A Rhetorical Model of Institutional Deci

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 21

Q Academy of Management Review

2016, Vol. 41, No. 1, 130–150.


http://dx.doi.org/10.5465/amr.2014.0330

A RHETORICAL MODEL OF INSTITUTIONAL DECISION MAKING:


THE ROLE OF RHETORIC IN THE FORMATION AND CHANGE OF
LEGITIMACY JUDGMENTS
ROLF L. HOEFER
INSEAD

SANDY E. GREEN, JR.


California State University, Northridge

We integrate a rhetorical perspective with neoinstitutional theory to develop a rhetorical


model of institutional decision making. We use this model to describe how the com-
municative practices of decision makers both enable and constrain how actors manage
the risk and uncertainty of their judgments and decisions within an institutional context.
We first develop a dual conception of reason as both communication (public argument)
and cognition (private argument). With this dual conception of reason, we conceptualize
actors as active and passive speakers and listeners who interpret, produce, and present
public and private arguments to persuade themselves and others to adopt, maintain, or
reject practices. Speakers and listeners have cognitive limits and thus create pre-
sumptions or shared decision-making rules to help them efficiently produce and process
the arguments needed to debate, evaluate, and adjudicate recurring institutional de-
cisions. We suggest that arguments shape actors’ reasoning and judgment because they
reflect appeals to pathos (emotion), logos (logic), and ethos (values) that support or
criticize decisions to act. These appeals also shape the nature and construction of
presumptions that bind rationality. We describe how these binds on rationality affect
the formation of judgments and decisions, as well as the performance evaluation of
institutional practices.

How does rhetoric influence legitimacy judg- Luckmann, 1966: 64). This communicative per-
ments in institutional decisions to adopt or reject spective of institutional theory frequently em-
practices? Recently, two emerging streams of re- phasizes the performative aspects of language
search have developed that help neoinstitutional and thus attempts to explain how communication
theorists answer this question. The first stream of causally shapes legitimacy judgments and the
research, often labeled “rhetorical institution- institutionalization process (Suddaby, 2010). Al-
alism” (Cornelissen, Durand, Fiss, Lammers, & though there are many variants of the rhetorical
Vaara, 2015: 12; Green & Li, 2011), suggests that institutional approach, such as “framing (Fiss &
communication in general and rhetoric in partic- Zajac, 2006), tropes (Etzion & Ferraro, 2010), dis-
ular play a critical role in shaping the legitimacy course (Phillips, Lawrence, & Hardy, 2004), and
process (Golant & Sillince, 2007; Green, 2004; rhetoric (Green, 2004),” (Cornelissen et al., 2015:
Hartelius & Browning, 2008; Heracleous & Barrett, 12–13), in most of this research there is an as-
2001; Phillips, Lawrence, & Hardy, 2004; Sillince & sumption that communication plays a perfor-
Suddaby, 2008; Suddaby & Greenwood, 2005). mative role in the development of legitimacy
Scholars with this perspective theorize that judgments. More broadly, this research grapples
communication shapes legitimacy because le- with explaining how the performative use of
gitimation “is built upon language and uses lan- language “affects actors in their thoughts and
guage as its principal instrumentality” (Berger & behaviors” because the “cognitive contents and
inferences for institutionally prescribed actions
We thank Roy Suddaby, John Lammers, and three anony- are produced and realized through and in the use
mous reviewers for their helpful and insightful comments on of language” (Cornelissen et al., 2015: 13).
ideas expressed here. We also thank Philip Anderson, In contrast to the rhetorical institutionalism re-
Thomas Goodnight, Derek Harmon, and Sorah Seong for
support and/or feedback on earlier drafts of the manuscript. search stream, which emphasizes communica-
Both authors contributed equally. All errors and omissions tion, a second more recent stream of research
are entirely our own. emphasizes the role of cognition in the formation
130
Copyright of the Academy of Management, all rights reserved. Contents may not be copied, emailed, posted to a listserv, or otherwise transmitted without the copyright
holder’s express written permission. Users may print, download, or email articles for individual use only.
2016 Hoefer and Green 131

of legitimacy judgments (Bitektine, 2011; Bitektine & integrated understanding of the role of communi-
Haack, 2015; Tost, 2011). Scholars focusing on the cation and cognition in institutions in general
role of cognition in the formation of legitimacy and the formation of legitimacy judgments in
judgments argue that past institutional research in particular.
general and rhetorical institutionalism research in To address the aforementioned issues, we build
particular (e.g., Maguire, Hardy, & Lawrence, 2004; on suggestions about the promising potential of
Suddaby & Greenwood, 2005) mistakenly concep- rhetoric for further developing institutional theory
tualize listeners or audiences as passive evalua- (Suddaby, 2010: 17). We acknowledge the critique
tors of legitimacy. Scholars working from this that previous rhetorical institutional approaches
cognitive perspective argue that ignoring the role have overemphasized classical rhetoric’s concern
of listeners as active agents “underestimates the with the speaker and (the means of) persuasion in
importance of active cognitive processing, in- the formation of legitimacy at the expense of the
formation search efforts, and social interactions active role of the listener and interpretation in
that precede the formation of legitimacy” (Bitektine, the construction of legitimacy judgments. In re-
2011: 151). These scholars go on to argue that sponse, we develop and propose a rhetorical
ignoring the role of individuals’ active cognitive model of decision making that incorporates the
processing hinders institutional theorists from speaker and persuasion as well as the listener
explaining how individual judgments of legitimacy and interpretation. In particular, our proposed
form, as well as “how those judgments emerge to model retains aspects of “classical rhetoric” that
motivate individuals to work for change or main- describe the performative role of language in the
tain the status quo” (Tost, 2011: 694). To resolve these formation of legitimacy judgments. However, we
shortcomings, scholars have recently focused more also introduce and integrate aspects of the “new
attention on the active role that audiences or eval- rhetoric,” which emphasizes the listener and in-
uators play in rendering legitimacy judgments terpretation and thus resonates and is consistent
(Bitektine, 2011; Bitektine & Haack, 2015; Tost, 2011). with more cognitive explanations of the formation
In aggregate, both streams of research in- of legitimacy.
dependently increase our understanding of the We believe that integrating both classical and
role of communication and cognition in legiti- new rhetoric into a model of decision making pro-
mation processes. However, these independent vides four key contributions to our understanding
streams of research are limited because they fail to of how rhetoric affects the legitimacy judgments
integrate and explain the reflexive interplay be- that shape institutional decisions. Our first contri-
tween cognition and communication in legitima- bution is the integration of classical and new
tion processes. This critique was an important rhetoric to develop and propose a dual conception
motivation for the recent Special Topic Forum of reason as both communication (public argu-
on Communication, Cognition, and Institutions ment) and cognition (private argument). The com-
in the Academy of Management Review (see bination of new rhetoric’s emphasis on the listener
Cornelissen et al., 2015). Specifically, largely and interpretation with classical rhetoric’s em-
missing from the first research stream on commu- phasis on the speaker and persuasion highlights
nication and legitimacy are insights about the how speakers and listeners coproduce meaning
cognitive and interpretive processes that listeners (Crusius, 1991; Hyde & Smith, 1979). Integrating
actively and passively deploy when evaluating classical and new rhetoric suggests that cognition
communications about legitimacy. Largely miss- is inherently communicative and, thus, social, di-
ing from the second research stream on cognition alogic, and double-sided because cognition re-
and legitimacy are explanations of the funda- flects and constitutes actors’ private and public
mental role of communication in the hermeneutic arguments (Billig, 1996). Moreover, an integration
or interpretive processes that social actors in- of classical and new rhetoric also suggests that
tentionally and unintentionally use to shape their communication is inherently cognitive because
own as well as others’ cognitive judgments about actors’ arguments or appeals (e.g., pathos, logos,
legitimacy. Consistent with the calls for future re- and ethos) essentially reflect as well as constitute
search in the recent Communication, Cognition, actors’ emotions, logics, and morals.
and Institutions special issue, here we attempt Our second contribution is our use of this dual
to integrate these two research streams in order conception of reason to describe the formation
to develop a more sophisticated, robust, and of legitimacy judgments as an argumentative
132 Academy of Management Review January

