Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology © 2011 American Psychological Association

2012, Vol. 32, No. 1, 1–9 1068-8471/11/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0025819

Placing Virtue and the Human Good in Psychology


Blaine J. Fowers
University of Miami

This article contextualizes and critiques the recent increase in interest in virtue ethics
and the good life (eudaimonia) in psychology. Theoretically, psychologists’ interests in
virtue and eudaimonia have followed the philosophical revival of these topics, but this
work has been subject to persistent, disguised commitments to the ideologies of
individualism and instrumentalism. Moreover, psychologists’ tendency to separate the
topics of virtue and eudaimonia is described and critiqued as theoretically misguided,
particularly because Aristotle, the originator of these concepts, saw them as mutually
entailing one another. Historically, psychology turned away from the topic of virtue in
tandem with the popular cultural interest in favor of personality rather than character.
The article concludes with a brief overview of Aristotle’s account of eudaimonia as the
overarching human good consisting of participation in characteristically human goods
(e.g., knowledge, belonging) through virtuous activity.

Keywords: eudaimonia, virtue, goods, ideology, Aristotle

The first decade of the 21st century saw a address two of the most vexing confusions.
tremendous upsurge in interest in virtue and the First, some notable psychologists remain sur-
good life among psychologists. Part of this interest prisingly ambivalent about acknowledging that
is directly connected to the positive psychology virtue and the good life are inherently moral
movement, but it is important to remember that concepts that cannot be investigated solely from
there are many theorists and researchers who are a detached, value-neutral perspective if they are
interested in these topics who have limited or no to be studied scientifically (e.g., Peterson &
ties to that movement. At this point, the psycho- Seligman, 2004). This oxymoronic approach to
logical literatures on the topics of virtue and the inextricably moral concepts has required ex-
good life are extremely fragmented, lacking cohe- treme lexical and conceptual gymnastics,
sion in either domain and exhibiting precious few thereby obfuscating more than it has revealed.
connections between these two growing and Richardson (this issue) and I (Fowers, this is-
deeply interconnected areas of interest. This frag-
sue) address the singular inappropriateness of
mentation is partly due to the novelty of psychol-
the attempt to maintain the fact-value dichot-
ogists’ interest, and it would take some time for
these literatures to cohere even in the absence of omy in inquiries about virtue and the good life
enormous conceptual confusions. Unfortunately, (cf. Richardson, Fowers, & Guignon, 1999;
there is deep and widespread conceptual confu- Slife & Williams, 1995; Taylor, 1985).
sion, and these literatures will remain disordered Second, psychologists who theorize about
until theoretical clarity can be established (Fow- and investigate virtue seldom tie their work to
ers, 2010a). an explicit theory of the good life. Similarly,
This special issue was designed to contribute those who theorize about and study the good life
to the theoretical systematization of these liter- generally neglect the virtues. This disconnect is
atures. The authors of the articles in this issue remarkable because Aristotle’s (1999) philoso-
phy forms the basis for most of this work in
psychology, whether that is explicitly acknowl-
edged or not. From an Aristotelian perspective,
This article was published Online First October 10, 2011. virtues are simply the excellences that make it
Correspondence concerning this article should be ad- possible to live the good life, meaning that these
dressed to Blaine J. Fowers, PhD, Department of Educa-
tional and Psychological Studies, University of Miami, P.O.
two concepts mutually entail one another. All of
Box 248065, Coral Gables, FL 33124. E-mail: the contributions to this special issue address
bfowers@miami.edu the connections between virtue and the good.
1
2 FOWERS

