Sleeping Beauty Problem: History The Problem Solutions

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5

Sleeping Beauty problem

The Sleeping Beauty problem is a puzzle in decision theory in which whenever an ideally rational
epistemic agent is awoken from sleep, she has no memory of whether she has been awoken before. Upon
being told that she has been woken once or twice according to the toss of a coin, once if heads and twice if
tails, she is asked her degree of belief for the coin having come up heads.

Contents
History
The problem
Solutions
Thirder position
Halfer position
Double halfer position
Connections to other problems
Variations
Extreme Sleeping Beauty
Sailor's Child problem
See also
References
Other works discussing the Sleeping Beauty problem
External links

History
The problem was originally formulated in unpublished work in the mid 1980s by Arnold Zuboff (the work
was later published as "One Self: The Logic of Experience")[1] followed by a paper by Adam Elga.[2] A
formal analysis of the problem of belief formation in decision problems with imperfect recall was provided
first by Michele Piccione and Ariel Rubinstein in their paper: "On the Interpretation of Decision Problems
with Imperfect Recall" where the "paradox of the absent minded driver" was first introduced and the
Sleeping Beauty problem discussed as Example 5.[3][4] The name "Sleeping Beauty" was given to the
problem by Robert Stalnaker and was first used in extensive discussion in the Usenet newsgroup
rec.puzzles in 1999.[5]

The problem
Sleeping Beauty volunteers to undergo the following experiment and is told all of the following details: On
Sunday she will be put to sleep. Once or twice, during the experiment, Sleeping Beauty will be awakened,
interviewed, and put back to sleep with an amnesia-inducing drug that makes her forget that awakening. A
fair coin will be tossed to determine which experimental procedure to undertake:
If the coin comes up heads, Sleeping Beauty will be awakened and interviewed on Monday
only.
If the coin comes up tails, she will be awakened and interviewed on Monday and Tuesday.

In either case, she will be awakened on Wednesday without interview and the experiment ends.

Any time Sleeping Beauty is awakened and interviewed she will not be able to tell which day it is or
whether she has been awakened before. During the interview Sleeping Beauty is asked: "What is your
credence now for the proposition that the coin landed heads?"

Solutions
This problem continues to produce ongoing debate.

Thirder position

The thirder position argues that the probability of heads is 1/3. Adam Elga argued for this position
originally[2] as follows: Suppose Sleeping Beauty is told and she comes to fully believe that the coin landed
tails. By even a highly restricted principle of indifference, given that the coin lands tails, her credence that it
is Monday should equal her credence that it is Tuesday, since being in one situation would be subjectively
indistinguishable from the other. In other words, P(Monday | Tails) = P(Tuesday | Tails), and thus

P(Tails and Tuesday) = P(Tails and Monday).

Suppose now that Sleeping Beauty is told upon awakening and comes to fully believe that it is Monday.
Guided by the objective chance of heads landing being equal to the chance of tails landing, it should hold
that P(Tails | Monday) = P(Heads | Monday), and thus

P(Tails and Tuesday) = P(Tails and Monday) = P(Heads and Monday).

Since these three outcomes are exhaustive and exclusive for one trial, the probability of each is one-third by
the previous two steps in the argument.

An alternative argument is as follows. Credence can be viewed as the amount a rational risk-neutral bettor
would wager if the payoff for being correct is 1 unit (the wager itself being lost either way). In the heads
scenario, Sleeping Beauty would spend her wager amount one time, and receive 1 money for being correct.
In the tails scenario, she would spend her wager amount twice, and receive nothing. Her expected value is
therefore to gain 0.5 but also lose 1.5 times her wager, thus she should break even if her wager is 1/3.

Halfer position

David Lewis responded to Elga's paper with the position that Sleeping Beauty's credence that the coin
landed heads should be 1/2.[6] Sleeping Beauty receives no new non-self-locating information throughout
the experiment because she is told the details of the experiment. Since her credence before the experiment is
P(Heads) = 1/2, she ought to continue to have a credence of P(Heads) = 1/2 since she gains no new
relevant evidence when she wakes up during the experiment. This directly contradicts one of the thirder's
premises, since it means P(Tails | Monday) = 1/3 and P(Heads | Monday) = 2/3.

