Psychological Spacetime

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

674511

research-article2016
SGOXXX10.1177/2158244016674511SAGE OpenConway et al.

Article

SAGE Open

Psychological Spacetime: Implications of


October-December 2016: 1­–14
© The Author(s) 2016
DOI: 10.1177/2158244016674511
Relativity Theory for Time Perception sgo.sagepub.com

Lucian Gideon Conway III1, Meredith A. Repke1,


and Shannon C. Houck2

Abstract
It has been an accepted scientific fact in physics for almost 100 years that time speeds up and slows down for an observer
based on factors—such as motion and gravity—that affect space. Yet this fact, drawn from the theory of relativity, has not
been widely integrated into the study of the psychology of time. The present article helps to fill in this gap between physics
and psychology by reviewing evidence concerning what a psychological spacetime processor—one that accounted for the
theory of relativity’s empirically validated predictions of the compensatory relationship between time and space—would
look like. This model of the spacetime processor suggests that humans should have a psychological mechanism for slowing
time down as motion speeds up, a prediction that already has widespread research support. We also discuss several novel
hypotheses directly suggested by the spacetime model and a set of related speculations that emerge when considering
spacetime (some of which have already received empirical support). Finally, we compare and contrast three very different
potential reasons why we might have developed a spacetime processor in the first place. We conclude that the spacetime
model shows promise for organizing existing data on time perception and generating novel hypotheses for researchers to
pursue. Considering how humans might process spacetime helps reduce the existing gap between our understanding of
physics and our understanding of human psychology.

Keywords
time perception, spacetime, physics, relativity theory

Everyday experience thus fails to reveal how the universe really Yet, in spite of this long-accepted fact in physics, the
works, and that’s why a hundred years after Einstein, almost no notion of spacetime has received curiously little attention
one, not even professional physicists, feels relativity in their from psychologists studying time perception. We suspect
bones. This isn’t surprising; one is hard pressed to find the that this is very likely because most academics share promi-
survival advantage offered by a solid grasp of relativity.
nent physicist Brian Greene’s (2004) assessment—illus-
Newton’s flawed conceptions of absolute space and absolute
trated in the above quote—of the relationship between
time work wonderfully well at the slow speeds and moderate
gravity we encounter in daily life, so our senses are under no actual spacetime and our perception of spacetime. That
evolutionary pressure to develop relativistic acumen. assessment could be summarized as follows: Who needs it?
After all, if the added predictive “everyday” value of space-
—Brian Greene (2004, p. 77). time perception is so small that it conveys no survival
advantage at all, then why would we have ever developed a
The intimately woven bond between space and time—a mechanism to account for it? And if we would not have ever
relationship so entrenched that it is referred to by physi- developed such a mechanism, why bother thinking about the
cists as a single entity called spacetime—has been an relationship between our psychological functioning and
accepted scientific fact for generations of scientists. spacetime in the first place?
Repeated tests have confirmed empirically that time is not
the static entity that Newton imagined it to be; rather, in
line with the theory of relativity, motion and gravity not 1
University of Montana, Missoula, USA
only affect space but also simultaneously affect time. Time 2
Syracuse University, NY, USA
in reality slows up and slows down for each observer based
Corresponding Author:
on their movement through spatial dimensions in highly Lucian Gideon Conway III, University of Montana, 143 Skaggs, Missoula,
predictable ways (see, for example, Greene, 2004; Penrose, MT 59812, USA.
2010; Shankar, 2013). Email: luke.conway@umontana.edu

Creative Commons CC-BY: This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License
(http://www.creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/) which permits any use, reproduction and distribution of
the work without further permission provided the original work is attributed as specified on the SAGE and Open Access pages
(https://us.sagepub.com/en-us/nam/open-access-at-sage).
2 SAGE Open

Why Should Psychology Researchers integrative perception of spacetime. And, as we shall see
Care About Psychological Spacetime? below, some research suggests that we may indeed have
spacetime-like mechanisms for perceiving the intimate, rela-
The sentiment is understandable. Yet we nonetheless believe tivistic relation between space and time.
that there are at least two separate reasons to care about psy- The implications of understanding the psychological
chological spacetime. First, available evidence suggests that overlap between space and time are vast. To the degree that
the psychology of time and the psychology of space are in humans do possess spacetime-like processors, understanding
reality intimately bound up; and yet this fact is rarely tied to those mechanisms could contribute a great deal to our funda-
the physical relationship between time and space. For exam- mental understanding of how humans process time. The
ple, positron emission tomography (PET) and functional largely untested set of hypotheses generated by the new pro-
magnetic resonance imaging (FMRI) studies suggest that posed model could importantly alter our understanding of
time perception and motion perception systems have quite a the psychology of time.
bit of direct overlap in shared biological space in the brain This is no small matter: The psychological processing of
(Coull, Frith, Buchel, & Nobre, 2000; Coull & Nobre, 1998; time has multiple practical implications for human emotion,
Doherty, Rao, Mesulam, & Nobre, 2005; Griffin & Nobre, life satisfaction, and mental health (e.g., Carstensen, Isaacowitz,
2005; Janssen & Shadlen, 2005; for a review, see Eagleman & Charles, 1999; Conway, 2004; Droit-Volet, Fayolle, & Gil,
et al., 2005). Similar work reveals that localized hemispheric 2011; Droit-Volet & Meck, 2007; Flaherty, 1991; Fredrickson,
deficits in space perceptions show corresponding deficits in Mancuso, Branigan, & Tugade, 2000; Gil & Droit-Volet, 2009,
time perception, further suggesting that “representations of 2012; Hawkins, French, Crawford, & Enzle, 1988; Rowe,
space and time share neural underpinnings” (Saj, Fuhrman, & Hirsh, & Anderson, 2007; Zimbardo & Boyd, 2008). If how
Vuilleumier, 2014, p. 207; for related evidence, see Mauk & people process time is altered by space and motion (as we dis-
Buonomano, 2004). Although this overlap does not mean we cuss below), then interventions that use time as a mechanism
have a spacetime processor in line with relativity theory, it is for improving life quality could be potentially improved by
at least consistent with the notion that space and time are per- including considerations of space and motion.
haps more intricately bound up in human psychology than a
Newtonian processor might expect. Thus, it is worth more
fully conceptually and empirically exploring the nature of this
The Present Article
overlap, and the actual operation of space and time in physics The purpose of the present article is to address this gap
is one potential guiding model to aid our understanding. between physical spacetime and the psychology of time. Our
Second, we have at times in history underestimated the primary method to accomplish this goal is to consider what a
human capacity for sensing and assimilating information spacetime processor—one that processed spacetime in line
from the environment. For example, 100 years ago, few with relativity theory—would look like if humans possessed
would have predicted the profound ability of the human it. As we discuss below, our model does not (necessarily)
psyche to sense, interpret, and assimilate information pre- predict that physical spacetime and psychological spacetime
sented below the level of conscious awareness, or the degree directly overlap in one-to-one correspondence. It rather sug-
that human psychology occurs beyond our explicit knowl- gests larger directional principles concerning how we would
edge or consent. Yet, today, such unconscious and implicit process the relationship between space and time.
effects are accepted scientific fact (see, for example, Bargh To illustrate our model, we discuss a set of predictions
& Chartrand, 1999; Conway, 2004; Hsieh & Colas, 2012; that can be made, when considering physical spacetime,
Kouider, de Gardelle, Dehaene, Dupoux, & Pallier, 2010; about how people might perceive time and space. This
Proulx & Heine, 2008). For example, research demonstrates includes a substantial research literature supporting one of
that one can implicitly prime stereotypical schemas and alter the key predictions from our newly conceptualized psycho-
subsequent behavior in ways consistent with the stereo- logical spacetime model, as well as additional novel hypoth-
type—such as slowing down persons’ walking speed by eses that have yet to be tested. We then discuss a set of related
priming words related to “old”—without persons being con- speculations that emerge when considering spacetime.
sciously aware that the process is happening (see Bargh & Finally, we compare and contrast three very different poten-
Chartrand, 1999). tial reasons why we might have developed a spacetime pro-
Although our species has only recently begun to articulate cessor in the first place.
the concepts of spacetime, it seems nearly certain that physi-
cal spacetime has existed in its present integrative form The Backstory Sketch of a Spacetime
throughout human history. As such, any evolutionary pro-
Processor
cesses1 acting upon our species would have acted in the con-
stant presence of such spacetime as a certain reality, and thus The theory of relativity suggests that movements through
it is perhaps premature to dismiss out of hand the possibility time and space are compensatory, so that movement through
that we do have some mechanisms that aid us in the space affects movement through time and vice versa. This
Conway et al. 3