(see Fowers, 2005, 2008, 2010a for additional discarded based on effectiveness. This view-
commentary). point is termed instrumentalism because all hu-
In setting the stage for the special issue, I man behavior tends to be portrayed as instru-
briefly recount arguments by prominent theo- mental. Indeed, rationality is often defined in
rists that psychology’s efforts to account for terms of the ability to recognize and utilize
human action have been hamstrung by the im- means that will help in achieving one’s aims.
plausible attempt to sharply separate facts and These theorists have shown the profound in-
values (Flyvbjerg, 2001; Gadamer, 1975; Hab- fluence of individualism and instrumentalism in
ermas, 1970; Richardson, Fowers, & Guignon, the conceptualization of persons, research meth-
1999; Slife & Williams, 1995; Taylor, 1985). ods, and practice approaches. A few illustra-
The articles in this issue build on this extensive tions can indicate the pervasive influence of
literature critiquing the attempt to avoid ques- these ideologies. Interested readers can find
tions of what is valuable, choiceworthy, and many examples and clear demonstrations of
good in psychology. I highlight ontological these ideologies in the literature cited above.
hermeneutics as one of the key sources of this One prominent example of the ideology of in-
critique, but note its shortcomings as a source of dividualism is evident in self-determination the-
an alternative framework for a positive theory ory (Ryan & Deci, 2000), which posits three
of the human good. Interestingly, the authors of universal individual needs: autonomy, compe-
this special issue suggest that a systematic un- tence, and social relatedness. Individual auton-
derstanding of virtue and the good life can point omy and personal ownership of goals and
the way to overcoming the fact-value antinomy. behaviors are the core of this theory, with
Among the many possible perspectives from competence and social relatedness seen as dem-
which such a positive framework can be devel- onstrations of and supports for autonomy. Indi-
oped, the articles in this issue will focus on vidualism is also apparent in that this theory
Aristotle’s ethical philosophy. Following this, I suggests that the business of life is satisfying
provide a brief history of the waxing and wan- these three individual needs, and a good life is
ing of virtue theory in psychology and conclude one in which this satisfaction is consistently
with a description of contemporary virtue the- obtained. The ideology of instrumentalism is
ory and eudaimonism. apparent in the widespread use of concepts such
as technique, strategy, skill, manipulation,
The Critiques of Individualism and mechanism, and effect, all of which imply uni-
Instrumentalism lateral action and a separation of means and
ends. The most prominent theories of interper-
A sustained and detailed series of critiques sonal relationships, social exchange theory
has illuminated the prominent ideologies of (Cook & Rice, 2003) and interdependence the-
individualism and instrumentalism in psycho- ory (Kelley & Thibaut, 1978), are built on an
logical theory, research, and practice (Bellah, economic exchange model construing the es-
Madsen, Sullivan, Swidler, & Tipton, 1985; sential reality of relationships as an economic
Cushman, 1995; Danziger, 1990; Fowers, 1998; model of exchange. These theories portray in-
Fowers, 2010b; Richardson et al., 1999). Indi- dividuals as traders and relationships as quid
vidualism takes the individual to be the ultimate pro quo interactions to be continued as long as
social reality and views the autonomous pursuit the individuals believe they are getting a rea-
and satisfaction of individually defined ends as sonably good relationship “deal.”
the ultimate goods in life (Bellah et al., 1985). The mainstream portrayal of the individual as
This perspective is termed individualism be- a strategic actor in pursuit of need and desire
cause all human phenomena tend to be inter- satisfaction through instrumental activity is per-
preted in terms of the individual. The predom- vasive in psychology, and it is seldom ques-
inant understanding is that individuals pursue tioned in mainstream circles. Although critical
their chosen goods instrumentally, which means perspectives are available from many sources,
that they have subjectively predetermined ends, including critical theory (Habermas, 1970),
and they select the best strategies, techniques, postmodern perspectives (e.g., Foucault, 1980),
and skills to attain those ends. The means are and feminism (e.g., Fox-Genovese, 1991), the
separate from the ends and can be taken up or most sustained critique of these ideologies
VIRTUE AND THE HUMAN GOOD IN PSYCHOLOGY 3

within psychology has originated in ontological From Hermeneutics to Aristotle’s Ethics