Nick Bostrom argues that Sleeping Beauty does have new evidence about her future from Sunday: "that
she is now in it," but does not know whether it is Monday or Tuesday, so the halfer argument fails.[7] In
particular, she gains the information that it is not both Tuesday and the case that Heads was flipped.
Double halfer position

The double halfer position[8] argues that both P(Heads) and P(Heads | Monday) equal 1/2. Mikaël Cozic,[9]
in particular, argues that context-sensitive propositions like "it is Monday" are in general problematic for
conditionalization and proposes the use of an imaging rule instead, which supports the double halfer
position.

Connections to other problems


Nick Bostrom argues that the thirder position is implied by the Self-Indication Assumption.

Credence about what precedes awakenings is a core question in connection with the anthropic principle.

Variations

Extreme Sleeping Beauty

This differs from the original in that there are one million and one wakings if tails comes up. It was
formulated by Nick Bostrom, and is used to argue for the thirder position.

Sailor's Child problem

The Sailor's Child problem, introduced by Radford M. Neal, is somewhat similar. It involves a sailor who
regularly sails between ports. In one port there is a woman who wants to have a child with him, across the
sea there is another woman who also wants to have a child with him. The sailor cannot decide if he will
have one or two children, so he will leave it up to a coin toss. If Heads, he will have one child, and if Tails,
two children. But if the coin lands on Heads, which woman would have his child? He would decide this by
looking at The Sailor's Guide to Ports and the woman in the port that appears first would be the woman that
he has a child with. You are his child. You do not have a copy of The Sailor's Guide to Ports. What is the
probability that you are his only child, thus the coin landed on Heads (assume a fair coin)?[10]

See also
Doomsday argument
Bayesian probability
Monty Hall problem

References
1. Arnold Zuboff (1990). "One Self: The Logic of Experience". Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary
Journal of Philosophy. 33 (1): 39–68. doi:10.1080/00201749008602210 (https://doi.org/10.1
080%2F00201749008602210).(subscription required)
2. Elga, A. (2000). "Self-locating Belief and the Sleeping Beauty Problem". Analysis. 60 (2):
143–147. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.32.3107 (https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/summary?doi=10.
1.1.32.3107). doi:10.1093/analys/60.2.143 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fanalys%2F60.2.143).
JSTOR 3329167 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3329167).
3. Michele Piccione and Ariel Rubinstein (1997) “On the Interpretation of Decision Problems
with Imperfect Recall,” Games and Economic Behavior 20, 3-24.
4. Michele Piccione and Ariel Rubinstein (1997) “The Absent Minded Driver's Paradox:
Synthesis and Responses,” Games and Economic Behavior 20, 121-130.
5. Nick Wedd (June 14, 2006). "Some "Sleeping Beauty" postings" (http://www.maproom.co.u
k/sb.html). Retrieved November 7, 2014.
6. Lewis, D. (2001). "Sleeping Beauty: reply to Elga" (http://www.fitelson.org/probability/lewis_s
b.pdf) (PDF). Analysis. 61 (3): 171–76. doi:10.1093/analys/61.3.171 (https://doi.org/10.109
3%2Fanalys%2F61.3.171). JSTOR 3329230 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3329230).
7. Bostrom, Nick (July 2007). "Sleeping beauty and self-location: A hybrid model" (http://www.a
nthropic-principle.com/preprints/beauty/synthesis.pdf) (PDF). Synthese. 157 (1): 59–78.
doi:10.1007/s11229-006-9010-7 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs11229-006-9010-7).
JSTOR 27653543 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/27653543). S2CID 12215640 (https://api.sem
anticscholar.org/CorpusID:12215640).
8. Meacham, C. J. (2008). "Sleeping beauty and the dynamics of de se beliefs". Philosophical
Studies. 138 (2): 245–269. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.517.4904 (https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/
summary?doi=10.1.1.517.4904). doi:10.1007/s11098-006-9036-1 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2
Fs11098-006-9036-1). JSTOR 40208872 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/40208872).
S2CID 26902640 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:26902640).
9. Mikaël Cozic (February 2011). "Imaging and Sleeping Beauty: A case for double-halfers".
International Journal of Approximate Reasoning. 52 (2): 137–143.
doi:10.1016/j.ijar.2009.06.010 (https://doi.org/10.1016%2Fj.ijar.2009.06.010).
10. Neal, Radford M. (2006). "Puzzles of Anthropic Reasoning Resolved Using Full Non-
indexical Conditioning". arXiv:math/0608592 (https://arxiv.org/abs/math/0608592).

