Are We Bodies or Souls - Reviews - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews - University of Notre Dame

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 8

23/1/22 21:40 Are We Bodies or Souls?

| Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

Are We Bodies or Souls?


Richard Swinburne, Are We Bodies or
Souls?, Oxford University Press, 2019,
188pp., $19.95 (hbk), ISBN 9780198831495.

Reviewed by Thomas Nagel, New York University

2020.04.07

Richard Swinburne is a dualist of long standing, in


the tradition of Descartes, and in this book he offers
a comprehensive exposition and defense of the
position, which makes its philosophical motivation
clear. Even those who are not persuaded can be grateful to Swinburne for explaining
the distinctive appeal of this significant view, which is often treated in contemporary
discussion of the mind-body problem as an obsolete historical curiosity -- or a
bogeyman for which it is the task of philosophy to discover palatable alternatives.

Swinburne's substance dualism of individual souls and bodies is opposed not only to
all forms of psychophysical reductionism, but to anti-reductive forms of mere
property dualism or dual aspect theory. According to Swinburne, each of us is an
individual soul or self, a purely mental substance whose only essential property is
the capacity for consciousness, and whose identity is independent both of the body
to which it is attached and of the contingent experiences and other mental states and
events that make up our actual conscious lives. Each of us recognizes this unique
individual in our own case simply as "I". As Swinburne puts it, "We know who we
are."

There is a methodological question at the heart of this topic: How much authority
should be given to judgments made from the first-person point of view? Most
disagreements among philosophers of mind can be traced to different answers to
this question. There are hard-line reductionists who regard all subjective
appearances with suspicion, think anything real must be describable in the objective

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/are-we-bodies-or-souls/ 1/8
23/1/22 21:40 Are We Bodies or Souls? | Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

terms of physical science, and are even prepared to regard consciousness as an


illusion. Others admit the reality of consciousness and the irreducibility of its
phenomenological features, as revealed to the first-person point of view, but think
the nature of the person or self cannot be understood apart from the objective
conditions, mental and physical, by which we identify and reidentify human beings
other than ourselves. Swinburne, resisting such compromise, accords decisive
authority to certain first-person convictions and intuitions, much in the manner of
Descartes, as the basis for direct knowledge of our nature -- knowledge of a kind that
can neither be grounded nor called into question by external empirical observation.

Swinburne proceeds in three stages. First, he argues that a simple, indivisible subject
-- neither physically nor psychologically analyzable -- is the answer to the traditional
problem of what constitutes personal identity over time. Second, he argues that this
subject is a purely mental substance or soul distinct from the body, and that each of
us is essentially this soul, rather than a combination of soul and body. Third, he
discusses the causal interaction of soul and body, in both directions, and the natural
laws that govern those interactions. I shall limit my comments to the first two topics.

Swinburne's response to the problem of personal identity relies on the strong


intuitive judgment that whether a particular person identified in the present will
exist at some time in the future has a definite yes or no answer, and if the answer is
yes, there is a unique answer to the further question who that person will be. I will
either exist a year from now, or not, full stop: it can't be indeterminate, or a matter
of degree. And I will exist, if I do, only as a single self. This intuition -- which anyone
can feel the force of -- appears originally in my thoughts about myself, but it extends
naturally to our thoughts about other selves, if we think about them by taking up
their point of view.

Reliance on the authority of this first-person judgment underlies the two explicit
arguments Swinburne offers against alternatives to the simple theory of personal
identity: the arbitrariness objection and the more-than-one-candidate objection.
Alternatives to the simple theory all propose complex conditions -- physical, mental,
or mixed -- for the identity of a person over time. Swinburne points out, correctly,
that any analysis of personal identity in terms of physical continuity of the organism
or brain, mental continuity of experience, memory, character, and so forth, or some
combination of the two, will inevitably entail the possibility of borderline cases in
which it is not clear whether the conditions have been met. Some of these cases are

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/are-we-bodies-or-souls/ 2/8
23/1/22 21:40 Are We Bodies or Souls? | Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

actual and some merely hypothetical, but a criterion of this type cannot give a
decisive yes-or-no answer unless it draws an arbitrary line at some point in the
spectrum of cases of partial brain replacement or psychological discontinuity. The
charge of arbitrariness in Swinburne's objection is that the slight physical or
psychological differences between two cases that are close to the line but on opposite
sides of it are inherently unsuited to constitute something as momentous and all-or-
nothing as the difference between my existing and my not existing. It is the
simplicity and starkness of those alternatives, as presented to first-person intuition,
that makes any analysis by a point on a continuum of complex properties seem
arbitrary. As Swinburne says,

surely it is reasonable for some P1 who knows that she is going to undergo a
brain operation which would involve replacing 51 per cent of her previous
brain matter to hope to survive the operation. It looks as if there is an
important truth about whether P1 will survive, which cannot be settled by an
arbitrary philosophical definition of this kind. (p. 53)

Yes, from P1's point of view it certainly looks as if there is an "important truth" of
this kind -- as if the question must have a definite yes or no answer. The difficult
philosophical question is whether this conviction might be an illusion, better given
up in favor of a more external conception of P1 and her prospects, according to
which there is not always a determinate answer -- as with the survival of other
complex things in borderline cases (same restaurant, same bicycle). Admittedly the
intuition that "I" is never indeterminate does not go away on reflection, but may it
not be an illusion nonetheless -- an illusion we are stuck with because no alternative
is imaginable from the first-person point of view?