hermeneutics (e.g., Richardson et al., 1999;
Taylor, 1985). In spite of psychology’s la- Before exploring Aristotle’s perspective on
bored attempts to maintain a detached objec- human goods, I want to describe how this proj-
tivity about human behavior, the discipline ect got off the ground. The critiques of individ-
has adopted an individualistic view of human ualism and instrumentalism that laid the
life in which individuals perpetually pursue groundwork for this special issue were formu-
need and desire satisfaction through strategic lated through the application of ontological
means. Ironically, neutrality about individual hermeneutics to psychology (e.g., Richardson et
ends was adopted in the service of maintain- al., 1999). Hermeneutic philosophy addresses
ing objectivity. This supposed neutrality is human goods by clarifying that people are al-
belied, however, because taking a neutral ways living out a vision of the human good
stance on what is needed or desired by leav- every day, both personally and professionally.
ing it to the individual is at the core of indi- All people inherit a set of ethical commitments
vidualism and viewing behaviors as mere from and are shaped by ongoing historical com-
means to individual ends is the definition of munities with their understandings of the good.
instrumentalism. Therefore, the idea that hu- In this milieu, we perceive and move within a
man life amounts to satisfying individual moral space oriented to particular goods (Tay-
needs and desires through instrumental action lor, 1989). We are not trapped by our inherited
does not free psychology from having a vision values because the human capacity for reflec-
tion on the valuable allows us to call these
of the human good. Rather, it means that
traditions into question and reinterpret them.
psychology has unwittingly built individual-
These reinterpretations arise from many differ-
ism and instrumentalism into its understand-
ent perspectives within a given tradition. For
ing of the good throughout its theory, re-
these reasons, all traditions are multivocal.
search, and practice. As the articles in this
Moreover, our appreciation of what is valuable
special issue will argue, not only does psy- can be deepened and broadened through dia-
chology fail to attain the desired detached logue with our historical forbearers and with
objectivity, it fails rather miserably by pro- contemporaries who espouse differing view-
moting a distinctly thin and grubby vision of points. Ontological hermeneutics argues power-
the human good. fully that claims about the human good are
The takeaway lesson from this array of the- inescapable in psychological practices and in
oretical critiques of disguised ideology is that ordinary life. Much can be said about the human
the strenuous efforts of a great many intelligent, good with the hermeneutic framework, but the
dedicated, and visionary psychologists have full-bodied, substantive account of the human
been insufficient to separate psychological sci- good one would like has remained elusive. As a
ence from commitments to a vision of the good. result, hermeneutically oriented critiques of dis-
The hermeneutic recommendation is to ac- guised ideologies in psychology begin strongly,
knowledge that the ideal of detached objectivity but frequently peter out to vague generalities in
has failed and recognize that commitment to conclusion, typically providing relatively ab-
some set of goods and goals is inescapable in stract and contentless comments regarding the
any human endeavor, including science. Then human good. In other words, hermeneutics calls
we can begin to reveal, discuss, and critique the for a substantive theory of the good, but does
hidden commitments to particular goods in our not seem to have the resources to provide such
discipline. Instead of settling for a set of unac- a theory. In this special issue, the contributors
knowledged culturally guided goods, it seems take up the challenge of developing a substan-
preferable to explicitly explore the systematic tive theory of the good by exploring the re-
frameworks that are available for understanding sources of Aristotle’s ethics.
human goods. The purpose of this special issue Among the background sources of hermeneu-
is to explicate an understanding of Aristotle’s tics, Aristotle (1999) is the premier guide re-
framework of virtues and the good life as one garding a substantive perspective on the human
promising way to explicitly incorporate the good. He begins by making the good the chief
good in psychology. priority of ethics in the opening paragraph of the
4 FOWERS

Nicomachean Ethics. The orienting statement of (1973) recounts a significant shift in American
this central text is “every action and choice culture from character to personality beginning
seem to aim at some good” (1094a 2). Although in the late 19th century. Psychologists followed
one can be mistaken or misguided about the as much as led this shift in emphasis away from
good, Aristotle located the good at the center of character and toward the more “expressive,
human action because it orients all choice and adaptable, and morally unencumbered” self that
activity. Just so it is clear that he did not aban- seemed necessary for a more “industrialized and
don this position in his characteristic back-and- urbanized age” (Nicholson, 1998, p. 52). By the
forth style of inquiry, he repeats this point sev- mid-20th century, personality research had en-
eral times. For example, in book 6 he states: tirely eclipsed interest in character.
“For the originating causes of the things that are Character and virtue fell into disfavor as the
done consist in the end at which they are aimed” discipline attempted to split scientific fact from
(1140 b 20 –21). moral value in its drive to become an accepted
There are four reasons that Aristotle provides social science (Nicholson, 1998; Ross & Nis-
a good beginning for the exploration of human bett, 1991). Two key moments in the waning of
goods. First, the Nicomachean Ethics (Aristotle, character are particularly important. First, All-
1999) has been a primary source for Western port (1937) engaged in a sustained critique of
explorations of the good life, having stood the character as a fitting subject for psychology. His
test of time by remaining relevant over the pointed couplet is emblematic for this move:
course of two millennia. Although Plato’s “Character is personality evaluated, and per-
works provide a similarly valuable set of sonality is character devaluated” (p. 52, em-
sources, they have not enjoyed the same degree phasis in original). This devaluation of charac-
of interest that Aristotle’s more straightforward ter has been an important part of psychology’s
and systematic approach has. Second, there is attempt to exclude evaluative and popular terms
widespread interest in appropriating Aristotle’s from personality psychology. In the service of a
ethics to contemporary concerns among philos- science of personality, Allport frequently as-
ophers and psychologists, with rapidly expand- serted the necessity of rigidly separating person-
ing literatures in both disciplines. Third, as the ality traits as scientific from character and virtue
articles in this issue show, Aristotle provides as normative elements of ethics (Allport, 1921;
excellent resources for transcending the individ- Allport & Vernon, 1930). Nicholson (1998)
ualism and instrumentalism in which psychol- suggests that “Allport’s goal was not to destroy
ogy is currently mired. Finally, Aristotle’s eth- the traditional ethical foundations of America
ics is directed toward living a good life, but he but to revitalize them” through scientific rigor.
does not commit himself to a narrow or pre- His rationale for this approach was that “he was
scriptive understanding of a single form of the convinced that the solution to America’s ethical
good life. This allows for the incorporation of a dilemmas lay not in history, culture, or religion,
diversity of goods, which is an essential feature but in science, in particular, psychology” (p.
of an acceptable ethics in our time. Clearly, 64). Allport had difficulty fully effecting the
Aristotle’s is not the only perspective on human separation of character and personality partly
goods that is worth exploring, but this special because he worried that psychologists would
issue focuses on his thought in the service of not do “justice to the richness and dignity of
depth of presentation. Explorations of other per- human personality” (Allport, 1937, p. vii, em-
spectives and comparisons among them have phasis added). His commitment to a morally
great value, but doing them justice will require informed understanding of living well is even
a similar depth of presentation. clearer in his description of “the mature person-
ality” who is loyal, dignified, devoted, and who
The Waxing and Waning and Waxing of eschews egoism, self-seeking, vanity, and self-
Virtue Theory in Psychology justification.
Allport’s theory of personality illustrates the
Character and virtue were very prominent difficulty in separating description and prescrip-
topics in the early decades of psychology, and tion. This difficulty of separating moral ideals
character training was seen as very important from detached, objective descriptions of person-
(Leahey, 1994; Sussman, 1973). Sussman ality was not limited to Allport’s theorizing,
VIRTUE AND THE HUMAN GOOD IN PSYCHOLOGY 5