means that if we perceived spacetime in line with relativity, general relationship between space and time as a corollary to
we would have mechanisms that would in some way corre- their actual physical relationship.
spond to this interaction between time and space. It further
suggests that all things that “bend” space or alter motion—
Human Processing Involves Perceptions of
such as gravity—would also affect time perception. Below,
we discuss what we might expect to find in a human proces- Observable Markers
sor if, in fact, there were mechanisms for processing space- Time perception is highly malleable (see, for example,
time in this manner. Before doing so, however, it is necessary Conway, 2004; Droit-Volet et al., 2011; Droit-Volet & Meck,
to first discuss, writ large, how human processes typically 2007; Flaherty, 1991). For such malleable systems, human
interface with the real world. processing most typically involves perceptions of observable
markers of objective reality and not the underlying reality
Human Processing Involves Exaggerated itself. For example, evolutionary psychology theories of
mate selection emphasize that we do not have a direct line to
Comparative Perceptions the “fertility” of a particular mate; rather, there are markers
No human processing mechanism interfaces with physical that themselves are correlated with fertility (e.g., markers of
reality by producing a one-to-one correspondence with that age, beauty, health), and it is those markers that we use (e.g.,
reality. We do not “copy” reality into our mind; it is always Buss & Schmitt, 2011). Similarly, there are markers of
a reconstructive process. For example, from the moment whether or not someone is related to us (Park, Schaller, &
light photons hit the eye, the visual system is reconstruct- Van Vugt, 2008), or whether or not someone has a disease
ing, altering, transmuting, and adapting the reality “out that might harm us (Park, Schaller, & Crandall, 2007). These
there” into an image “in here” (see, for example, Weiten, markers are not direct lines to kinship or disease; they are
2013). As a result, it would be unrealistic to expect that a rather observable indicators that are correlated with those
human psychological mechanism would exist that might factors.
produce an exact replication of spacetime in the human When we are thinking of how we might process space-
mind. Rather, if we look across known human processing time, it is likely that we have mechanisms that note observ-
mechanisms, what we see instead are a series of exaggera- able markers in our world that alter time perception, much in
tions and perceptual heuristics that roughly correspond, the same way we might assume that someone with a sym-
most of the time, to something “out there.” So, for example, metrical face is more likely to be fertile. This would mean
our mechanisms for distinguishing objects in our environ- that, as in the case of fertility markers, the markers will
ment involve a series of processes that essentially exagger- sometimes not correspond to reality in a given instance.
ate differences between features in our visual world: We Much evolutionary psychology suggests that we have psy-
have systems that visually enhance edges, systems that chological modules that operate in this manner (e.g., Buss &
overemphasize clustering of like stimuli, and systems that Schmitt, 2011).
finish apparently unfinished familiar objects (see, for As a result, it is not necessarily the case that we have to be
example, Weiten, 2013). experiencing spacetime alterations ourselves to show the
These perceptions do not exist in a vacuum and, as a effect of the markers. As an example, consider that if we
result, are often as responsive to relative changes on a par- have a heuristic that suggests “darkness = exaggerate danger-
ticular variable as to the absolute level of that variable (see related traits,” we do not need to feel “in danger” for the
Cialdini, 2001). A common example involves judgments of heuristic to cause the expected outcome (e.g., Schaller, Park,
temperature—A 70-degree room will feel hot if someone & Mueller, 2003). Similarly, many of the hypotheses sug-
enters it from a 40-degree environment, but the same gested by spacetime may not require people to actually expe-
70-degree room will feel cold if a person enters it from a rience spacetime alterations; but rather, people may have
100-degree environment. This simple example illustrates corresponding implicit mechanisms to alter their time per-
that we often process changes in the general direction (e.g., ceptions based on observable markers that are generally
hot to cold, cold to hot) of variables as much as we process associated with spacetime changes.
the absolute level of those variables.
As a result of this general tendency to have exaggerated What Would a Spacetime Processor
comparative perceptual mechanisms, what we might expect
to find in terms of our psychological interface with space-
Look Like?
time is not a one-to-one measurement of spacetime, but Having painted a sketch in broad brushstrokes of how we
rather a set of similarly exaggerated mechanisms for perceiv- might expect a psychological spacetime processor to inter-
ing the general direction of the relationship between the face with the real world, we now turn our attention to the
variables involved in spacetime alterations. This looser per- features a spacetime processor should possess. To do so, we
spective suggests a set of hypotheses (described in detail lay out some specific psychological factors we would expect
later in this article) about how we ought to perceive the a time perception processor to operate on if it corresponded
4 SAGE Open

in some way to the known physical relation of space and effect is often directly tied to the phenomenological percep-
time. Each factor suggests some specific hypotheses relevant tion of velocity or motion (see, for example, Jones & Huang,
to human time perception. In perhaps the most salient 1982; Masuda et al., 2011), and—consistent with relativity
hypothesis, data already exist that are consistent with the theory—it becomes larger as stimuli move more quickly
spacetime model; for the other hypotheses, no tests that we (Masuda et al., 2011).
know of have been performed. Additional studies from different paradigms have investi-
gated how the presence of action for a stimulus affects time
A Spacetime Processor Would Account for the duration estimates. For example, Yamamoto and Miura
(2012) found that after viewing an image of a person run-
Compensatory Interplay of Motion and Time: ning, participants perceived time to be lengthened—that is,
Evidence for the Spacetime Model they perceived the presentation duration to be longer—com-
One of the most eye-opening predictions of relativity theory pared with participants who viewed an image devoid of
is that motion through space and motion through time are action. Brown (1995) also found that stimulus motion length-
compensatory: The more we travel through space, the less ened perceived duration, and further showed that higher
we travel through time (see, for example, Greene, 2004; velocity stimuli led to increasingly lengthened estimates of
Hawking, 1996, 2001; Hawking & Mlodinow, 2010; Kaku, perceived time, relative to lower velocity stimuli.
2008; Krauss, 2007; Penrose, 2010; Shankar, 2013). At the Other work paints a similar picture. Tayama (2006) con-
speeds we normally travel at, this effect on time is not explic- cluded that increased velocity of motion led to increased esti-
itly noticeable; but it is occurring just the same. So if a space- mates of time elapsed. Matthews (2011) investigated the role
time processor existed, it would have some kind of of velocity by testing whether the time-lengthening effect
exaggerated mechanism for accounting for this interaction. was equal for objects in constant motion, accelerating
This suggests a straightforward hypothesis for the spacetime objects, and decelerating objects. Viewing objects in con-
processor: That perceptions of motion ought to make time stant motion led to the greatest degree of perceived time
psychologically slow down. Operationally, this means that lengthening. Furthermore, Matthews found that when par-
motion ought to increase estimates of duration (e.g., Cohen, ticipants viewed an accelerating object, followed by a sta-
Hansel, & Sylvester, 1953; Goldreich, 2007; Helson & King, tionary object, the result was a perceived lengthening of the
1931), because if time appears to move slower to Observer A duration of the stationary object.
than Observer B, Observer A will report that more time has Other studies have explored the effect of the perception of
passed in the same interval. motion by putting participants themselves into motion.
When we go to the literature on time perception, this is— Consistent with the spacetime model, Kroger-Costa et al.
with a couple of exceptions (Chen, Pizzolato, & Cesari, 2013; (2013) found that when a participant is in motion, perception
Orgs, Bestmann, Schuur, & Haggard, 2011)—exactly what sci- of stimuli duration is lengthened. Decades earlier, Brehmer
entists have found. Despite the fact that there is a widespread (1970) found that participants riding in faster moving cars
assumption that our time perception mechanisms are funda- made longer estimates of duration than those in slower mov-
mentally Newtonian, numerous studies across multiple para- ing cars.
digms have shown that as people perceive motion, time slows In summary, although there exists a small amount of evi-
down for them (Abe, 1935; Brehmer, 1970; Brown, 1995; dence that might be construed as inconsistent with the space-
Cohen et al., 1953, 1955; Helson, & King, 1931; Jones & time model (Chen et al., 2013; Orgs et al., 2011),2 an
Huang, 1982; Kanai & Watanabe, 2006; Kroger-Costa, overwhelming array of evidence from multiple paradigms is
Machado, & Santos, 2013; Lebensfeld & Wapner, 1968; consistent with a model suggesting that humans have mecha-
Masuda, Kimura, Dan, & Wada, 2011; Matthews, 2011; Mauk nisms for processing spacetime in the general direction of
& Buonomano, 2004; Newman & Lee, 1972; Price-Williams, relativity theory’s predictions.
1954; Sarrazin, Giraudo, Pailhous, & Bootsma, 2004; Tayama,
2006; Tse, Intrilligator, Rivest, & Cavanagh, 2004; Yamamoto
Novel Predictions of the Spacetime Processor
& Miura, 2012). We next provide a summary of this evidence.
Indeed, a long history of research on the well-established All good theoretical perspectives are first and foremost gen-
kappa effect is consistent with this time-stretching effect of erative (see, for example, Conway & Schaller, 2002). Thus,
perceived motion (Abe, 1935; Cohen et al., 1953, 1955; although it is interesting to note that one of the spacetime
Jones & Huang, 1982; Lebensfeld & Wapner, 1968; Masuda model’s key predictions has received empirical validation—
et al., 2011; Newman & Lee, 1972; Price-Williams, 1954; and it gives us a good reason to continue pursuing the
Sarrazin et al., 2004). The kappa effect occurs when partici- model—it nonetheless is important to use the model to make
pants overestimate the amount of time occurring between future predictions that help us generate new knowledge.
two repeated stimuli as the physical space between the stim- Below, we illustrate three additional predictions made by the
uli becomes larger. The kappa effect thus involves the depen- spacetime model that provide the potential to generate novel
dence of temporal judgments on the spatial context; the findings.
Conway et al. 5