The situation is similar with Swinburne's more-than-one-candidate objection. He


imagines a double transplantation case with a divided brain, and the subject asking
whether she will be the person who receives her left hemisphere, or the person who
receives her right hemisphere, or neither. A complex physical or psychological
theory of identity can give no nonarbitrary answer to this question. The first-person
intuition on which Swinburne relies is that not only must there be an answer, but it
cannot be that the person will survive as both. The antecedent person cannot be even
partially identical with two subsequent persons who are distinct from one another:

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/are-we-bodies-or-souls/ 3/8
23/1/22 21:40 Are We Bodies or Souls? | Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

If the experiences of Alex and of Sandra [the successors] were both in some
sense also Alexandra's [the predecessor's] experiences, then whoever has one
experience should be in some degree aware of having the other experience.
For if someone is not to any degree aware of some experience, that experience
is not in any sense their experience. (p. 61)

Swinburne here rejects as unintelligible the idea of the self splitting into two
noncommunicating halves, which would permit the antecedent subject to look
forward to two separate streams of consciousness, each of which would seem to itself
like a continuation of the original one. This first-person intuition of uniqueness
seems to me less robust than the intuition that whether I will exist at all must have a
definite yes or no answer. The possibility that I might have a divided consciousness
seems subjectively imaginable in a way that future indeterminacy does not. But even
if I am wrong about this, there remains the question whether these subjective
judgments are immune to revision on the basis of third-person physical and
psychological observations.

Swinburne concludes:

The failure of all such complex theories leaves us inevitably with the 'simple
theory of personal identity': that there are no necessary or sufficient
conditions for personal identity in terms of the degree of any feature of which
there can be degrees. The obvious thing to say is that in all cases, physical and
mental continuity (and perhaps also connectedness) with a previous person is
evidence of identity with her, but does not constitute it. The more P2 has of
P1's brain, and the more P2 a-remembers what P1 did and experienced, the
more probable it is that P2 is P1; but being P1 is something other than and
beyond the evidence for it. (p. 65)

The next question Swinburne takes up is this: In what does the simple identity of the
person over time consist? To get the answer that it consists in the persistence of a
pure mental substance, or soul, he must rule out the possibility that it cannot be
analyzed further -- that it is simply a brute fact, about which nothing further can be
said, that a future person will or will not be me. Swinburne's argument against this
possibility is subtle and not altogether convincing. He imagines another transplant
case:

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/are-we-bodies-or-souls/ 4/8
23/1/22 21:40 Are We Bodies or Souls? | Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

If the two cerebral hemispheres were taken out of the brain of a person
Alexandra's skull, and one of these was put in the skull of another person Alex
from which the corresponding hemisphere had been removed, it would be
logically possible that the resulting person is Alexandra and also logically
possible that the resulting person is not Alexandra. (p. 68)

Swinburne claims that these are two distinct possibilities even if in both of them the
physical facts are exactly the same, as well as the mental facts, understood as the
complete description of the new Alex's mental properties. So there must be
something else that distinguishes them:

Since the two possible humans (Alexandra and the person who is not
Alexandra) would have all the same properties, they could only be different
from each other if one has a part which the other lacks. And, since they have
all the same bodily, that is physical, parts, they must differ in the respect that
one of them has a certain pure mental part which the other lacks, which I will
call their 'soul'. (p. 70)

But it isn't clear that a theory of mere property dualism cannot make sense of the
difference between these two possibilities. Even if the only substance involved is the
body, which is the same in both cases, and the body has irreducibly mental
properties which are qualitatively the same in both cases, why couldn't those mental
states just have the further property of being Alexandra's in one case and not in the
other? In the vein of first-person intuition that drives Swinburne's arguments, this
seems imaginable without recourse to the presence or absence of a further, purely
mental substance that underpins it.

Swinburne's next step is to argue that, although a human being is the combination of
a soul and a body, each of us is essentially not a human being, but just a soul -- a
purely mental substance without physical properties. His argument for this
Cartesian conclusion is a variant of Descartes': that though he has a body, it is
conceivable that while he is thinking, he ('I') and his mental life should continue
while his body is suddenly destroyed. The essence of the argument is this first-
person judgment about what is sufficient for his existence, and what is unnecessary.
(The possibility here is metaphysical possibility: he does not claim that it would be
causally possible for him to go on thinking if his body were destroyed -- only that it
is conceivable.)

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/are-we-bodies-or-souls/ 5/8
23/1/22 21:40 Are We Bodies or Souls? | Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

As with the previous appeals to first-person intuition, the crucial philosophical


question is whether this one can maintain its authority, in determining what is really
possible, in the face of doubts supported by a more external view of the person. Can
we be sure that our first-person grasp of ourselves and who we are is sufficiently
complete and accurate to allow us to determine with confidence the necessary and
sufficient conditions of our existence, just by thinking?