however. Character remains embedded in the virtue concepts are entirely amenable to empir-
most widely accepted and best documented ical research with available methods. The ad-
contemporary understanding of personality: the vent of positive psychology, with its interest in
Five Factor Model (Costa & McCrae, 1991). virtue has also contributed to this literature (Pe-
McCrae and John (1992) comment that two of terson & Seligman, 2004). There is a growing
the famed Five Factors are clearly related to empirical literature on virtue in general (Caw-
traditional virtue terms: Agreeableness (A) and ley, Martin, & Johnson, 2000; Hawkins, Fow-
Conscientiousness (C). “Like A, C is a highly ers, Carroll, & Yang, 2006; Walker & Pitts,
evaluated dimension: indeed, A and C are the 1998) and specific virtues such as gratitude
classic dimensions of character describing (Emmons & Crumpler, 2000; McCullough, Em-
‘good’ versus ‘evil’ and ‘strong-willed’ versus mons, & Tsang, 2002), courage (Pury & Kow-
‘weak-willed’ individuals. Perhaps it was these alski, 2007), and practical wisdom (Kramer,
moral overtones that often led scientific psy- 2000; Staudinger, Lopez, & Baltes, 1997). In
chologists to ignore these factors, but in fact, addition, some investigators have studied per-
both represent objectively observable dimen- ceptions of what makes a life good (King &
sions of individual differences” (p. 197, empha- Napa, 1998; McGregor & Little, 1998).
sis added). This recent upsurge of theoretical and empir-
The second important moment in psychology’s ical interest in virtue and the good life demon-
move away from character was the publication of strates a waxing interest in these topics. Unfor-
Hartshorne and May’s celebrated studies of hon- tunately, the vast majority of authors in this
esty among schoolchildren (Hartshorne & May, emerging literature in psychology has only a
1928; Hartshorne, May, & Maller, 1929; Hart- rudimentary and fragmented understanding of
shorne, May, & Shuttleworth, 1930). The stan- the rich theory available on virtue and the good
dard interpretation of their results (Doris, 2002; life (Fowers, 2005, 2008, 2010a). One of the
Emler, 1999; Ross & Nisbett, 1991) has been primary purposes of this special issue is to ad-
that children are typically dishonest when given dress that lack of knowledge.
the opportunity, even those students who were
rated as honest by peers and teachers. Because A Précis of Virtue and the Human Good
many students exploited experimenter contrived
opportunities for dishonesty, these authors con- Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (NE) (1999)
cluded that situational factors were more impor- is the locus classicus on virtue and the good life.
tant for moral behavior than character. This In addition, Aristotle had much to say about
interpretation has been extremely influential. these topics in his other works, and there is a
Hartshorne and May’s results have been sub- voluminous secondary literature. I will provide
sequently reinterpreted theoretically and empir- an extremely brief, but close interpretation of
ically. Virtue theory does not suggest that the what Aristotle said about these topics here, and
majority of adult individuals will act virtuously encourage the reader to study Aristotle’s works
in all situations, much less the majority of chil- and recent philosophical scholarship for greater
dren. The finding that some children acted hon- depth of understanding.
estly in spite of incentives not to, suggests the The central concept of the NE is eudaimonia,
presence of a character strength. Statistical re- which is Aristotle’s term for the highest form of
analyses have also cast doubt on Hartshorne and human life. It can be translated as happiness or
May’s conclusions (Burton, 1963; Epstein & flourishing. Translating it as happiness can be
O’Brien, 1985; Rushton, 1984). misleading, however, as happiness generally
Virtue ethics was also marginal in philosophy connotes an affective state, particularly in psy-
until a dramatic upsurge in interest in recent chology. Aristotle understood eudaimonia as liv-
decades (Anscombe, 1958; Broadie, 1991; Ma- ing a complete human life that is fully realized
cIntyre, 1984; Rorty, 1980). This renewal has through virtuous activity. For these reasons, I pre-
spurred theoretical and empirical work on virtue fer the term flourishing as a translation. I will rely
and the good life in psychology as well (Fow- primarily on the term eudaimonia, but occasion-
ers, 1998, 2005; Meara, Schmidt, & Day, 1996; ally employ flourishing as a synonym.
Tjeltveit, 2003). Contrary to earlier dismissals, Aristotle begins the NE with eudaimonia be-
Baumeister and Exline (1999) have argued that cause, as MacIntyre (1984) noted, “the concept
6 FOWERS

