Charles S. Peirce v. 1, p. 485. [48] Gell, A. 1984, Art and Agency. Oxford: Oxford. p 14
See under "Hypothesis" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce’s
Terms. [49] Bowden, R. (2004) A critique of Alfred Gell on Art and
Agency. Retrieved Sept 2007 from: Find Articles at
[38] Peirce, C. S., “A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic”, BNET
written 1903. See The Essential Peirce v. 2, p. 287.
Quote viewable under "Abduction" at Commens Dictio- [50] Whitney D. (2006) 'Abduction the agency of art.' Re-
nary of Peirce’s Terms. trieved May 2009 from: University of California, Berke-
ley
[39] Peirce, A Letter to Paul Carus 1910, Collected Papers v.
8, see paragraph 223.

[40] Peirce, C. S. (1902), Application to the Carnegie Institu-


9 External links
tion, Memoir 27, Eprint: “Of the different classes of ar-
guments, abductions are the only ones in which after they • Abduction entry by Igor Douven in the Stanford En-
have been admitted to be just, it still remains to inquire cyclopedia of Philosophy
whether they are advantageous.”
• Abductive reasoning at the Indiana Philosophy On-
[41] Peirce, “On the Logic of Drawing Ancient History from tology Project
Documents”, Essential Peirce v. 2, see pp. 107–9 and 113.
On Twenty Questions, p. 109, Peirce has pointed out that • Abductive reasoning at PhilPapers
if each question eliminates half the possibilities, twenty
questions can choose from among 220 or 1,048,576 ob- • "Abductive Inference" (once there, scroll down),
jects, and goes on to say: John R. Josephson, Laboratory for Artificial Intel-
ligence Research, Ohio State University. (Former
Thus, twenty skillful hypotheses will as-
webpage via the Wayback Machine.)
certain what 200,000 stupid ones might fail
to do. The secret of the business lies in the
• "Deduction, Induction, and Abduction", Chapter 3
caution which breaks a hypothesis up into its
smallest logical components, and only risks
in article "Charles Sanders Peirce" by Robert Burch,
one of them at a time. 2001 and 2006, in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Phi-
losophy.
[42] Schwendtner, Tibor and Ropolyi, László and Kiss, Olga
(eds): Hermeneutika és a természettudományok. Áron • "Abduction", links to articles and websites on ab-
Kiadó, Budapest, 2001. It is written in Hungarian. Mean- ductive inference, Martin Ryder.
ing of the title: Hermeneutics and the natural sciences.
See, e.g., Hanson’s Patterns of Discovery (Hanson, 1958), • International Research Group on Abductive Infer-
especially pp. 85-92 ence, Uwe Wirth and Alexander Roesler, eds. Uses
frames. Click on link at bottom of its home
[43] Rapezzi, C; Ferrari, R; Branzi, A (24 December 2005). page for English. Wirth moved to U. of Gießen,
“White coats and fingerprints: diagnostic reasoning in Germany, and set up Abduktionsforschung, home
medicine and investigative methods of fictional detec- page not in English but see Artikel section there.
tives”. BMJ (Clinical research ed.) 331 (7531): 1491–4.
Abduktionsforschunghome page via Google transla-
doi:10.1136/bmj.331.7531.1491. PMC 1322237. PMID
16373725. Retrieved 17 January 2014.
tion.

[44] Rejón Altable, C (October 2012). “Logic structure of • "'You Know My Method': A Juxtaposition of
clinical judgment and its relation to medical and psy- Charles S. Peirce and Sherlock Holmes" (1981), by
chiatric semiology”. Psychopathology 45 (6): 344–51. Thomas Sebeok with Jean Umiker-Sebeok, from
doi:10.1159/000337968. PMID 22854297. Retrieved 17 The Play of Musement, Thomas Sebeok, Blooming-
January 2014. ton, Indiana: Indiana University Press, pp. 17–52.
12 9 EXTERNAL LINKS

• Commens Dictionary of Peirce’s Terms, Mats


Bergman and Sami Paavola, editors, Helsinki U.
Peirce’s own definitions, often many per term across
the decades. There, see “Hypothesis [as a form
of reasoning]", “Abduction”, “Retroduction”, and
“Presumption [as a form of reasoning]".
13