Novel Prediction 1: A spacetime processor would account for the should perceive time as moving more quickly as we perceive
magnification of time–motion compensation across large dis- increases in altitude. Objects farther from the earth are higher
tances. Although much evidence supports that we have a up, and relativity theory suggests (and empirical observa-
mechanism that in some way accounts for relativity theory’s tions confirm) that time should move faster at higher alti-
prediction of the compensatory nature of motion and time, a tudes. Thus, as a person perceives increases in altitude, time
related (and, in physics, an equally clear and demonstrable) should psychologically speed up for the spacetime processor.
prediction from relativity theory has received no attention at Second, and more generally, we should perceive time as
all in the time perception literature. Brian Greene (2004) moving more slowly when we perceive that a target is close
illustrated by showing that if two observers were 10 billion to a mass that is large on a cosmic scale. Thus, if we perceive
light years apart, relativity theory shows that Observer A that a target is very close to a mass large enough to affect
moving a paltry 10 miles an hour toward Observer B would gravity substantially (e.g., an astronaut is close to the sun vs.
cause Observer A to move 150 years into the future of far away), our spacetime model predicts that time would be
Observer B! Thus, relativity theory directly shows that the dilated for that target.
effect of relative motion on time perception ought to be
greater the farther the two objects in question are from each Novel Prediction 3: A spacetime processor would recognize that
other. Although, like all the other spacetime effects observed other people’s experiences of time are different from its own. The
here, this magnification effect of distance in space is negli- thoughtful observer may have noticed that, up to this point,
gible at the small distances we typically travel in, a space- we have conflated the effects of observing alterations that
time processor might nonetheless have an exaggerated would affect other people’s conception of time and observing
mechanism to track it. alterations that would affect our own conception of time.
This suggests a series of testable hypotheses. For example, That is in part because perceptual heuristics and primes often
one could run typical experiments showing the motion–time function this way—They often function like direct links tap-
perception link while systematically varying the distances ping into perception mechanisms, and those links sometimes
between perceiver and perceived object. Furthermore, one work independent of context. For example, a lot of work on
can run experiments that systematically vary the distance (or priming shows that subtle exposure to words along specified
perceived distance) between two objects and their relative dimensions directly alters subsequent behavior, even when it
motion to each other—Based on the spacetime model, we makes no conceptual sense based on the context, such as
would predict that as perceived distance increased, the when people walk more slowly after they are exposed to
strength of the motion–time perception relationship would words related to being “old” (for a summary, see Bargh &
increase as well. Chartrand, 1999). In the same way, it is entirely possible that
our spacetime mechanisms might be “primed” by images
Novel Prediction 2: A spacetime processor would account for the even in circumstances where they would not normally make
compensatory interplay of gravity and time.  Relativity shows direct sense, and as such might alter our time perception in
that because gravity bends space, it also bends time. As a the same way that priming “old” alters walking speed. Thus,
result, for objects that are closer to large masses (where grav- even if we see other people in motion, or other people close
itational pull would be more immediately present), time to large gravitational objects, we might show effects of
moves slower than for objects farther from those masses spacetime processing.
(see, for example, Hawking, 1996, 2001). A straightforward On the contrary, one of the more important suggestions of
prediction made by relativity theory, then, is that time moves relativity theory is that each observer’s sense of time will
slower on the earth at low altitudes than at high altitudes, differ from every other observer’s sense, based on the prin-
because low altitudes experience more “pull” from the ciples outlined above. Although spacetime might potentially
earth’s gravity. And in fact, numerous studies using high- suggest a number of more speculative hypotheses in this
powered, precise atomic clocks have confirmed this effect— regard—an issue we return to in a later section—one of the
One such study showed that time ran faster for clocks that more straightforward things we might expect from a space-
differed in altitude by only 33 inches (Chou, Hume, Rosen- time processor is that it would account for the fact that other
band, & Wineland, 2010). Indeed, the effect is important people’s senses of time might not always be the same as our
enough that if satellite global positioning system (GPS) did own. For example, if (a) we have a mechanism for recogniz-
not account for it, their predictions would sometimes be off ing that objects at different altitudes move through time at
by several miles (Hawking, 1996; Hawking & Mlodinow, different speeds, and (b) Person A recognizes that she is cur-
2010). rently at a different altitude from Person B, it follows that (c)
If we have mechanisms for processing time in line with Person A would recognize that she and Person B are cur-
relativity theory, two related psychological hypotheses are rently moving through time at different speeds.
suggested by the effect of gravity on time (neither of which General evidence suggests that we adjust for the fact that
has received direct empirical testing to our knowledge). time “slows down” and “speeds up” across contexts (e.g.,
First, and more local to our typical experience, is this: We Carstensen et al., 1999; Conway, 2004; Droit-Volet et al.,
6 SAGE Open