of the good life is prior to the concept of a problematic because these scholars seldom have
virtue” (p. 184, emphasis in original). The rea- a clear, systematic conceptualization of what a
son for this is that virtues are the character virtue is. The original Greek term for virtue was
excellences that make it possible to pursue the arête, best translated as excellence. Virtues are,
good life. Aristotle defined eudaimonia as simply, human excellences or character
the best, most complete form of human life and strengths that make it possible for individuals to
he highlighted a number of features that com- pursue characteristically human goods (e.g., so-
prise this kind of life. The first and most basic cial connections, knowledge) that allow them to
point about eudaimonia is that it is an inextri- flourish as human beings. Broadie (1991) put it
cably ethical concept because it is about living simply: “an excellence or virtue . . . is nothing
the best kind of life. Aristotle understood the but a characteristic which makes the difference
best kind of life in terms of human nature, between functioning and functioning well”
defining eudaimonia as realizing one’s full hu- (p. 37, emphasis in original). The capacities to
man potential given the particular kind of nat- act generously, loyally, courageously, and justly
ural beings we are. This formulation, wherein a allow individuals to fulfill their potential as the
being’s good is a matter of the full expression of rational social beings we are.
its nature, is known as the function argument. Virtues are multidimensional characteristics
Throughout the NE, Aristotle emphasized that that include a cognitive understanding of the
eudaimonia is a form of activity.1 That is, eu- character strength and its relationship to the
daimonia is a way of living and cannot be good life, which creates a strong and spontane-
limited to a mental state or process. The every- ous motivation to enact the virtue, a reliable
day activities that constitute eudaimonia are de- disposition or habit of enacting the virtue, and
voted to the pursuit of characteristically human the practical wisdom to know how to enact the
goods such as friendship, knowledge, and the virtue. The ability to make wise decisions about
best form of politics. He made the case that how best to pursue one’s aims, which character
eudaimonia is comprised of a broad set of such strengths to employ and in what way is also
choiceworthy ends. Aristotle argues that one essential to a virtue framework and is known as
can pursue these ends and live a eudaimonic life practical wisdom. The cognitive, emotional,
in so doing only through virtuous action. This dispositional, behavioral, and wisdom aspects
means that, for Aristotle, a good human life is of character strengths comprise a seamless
inextricably tied to being a good person. This is whole. Individuals who have developed good
one of the key reasons that eudaimonia cannot character want to act ethically out of an attach-
be studied in a value-neutral way. Aristotle also ment to what is good.
saw eudaimonia as inherently pleasant because A brief illustration of the necessary role of
excellent activity is pleasant. He distinguished virtue in pursuing human goods can clarify the
noble pleasures (e.g., learning) from base plea- features of virtue and the relationship between
sures (e.g., gluttony), but he clearly saw both virtue and what is good. The sustained interest
virtuous activity and a eudaimonic life as deeply in and peculiar kinds of knowledge that humans
pleasurable. pursue makes knowledge a characteristically
Aristotle defined eudaimonia as the ultimate human good. There are many ways to pursue
and sufficient end for human life. This means knowledge, with science as one of the paradig-
that it is chosen for itself and not for the sake of matic approaches. The pursuit of scientific
some other end and that there is nothing that can
be added to a flourishing life to make it better.
1
Finally, eudaimonia is comprised by a complete Through most of the NE, Aristotle describes rational,
social, and political activity as it takes place in everyday
life, meaning that eudaimonia is a matter of how life. In part of Book X of the NE, however, he discusses
one’s life comes together as a whole rather than contemplation as the highest human activity. There is a
being comprised of a series of transitory states good deal of controversy regarding how this concept is to be
such as emotions, moods, or experiences. integrated into the rest of Aristotle’s account of eudaimonia.
Psychologists who theorize about and study I have downplayed this concept and the controversy here
because it is beyond the scope of this special issue due to its
virtue generally do so by focusing on a single complexity. For more on this fascinating, but vexing ques-
virtue or a list of virtues. Although these ap- tion, see Broadie (1991), Nussbaum (1986), and Rorty
proaches have some merits, they are deeply (1980).
VIRTUE AND THE HUMAN GOOD IN PSYCHOLOGY 7