Swinburne faces this question directly. He observes that many contemporary


philosophers would say that Descartes "does not know to what substance he is
referring by 'I', and so he is in no position to assess what is logically possible for that
substance to be or do. And, they claim, each of us is in just the same position of
ignorance about what we are referring to by 'I'." (p. 85) In fact, the objection is not
new: Arnauld offers a version of it in the fourth set of replies to Descartes'
Meditations.

To answer it, Swinburne introduces a distinction between what he calls informative


and uninformative designators.

I define a word as an 'informative designator' iff it is such that if we know what


the word means, necessarily we know what is the object (substance, property,
or whatever) to which it refers (its 'referent'), in the sense that we know what
it is for an object to be that object and so we know what I shall call the
'essence' of that object. I define a word as an 'uninformative designator' iff it is
such that even if we know what the word means, we do not necessarily know
the essence of the object to which it is referring; that is, know what it is to be
the object to which it is referring. (pp. 86-7)

Uninformative designators include definite descriptions like "the tallest building in


London" or prescientific natural kind terms like 'salt' (whose meaning does not
include the information that it is sodium chloride). Informative designators include
terms like 'postage stamp' or 'proton', that can be defined verbally. But ultimately
these definitions must come to an end with some terms whose meanings we
understand more directly. Swinburne describes these as "words whose meaning we
know in virtue of being able to recognize straight-off instances of them." (p. 88) The
examples he gives include 'line', 'angle', 'red', 'door', 'road', 'side', 'shoe', 'cat', 'flower',
'kiss', 'London', 'the Eiffel Tower', and the names of numbers. Swinburne then says
the following:

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/are-we-bodies-or-souls/ 6/8
23/1/22 21:40 Are We Bodies or Souls? | Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

In the case of words whose meaning we know straight-off and so are able to
recognize under ideal conditions whether or not they apply, we know -- simply
in virtue of knowing the meaning of the word -- what it is for the object to
which they apply to be that object; we know the logically necessary and
sufficient conditions for something to be that object . . . Hence these words
whose meaning we know straight-off are all informative designators. (p. 90)

This claim is crucial to his argument, for Swinburne will go on to assert that each
person's use of 'I' to refer to himself meets these conditions. But the general claim
seems dubious. There is no necessary connection between a capacity to recognize
immediately some thing or property, and knowledge of its necessary and sufficient
conditions. The way that the recognitional capacity works may be quite opaque to
the person using the term, even if the recognition itself is fully conscious. This seems
clearly to be true of some of Swinburne's examples, like 'kiss', 'line', and 'London'.

What about 'I'? Swinburne wants to establish that, used by each of us about himself,
it is an informative designator of a mental substance. But he begins with the broader
subject of mental properties, claiming that for each person, the words referring to
his own mental properties are informative designators for that person, though not
for others. This is because each person has privileged direct access to his own mental
states, in contrast to the indirect evidential access he has to the mental states of
others. He knows without the possibility of error what pain is in his own case,
provided he knows the meaning of the word.

But does it follow that he knows everything about what pain is? Clearly he knows its
essential phenomenological character, which is sufficient to identify it when he
experiences it. But it might also have further essential features, perhaps physical,
which though inseparable from how it feels are not included in the meaning of his
first-person concept of pain. Perhaps the concept is incomplete. Each person may
have a form of access to the nature of his own sensations that is superior to the
access of others, but it does not follow that his access tells him everything about their
essential nature.

The same problem arises when we come finally to the reference of 'I'. It is certainly
true that with this term I cannot fail to pick out accurately the subject of my
experiences. In using it I refer to myself straight-off, in an unmediated way that is
not available to anyone else: I can't misidentify myself. But it does not follow that I

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/are-we-bodies-or-souls/ 7/8
23/1/22 21:40 Are We Bodies or Souls? | Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

know what I am referring to by 'I', in the sense of knowing all the logically necessary
and sufficient conditions for its existence. Only if I had such complete knowledge
could I discover by first-person reflection alone that it was conceivable that I should
continue to exist while my body was suddenly destroyed. And so far as I can tell,
Swinburne has not shown that my privileged access to my own identity necessarily
involves such knowledge, i.e., that 'I' is an informative designator.

Swinburne goes on to claim that the soul has haecceity or 'thisness', independent of
all its other properties. This means that it would be logically possible for the
biological organism Thomas Nagel to have been born to my parents and gone
through a life exactly like the one that I have led, physically and mentally, but with a
different self or soul -- so that I never existed. Again, this dreadful possibility is
supported by a vivid first-person intuition, but can the intuition be trusted?

There is a standoff here. Swinburne has shown that our first-person self-awareness
appears to reveal a mental reality independent of anything physical; but we can take
this appearance at face value only if we are confident that the mental has no
metaphysically necessary connections with the physical that are concealed from the
first-person point of view -- which is precisely the issue. If Swinburne is right, we
know who we are. If he is wrong, his arguments show that our natural sense of
ourselves includes a large dose of stubborn illusion.

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/are-we-bodies-or-souls/ 8/8

You might also like