2011; Droit-Volet & Meck, 2007; Flaherty, 1991; Gil & speculations and questions it inspires. For example, an evo-
Droit-Volet, 2009, 2012) and that we are aware of time dis- lutionary perspective of cultural transmission has not only
tortions (e.g., Lamotte, Izaute, Droit-Volet, 2012). For exam- generated specific hypotheses, it has also inspired research-
ple, participants in one study (Conway, 2004) showed time ers to consider questions about how culture grows that might
estimates that converged with those of other group members not have even been asked otherwise (see, for example,
if they worked with them on a face-to-face task, demonstrat- Schaller, Conway, & Tanchuk, 2002). Here, we briefly lay
ing that time perceptions are implicitly malleable at a funda- out three potential areas of research that are inspired by a
mental level. As a result of this malleability, it is reasonable consideration of spacetime. These do not directly follow
to assume that we are aware that time would subjectively from classic relativity theory, yet they emerge largely because
move differently for different people based on circumstances. of a consideration of the issues involved with the theory. If
However, none of that evidence to our knowledge tests the relativity theory is a pebble dropped in a pond, these specula-
hypothesis that we directly account for spacetime effects tions are the outward psychological ripples that emerge from
when considering other people’s movement through time. that pebble.
One simple way to test this would be to show pictures/videos
of other persons in various conditions where spacetime
effects are manipulated, and then ask people to either (a) esti-
A Spacetime Processor May Account for the
mate how much time they think has passed for themselves, or Malleability of Time’s Arrow: Precognition
(b) estimate how much time do they think has passed for that Although we generally perceive that time only moves in one
person in the picture/video. To the degree that spacetime pro- direction (from the “past” to the “future”), classic relativity
cessing effects are larger for participants’ time estimates for theory shows that there is no reason it cannot move both for-
the other people who (in those conditions) would actually be ward and backward. Unlike in Newtonian physics, relativity
experiencing the effects, this would suggest that we have a theory suggests that space and time are one whole self-con-
mechanism to directly account for the differential effects of tained entity, lumped together as a kind of “frozen river.”
spacetime on different targets. This means that, in principle, spacetime implies that time
Thus, although we might expect effects of perceived could be bidirectional. In the words of Sheehan (2006), both
motion and gravity to some degree regardless of context and relativity theory and quantum physics “formally and equally
actor, the spacetime model would expect those effects to be admit time-forward and time-reversed solutions . . . it seems
larger when explicitly considering the person(s) to whom the untenable to assert that time-reverse causation (retrocausa-
effects should directly affect. tion) cannot occur, even though it temporarily runs counter
to the macroscopic arrow of time” (p. vii).
Additional Implications of Relativity: From a psychological point of view, this asymmetry
potentially opens the door for things in the future to affect
Speculations Raised by Considering things in the present. As such, if we had a spacetime proces-
Spacetime sor that accounted for this fact, it would be psychologically
We have thus far discussed hypotheses that follow in a possible that things in the future might influence what is psy-
straightforward fashion from the theory of relativity as classi- chologically happening right now, in the same way that
cally understood. This generally involves taking empirically things in the past influence what is happening right now. This
validated or theoretically understood findings from the last would suggest that the existence of what are sometimes
100 years of physics—things on which almost all physicists called “psi” phenomena may actually be rooted in both phys-
would agree—and extrapolating in a direct way what we ical and psychological science.
might expect a spacetime processor to look like in the human And indeed, recent evidence for precognition offers some
species. While of course, as we have emphasized, no psycho- reason to believe that this idea of relativity theory might hold
logical interface with reality is perfectly straightforward, some weight. Precognition refers to an anticipatory cogni-
these hypotheses nonetheless mostly follow fairly directly tive or affective awareness, conscious or unconscious, of
from consensually agreed-upon implications of classical future events. Operationally, it is the influence of future stim-
physics. Few physicists would disagree that time slows down uli on one’s present psychological processes. Recent experi-
as motion speeds up, that the time dilation effect of motion is mental research has demonstrated precognitive effects
larger as objects are farther apart, that time slows down near relevant to reinforcement, priming, habituation, and mem-
objects with large mass, and that different observers often ory, such that effects operate “backwards in time” (Bem,
travel through time at different speeds. The psychological 2011; Bem, Tressoldi, Rabeyron, & Duggan, 2014; Tressoldi,
spacetime implications we have drawn thus far correspond Lance, & Radin, 2010). For example, Bem (2011), in a pack-
closely to those known facts drawn from relativity theory. age of nine studies published in the Journal of Personality
However, sometimes a theoretical perspective can be use- and Social Psychology, found that participants were more
ful not only for the direct hypotheses it offers but also for the likely to respond in ways that were later reinforced, when
Conway et al. 7

both the random assignment of reinforcement and the rein- time and entropy are closely linked. Brian Greene (2004)
forcement itself occurred after the responses in question summed this up:
were already made. In other words, Bem showed that what is
about to happen to participants influenced their responses [T]he only convincing framework we found for explaining
before it happened to them. This surprising finding suggests time’s arrow was that the early universe had extremely high
that current responses were influenced by future reinforce- order, that is extremely low entropy, which set the stage for a
ment of those responses, reinforcement for which partici- future in which entropy got ever larger. (p. 314)
pants would ostensibly be unaware because it had not
“happened” yet. In other, similar studies, participants’ judg- This quote illustrates a commonly accepted physical fact
ments were influenced by primes that occurred after their about spacetime: That one the most fundamental aspects of
judgments were reported, and participants performed better our experience of time—namely, that it only moves in one
on a recall test for words that were rehearsed after the recall direction—is intricately bound to entropy (see also Hawking,
test was completed. 1996; Penrose, 2010). Time’s arrow moves from low entropy
These findings have been met with a fair amount of criti- to high entropy: If we see a picture of a whole egg and then a
cal skepticism, in part because results have been inconsis- picture of the same egg smashed to bits on the floor, we
tently replicable (e.g., see Galak, LeBoeuf, Nelson, Leif, & assume that the high-entropy smashed egg came after the
Simmons, 2012), and more frequently due to both a lack of low-entropy whole egg.
theoretical explanation and a limited understanding of the Although this tie seems fundamental, no research to our
potential underlying mechanism(s) of precognitive effects knowledge has directly explored this entropy–time percep-
(Bem, 2011). Although we also share a skeptical view in part tion connection. A consideration of this relationship suggests
for these same reasons, it is worth noting that data from a that, if we have some mechanism that is sensitive to the
recent meta-analysis of 90 experiments attempting to repli- entropy–time relationship, our time perception might be dra-
cate precognitive effects—using either exact or modified matically affected by “reversing” entropy as it is presented in
methods outlined in Bem (2011)—provide support overall linear time. So by playing video clips that go from high
for the existence of precognition (Bem et al., 2014; for a entropy to low entropy (instead of the reverse)—for exam-
review of other meta-analytic evidence, see Tressoldi et al., ple, if one played a clip of billiard balls all “re-assembling”
2010). into their typical beginning state on the pool table, rather
Although neither relativity theory nor modern quantum than the balls moving from that state to becoming more scat-
physics directly predicts the specific mechanisms associated tered—one might expect that our time perception mecha-
with existing precognition effects, classic spacetime theory nisms would not function in their normal way. In particular,
at the very least offers a theoretical starting point whereby this could mean that that time slows down because we asso-
the future might psychologically affect the present. As Bem ciate high entropy with the “end” state and, if it is instead at
et al. (2014) discussed, physicists accept that time is both the beginning, are more likely to infer that time must be
symmetric and asymmetric; it may be that precognition and moving more slowly.
physics coincide in ways we do not yet understand. As such,
precognition fits within the larger framework of relativity
theory by suggesting that the direction of time is somewhat
A Spacetime Processor May Have Shared Time
malleable at least some of the time. Perception Mechanisms
We earlier outlined a straightforward prediction of the space-
A Spacetime Processor May Have Time Closely time model pertaining to others’ time perception mecha-
nisms—namely, that a spacetime processor would account
Linked to Entropy
for the fact that other persons’ time clocks are different from
Of course, although relativity theory allows for the possibil- ours in ways conforming to classical relativity theory.
ity of temporal causality to be reversed, this fact raises a bit However, it is worth noting that, to the degree that we do
of a psychological puzzle: Why do we explicitly perceive account for this, it may also have other implications for
time moving in only one direction (called “time’s arrow”)? human psychology. Here, we speculate briefly on what those
This puzzle only emerges because of relativity’s conception may be.
of spacetime; in a commonsense Newtonian framework, we Humans are inherently social beings. We have a funda-
expect time to only move in one direction. Relativity theory mental desire to belong; we do not want to be permanently
thus creates the puzzle of time’s arrow. alone or outcast; we live by being together (see, for example,
So what does modern physics say about the question of Baumeister & Leary, 1995; Conway, Houck, & Gornick,
time’s arrow? If time can be bidirectional, why do we per- 2014). As a result, it is likely the case that, although we may
ceive it to move in only one direction? The most common implicitly account for the fact that other people’s time moves
assumption of modern physics is that this emerges because differently from ours, we do not want to be on a different
8 SAGE Open