knowledge cannot proceed unless scientists ex- thoroughly to misdescribe and distort the expe-
ercise the virtue of honesty in reporting their rience of cherished friendships.
procedures and findings accurately, and science This special issue makes the case for the
is utterly dependent on this kind of honesty. systematic theorizing of virtues in psychology.
From time to time, spectacular cases of scien- Richardson (this issue) begins by laying bare
tific fraud remind us that we cannot take this the pretensions of psychology to value-neutral
honesty for granted. Moreover, there are enor- inquiry and suggests that attention to substan-
mously powerful incentives for fabricating re- tive moral issues is inescapable for the disci-
sults, misrepresenting findings, or “massaging” pline. He argues that a virtue framework pro-
data, including academic tenure and promotion, vides a promising approach to this challenge. I
grant funding, public notoriety, and political follow this line of thought in arguing that eu-
influence. Although honesty could be a matter daimonia is constituted by the consistent pursuit
of conventional rule following or the avoidance of characteristically human goods, which are, in
of negative consequences, a more powerful and turn, a matter of virtuous activity (Fowers, this
appealing reason for honesty is an enduring issue). Slife (this issue) provides an extended
interest in truthfulness that grows out of a per- and compelling account of the role that teaching
sonal devotion to seeking knowledge. At their virtues plays in encouraging troubled girls to-
best, scientists are engaged in a genuine search ward a flourishing life in a residential school.
for the best ways to understand the phenomena Aho (this issue) reflects on the contribution of
of interest. Dishonesty about one’s results is not the articles in this issue and suggests critical
merely an error. Rather, it is a kind of bad faith. questions and future directions for psychologi-
Deception is inherently contradictory to science cal theory and research on virtue and the human
because it is destructive to the very possibility good.
of pursuing the most accurate account of a phe-
nomenon by distorting or fabricating one’s find- References
ings. Scientists who willingly and consistently
report procedures and findings accurately are Allport, G. W. (1921). Personality and character.
enacting the virtue of honesty. Scientific hon- Psychological Bulletin, 18, 441– 455. doi:10.1037/
esty serves the good of expanding human h0066265
knowledge and is the only way to pursue this Allport, G. W. (1937). Personality: A psychological
good. The pursuit of knowledge and other char- interpretation. New York, NY: Henry Holt.
Allport, G. W., & Vernon, P. E. (1930). The field of
acteristically human goods through virtuous ac- personality. Psychological Bulletin, 27, 677–730.
tion is what makes for a eudaimonic life. It is doi:10.1037/h0072589
essential that theorists and investigators recog- Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral philoso-
nize the central and ineliminable theoretical phy. Philosophy, 33, 1–19. doi:10.1017/
connection between virtue, human goods, and S0031819100037943
eudaimonia. Aristotle. (1999). Nicomachean ethics. (M. Ostwald,
Deep friendship provides a more everyday Trans.) Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
example as a key good in human life that can Baumeister, R. F., & Exline, J. J. (1999). Virtue,
personality, and social relations: Self-control as
only come into being through an extended his- the moral muscle. Journal of Personality, 67,
tory of loyalty and honesty. Such a friendship is 1165–1194. doi:10.1111/1467-6494.00086
called into question and perhaps fatally under- Bellah, R. N., Madsen, R., Sullivan, W. M., Swidler,
mined by acts of betrayal, manipulation, or A., & Tipton, S. M. (1985). Habits of the heart.
abandonment because those actions contradict Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
the constitutive elements of deep friendship. Broadie, S. (1991). Ethics with Aristotle. Oxford,
Perhaps the unwillingness of psychologists to UK: Oxford University Press.
address the virtue terms so elemental to deep Burton, R. V. (1963). Generality of honesty recon-
sidered. Psychological Review, 70, 481– 499. doi:
friendship helps to explain why psychological 10.1037/h0047594
accounts of friendship (e.g., social exchange Cawley, M. J., III, Martin, J. E., & Johnson, J. A.
theory) so blithely include manipulation and (2000). A virtues approach to personality. Person-
potential abandonment as defining features of ality and Individual Differences, 28, 997–1013.
friendships and why such accounts seem so doi:10.1016/S0191-8869(99)00207-X
8 FOWERS