process. As an argumentative process, speakers institutions. We theorize how variation in pre-


and listeners with cognitive limits coproduce the sumptions shapes the level of questioning and
meanings that form legitimacy judgments while interrogation and the deployment of cognitive re-
persuading and interpreting the world for them- sources. We then theorize how the level of in-
selves and others. Within this framework, argu- terrogation and deployment of cognitive resources
mentation is the product and process by which might influence the performance evaluation of or-
speakers and listeners interrelate system 1 ganizational practices.
(i.e., automatic and unconscious) cognitive pro- Our fourth contribution is our description of how
cesses with system 2 (i.e., deliberate and con- presumptions allow us to construct an institutional
scious) cognitive processes (Green & Li, 2011; Tost, model of decision making that integrates pro-
2011). Actors deploy deliberate cognitive pro- cedural and substantive rationality. Specifically,
cesses (Evans, 2008; Kahneman, 2003; Stanovich, with the introduction of pathos, logos, and ethos
1999) when they consciously use arguments to appeals to reason, we theorize how presumptions
balance and weigh their reasons. However, the are in many ways artifacts of substantive ratio-
deliberate and conscious use of these arguments nality (e.g., emotion, logic, and values) manifested
also produces and establishes presumptions— in procedural rationality (e.g., satisficing). These
decision rules regarding a class of situations. appeals construct and shape the tilt and strength
Presumptions are devices of argumentation and of presumptions and thus reflect the content or
deliberation (Godden & Walton, 2007) that help “substance” that binds decision maker rationality.
actors organize and weave reasons into their un- In sum, our rhetorical model of institutional de-
conscious webs of belief. These unconscious cision making details how cognition and commu-
webs of belief reflect automatic cognitive pro- nication entwine procedural and substantive
cesses that structure and bind decision maker rationality for a more holistic and realistic view of
rationality. We believe this communicative and human reasoning and, thus, institutional decision
cognitive model details how actors as both making built on logic, values, and emotion.
speakers and listeners passively and actively We organize the article as follows. We first de-
participate in the formation of legitimacy judg- scribe and integrate classical and new rhetoric to
ments and institutional decisions, thereby offer- reconceptualize institutional decision making as
ing a portrayal of institutional embeddedness a product and process of arguments deployed by
that is neither too underrationalized nor too speakers and listeners. Based on this integrated
overrationalized (Powell & Colyvas, 2008). rhetorical conception of institutional decision mak-
Our third contribution is the further elaboration of ing, we theorize how speakers use arguments to
the concept of presumption to model the formation persuade or influence listeners’ legitimacy judg-
of legitimacy judgments and the making of in- ments and how listeners use arguments to interpret
stitutional decisions as a joint communicative ac- and form legitimacy judgments from the communi-
tivity that entwines the cognitions of both speakers cations they evaluate. We then use this model of
and listeners (Bitektine, 2011; Cornelissen et al., how arguments shape both persuasion and in-
2015; Tost, 2011). Specifically, we conceptualize terpretation to explain the role of rhetoric in the
presumptions as the communicative and cognitive formation of legitimacy judgments and, thus, actors’
mechanism through which institutions organize decisions to adopt and institutionalize practices or
actors’ communicative interactions and limited reject and deinstitutionalize practices. Finally, we
cognitive resources. Presumptions organize com- elaborate on what this means for our understanding
municative interactions by assigning the burden of of institutional decision making, the interrelation-
proof to one or the other side of an argument. They ship of communication and cognition, and the per-
organize cognitive resources by deploying decision formance evaluation of institutional practices.
rules that govern the rationality of actions within
a particular class of situations. Sometimes pre-
sumptions dictate that actors decrease the de- RHETORIC AND DECISION MAKING
ployment of cognitive resources, and this often
Rhetorical Theory: Integrating Classical and
predisposes actors to imitate and maintain in-
New Approaches
stitutions. Other times presumptions pressure ac-
tors to increase the use of cognitive resources, and Rhetoric is the symbolic manipulation of limited
this often drives actors to innovate and change attention and cognitive resources to persuade
2016 Hoefer and Green 133

or “make known” meaning to oneself and to (Hyde & Smith, 1979: 354; Jasinski, 2001: 289). More-
others in order to influence social action (Hyde & over, new rhetoric often emphasizes rhetoric as
Smith, 1979: 348; see also Bizzell & Herzberg, “ontological” or private discourses that exist
2001, and Perelman & Olbrechts-Tyteca, 1969). within the individual’s intrapersonal domain to
Although the scope of rhetorical theory is large form personal interpretation and personal judg-
(Bizzell & Herzberg, 2001), in this article we in- ments (Bonet, 2014: 802; Hyde & Smith, 1979: 354;
tegrate classical and new approaches to rheto- Jasinski, 2001: 292).
ric to inform our understanding of institutional Integrating new and classical rhetoric suggests
decision making. The classical approach to that speakers and listeners have cognitive limits
rhetoric emphasizes the speaker’s use of rhetor- and thus coproduce meaning while persuading and
ical strategies, especially appeals of pathos interpreting the world for themselves and others.
(e.g., emotions), logos (e.g., logic), and ethos Focusing on the contingency of human actions and
(e.g., values), in the construction and deployment the coproduction of meaning suggests that the art of
of rationality (Aristotle, 1992). It starts with the persuasion and the art of interpretation entwine
assumption that actors’ cognitive limits are crit- when actors deploy phronesis or practical judgment
ical to understanding rationality, decision mak- needed to make decisions based on common sense,
ing, and behavior, and it emphasizes a direct plausible interpretations, or persuasive argument
relationship between communication, cognition, (Booth, 1974; Crusius, 1991: 9; Perelman & Olbrechts-
and action in an uncertain, contingent world Tyteca, 1969). Within this framework, rhetoric ini-
(Aristotle, 1992). Classical rhetoric emphasizes tially shows itself in a person’s thinking and, thus,
persuasion and the point of view of the speaker or in the intrapersonal domain as actors interpret
rhetor, as opposed to the listener or audience, the world and persuade themselves. Rhetorical
and thus conceptualizes the audience “as a tar- scholars theorize that this internal process often
get, a source of expectations” that guides the leaves traces in public discourse (Hyde & Smith,
production of speakers’ persuasive messages 1979: 354; Jasinski, 2001: 292). In addition, rhetori-
(Benoit & Smythe, 2003: 96). Moreover, classical cal scholars argue that for actors to share their
rhetoric often emphasizes rhetoric as “ontic” or interpretations and persuade other actors about
public discourses that exist between individuals the validity of their interpretations, they must
as speakers and listeners for the purpose of transition this private discourse into public dis-
persuasion (Bonet, 2014: 794–796; Hyde & Smith, course. Once actors transition their private dis-
1979; also see Jasinski, 2001: 292). course into public discourse, speakers and listeners
In contrast to classical rhetoric, new rhetoric negotiate and coproduce shared meanings be-
emphasizes identification and interpretation from tween each other through rhetorical exchanges
the point of view of the listener or audience, as (Jasinski, 2001: 292; Mailloux, 1990).
opposed to the speaker or rhetor. It focuses on the
audience as an active agent in the persuasion pro-
Deploying an Integrated Rhetorical Perspective
cess by elaborating on the role of rhetoric in self-
in Human Decision Making
persuasion, interpretive processes, and personal
judgments (Bonet, 2014: 800–804; Crusius, 1991: Rhetoric, as a field of inquiry, was the first field
70-80). New rhetoric emerged with Kenneth Burke’s of study developed to examine human choice
A Rhetoric of Motives (1969a), Chaı̈m Perelman under conditions of contingency and probability
and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca’s The New Rhetoric: (Aristotle, 2001). Decisions are choices that bring
A Treatise on Argumentation (1969), and Martin into existence or confer actuality on contingent
Heidegger’s student Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Truth courses of action (e.g., the adoption or rejection of
and Method (1975). Similar to classical rhetoric, practices; Lonergan, 2005: 613). These decisions or
new rhetoric emphasizes the importance of cogni- choices for action often result from judgments or
tive limits and the way actors use language to choices that temporarily complete one’s knowl-
manage the uncertainty inherent in “living through” edge and assessment or evaluation of an existing
and existing “in a world of almost infinite linguistic actuality (e.g., a practice is good or bad; Lonergan,
possibilities” (Jasinski, 2001: 289). Within this 2005: 613). Deploying a rhetorical perspective
framework, rhetoric is the process humans use sensitive to concerns of both classical rhetoric
to select and reveal a linguistic possibility and new rhetoric produces a powerful framework
“as something” and thus to make known meaning for understanding decision making. For instance,
134 Academy of Management Review January