time continuum than they are. The thought that we are not However, to this point we have spoken loosely of the
moving “together” on such a fundamentally basic dimension spacetime processor without consideration of where or how
as time may feel undesirable. This suggests a set of related we might have acquired it. Below, we explore three separate
hypotheses. reasons why we might process temporal information in a
One hypothesis is that we may have a mechanism for manner consistent with relativity theory: direct adaptations,
mentally “synchronizing” our perceptions of time with oth- analogical overlap, and cultural learning.
ers, so that we feel like we are, in fact, on the same time
plane as they are. And indeed, some evidence suggests that
As Direct Adaptations
we do have just such an implicit mechanism. In one study
(Conway, 2004), participants worked on a task either side- It is possible that psychological mechanisms evolved as
by-side (no interaction) or face-to-face (such that they inter- direct adaptations to spacetime itself. But is this a legitimate
acted with others). Participants did not talk about time in any possibility? Although, on the surface, we agree with Brian
session, yet face-to-face participants showed a tendency to Greene’s opening assessment that there is no necessary sur-
converge in their perceptions of time’s passage, so that their vival benefit to perceiving spacetime effects, there are none-
perceptions of time became more like those of their fellow theless good reasons for being skeptical of arguments based
group members (an effect that did not occur in the side-by- on our capacity to perceive the survival value of a psycho-
side control conditions and was not accounted for by partici- logical mechanism in the distant past (see, for example,
pants’ mood). This research suggests that people seem to Conway, 1999; Conway & Schaller, 2002). We do not fully
have an independent mechanism to implicitly “share” the know or understand the context in which humans emerged,
time perceptions of others they interact with, even when they and the relationship of genetics to survival is immensely
never talk about that perception directly. This and other find- complex; as a result, it might be premature to assume that a
ings at the cultural level that suggest cultures have a shared set of mechanisms to more completely assess the nature of
sense of “pace of life” (Conway, Ryder, Tweed, & Sokol, spacetime would have conveyed no survival value to its
2001; Levine, 1997) fit in with a spacetime perspective—If, holders.
in fact, we do implicitly recognize that others have different Equally as importantly, no evolutionary theory suggests
time clocks than we do, we may have a compensatory mech- that only traits are related to survival last—Many of our
anism to reestablish that we belong with them, in the same existing traits appear to be either “spandrels” or “noise” that
way that our implicit existential fear of death leads us to have serve no necessary survival function (see, for example, Buss,
compensatory motivational “buffers” (e.g., Rosenblatt et al., Haselton, Shackelford, Bleske, & Wakefield, 1998; Conway,
1989). 1999; Conway & Schaller, 2002). A common example is our
A second, related set of hypotheses involves the potential bone color, which is likely just an offshoot (a “spandrel”) of
psychological unease caused by feeling one is separate from other factors relevant to bone density and structure that affect
others on the time dimension. In particular, showing others in survival—In other words, bone color itself is simply irrele-
situations where they would be experiencing different time vant to survival (see, for example, Buss et al., 1998). Many
speeds than the target according to relativity theory (e.g., of our traits are doubtless like that, and it is possible that we
seeing others in higher altitudes than we are or in a motion might have developed a mechanism for perceiving spacetime
state that we are not currently experiencing) may cause us to that conveyed no survival value, but it survived as a trait
exhibit signs of wanting to “reconnect” with the people because it did not inhibit gene survival.
around us as a compensatory mechanism. This may involve Relatedly, and more importantly, is the fact that non-
a heightened effect size for reestablishing shared time (either Newtonian spacetime effects would seem on the surface to
implicitly or by explicit efforts), or more general efforts to be so small that they would appear to be outside of the
“fit in” or feel like one belongs. human capacity to perceive. As an analog, humans do not
appear to have the capacity to see most ultraviolet radiation
Where Would a Spacetime Processing or to hear sound waves beyond 50,000 Hz. It is perhaps
therefore useless to talk about the “interface” of our percep-
Mechanism Come From? tion mechanisms with those physical phenomena, because
So far, we have discussed what a potential mechanism for we do not seem to have them at all. So given that the effects
processing spacetime might look like if humans had such a of spacetime beyond Newtonian physics would be negligi-
mechanism. We have shown that, in addition to there being ble (often measured in fractions of a nanosecond), it seems
reason to believe that space and time are intimately bound in unlikely at first blush that we would perceive them at all.
biological substrate in the human brain, there is further The distance between the proposed “exaggerated” mecha-
already substantial evidence for one of the key predictions of nisms for human psychology and the reality of spacetime
the psychological spacetime model. In addition, there is at effects in physics seems too great. It is thus a plausible
least some evidence for two of the speculative hypotheses hypothesis that we simply do not have a fine-grained enough
drawn from the spacetime model. temporal mechanism for detecting the effects of spacetime
Conway et al. 9

at really small units of time, and the psychological space- for helping explain another phenomenon has been seen
time effects that exist occur for different reasons (we explore across multiple areas within psychology. So, for example,
two other possibilities below). although human neural memory networks bear little struc-
However, it is also worth noting that a glance at the his- tural resemblance to traditional computers, computer-based
tory of research on time perception suggests a pattern of metaphors have led to great advances in our framing and
demonstrating that we can perceive time in progressively understanding of memory (for a summary, see Solso,
smaller and smaller units. Based on what we currently know MacLin, & MacLin, 2007). Similarly, although cultural sys-
about temporal-visual-related systems, we can detect stimuli tems do not operate under the same processes and constraints
at least on scales of a few dozen milliseconds (Clifford, as biological evolution, nonetheless the Darwinistic evolu-
Holcombe, & Pearson, 2004; Holcombe & Cavanagh, 2001; tionary metaphor has served to inspire and aid a generation
see Eagleman et al., 2005, for a review; see also Eagleman, of new research ideas on how culture changes over time (see,
2010; Sadeghi, Pariyadath, Apte, Eagleman, & Cook, 2011). for example, Claidière, Scott-Phillips, & Sperber, 2014;
Although this is nowhere near the speeds necessary to detect Conway & Schaller, 2002, 2007; Gornick, Conway, Cvasa,
spacetime fluctuations in our current environment beyond & Houck, 2013; Mesoudi & Danielson, 2008; Schaller et al.,
Newtonian levels, as our ability to measure the human mind 2002).
increases, scientists are discovering faster and faster process- Of course, the potential scientific value of pursuing any
ing and perception mechanisms. Given the fact that to our analog is dependent on having reasons for suspecting that
knowledge, no concerted scientific effort has been made to the analog will reflect some underlying reality of the studied
discover if such fine-grained levels of spacetime perception phenomenon. In this case, there are at least two potential
are possible, it may be premature to assume that such super- sets of reasons why there might be overlap. The first set
speedy processing mechanisms do not exist; rather, it is pos- involves empirical considerations: We have already dis-
sible that we simply have not yet detected them. cussed that space and time are clearly linked in the human
brain (see, for example, Eagleman et al., 2005) and that one
of the key direct predictions of the spacetime model has
As a Metaphorical Analog received empirical support (e.g., Cohen et al., 1953; Jones &
Of course, we too feel the same thing that Brian Greene Huang, 1982; Kanai & Watanabe, 2006; Kroger-Costa et al.,
(2004) and others have felt—that it seems unlikely that we 2013; Masuda et al., 2011; Matthews, 2011; Mauk &
have any direct psychological adaptations to spacetime. Buonomano, 2004; Sarrazin et al., 2004; Tse et al., 2004;
However, even if that turned out to be true, there are still Yamamoto & Miura, 2012). Thus, the early returns from the
reasons to believe that we may have perceptual mechanisms model are promising, offering a number of reasons to believe
that would roughly correspond to relativity theory’s predic- that some of the other, as yet untested, hypotheses may be
tions of the relation between space and time. Even when a worth pursuing.
specific model does not directly apply in perfect correspon- Second is a variant of the anthropic principle. This prin-
dence to the observed phenomenon, it can still be beneficial ciple argues that the things we discover about our universe
as a rough metaphor (see, for example, Fredrickson, 2013). must in some way be compatible with our conscious process-
As such, the consideration of spacetime might in that case ing mechanisms (see, for example, Hawking, 1996). So, for
still serve as a useful metaphorical analog for how humans example, with respect to the analogical connection between
process time perception information. human memory and computer memory, a view from the
We are not the first to make this suggestion: Others have anthropic principle would consider that the human mind
noted that relativity theory may serve as a useful loose meta- would not have discovered the possibility of computer stor-
phor for understanding the relation of time and motion per- age units if it bore no resemblance to the way we actually
ception (e.g., Goldreich, 2007; Helson & King, 1931; see process information. Thus, although neurons are nothing like
Jones & Huang, 1982). Goldreich, for example, uses the rel- the central processing units (CPUs) in computers, it is per-
ativity-inspired name time dilation to describe the stretching haps unsurprising that computer memory systems and human
of time during motion—The name is explicitly chosen memory systems bear some phenomenological overlap.
because of the rough conceptual overlap with relativity the- Indeed, it is likely the very reason that we made computer
ory. However, although these examples highlight that there is memory systems the way they are—We would be highly
clearly empirical reason to believe in the overlap between unlikely to invent a memory system that was wildly discrep-
physical spacetime and psychological spacetime, to date ant from our own.
researchers have made little effort to fully explore this con- Similarly, the anthropic principle suggests that it is pos-
ceptual overlap and what it means, or to explore potentially sible that we process information in a spacetime-like way for
new hypotheses and areas of research that might be opened reasons that are independent entirely of the minutiae of
up by a serious consideration of spacetime. spacetime itself, and yet it is that very fact that allowed us to
Generally speaking, the value of co-opting a process from ultimately discover the more complicated nuances of space-
one physical or biological phenomenon to use as a metaphor time to begin with. Although processing spacetime is not
10 SAGE Open