Cook, K. S., & Rice, E. (2003). Social exchange Habermas, J. (1970). Toward a rational society: Stu-
theory. In J. Delameter (Ed.), Handbook of social dent protest, science, and politics. Boston, MA:
psychology (pp. 53–76). New York, NY: Kluwer. Beacon.
Costa, P. T., Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1991). Facet Hartshorne, H., & May, M. A. (1928). Studies in the
scales for Agreeableness and Conscientiousness: A nature of character. Vol. 1: Studies in deceit. New
revision of the NEO Personality Inventory. Per- York, NY: Macmillan.
sonality and Individual Differences, 12, 887– 898. Hartshorne, H., May, M. A., & Maller, J. B. (1929).
doi:10.1016/0191-8869(91)90177-D Studies in the nature of character. Vol. 2: Studies
Cushman, P. (1995). Constructing the self, construct- in service and self-control. New York, NY: Mac-
ing America: A cultural history of psychotherapy. millan. doi:10.1037/11334-000
Reading, MA: Addison Wesley. Hartshorne, H., May, M. A., & Shuttleworth, F. K.
Danziger, K. (1990). Constructing the subject: His- (1930). Studies in the nature of character. Vol. 3:
torical origins of psychological research. Cam- Studies in the organization of character. New
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. doi: York, NY: Macmillan.
10.1017/CBO9780511524059 Hawkins, A. J., Fowers, B. J., Carroll, J. S., & Yang,
Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character: Personality C. (2006). Conceptualizing and measuring marital
and moral behavior. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge virtues. In S. Hofferth & L. Casper (Eds.), Hand-
University Press. book of measurement issues in family research
Emler, N. (1999). Moral character. In V. J. Derlega & (67– 83). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
B. A. Winstead (Eds.), Personality: Contemporary Kelley, H. H., & Thibaut, J. W. (1978). Interpersonal
theory and research (2nd ed., pp. 376 – 404). Chi- relations: A theory of interdependence. New York,
cago, IL: Nelson–Hall. NY: Wiley.
Emmons, R. A., & Crumpler, C. A. (2000). Gratitude King, L. A., & Napa, C. K. (1998). What makes a life
as a human strength: Appraising the evidence. good? Journal of Personality and Social Psychol-
Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 19, ogy, 75, 156 –165. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.75
.1.156
56 – 69. doi:10.1521/jscp.2000.19.1.56
Kramer, D. A. (2000). Wisdom as a classical source
Epstein, S., & O’Brien, E. J. (1985). The person-
of human strength: Conceptualization and empiri-
situation debate in historical and current perspec-
cal inquiry. Journal of Social and Clinical Psy-
tive. Psychological Bulletin, 98, 513–537. doi:
chology, 19, 83–101. doi:10.1521/jscp.2000.19
10.1037/0033-2909.98.3.513
.1.83
Flyvbjerg, B. (2001). Making social science matter:
Leahey, T. H. (1994). A history of modern psychol-
Why social inquiry fails and how it can succeed
ogy, 2nd Ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
again. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue: A study in moral
Press. theory, 2nd ed. Notre Dame, IN: University of
Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge: Selected in- Notre Dame Press.
terviews and other writings (C. Gordon, Ed.). New McCrae, R. R., & John, O. P. (1992). An introduction
York, NY: Pantheon. to the five-factor model and its applications. Jour-
Fowers, B. J. (1998). Psychology and the good mar- nal of Personality, 60, 175–215. doi:10.1111/
riage: Social theory as practice. American Behav- j.1467-6494.1992.tb00970.x
ioral Scientist, 41, 516 –541. doi:10.1177/ McCullough, M. E., Emmons, R. A., & Tsang, J.-A.
0002764298041004005 (2002). The grateful disposition: A conceptual and
Fowers, B. J. (2005). Virtue and psychology: Pursu- empirical topography. Journal of Personality and
ing excellence in ordinary practices. Washington, Social Psychology, 82, 112–127. doi:10.1037/
DC: APA Press. doi:10.1037/11219-000 0022-3514.82.1.112
Fowers, B. J. (2010a). Aristotle on eudaimonia: On McGregor, I., & Little, B. R. (1998). Personal proj-
the virtue of returning to the source. Unpublished ects, happiness, and meaning: On doing well and
manuscript. being yourself. Journal of Personality and Social
Fowers, B. J. (2010b). Instrumentalism and psychol- Psychology, 74, 494 –512. doi:10.1037/0022-
ogy: Beyond using and being used. Theory & 3514.74.2.494
Psychology, 20, 1–23. doi:10.1177/ Meara, N. M., Schmidt, L. D., & Day, J. D. (1996).
0959354309346080 Principles and virtues: A foundation for ethical
Fox-Genovese, E. (1991). Feminism without illu- decisions, policies, and character. The Counseling
sions: A critique of individualism. Chapel Hill, Psychologist, 24, 4 –77. doi:10.1177/
NC: University of North Carolina Press. 0011000096241002
Gadamer, H.-G. (1989). Truth and method (2nd rev. Nicholson, I. A. M. (1998). Gordon Allport, charac-
ed.). New York, NY: Continuum. ter, and the “culture of personality,” 1897–1937.
VIRTUE AND THE HUMAN GOOD IN PSYCHOLOGY 9