discussing the importance of studying rhetoric in Carnegie model of institutional decision mak-
decision-making, Aristotle stated: ing rests on a theory of choice that explains and
describes human behavior as shaped by actors’
Most of the things about which we make decisions,
and into which therefore we inquire, present us attempts to manage the uncertainty of their de-
with alternative possibilities. For it is about our cisions and actions (March & Simon, 1958; Simon,
actions that we deliberate and inquire, and all our 1976). Within this framework, actors use argu-
actions have a contingent character; hardly any of ments or premises to direct attention and struc-
them are determined by necessity (Aristotle, 1992: ture the beliefs that underlie institutional
1357).
decisions (Green, Li, & Nohria, 2009; Suddaby &
From an integrated rhetorical perspective, Greenwood, 2005).
rhetorical scholars describe beliefs, thinking, Beliefs are the content of judgments. Beliefs
reasoning, and decision making as entangled in- are critical to institutional decisions because they
extricably with arguing and arguments (Billig, are the substantive content of actors’ legitimacy
1996; Brown, 1987). This view suggests that actors’ judgments—evaluators’ opinions about whether
arguments or reasons are often double-sided and, an individual, organization, or practice is legiti-
thus, embedded within an uncertain argumenta- mate or illegitimate (Bitektine, 2011: 152; Tost,
tive context—designed to describe the world in 2011: 687). Legitimacy judgments occur when ac-
ways that either criticize or support alternative tors acquire, manifest, or change their beliefs.
courses of action (Billig, 1996; Bonet, 2014: 794; When actors believe in the appropriateness of
Potter, 1996). Arguments are double-sided be- a practice, they often judge the practice as legiti-
cause choice is inherently about contingencies mate and thus are motivated to decide to adopt
and probability. We argue that the double- and institutionalize the practice. When actors doubt
sidedness of arguments is best captured in com- the appropriateness of a practice, they often judge
munication and the communicative nature of the practice as not legitimate and thus are moti-
cognition because decision makers are simulta- vated to decide to reject and deinstitutionalize the
neously speakers and listeners when they seek to practice. Within this framework, understanding
construct and deploy reasons that justify their how arguments shape and reflect beliefs is criti-
choice, to themselves and to others (Aristotle, 1992; cal to explaining the adoption and institution-
Billig, 1996; Tetlock, 1992). Within this framework, alization of practices, because the acquisition,
argumentation or the weighing of reasons for or manifestation, or change in beliefs shapes the
against various alternatives is the best model of formation and evolution of legitimacy judgments,
human decision making because the cognitive which, in turn, shape actors institutional deci-
processes underlying our thoughts and decisions sions to adopt and institutionalize or reject and
are both the product and process of arguing deinstitutionalize practices.
(Billig, 1996). This formulation resonates with Arguments shape beliefs. An integrated view
scholarship suggesting that communication pro- of rhetoric suggests that actors shape others’ as
duces and constitutes our beliefs and rationalities well as their own beliefs via argumentation. Ar-
(Garfinkel, 1967; Habermas, 1984; Quinn, 1996; guments construct and modify beliefs and, thus,
Rorty, 1980; Wittgenstein, 1963). action, because actors have cognitive limits and
exist in an uncertain world where they never
fully know the performance implications of their
The Role of Rhetoric in Institutions: Arguments,
beliefs and the consequences of their actions
Beliefs, and Legitimacy
(Aristotle, 1992; Bitzer, 1968; Simon, 1976). Within
An integrated view of rhetoric complements this uncertain world, adherence to particular be-
and extends the model of decision making un- liefs and/or actions engenders risk and therefore
derlying neoinstitutional theory. The model of requires rhetorical justification. Despite the ef-
decision making presently used in neoinstitu- forts of analytic philosophers, there is no univer-
tional theory in many ways extends a set of criti- sal, unassailable justification for belief (Quine &
cal ideas and assumptions initially developed by Ullian, 1978; Toulmin, 1969). Whether a belief is
Herbert Simon and elaborated further by scholars justified is a matter of whether actors assess
within the Carnegie perspective of institutions that it merits further questioning. Similar to the
(Argote & Greve, 2007; DiMaggio & Powell, 1991). Carnegie perspective of institutions (Gavetti,
Similar to an integrated rhetorical view, the Levinthal, & Ocasio, 2007), an integrated rhetorical
2016 Hoefer and Green 135