10 Text and image sources, contributors, and licenses


10.1 Text
• Abductive reasoning Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Abductive_reasoning?oldid=687393254 Contributors: Timo Honkasalo, Toby
Bartels, Ellmist, Edward, Michael Hardy, Tez, Owl, Kku, Wapcaplet, Karada, Angela, Glenn, BAxelrod, Zoicon5, Markhurd, Maximus
Rex, Itai, Fredrik, Paul Murray, Ruakh, Filemon, Giftlite, Jason Quinn, Pgan002, Zuidervled, Chapplek, JimWae, Mathiasp, Æ, Robin
klein, Thorwald, Dufekin, Robert Horning, Guanabot, FiP, Bender235, El C, Chalst, Killtacular, Sbarthelme, Flammifer, Jhertel, Wicko3,
Zerofoks, Velho, Sandius, Andrea.gf, Tlroche, Rjwilmsi, Tizio, Jweiss11, Quiddity, Spencerk, YurikBot, Jimp, Walkie, Ninly, Palthrow,
Draicone, KnightRider~enwiki, SmackBot, Lifebaka, Josephprymak, Betacommand, Mhss, Ekoontz, Te24409nsp, Nbarth, Pertn, Kostmo,
Lumiere, Jon Awbrey, Byelf2007, Dankonikolic, Antonielly, Physis, Comicist, Iridescent, CmdrObot, Gregbard, Cydebot, Heavydpj,
Letranova, Thijs!bot, 271828182, Transhumanist, Good Vibrations, Kbthompson, Deflective, Magioladitis, Arno Matthias, MatthewJS,
Cathalwoods, Gorbag42, Platonic Realm, Anarchia, R'n'B, Lmagnani, Heyitspeter, Pjmpjm, Peepeedia, Borat fan, Rpeh, Robert Kowalski,
VolkovBot, Kyle the bot, The Tetrast, Philogo, Robert1947, Andrewaskew, Lova Falk, Hrafn, SieBot, Gravitan, Fitzador, MiNombre-
DeGuerra, Sunrise, CharlesGillingham, Melcombe, Josang, Logperson, Fiora0, Mild Bill Hiccup, Sun Creator, SchreiberBike, Kruusamägi,
Muspilli, Dthomsen8, WikHead, Kwjbot, Addbot, LaaknorBot, Denicho, Lightbot, Jan eissfeldt, CountryBot, Legobot, Luckas-bot, Yobot,
Chiendemer, KamikazeBot, AnomieBOT, Xqbot, Rodmunday, LucienBOT, Paradoxreseach, HamburgerRadio, Tkuvho, Frabbler, Trap-
pist the monk, Lam Kin Keung, Lotje, Dinamik-bot, LilyKitty, Arided, MegaSloth, Skadefryd, EmausBot, Hrld11, Axxonnfire, Chuis-
pastonBot, Just granpa, NTox, ClueBot NG, Ghb19, Frietjes, Thepigdog, Masssly, Rengas, COice6, Sadjesture, Siuenti, PsychiX0, Den-
nieswen, Psychology fun, Michelle.chui, Kogakoga11, Faiza93, Kenbausch, Monkbot, Lanzdsey and Anonymous: 103

10.2 Images
• File:Brain.png Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/7/73/Nicolas_P._Rougier%27s_rendering_of_the_human_
brain.png License: GPL Contributors: http://www.loria.fr/~{}rougier Original artist: Nicolas Rougier
• File:Logic_portal.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/7/7c/Logic_portal.svg License: CC BY-SA 3.0 Contrib-
utors: Own work Original artist: Watchduck (a.k.a. Tilman Piesk)
• File:Wiktionary-logo-en.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/f/f8/Wiktionary-logo-en.svg License: Public
domain Contributors: Vector version of Image:Wiktionary-logo-en.png. Original artist: Vectorized by Fvasconcellos (talk · contribs),
based on original logo tossed together by Brion Vibber

10.3 Content license


• Creative Commons Attribution-Share Alike 3.0

You might also like