History of Psychology, 1, 52– 68. doi:10.1037/ can Psychologist, 55, 68 –78. doi:10.1037/0003-
1093-4510.1.1.52 066X.55.1.68
Nussbaum, M. C. (1986). The fragility of goodness: Slife, B., & Williams, R. (1995). What’s behind the
Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy. research? Discovering hidden assumptions in the
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. behavioral sciences. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Peterson, C., & Seligman, M. E. P. (2004). Character Staudinger, U. M., Lopez, D. F., & Baltes, P. B.
strengths and virtues: A handbook and classifica- (1997). The psychometric location of wisdom-
tion. Washington, DC: American Psychological related performance: Intelligence, personality, and
Association. more? Personality and Social Psychology Bulle-
Pury, C. L., & Kowalski, R. M. (2007). Human tin, 23, 1200 –1214. doi:10.1177/
strengths, courageous actions, and general and per- 01461672972311007
sonal courage. Journal of Positive Psychology, 2, Sussman, W. I. (1973). Culture as history. New
120 –128. doi:10.1080/17439760701228813 York, NY: Pantheon.
Taylor, C. (1985). Philosophy and the human sci-
Richardson, F. C., Fowers, B. J., & Guignon, C.
ences: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Cambridge,
(1999). Re-envisioning psychology: Moral dimen-
UK: Cambridge University Press.
sions of theory and practice. San Francisco, CA:
Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self. Cambridge,
Jossey-Bass. MA: Harvard University Press.
Rorty, A. O. (Ed.). (1980). Essays on Aristotle’s Tjeltveit, A. C. (2003). Implicit virtues, divergent
ethics. Berkeley, CA: University of California goods, multiple communities: Explicitly address-
Press. ing virtues in the behavioral sciences. American
Ross, L., & Nisbett, R. E. (1991). The person and the Behavioral Scientist, 47, 395– 414. doi:10.1177/
situation. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University 0002764203256946
Press. Walker, L. J., & Pitts, R. C. (1998). Naturalistic
Rushton, J-P. (1984). The altruistic personality. In E. conceptions of moral maturity. Developmental
Straub, D. BarTal, J. Karylowski, & J. Reykowski Psychology, 34, 403– 419. doi:10.1037/0012-
(Eds.), Development and maintenance of prosocial 1649.34.3.403
behavior (pp. 271–290). New York, NY: Praeger.
Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2000). Self-determina- Received March 20, 2011
tion theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motiva- Revision received June 27, 2011
tion, social development, and well-being. Ameri- Accepted August 18, 2011 䡲

You might also like