perspective suggests that actors assess the merits decision premises underlying actors’ organiza-
of their beliefs for particular choices or decisions tional decisions. In fact, Simon argued that de-
through reason or the process of drawing conclu- cision premises were perhaps the most important
sions from premises (Aristotle, 1992; Simon, 1976; unit of analysis for understanding organizations
Tompkins, Tompkins, & Cheney, 1989). (Simon, 1976: 123, xii).
A rhetorical conception of institutional decision
making extends these ideas and suggests that
A Rhetorical View of Institutional Decision
institutions limit the phenomena that actors con-
Making: A Dual Conception of Reason
sider worthy of rational consideration via the
From both a rhetorical and a Carnegie per- management of decision premises. Sometimes
spective, decision premises are the reasons these decision premises or warrants are explicit
that justify the beliefs that form the judgments and consciously stated by organizational actors.
that shape our decisions or choices for action. In At such times the rationalization of practices
addition, in an integrated rhetorical view of as both comprehensible and appropriate is the
institutional decision making, these decision product of actors’ conscious and deliberate de-
premises or reasons are themselves essen- ployment of reasons or arguments (Green et al.,
tially public and/or private arguments and, 2009). Other times decision premises or warrants
thus, both communicative and cognitive (Billig, are implicit and taken for granted. At such times
1996; Nienkamp, 2001). Sometimes actors deploy the institutionalization of practices is the process
or state their premises or reasons for their choices by which actors weave their reasons for action
at the ontic level and therefore make public state- into their unconscious web of belief as they accept
ments or arguments. Other times, and for various and take these reasons for granted (Green et al.,
reasons that we discuss later, actors deploy their 2009). Taking premises for granted frees up limited
premises or reasons for their choices only at the cognitive resources for more pressing problems.
ontological level and therefore let their cognitive or This is an important benefit of institutionalization,
private arguments go unstated (Green et al., 2009). because for actors with cognitive limits complete,
This dual conception of reason as existing at both irrefutable proof for the beliefs supporting a prac-
the ontic and ontological levels and as both com- tice is often unobtainable.
municative and cognitive resonates with the com- Institutions help to allocate limited cognitive
monly understood semantic conception of reason resources efficiently by legitimating the trunca-
as both a communication or “statement offered tion of doubts that might otherwise completely
in explanation or justification” and a cognition absorb attention without providing a useful result
or “rational ground or motive” (Merriam-Webster (Collins, 1992). Accordingly, institutions and their
Dictionary, 2003). Moreover, from a rhetorical view corresponding beliefs are a blessing because
of institutional decision making, a dual concep- they help actors efficiently allocate limited cog-
tion of reason also provides the empirical and nitive resources (e.g., attention) across problems
conceptual bridge to integrate levels of analysis and solutions. However, this efficiency comes at
and move from the ontological or cognitive a cost. That is, institutions are also a curse be-
microprocess of individual thinking or private cause failing to question beliefs conserves lim-
argument to the ontic or communicative and in- ited cognitive resources at the expense of diligent
tersubjective macroprocess of social interaction evaluation and interrogation.
or public argument. Building on these ideas, we model important as-
From both a rhetorical and a Carnegie per- pects of institutional decision making as changes in
spective, actors have cognitive limits, and, thus, public and private argumentation. Sometimes ac-
the premises that underlie their decisions shape tors make public arguments and state their reasons.
and control their behavior (Aristotle, 1992; Simon, In such cases actors are likely not taking their prac-
1976). Decision premises have many institutional tices for granted. At other times actors make private
sources, including family, religion, and educa- arguments or cease to state their reasons. In these
tion (Douglas, 1986; Friedland & Alford, 1991; cases actors are likely taking their practices for
Tompkins & Cheney, 1985). The Carnegie per- granted. Within this framework, the production and
spective conceptualizes the organization as an acceptance of argument is the concrete mechanism
institution (Cyert & March 1963; March & Simon, that actors use to decide whether to initiate and
1958) and, therefore, an additional source of maintain institutions or dismantle and change
136 Academy of Management Review January

them, because actors use arguments to weigh the assessment of the risk of doubting indicates the
risk of believing and judging an institutional prac- institutionalization of those beliefs.
tice as legitimate versus the risk of doubting and Actors do not wish to experience the conse-
judging an institutional practice as not legitimate. In quences of failing to correctly assess what to believe
the next section we detail and describe how actors and what to doubt as legitimate. Rhetorical theory
use argument to weigh the risk of believing versus suggests that actors assess the risk of believing and
doubting institutional practices. doubting symbolically via the search for, the con-
struction and production of, and the competition
between arguments (Paglieri & Castelfranchi, 2010;
RHETORIC AND THE FORMATION OF Perelman & Olbrechts-Tyteca, 1969; Toulmin, 1969).
LEGITIMACY JUDGMENTS Actors use arguments to parsimoniously (Paglieri &
Woods, 2011) allocate their limited cognitive abili-
Argumentation and the Risks of
ties and attention in the evaluation of practices—
Forming Judgments
articulating beliefs and doubts so that they effi-
A primary goal of a rhetorical model of in- ciently and appropriately attend to and weigh
stitutional decision making is to describe how the relative risks of believing versus doubting
actors use arguments to weigh the risk of believ- (Perelman, 1982; Perelman & Olbrechts-Tyteca,
ing and judging a practice as legitimate versus 1969). When actors have a choice or decision to
the risk of doubting and judging a practice as not make that implies action or inaction, they often ex-
legitimate. We use the concept of risk because it is perience an increase in their desire to explain or
both an antecedent and consequence of decisions account for their behaviors; thus, they seek and
to communicate and act. When individuals take construct reasons to justify their choice, to them-
action or make utterances, they take risks and selves and to others (Irwin & Davis, 1995: 329; Lerner
subsequently modify the risks to themselves and & Tetlock, 1999; Tetlock, 1992). Within this frame-
others. The risk of believing describes the nega- work, the balance or weighing of reasons for and
tive consequences actors face when they initially against various alternatives determines the choice
believe something is true that they or their com- to believe or doubt (Burnstein & Vinokur, 1977;
munity later believes is false. Thus, the risk of Isenberg, 1986; Shafir, Simonson, & Tversky, 1993;
believing and judging a practice as legitimate Vinokur & Burnstein, 1978). Individuals and groups
includes the consequence of believing that a prac- make decisions by choosing the alternative with the
tice will perform well but having actors sub- highest tally (e.g., quality and/or quantity) or bal-
sequently evaluate that practice as not performing ance of reasons (Barber, Heath, & Odean, 2003;
as initially expected. The risk of believing and Shafir et al., 1993; Tversky, Sattath, & Slovic, 1988).
judging a practice as legitimate also includes the From a rhetorical perspective, actors shape the
risk that social neighbors will judge one as irra- balance of reasons through argumentation. Argu-
tional or incompetent for using or advocating the ments shape the balance of reasons and, thus,
use of the practice. A decrease in actors’ assess- beliefs by transforming the perception of risks. For
ment of the risk of believing indicates the institu- example, what may appear risky to believe prior to
tionalization of those beliefs. the presentation of an argument can appear risky
In contrast to the risk of believing, the risk of to doubt after the argument’s presentation. Ar-
doubting and judging a practice as not legitimate guers accomplish this transformation by guiding
includes the negative consequences of initially attention to valid reasons that are unseen or less
believing something is false that actors or the valued by the audience prior to their utterance
community later believes is true. These risks (Weick, 1979; Weick & Browning, 1986). Arguers,
include the risk of wasted time and attention, re- such as management gurus or consultants, can
dundant retesting and reinterrogation of effica- therefore decrease or mitigate a portion of the risk
cious practices, and/or benefits forgone because of doubting or believing experienced by them-
of delayed or half-hearted investment. An addi- selves and others by presenting a complete, or
tional risk of doubting and judging a practice as partially complete, search result (Abrahamson,
not legitimate is that social neighbors will judge 1996; March & Simon, 1958; Weick & Browning,
one as incompetent, irrational, or subversive by 1986). Within our rhetorical institutional frame-
failing to evaluate as true that which the com- work, the conferral of legitimacy is the consequence
munity perceives as true. An increase in actors’ of the successful reduction and management of
2016 Hoefer and Green 137