directly intuitively obvious to us, we nonetheless had the Do the Potential Origins of a Spacetime Processor
capacity to uncover, observe, and understand the way time, Matter?
motion, gravity, and space all interact. Although this in no
way means that we have implicit mechanisms to process We have briefly outlined three potential origins of a space-
spacetime in line with relativity theory, it does at least mean time processor. But if we have a spacetime processor, would
that the ability to understand spacetime was latent within the it matter why we acquired it? On the surface, it would seem
human species. It is therefore possible that this latent pro- that all three explanations of why we acquired it would make
cessing ability in fact corresponds to implicit processing the same set of predictions.
mechanisms. This is not a definitive argument for the space- And that is true in some large sense. However, ultimately,
time model; but it does suggest a reason why we might have as we gain more and more knowledge of how humans pro-
an analog spacetime mechanism even if it is not a direct cess temporal information, the three different proposed ori-
adaptation. The causal arrow for the overlap may, in a sense, gins would potentially make differing predictions. For
go from our spacetime-like mechanisms to our discovery of example, if we acquired the processor as a direct adaptation
spacetime, rather than the existence of spacetime causing us to real spacetime selection pressures, the predictions of the
to develop such mechanisms as direct adaptations. spacetime model should be more likely to continue to hold at
increasingly smaller units of time—because, in our local
pocket of the universe, those smaller increments are the units
As a Product of Cultural Learning at which spacetime alterations would actually exist.
An overarching knowledge structure may exist in human Conversely, if the spacetime processor emerged because of a
minds for multiple reasons. It may exist because it reflects metaphorical analog or due to cultural learning, we would be
some underlying pan-cultural psychological reality, in the less confident that it would continue to hold at incredibly
way that computer memory reflects aspects of human mem- small levels of temporal analysis. Instead, we might expect
ory (e.g., Solso et al., 2007). It may also exist because it that analogs or cultural learning would serve to guide time
originates in cultural learning, the way that knowledge struc- perception in a general way, only at the kinds of larger units
tures related to individualism and collectivism are largely for which we typically make such judgments at a phenome-
learned at the cultural level (e.g., Conway, Clements, & nological level. Thus, evidence that we show spacetime
Tweed, 2006; Conway et al., 2014; Conway et al., 2001; alterations at very small units of analysis would not defini-
Kitayama, Conway, Pietromonaco, Park, & Plaut, 2010; tively rule out the analogical or cultural learning origins, but
Kitayama, Ishii, Imada, Takemura, & Ramaswamy, 2006). would weigh more heavily in favor of a direct adaptation.
It is thus possible that relativity theory influences time Another potentially important factor on which the models
perception because it provides a conceptual cultural frame- make competing predictions involves cross-cultural replica-
work for shaping reality (e.g., Conway et al., 2001; Conway bility. If the spacetime processor has a cultural learning ori-
& Schaller, 2005; Grob, Little, Wanner, & Wearing, 1996; gin, one would expect that the level of knowledge a person or
Kitayama et al., 2010; Levine, 1997), and this learned culture had of relativity theory would directly correspond to
framework itself has an impact on time perception. The the predicted time perception effects outlined here. If it
human mind is incredibly malleable to such cultural influ- proved to be true that the effects outlined here held only for
ences, and as such, it is possible that people learn, for groups of persons with a strong knowledge of relativity, then
example, about the time–motion integration and compen- it would seem increasingly unlikely that the spacetime pro-
sate for it. If this were the case, the discovery of relativity cessor had a direct adaptation or metaphorical analog origin.
itself—and subsequent adoption across cultures—would Rather, that would make a stronger case for a cultural learn-
serve as a profound cultural framework for altering the per- ing origin.
ception of time. Consider, for example, that the reported effects of time–
Indeed, other researchers have suggested that time per- motion compensation were mostly performed in societies
ception is in part a cultural phenomenon (Conway, 2004; where there likely exists at least a cursory knowledge of the
Levine, 1997; Zimbardo & Boyd, 2008). Therefore, it is cer- theory of relativity. Although we strongly doubt that most of
tainly plausible that relativity theory might overlap with time the participants in these studies were aware of the specific
perception because it has become an accepted part of cultural predictions related to the studies in question, it is nonetheless
knowledge and, as a result, influences time perception in the possible that what those studies reflect is not a universal
same way other deeply accepted cultural folkways influence mechanism for accounting for motion–time perception inte-
human psychology. If true, the cultural learning approach to gration, but rather cultural learning of the theory of relativity.
the spacetime metaphor suggests the important idea that as If, however, such effects are found to be more or less univer-
knowledge of relativity becomes more and more pervasive, sal across cultures and independent of the knowledge of rela-
its spread will correspondingly affect time perception in line tivity theory, this suggests that the spacetime-like effects
with relativity theory. emerging from this conceptual analysis have some deeper
Conway et al. 11

basis that is more fundamental to the human species (whether 2008), it is vital that we understand it as well as we can. With
of adaptive or analogical origins). that goal in mind, the present article at the very least suggests
At this point, we do not have enough information to the potential usefulness of considering psychological space-
clearly distinguish between these various possible reasons time as a theoretical and conceptual device. It seems certain
that we might see conceptual and empirical overlap between that (a) time and space share a lot of biological overlap in the
physical spacetime and psychological spacetime. Like Brian brain, (b) we do at least in some way account for the relation-
Greene and others, we view a direct adaptation for spacetime ship of motion to time in a manner consistent with relativity
processing as fairly unlikely, and thus would expect either theory, (c) some speculative hypotheses consistent with the
the metaphorical analog or cultural learning explanations to spacetime model have received support, and (d) there are
be closer to the truth. However, our primary purpose in this additional conceptual reasons to think that relationship might
article is not to argue for any one potential origin. Rather, it apply across numerous other areas of time perception. Thus,
is to point out that there are multiple valid reasons why the more fully considering the overlap between physical space-
overlap between physical spacetime and psychological time and psychological spacetime might prove to bear fruit
spacetime may exist. As such, this suggests that it may be in our quest to better understand time perception.
worth more fully exploring the psychological spacetime
model as an explanatory mechanism for studying time Declaration of Conflicting Interests
perception. The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect
to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.
Concluding Thoughts
Funding
I had a sneaking suspicion that time was not constant, but I guess
The author(s) received no financial support for the research and/or
I could never prove it. I suppose it didn’t really matter. I even
authorship of this article.
had a theory that time didn’t go in straight line at all. I knew I
was no Albert Einstein, but I had the sneaking suspicion that
everything that had happened, was happening, or would happen Notes
was really happening all the time. There was no past, present, 1. The present article discusses possible evolutionary processes
and future. Everything was going on all at once and forever. from the lens of evolutionary psychology, but it does not nec-
(Mark A. Roeder) essarily assume a direct evolved adaptive mechanism. We
return to this issue later in the article.
Our altered understanding of spacetime was perhaps the 2. The Chen, Pizzolato, and Cesari (2013) study involved elite
most important scientific advance of the last century. And athletes rating time intervals following viewing action ver-
yet, in spite of this, its potential implications for human psy- sus nonaction pictures. Viewing action pictures compressed
(rather than dilated) time. However, this study did not involve
chology are largely not well understood. The guiding
the perception of actual (only implied) motion and was with
assumption seems to be that we are implicit Newtonians a very select population. The Orgs, Bestmann, Schuur, and
(e.g., Greene, 2004; see also Eagleman, 2004; Jones & Haggard (2011) study involved apparent motion based on
Huang, 1982); and because we do not likely have mecha- the timing of pictures of postures in different positions, and
nisms to perceive spacetime in a manner consistent with the they found that increased perceived movement in that sce-
complicated fashion that it actually exists, we can safely pro- nario compressed time perception. Even if one accepts both
ceed in ignoring psychological spacetime in our study of studies as direct evidence (and it is unclear whether the Chen
time perception. et al. study is directly related), most real effects generally have
That guiding assumption may end up being right; but counterexamples, and the overwhelming balance of evidence
existing evidence suggests that it may be at least partially is in support of the time dilation hypothesis derived from the
wrong. After all, although we may not—to use Brian proposed model.
Greene’s metaphor that we opened this article with—“feel
References
relativity in our bones,” we nonetheless have the capacity to
understand it at some level. Thus, popular author Mark A. Abe, S. (1935). Experimental study on the co-relation between time
Roeder’s “sneaking suspicion that time was not constant” and space. Tohoku Psychologica Folia, 3, 53-68.
may, after all, turn out to represent something real in human Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. L. (1999). The unbearable automatic-
ity of being. American Psychologist, 54, 462-479.
psychology that has yet to be fully explored.
Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong:
Given that time perception has incredibly important Desire for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human
implications for human emotion, life satisfaction, and mental motivation. Psychological Bulletin, 117, 497-529.
health (e.g., Carstensen et al., 1999; Conway, 2004; Droit- Bem, D. J. (2011). Feeling the future: Experimental evidence
Volet et al., 2011; Droit-Volet & Meck, 2007; Flaherty, 1991; for anomalous retroactive influences on cognition and
Fredrickson et al., 2000; Gil & Droit-Volet, 2009, 2012; affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100,
Hawkins et al., 1988; Rowe et al., 2007; Zimbardo & Boyd, 407-425.
12 SAGE Open