Other works discussing the Sleeping Beauty problem


Arntzenius, F (2002). "Reflections on Sleeping Beauty". Analysis. 62 (1): 53–62.
doi:10.1093/analys/62.1.53 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fanalys%2F62.1.53).
JSTOR 3329069 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3329069).
Bostrom, Nick (2002-07-12). Anthropic Bias. Routledge (UK). pp. 195–96. ISBN 978-0-415-
93858-7.
Bradley, D (2003). "Sleeping Beauty: a note on Dorr's argument for 1/3". Analysis. 63 (3):
266–268. doi:10.1093/analys/63.3.266 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fanalys%2F63.3.266).
JSTOR 3329324 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3329324).
Bruce, Colin (2004-12-21). Schrodinger's Rabbits: Entering the Many Worlds of Quantum (ht
tps://archive.org/details/isbn_9780309090513/page/193). Joseph Henry Press. pp. 193–96
(https://archive.org/details/isbn_9780309090513/page/193). ISBN 978-0-309-09051-3.
Dorr, C (2002). "Sleeping Beauty: in Defence of Elga". Analysis. 62 (4): 292–296.
doi:10.1093/analys/62.4.292 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fanalys%2F62.4.292).
JSTOR 3328920 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3328920).
Elga, A. (2000). "Self-locating Belief and the Sleeping Beauty Problem". Analysis. 60 (2):
143–147. doi:10.1093/analys/60.2.143 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fanalys%2F60.2.143).
JSTOR 3329167 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3329167).
Lewis, D. (2001). "Sleeping Beauty: reply to Elga" (http://www.fitelson.org/probability/lewis_s
b.pdf) (PDF). Analysis. 61 (3): 171–76. doi:10.1093/analys/61.3.171 (https://doi.org/10.109
3%2Fanalys%2F61.3.171). JSTOR 3329230 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3329230).
Meacham, C. J. (2008). "Sleeping beauty and the dynamics of de se beliefs". Philosophical
Studies. 138 (2): 245–269. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.517.4904 (https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/
summary?doi=10.1.1.517.4904). doi:10.1007/s11098-006-9036-1 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2
Fs11098-006-9036-1). JSTOR 40208872 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/40208872).
S2CID 26902640 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:26902640).
Monton, B. (2002). "Sleeping Beauty and the Forgetful Bayesian". Analysis. 62 (1): 47–53.
doi:10.1093/analys/62.1.47 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fanalys%2F62.1.47).
JSTOR 3329068 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/3329068).
Neal, R. (2006). Puzzles of Anthropic Reasoning Resolved Using Full Non-indexical
Conditioning, preprint (https://arxiv.org/abs/math.ST/0608592)
Rosenthal, J.S. (2009). "A mathematical analysis of the Sleeping Beauty problem". The
Mathematical Intelligencer. 31 (3): 32–37. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.151.2326 (https://citeseerx.ist.ps
u.edu/viewdoc/summary?doi=10.1.1.151.2326). doi:10.1007/s00283-009-9060-z (https://doi.
org/10.1007%2Fs00283-009-9060-z). S2CID 14152244 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/Cor
pusID:14152244).
Titelbaum, M. (2013). Quitting Certainties, 210–229, 233–237, 241–249, 250, 276–277
Zuboff, A. (1990). "One Self: The Logic of Experience". Inquiry. 33 (1): 39–68.
doi:10.1080/00201749008602210 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F00201749008602210).
Wenmackers, S. (2017). "The Snow White problem". Synthese. 196 (10): 4137–4153.
doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1647-x (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs11229-017-1647-x).

External links
Terry Horgan: Sleeping Beauty Awakened: New Odds at the Dawn of the New Day (http://w
ww.u.arizona.edu/~thorgan/papers/other/Beauty.htm) (review paper with references)
Franceschi, Paul. "A Two-Sided Ontological Solution to the Sleeping Beauty Problem" (htt
p://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00004376/01/A_Two-Sided_Ontological_Solution_to_the
_Sleeping_Beauty_Problem.pdf) (PDF).
Anthropic Preprint Archive (http://www.anthropic-principle.com/pre-sb.html): The Sleeping
Beauty Problem: An archive of papers on this problem
Phil Papers Entry on Sleeping Beauty (http://philpapers.org/browse/sleeping-beauty) (a
complete bibliography of papers on the problem)
Twoplustwo thread (http://forumserver.twoplustwo.com/47/science-math-philosophy/sleeping
-beauty-problem-1122271/) discussing the sleeping beauty problem in depth

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Sleeping_Beauty_problem&oldid=1066293132"

This page was last edited on 17 January 2022, at 17:52 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using
this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia
Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

You might also like