these risks. Decisions to adopt, maintain, or reject of listeners (Green, 2004; Harmon, Green, &
institutional practices are a consequence of belief Goodnight, 2015; Suddaby & Greenwood, 2005;
in or judgment about the legitimacy of a practice. Vaara & Monin, 2010). Social actors take on the
Belief or judgment about the legitimacy of a practice role of listener and the means of interpretation
is a consequence of the production, presentation, when they receive arguments from speakers
and processing of arguments. Thus, actors decide to that they attempt to make sense of (Cornelissen
adopt and institutionalize practices to the extent et al., 2015). Listeners also deploy many in-
they believe or judge these practices to be legiti- terpretive strategies to interpret and form le-
mate or appropriate and those who adopt or main- gitimacy judgments (Burke, 1969b).
tain these practices to be rational, competent, and Although in previous institutional research
themselves legitimate. These beliefs or judgments, scholars often conceptualized the formation of
in turn, depend on the production and presentation legitimacy judgments as a passive and/or unidi-
of arguments by actors, an activity that requires rectional process from speaker to listener, recent
actors to expend attention, use limited cognitive research emphasizes the active role of listeners in
resources, and undertake risks to produce and the construction of legitimacy judgments (Bitektine,
present arguments. 2011; Tost, 2011). Our rhetorical model of institu-
tional decision making attempts to build on this
conception of an active role for the listener and
Speakers, Listeners, and Legitimacy Formation
the means of interpretation without swinging the
An integrated rhetorical model of institutional pendulum too far and underemphasizing the
decision making provides a conceptual basis for role of the speaker and the means of persuasion
connecting institutional decisions to the argu- in the formation of legitimacy judgment. Thus,
ments social actors deploy to shape the risk of our rhetorical model of institutional decision
believing or doubting the legitimacy of organi- making highlights both the speaker and the
zations, events, or practices. The model we pro- listener and, thus, the dialogical construction
pose suggests that the formation of legitimacy or coproduction of legitimacy judgments. This
judgments takes place in a dialogical argumen- formulation resonates with recent calls from
tative environment where cognitively limited institutional researchers to emphasize and
speakers and listeners exchange public and pri- analyze meaning as a joint communicative and
vate arguments between themselves (i.e., ontic) cognitive product of speakers and listeners
and within themselves (i.e., ontologically), re- within institutions (Cornelissen et al., 2015:
spectively, to manage the risks involved with 13–14).
forming legitimacy judgments about practices. In Automatic or passive versus deliberate or
this section we discuss the persuasion and in- active cognitive processes. From a rhetorical
terpretation processes speakers and listeners use institutional perspective, argumentation is the
when they manage the risks involved in forming concrete process actors as speakers and listeners
legitimacy judgments and making institutional use to persuade and interpret for themselves and
decisions. others the risks of believing versus the risks of
Speakers and listeners. Social actors manage doubting. Through argumentation, or the rhetori-
the risks involved with forming judgments and cal management of the risks of believing versus
making decisions. Within our rhetorical in- the risks of doubting, speakers and listeners vary
stitutional model there are two primary roles for the amount of cognitive resources they deploy to
social actors: speakers and listeners. Speakers produce, present, and process future arguments.
and listeners manage the risks of making legiti- When the deployment of cognitive resources is
macy judgments via the production, presentation, high, speakers and listeners actively and con-
and processing of arguments. Social actors take sciously deliberate the choices before them.
on the role of speaker and the means of persua- When the deployment of cognitive resources is
sion when they produce and present argu- low, speakers and listeners passively and auto-
ments regarding the legitimacy or illegitimacy matically respond to the choices before them.
of institutional practices targeted at listeners These ideas resonate with frameworks such as
(Cornelissen et al., 2015). Speakers deploy many the cognitive response or elaboration likelihood
means or types of rhetorical strategies to per- model (see Benoit & Smythe, 2003, and Petty &
suade and influence the legitimacy judgments Cacioppo, 1986).
138 Academy of Management Review January

We argue that conceptualizing variation in the of arguments. In such cases actors will often
deployment of cognitive resources provides our struggle with meaning or multiple interpretations
model with a window into the dynamic and in- by asking themselves or others, “What does this
tegrated role of speakers and listeners and their mean?” yet it is only in the role of the speaker that
use of persuasion and interpretation processes. the active listener can raise questions or provide
For instance, we suggest that when speakers de- alternative answers to themselves (i.e., privately)
ploy a minimum amount of cognitive resources, or others (i.e., publicly). Similar to speakers, when
they are passively speaking, and when they de- listeners deploy large amounts of cognitive re-
ploy a larger amount of cognitive resources, they sources, the interpretation process entwines with
are actively speaking. When speakers actively the persuasion process because listeners must
speak, they take on the dual role of both speaker take on the role of speaker as they discuss with
and listener. Active speakers deploy more cogni- themselves or others the various interpretations of
tive resources and, thus, are highly conscious of the messages they have received.
or attuned to the many persuasive possibilities Ontic and ontological. Finally, our rhetorical
in the rhetorical situation. Active speakers, in model of institutional decision making proposes
a sense, are able to listen to the argument they are that speakers and listeners coproduce meaning in
presenting from the vantage point of the listener general and legitimacy judgments in particular at
in real time and are therefore able to comprehend two levels: the ontic level and the ontological
various potential interpretations of their argu- level. At the ontological level a social actor pro-
ment. This increases the ability of the speaker to duces private arguments that he or she only hears.
discover, invent, and articulate the many poten- At the ontic level social actors produce public argu-
tial available means of persuasion by becoming ments that both parties hear. If the listener creates
cognizant of the many potential ways listeners a private argument, he or she must take on the role
can interpret their arguments. Most important, of the speaker. If the speaker creates a private ar-
during active speaking, the persuasion process gument, he or she must take on the role of the
entwines with interpretation processes because listener. If the listener or speaker makes his or her
speakers must take on the role of listener as argument public, he or she takes on the role of the
they attempt to interpret the potential meaning of speaker, and the other party receiving the argu-
their arguments. In contrast, passive speaking ment takes on the role of the listener. Within this
takes place when speakers deploy minimal cog- framework, persuasion and interpretation takes
nitive resources and are, in effect, almost on place at the ontological level via self-persuasion
autopilot and so producing and presenting argu- and self-interpretation, as well as at the ontic level
ments in a rote or almost ritualistic manner, often via social persuasion and social interpretation. At
unaware of or unconcerned with the various in- the ontic level speakers and listeners produce,
terpretations of their arguments. present, and interpret arguments to manage the
Similar to active and passive speaking, we public or interpersonal risks of forming legitimacy
propose that when actors listen, they can also vary judgments. At the ontological level speakers and
the amount of cognitive resources they deploy. For listeners produce, present, and interpret argu-
instance, we suggest that when listeners deploy ments to manage the intrapersonal risks of form-
a minimum amount of cognitive resources, they ing legitimacy judgments.
are passively listening, and when they deploy
a larger amount of cognitive resources, they are
Presumption and the Management of Legitimacy
actively listening. Similar to speakers, when lis-
Judgment Risks
teners actively listen, they take on the dual role of
both listener and speaker. Active listeners deploy From a rhetorical institutional perspective,
more cognitive resources and, thus, are highly the formation of legitimacy judgments is a co-
conscious or attuned to the many interpretive production of cognitively limited speakers and
possibilities in the rhetorical situation. Active listeners who differently deploy cognitive re-
listeners, in a sense, are able to speak or present sources in order to produce, present, and process
the argument they are receiving from the vantage arguments. Although many factors can shape the
point of the speaker in real time and are therefore formation of legitimacy judgments (Bitektine,
able to comprehend the various potential in- 2011; Tost, 2011), a rhetorical perspective empha-
tentions and alternative persuasive constructions sizes presumptions as perhaps the most relevant
2016 Hoefer and Green 139