Bem, D. J., Tressoldi, P. E., Rabeyron, T., & Duggan, M. (2014). Conway, L. G., III, & Schaller, M. (2007). How communica-
Feeling the future: A meta-analysis of 90 experiments on the tion shapes culture. In K. Fiedler (Ed.), Frontiers of Social
anomalous anticipation of random future events. Retrieved Psychology: Social communication (pp. 107-127). New York,
from http://ssrn.com/abstract=2423692 NY: Psychology Press.
Brehmer, B. (1970). Note on the effect of velocity on perceived Coull, J. T., Frith, C. D., Buchel, C., & Nobre, A. C. (2000).
duration. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 11(1), 157-160. Orienting attention in time: Behavioural and neuroanatomi-
Brown, S. W. (1995). Time, change, and motion: The effects of cal distinction between exogenous and endogenous shifts.
stimulus movement on temporal perception. Perception & Neuropsychologia, 38, 808-819.
Psychophysics, 57, 105-116. Coull, J. T., & Nobre, A. C. (1998). Where and when to pay atten-
Buss, D. M., Haselton, M. G., Shackelford, T. K., Bleske, A. L., & tion: The neural systems for directing attention to spatial loca-
Wakefield, J. C. (1998). Adaptations, exaptations, and span- tions and to time intervals as revealed by both PET and fMRI.
drels. American Psychologist, 53, 533-548. Journal of Neuroscience, 18, 7426-7435.
Buss, D. M., & Schmitt, D. P. (2011). Evolutionary psychology and Doherty, J. R., Rao, A., Mesulam, M. M., & Nobre, A. C. (2005).
feminism. Sex Roles, 64, 768-787. Synergistic effect of combined temporal and spatial expecta-
Carstensen, L. L., Isaacowitz, D. M., & Charles, S. T. (1999). tions on visual attention. Journal of Neuroscience, 25, 8259-
Taking time seriously: A theory of socioemotional selectivity. 8266.
American Psychologist, 54, 165-181. Droit-Volet, S., Fayolle, S. L., & Gil, S. (2011). Emotion and
Chen, Y., Pizzolato, F., & Cesari, P. (2013). Time flies when we time perception: Effects of film-induced mood. Frontiers
view a sport action. Experimental Brain Research, 232, 629- in Integrative Neuroscience, 5, Article 33. doi:10.3389/
635. fnint.2011.00033
Chou, C. W., Hume, D. B., Rosenband, T., & Wineland, D. J. Droit-Volet, S., & Meck, W. H. (2007). How emotions colour our
(2010). Optical clocks and relativity. Science, 329, 1630-1633. perception of time. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11, 504-513.
Cialdini, R. B. (2001). Influence: Science and practice (4th ed.). doi:10.1016/j.tics.2007.09.008
Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon. Eagleman, D. M. (2004). The where and when of intention. Science,
Claidière, N., Scott-Phillips, T., & Sperber, D. (2014). How 303, 1144-1146.
Darwinian is cultural evolution? Philosophical Transactions Eagleman, D. M. (2010). How does the timing of neural signals map
of the Royal Society, Series B: Biological Science, 369. doi: onto the timing of perception? In R. Nihawan & B. Khurana
10.1098/rstb.2013.0368. (Eds.), Space and time in perception and action (pp. 216-231).
Clifford, C. W. G., Holcombe, A. O., & Pearson, J. (2004). Rapid New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
global form binding with loss of associated colors. Journal of Eagleman, D. M., Tse, P. U., Buonomano, D., Janssen, P., Nobre, A.
Vision, 4, 1090-1101. C., & Holcombe, A. O. (2005). Time and the brain: How sub-
Cohen, J., Hansel, C. E. M., & Sylvester, J. D. (1953). A new phe- jective time relates to neural time. The Journal of Neuroscience,
nomenon in time judgment. Nature, 172, Article 901. 25, 10369-10371. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3487-05.2005
Cohen, J., Hansel, C. E. M., & Sylvester, J. D. (1955). Flaherty, M. G. (1991). The perception of time and situated engross-
Interdependence in judgments of space, time and movement. ment. Social Psychology Quarterly, 54, 76-85.
Acta Psychologica, 11, 360-372. Fredrickson, B. L. (2013). Updated thinking on positivity ratios.
Conway, L. G., III. (1999). Noise, logic, and the span of time. American Psychologist, 68, 814-822.
American Psychologist, 54, 440-441. Fredrickson, B. L., Mancuso, R. A., Branigan, C., & Tugade, M. M.
Conway, L. G., III. (2004). Social contagion of time perception. (2000). The undoing effect of positive emotions. Motivation
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 40, 113-120. and Emotion, 24, 237-258.
Conway, L. G., III, Clements, S. M., & Tweed, R. G. (2006). Galak, J., LeBoeuf, R. A., Nelson, L. D., & Simmons, J. P. (2012).
Collectivism and governmentally initiated restrictions: A cross- Correcting the past: Failures to replicate psi. Journal of
sectional and longitudinal analysis across nations and within a Personality and Social Psychology, 103, 933-948.
nation. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 37, 20-41. Gil, S., & Droit-Volet, S. (2009). Time perception, depression and
Conway, L. G., III, Houck, S. C., & Gornick, L. J. (2014). Regional sadness. Behavioural Processes, 80, 169-176. doi:10.1016/j.
differences in individualism and why they matter. In J. Rentfrow beproc.2008.11.012
(Ed.), Psychological geography (pp. 31-50). Washington, DC: Gil, S., & Droit-Volet, S. (2012). Emotional time distortions: The fun-
American Psychological Association. damental role of arousal. Cognition and Emotion, 26, 847-862.
Conway, L. G., III, Ryder, A. G., Tweed, R. G., & Sokol, B. W. Goldreich, D. (2007). A Bayesian perceptual model replicates the
(2001). Intranational cultural variation: Exploring further cutaneous rabbit and other tactile spatiotemporal illusions.
implications of collectivism within the United States. Journal PLoS ONE, 2(3), e333. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0000333
of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 32, 681-697. Gornick, L. J., Conway, L. G., III, Cvasa, G. P., & Houck, S. C.
Conway, L. G., III, & Schaller, M. (2002). On the verifiability (2013). Cultural transmission. In K. Keith (Ed.), Encyclopedia
of evolutionary psychological theories: An analysis of the of cross-cultural psychology (pp. 335-338). Hoboken, NJ:
psychology of scientific persuasion. Personality and Social Wiley-Blackwell.
Psychology Review, 6, 152-166. Greene, B. (2004). The fabric of the cosmos: Space, time, and the
Conway, L. G., III, & Schaller, M. (2005). When authorities’ com- texture of reality. New York, NY: Random House.
mands backfire: Attributions about consensus and effects on Griffin, I. C., & Nobre, A. C. (2005). Temporal orienting of atten-
deviant decision making. Journal of Personality and Social tion. In L. Itti, G. Rees, & J. Tsotsos (Eds.), Neurobiology of
Psychology, 89, 311-326. attention (pp. 257-263). San Diego, CA: Elsevier.
Conway et al. 13

Grob, A., Little, T. D., Wanner, B., & Wearing, E. (1996). Masuda, T., Kimura, A., Dan, I., & Wada, Y. (2011). Effects of
Adolescents’ well-being and perceived control across 14 environmental context on temporal perception bias in apparent
sociocultural contexts. Journal of Personality and Social motion. Vision Research, 51, 1728-1740.
Psychology, 71, 785-795. Matthews, W. J. (2011). How do changes in speed affect the percep-
Hawking, S. (1996). A brief history of time: Updated and expanded tion of duration? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human
edition. New York, NY: Random House. Perception and Performance, 37, 1617-1627.
Hawking, S. (2001). The universe in a nutshell. New York, NY: Mauk, M. D., & Buonomano, D. V. (2004). The neural basis of
Random House. temporal processing. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 307-
Hawking, S., & Mlodinow, L. (2010). The grand design. New 340.
York, NY: Random House. Mesoudi, A., & Danielson, P. (2008). Ethics, evolution and culture.
Hawkins, W. L., French, L. C., Crawford, B. D., & Enzle, M. E. Theory in Biosciences, 127, 229-240. doi:10.1007/s12064-008-
(1988). Depressed affect and time perception. Journal of 0027-y
Abnormal Psychology, 97, 275-280. Newman, C. V., & Lee, S. G. (1972). The effect of real and imputed
Helson, H., & King, S. M. (1931). The tau effect: An example of distance on judgments of time: Some experiments on the kappa
psychological relativity. Journal of Experimental Psychology, effect. Psychonomic Science, 29, 207-211.
14, 202-217. Orgs, G., Bestmann, S., Schuur, F., & Haggard, P. (2011). From
Holcombe, A. O., & Cavanagh, P. (2001). Early binding of feature body form to biological motion: The apparent velocity of
pairs for visual perception. Nature Neuroscience, 4, 127-128. human movement biases subjective time. Psychological
Hsieh, P.-J., & Colas, J. T. (2012). Awareness is necessary for Science, 22, 712-717.
extracting patterns in working memory but not for directing Park, J. H., Schaller, M., & Crandall, C. S. (2007). Pathogen-
spatial attention. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human avoidance mechanisms and the stigmatization of obese people.
Perception and Performance, 38, 1085-1090. Evolution & Human Behavior, 28, 410-414.
Janssen, P., & Shadlen, M. N. (2005). A representation of the Park, J. H., Schaller, M., & Van Vugt, M. (2008). Psychology of
hazard rate of elapsed time in macaque area LIP. Nature human kin recognition: Heuristic cues, erroneous inferences,
Neuroscience, 8, 234-241. and their implications. Review of General Psychology, 12,
Jones, B., & Huang, Y. L. (1982). Space-time dependencies in psy- 215-235.
chophysical judgment of extent and duration: Algebraic mod- Penrose, R. (2010). Cycles of time. New York, NY: Random
els of the tau and kappa effects. Psychological Bulletin, 91, House.
128-142. Price-Williams, D. R. (1954). The kappa effect. Nature, 173,
Kaku, M. (2008). Physics of the impossible. New York, NY: 363-364.
Random House. Proulx, T., & Heine, S. J. (2008). The case of the transmogrify-
Kanai, R., & Watanabe, M. (2006). Visual onset expands subjective ing experimenter: Affirmation of a moral schema following
time. Perception & Psychophysics, 68, 1113-1123. implicit change detection. Psychological Science, 19, 1294-
Kitayama, S., Conway, L. G., III, Pietromonaco, P. R., Park, H., & 1300.
Plaut, V. C. (2010). Ethos of independence across regions in Rosenblatt, A., Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., Pyszczynski, T., &
the United States: The production-adoption model of cultural Lyon, D. (1989). Evidence for terror management theory: I.
change. American Psychologist, 65, 559-574. The effects of mortality salience on reactions to those who
Kitayama, S., Ishii, K., Imada, T., Takemura, K., & Ramaswamy, violate or uphold cultural values. Journal of Personality and
J. (2006). Voluntary settlement and the spirit of inde- Social Psychology, 57, 681-690.
pendence: Evidence from Japan’s “Northern frontier.” Rowe, G., Hirsh, J. B., & Anderson, A. K. (2007). Positive affect
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 369-384. increases the breadth of attentional selection. Proceedings
doi:10.1037/0022-3514.91.3.369 of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of
Kouider, S., de Gardelle, V., Dehaene, S., Dupoux, E., & Pallier, America, 104(1), 383-388. doi:10.1073/pnas.0605198104
C. (2010). Cerebral bases of subliminal speech priming. Sadeghi, N. G., Pariyadath, V., Apte, S., Eagleman, D. M., & Cook,
NeuroImage, 49, 922-929. E. P. (2011). Neural correlates of subsecond time distortion in
Krauss, L. M. (2007). The physics of Star Trek. Philadelphia, PA: the middle temporal area of visual cortex. Journal of Cognitive
Basic Books. Neuroscience, 23, 3829-3840. doi:10.1162/jocn_a_00071
Kroger-Costa, A., Machado, A., & Santos, J. A. (2013). Effects Saj, A., Fuhrman, O., & Vuilleumier, P. (2014). Patients with left
of motion on time perception. Behavioural Processes, 95, spatial neglect also neglect the “left side” of time. Psychological
50-59. Science, 25, 207-214. doi:10.1177/0956797612475222
Lamotte, M., Izaute, M., & Droit-Volet, S. (2012). Awareness Sarrazin, J. C., Giraudo, M. D., Pailhous, J., & Bootsma, R. (2004).
of time distortions and its relation with time judgment: A Dynamics of balancing space and time in memory: Tau and
metacognitive approach. Consciousness and Cognition: kappa effects revisited. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
An International Journal, 21, 835-842. doi:10.1016/j.con- Human Perception and Performance, 30, 411-430.
cog.2012.02.012 Schaller, M., Conway, L. G., III, & Tanchuk, T. (2002). Selective
Lebensfeld, P., & Wapner, S. (1968). Configuration and space-time pressures on the once and future contents of ethnic stereotypes:
interdependence. American Journal of Psychology, 81, 106- Effects of the communicability of traits. Journal of Personality
110. and Social Psychology, 82, 861-877.
Levine, R. (1997). A geography of time: The temporal misadven- Schaller, M., Park, J. H., & Mueller, A. (2003). Fear of the dark:
tures of a social psychologist. New York, NY: Basic Books. Interactive effects of beliefs about danger and ambient darkness
14 SAGE Open

on ethnic stereotypes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Zimbardo, P. G., & Boyd, J. N. (2008). The time paradox. New
29, 637-649. York, NY: Free Press.
Shankar, R. (2013). Fundamentals of physics: Mechanics, relativ-
ity, and thermodynamics. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Author Biographies
Sheehan, D. P. (2006). AIP Conference Proceedings: Frontiers of Lucian Gideon Conway, III received his Ph.D. from the University
time: Retrocausation—Experiment and theory. San Diego, CA: of British Columbia in 2001 and is currently a Full Professor of
American Institute of Physics. Psychology at the University of Montana. His primary research inter-
Solso, R. L., MacLin, O. H., & MacLin, M. K. (2007). Cognitive ests revolve around (1) how shared cultural beliefs – including those
psychology (8th ed.). Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon. related to time perception – emerge, persist, and have influence, and
Tayama, T. (2006). Time perception during perceiving motion pat- (2) the causes of complex (as opposed to simple) thinking and the
tern. The Japanese Journal of Psychonomic Science, 25, 212- subsequent consequences on decision-making in political and social
220. arenas. He is the author of over 50 articles, commentaries, and book
Tressoldi, P. E., Lance, S., & Radin, D. (2010). Extrasensory per- chapters in these areas, and his work has been featured in major media
ception and quantum models of cognition. NeuroQuantology, outlets such as the Washington Post, USA Today, and BBC Radio.
8, 81-87.
Meredith A. Repke is an Experimental Psychology Ph.D. candi-
Tse, P. U., Intrilligator, J., Rivest, J., & Cavanagh, P. (2004).
date at the University of Montana. Her research focuses on political
Attention and the subjective expansion of time. Perception &
communication and attitudes/behaviors related to the natural envi-
Psychophysics, 66, 1171-1189.
ronment and wellbeing.
Weiten, W. (2013). Psychology: Themes and variations (9th ed.).
Boston, MA: Cengage Learning. Shannon C. Houck is a faculty member at Syracuse University.
Yamamoto, K., & Miura, K. (2012). Time dilation caused by static She researches social and moral decision-making, dynamics of
images with implied motion. Experimental Brain Research, peace and conflict, and the causes and consequences of complex
223, 311-319. (versus simple) thinking.

You might also like