and important cognitive and communicative legitimacy of a practice for granted, they often
mechanism or device actors use to manage the intentionally or unintentionally create pre-
risks of forming judgments and making decisions sumptions: they assign a cognitive and commu-
(Goodnight, 1980). The concept of presumption nicative advantage that shapes the production of
fully embraces a dual conception of reason as future arguments for one side or the other within
both communicative and cognitive. Specifically, a class of recurring situations (e.g., the decision
presumptions are decision rules that give a cog- to adopt a given practice). Describing pre-
nitive and communicative advantage to one sumptions as an argumentative bind on future
side of a decision or dilemma (Goodnight, 1980; judgments and decisions to act suggests that
Whately, 2009). A rhetorical model of institutional actors also form judgments and make decisions
decision making suggests that actors create and about communication. Specifically, as with many
deploy presumptions so as to effectively de- other decisions to act, social actors weigh the costs
liberate with themselves and others about a re- and benefits of taking the act of communication for
curring class of situations or problems requiring granted by either “letting the taken-for-granted
a decision (Ullman-Margalit, 1983). pass” and moving on with a conversation, or chal-
Presumptions function as decision rules be- lenging the taken-for-granted by conducting
cause they form assumptions made before prac- further analysis through questioning (Hopper,
tical deliberation that tilt the burden of proof for or 1981: 207–208). The creation and deployment of
against an alternative unless there is sufficient presumptions provide a concrete way to un-
reason to believe otherwise (Godden & Walton, derstand how the taken-for-granted can operate
2007; Ullman-Margalit, 1983). In a sense, pre- recursively on other taken-for-granteds (Hopper,
sumptions are judgments because they judge one 1981; Townley, 2008).
side of an argument as more acceptable than Most important, presumptions are previously
the other side, holding all else constant. In an- negotiated settlements or agreements between
other sense, presumptions are also decision rules speakers and listeners concerning the organiza-
because they shape the production of arguments— tion and weighing of reasons for and against re-
the communicative actions of speakers and lis- curring choices to believe that a practice is
teners. The side with the burden of proof finds it legitimate or illegitimate and, thus, worthy of
more difficult to produce interpretable and per- maintenance and adoption or rejection. The cre-
suasive arguments because this side carries ation and evolution of presumptions provide
a cognitive and communicative burden or disad- an important lens or window from which re-
vantage and thus needs more evidence to support searchers may observe how social actors col-
its claims. By shifting the burden of proof, pre- lectively form legitimacy judgments. The concept
sumptions can help decision makers achieve de- of presumption also complements and extends
sired outcomes when the best course of action the Carnegie concept of “satisficing.” Specifically,
depends on whether a “certain state of affairs the Carnegie perspective suggests that satisfi-
obtains,” yet the boundedly rational agent “is in cing is a key cognitive mechanism of procedural
a state of ignorance or doubt concerning” the true rationality, because satisficing describes how
state of affairs (Ullman-Margalit, 1983: 155). In the decision makers sample and evaluate alterna-
context of forming legitimacy judgments, pre- tives during the search process. In the context of
sumptions help define which side of the legiti- making a decision, we can use the concept of
macy judgment (e.g., legitimate or not legitimate) satisficing to describe part of the process by
is required to deploy more cognitive resources which an actor reaches a judgment or decision
and to engage in more active listening and/or that is good enough to act on or live with. More-
speaking. over, satisficing also helps describe how actors
As communicative and cognitive devices, pre- might manage their searches by using heuris-
sumptions are both a product and process of tics or stop rules based on adjustable aspirations
actors’ use of rhetoric to manage their limited in order to achieve their goals (Gavetti, Greve,
cognitive resources. From a rhetorical perspec- Levinthal, & Ocasio, 2012; Simon, 1997). Within
tive, institutionalization is the process through this framework, satisficing is a procedural con-
which actors manage and optimize limited cog- straint on rationality because it selects a mini-
nitive resources by taking the legitimacy of mally acceptable as opposed to an optimum state
a practice for granted. When actors take the of affairs, and it limits the search for solutions to
140 Academy of Management Review January

the first one expected to achieve this state of less expensive alternatives of similar quality be-
affairs (Baumol, 2004). This makes actors “in- cause of the common business presumption that,
tendedly rational, but only limitedly so” (Simon, all else being equal, IBM technology was superior
1976: xxviii). (Rawsthorn, 2011). Managers summarized the es-
Yet while satisficing describes an important sence of this presumption in the popular phrase
aspect of how actors might choose to deploy cog- “no one ever got fired for buying IBM” (Rawsthorn,
nitive resources when making decisions, we ar- 2011). In this institutional context, the burden of
gue that the addition of presumption furthers our proof tilted heavily in favor of judging the pur-
understanding of how actors form judgments and chase of an IBM product as legitimate compared
make decisions, because presumptions help us to the purchase of competitors’ products. All else
understand how decisions contain both cognitive being equal, one would expect managers buying
and communicative properties. Specifically, while non-IBM products in such an environment to find
the concepts of presumption and satisficing de- it more difficult to search for and produce in-
scribe a similar cognitive function—to help actors terpretable and persuasive arguments that justi-
find a minimally acceptable as opposed to an fied their purchase decisions than managers who
optimum state of affairs—presumption organizes decided to buy IBM products.
the burden of proof between speakers and lis- Presumption, interpretation, and persuasion.
teners and thus orients decision making within In short, presumptions tilt the burden of proof in
a communicative context by incorporating the favor of one alternative. This burden of proof
intersubjective symbolic environment where places different argumentative requirements on
satisficing takes place. the proponents of the presumption compared to
Not surprisingly, presumptions are common the opponents of the presumption. Presumption
communicative and cognitive devices used proponents may produce arguments that pre-
throughout organizations to make legitimacy sume matters of fact “in the absence of certain
judgments and institutional decisions. For exam- reasons for belief” (Ullman-Margalit, 1983: 152).
ple, in the practice of U.S. criminal justice, courts Presumption opponents, however, must possess
presume that defendants accused of a crime are those certain reasons for belief in order to produce
innocent until proven guilty (Bentham & Dumont, arguments that rebut the presumption (Ullman-
1981). Within this institutional context, judges and Margalit, 1983). Simply put, to produce interpret-
juries are predisposed to believe and thus decide able and persuasive arguments, those objecting
not guilty because the assignment of the burden of to the presumption must deploy more cognitive
proof makes it more difficult for the prosecution to resources than those supporting it (Godden &
produce interpretable and persuasive arguments Walton, 2007).
compared to the defense. Similarly, for corporate
Proposition 1: As the strength of pre-
law cases, courts often abide by the Business
sumption in favor of conferring a judg-
Judgment Rule, which presumes that directors of
ment of legitimacy for a given practice
a corporation act in good faith and in accordance
increases, organizational members will
with the interests of the corporation’s stakeholders
find it easier to produce interpretable
unless proven otherwise (Wasserstein, 1998). In
and persuasive arguments in favor of
this situation the burden of proof is in favor of in-
that practice.
cumbent managers’ decisions, and, thus, critics of
incumbent managers find it more difficult to pro- Proposition 1 suggests that the strength of pre-
duce interpretable and persuasive arguments rela- sumption represents an important factor in the
tive to arguments in favor of managerial decisions. formation of legitimacy judgments, because the
Managers also use presumptions in business strength of presumption tells decision makers
institutions to make legitimacy judgments and which side of the legitimacy judgment has the
decisions about adopting or rejecting practices. burden of proof. For example, with respect to
For example, consider decisions by information presumptions that support the conferral of legiti-
technology managers in the 1970s and 1980s to macy, the strength of presumption shapes the
purchase and use computer equipment. During production, presentation, and interpretation of
this period, information technology managers of- arguments in favor of lowering the risks of be-
ten purchased the more expensive International lieving and raising the risks of doubting the
Business Machines (IBM) computers rather than legitimacy of a given practice. In such cases
2016 Hoefer and Green 141

interlocutors are more likely to find arguments actors take that institutional practice for granted.
supporting the legitimacy of that practice in- The higher the strength of presumption, the more
terpretable or minimally reasonable and legiti- entrenched an institutional practice and, thus,
mate and/or persuasive and highly appropriate. the more cognitive and communicative resources
In contrast, interlocutors hoping to rebut or criti- needed to change that institutional practice.
cize the legitimacy of the practice will find it more Although existing institutional practices often
difficult to produce interpretable and persuasive have presumption on their side (Hirschman, 1991;
arguments critical of the legitimacy of that Whately, 2009), the strength of presumption varies
practice. To accomplish their goals, these in- across institutional practices. Some institutional
terlocutors will have to expend far more cognitive practices have strong presumptive support and
and communicative resources than those in favor are deeply embedded and entrenched. These
of the practice. institutional practices, therefore, are highly re-
Proposition 1 also suggests that presumptions sistant to change and require the deployment of
are potentially an important way actors embed a great deal of cognitive and communicative re-
themselves within institutions by participating in sources before they will change. In contrast, other
the communicative organization of cognitive re- institutional practices have weak presumptive
sources across problems and social actors. Pre- support and are fragile. These institutional prac-
sumptions as the communicative organization or tices are more susceptible to change and require
construction of a burden of proof constrain or bind the deployment of far less cognitive and commu-
the individual and collective rationality of actors nicative resources in order to change.
in the context of recurring institutional decisions.
Proposition 2: As the strength of pre-
Presumptions, once formed and taken for granted,
sumption in favor of legitimacy judg-
define how actors’ automatic cognitive processes
ment for a given practice increases, the
come to bind or constrain actors’ deliberate cog-
institutional persistence of that prac-
nitive processes. Moreover, Proposition 1 suggests
tice will increase and the institutional
that communication or symbolic exchange is
change of that practice will decrease.
a critical element in the formation of legitimacy
judgments. This conceptualization transforms
the formation of judgment and institutional de-
Presumption and Substantive Rationality
cision making from a solitary cognitive process
implied by the traditional concept of satisficing With the introduction of the concept of pre-
(see Miller, 1990) and recent descriptions of the sumption, Propositions 1 and 2 help us integrate
formation of legitimacy (e.g., Bitektine, 2011; the communicative elements of procedural ratio-
Bitektine & Haack, 2015) into a social process nality with the cognitive elements of procedural
where communication and cognition interrelate rationality in the formation of legitimacy judg-
as speakers and listeners deliberate about the ments. In addition, the concept of presumption
choices available to them. also lays the groundwork for increasing our
Presumption, adoption, and institutional understanding of substantive rationality in
persistence. Building on Proposition 1, we also judgment formation and institutional decision
argue that presumptions shape adoption, insti- making. Specifically, the development of Prop-
tutionalization, and institutional persistence. For ositions 1 and 2 suggests that the strength of
instance, presumptions may shift the burden of presumption shapes and mediates the forma-
proof to those who want to change institutions tion of legitimacy judgments and, thus, de-
(Block, 1978), making it more difficult for those cisions to adopt or institutionalize a practice.
in favor of change to produce and present in- Although there are many potential reasons for
terpretable and persuasive arguments in favor of actors to construct and/or vary the strength of
institutional change. In such cases institutional presumptions, rhetorical theory posits that ac-
practices are very persistent, and social actors tors vary the strength of presumptions in order to
will need to deploy more cognitive and commu- manage the risks of making decision errors—
nicative resources to convince themselves and Type I and Type II errors (Goodnight, 1980). Type I
others to change or deinstitutionalize them. The errors, or false positives, are decision errors
strength of presumption in favor of an insti- where actors initially believe something is true
tutional practice also often relates to the degree that they later believe is false. Type II errors, or
142 Academy of Management Review January

false negatives, are decision errors where actors years are, in fact, dead. It only means that it
initially believe something is false that they later makes good practical sense to infer that they are
believe is true. Type I and II errors are especially indeed dead unless there is evidence to suggest
important in the context of organizational de- otherwise.
cision making (Shapira, 1995). An important factor shaping the development
Rhetorical theory incorporates substantive ra- and evolution of presumptive rules is the per-
tionality into decision making by suggesting that ceived performance of the presumptive rule
three main types of reason (i.e., pathos, logos, and (Ullman-Margalit, 1983). If the performance of
ethos) influence actors’ decision error prefer- a presumptive rule fails to reduce the chance of
ences. Logos (particularly induction) strengthens decision errors, actors may begin to question
presumption in the direction of the decision error and change the presumptive rule. For example,
that is least likely to occur. Logos appeals often business managers and legal courts may aban-
relate to the production of pragmatic or technical don or change presumptive rules if the purchase
legitimacy judgments (Green, 2004; Suchman, of IBM products fails to deliver initially expected
1995). Pathos and ethos strengthen presumption returns or if individuals missing for more than
in the direction of decision errors that the indi- seven years begin to show up alive.
vidual actor or the community, respectively, is Presumption and pathos and ethos. Rhetorical
most comfortable accepting. Actors’ use of pathos theory also suggests that actors tilt presump-
appeals usually relates to the production of tions out of concern for the emotional or social
pragmatic or emotional legitimacy judgments. In acceptability of decision errors (Goodnight, 1980;
contrast, ethos appeals usually relate to and Ullman-Margalit, 1983). There are two main ways
produce normative or moral legitimacy judg- actors rhetorically manage these errors: pathos
ments (Green, 2004; Suchman, 1995). Pathos, logos, and ethos appeals. “Pathos appeals connect with
and ethos appeals coexist, yet one usually out- the emotions of individuals (e.g., fear, greed, etc.)”
weighs the others in constructing and defining the (Green, 2004: 659). Ethos appeals link to moral or
nature or strength of a given presumption. Con- ethical concerns usually manifested in socially
ceptualizing pathos, logos, and ethos appeals as accepted norms and mores. While culture shapes
shaping the strength of presumptions extends both appeals, pathos (like logos) justifications
and builds on our understanding of how in- “emphasize individual concerns and interests,”
stitutions might procedurally bind rationality to whereas “ethos appeals focus on social and col-
encompass and incorporate the way institutions lective interests” (Green, 2004: 660).
substantively bind rationality. Presumptions based on ethos offer a useful way
Presumption and logos. Rhetorical theory sug- to understand the influence of culture on in-
gests that actors with cognitive limits can never stitutional decisions. For example, it is entirely
avoid all decision errors. One way actors manage possible that most individuals charged with
decision errors is by using logos or logic. Logos a crime are indeed guilty. In such a world, a pre-
appeals usually induce formal and methodical sumptive rule of “guilty until proven innocent”
calculation of means and ends to achieve effi- reduces the total number of errors for most legal
ciency or effectiveness (Green, 2004). Presumptions decisions. However, even in the face of such in-
help cognitively limited actors manage and reduce ductive evidence, U.S. society prefers a pre-
Type I and II errors by providing deliberative rules sumptive rule of “innocent until proven guilty,”
and guidelines for choosing the best course of ac- because U.S. values or ethos prefers a world
tion in order to reduce the error (Type I or II) that is where the guilty go free over a world where the
most likely to occur (Goodnight, 1980; Perelman & innocent are imprisoned for crimes they did not
Olbrechts-Tyteca, 1969; Ullman-Margalit, 1983). commit (Bentham & Dumont, 1981). This prefer-
For example, in U.S. law courts, many important ence for one type of error over another is an im-
decisions depend on whether an individual is portant way that cultural, moral, and social
dead. Sometimes a body is not available to con- preferences constrain or bind the rationality of
firm death, and individuals are just missing. In actors’ judgment formation and decision making
these cases the courts presume that people are (Ullman-Margalit, 1983). This means that the analy-
dead if they are absent without explanation for sis of presumptions also offers a method for exam-
more than seven years. This does not mean that ining the influence of society and culture on social
individuals that are missing for more than seven decisions and actions (Edmondson, Roberto,
2016 Hoefer and Green 143

Bohmer, Ferlins, & Feldman, 2005; Lounsbury & decision premises with pathos (emotions), logic
Ventresca, 2002; Schein, 1996). (logos), and values (ethos). These appeals shape
In sum, presumptions based on logos consti- presumptions, which, in turn, influence the pro-
tute and reflect the logic of induction by reduc- duction, presentation, and interpretation of argu-
ing the probability or chance that actors will ments, and therefore institutional persistence and
make decision errors. Presumptions based on change.
ethos and pathos reduce decision errors that
actors find the most socially or emotionally un-
Presumption, Contestation, and
acceptable or least preferred. By shaping actors’
Performance Evaluation
perceptions of the probability of or preference
for particular decision errors, the rhetorical ap- So far we have described how a rhetorical
peals of pathos, logos, and ethos shape the tilt model of institutional decision making connects
and/or strength of presumption. As described presumptions and argumentation to actors’ be-
earlier, changes in the tilt and/or strength of liefs or doubts about legitimacy and decisions to
presumption can influence institutional persis- adopt or reject institutional practices. Next we
tence and change. discuss the performance evaluation implications
of our model. We define performance evaluation
Proposition 3: Variation in pathos,
as the degree of fit between a past or current
logos, and ethos can shape the tilt and/
and future belief or judgment about the state of
or strength of presumptive support and
the world. In the context of managerial decision
thus can influence institutional persis-
making, such a definition suggests that managers’
tence and change.
decisions under uncertainty are predictions about
Proposition 3 suggests that the rhetorical ap- the future (Shapira, 1995). We contrast decisions to
peals of pathos, logos, and ethos play an impor- adopt or reject a practice at time t1 and beliefs or
tant role in institutional decision making. In judgments about the effectiveness or legitimacy of
contrast to the conventional Carnegie view of in- that practice at time t1 with beliefs or judgments
stitutional decision making as primarily an ex- about the effectiveness or legitimacy of that prac-
ercise in procedural rationality (Simon, 1978), tice at time t2.
a rhetorical institutional view adds the commu- In our rhetorical model of institutional deci-
nicative appeals of pathos, logos, and ethos to sion making, we argue that the level of contes-
create a model of rationality that has both pro- tation during the institutionalization process
cedural and substantive qualities. Specifically, can shape a practice’s performance evaluations.
conceptualizing pathos, logos, and ethos ap- All else being equal, the higher the burden of
peals as shaping the tilt and/or strength of proof a practice has to face in order to institu-
presumptions extends and builds on our un- tionalize, the lower the risk of doubting the
derstanding of how institutions might procedur- effectiveness or legitimacy of that practice.
ally bind rationality to encompass and integrate Therefore, institutional practices facing a higher
the “substance” or content of these binds. This is burden of proof are more likely to emerge via
a much-needed improvement on the traditional deliberations that are contested, interrogated,
procedural view of decision making and rational- and scrutinized. In such cases actors’ initial
ity, which suggests that organizational behavior is evaluations of performance for institutional
ultimately “determined by the irrational and non- practices that have overcome such high burdens
rational elements that bound the area of rationality” of proof are more likely to match actors’ future
(Simon 1945: 79). evaluations of those practices’ performance
From a rhetorical view of institutions, our emo- (i.e., things we believe or judge as true that we
tions, as well as our values, are not irrational or also believe and judge as true at some later point
nonrational elements of decision making. In in time). We theorize that decision makers ex-
particular, an integrated rhetorical approach to amine institutional practices facing a higher
institutional decision making suggests that pre- burden of proof more rigorously than other in-
sumptions as communicative warrants are sub- stitutional practices facing less contestation.
stantively based on three appeals of reasoning Therefore, we theorize that practices facing
(pathos, logos, and ethos). Communication and higher burdens of proof should suffer less
deliberation establish, infuse, and embed our from decision-making problems that lead to errors
144 Academy of Management Review January

such as groupthink (Janis, 1972) and/or other un- contests that gave rise to an institutionalized
foreseen mistakes or problems. For example, practice may provide insight into that practice’s
Janis (1971) argued that a failure to reduce the risk future performance evaluation. Our basic sug-
of doubting and increase contestation helped gestion is that some institutionalized practices
produce groupthink for the Kennedy administra- may have a history of low interrogation, driven by
tion, which resulted in the failed Bay of Pigs a favorable initial presumptive tilt, whereas other
invasion in 1961 (see also Tetlock, Peterson, institutionalized practices may have a history of
McGuire, Chang, & Feld, 1992). Moreover, Janis high interrogation, driven by an initial critical
(1971) argued that reduction of the risk of doubting presumptive tilt. Practices developing in a favor-
and increased contestation prevented groupthink able presumptive tilt are more likely to represent
in the institutional decision-making processes of institutional practices that actors presently be-
the Kennedy administration during the Cuban lieve are effective or true but then believe are in-
Missile Crisis in 1962. effective or false in the future, compared to those
According to our model, variation in the tilt and/ practices that develop in a critical or unfavorable
or strength of presumption has a direct impact on presumptive tilt. Practices that develop in a favor-
the amount of contestation, because the tilt and/ able presumptive tilt must overcome fewer con
or strength of presumptions influences the pro- arguments and, thus, are more likely to represent
duction, presentation, and interpretation of argu- practices that actors evaluate as performing
ments. Specifically, if a practice begins with poorly in the future. Conversely, practices initially
a favorable as opposed to critical presumptive tilt, facing a critical presumptive tilt (e.g., controversial
critics of the practice will find it more difficult to practices) and a great many doubts or con argu-
produce interpretable and persuasive arguments ments necessitated more cognitive and communi-
critical of the practice. All else being equal, cative resources to rebut these critiques and
practices with a more favorable as opposed to produce interpretable and persuasive arguments
more critical presumptive tilt will overcome fewer in favor of their adoption and institutionalization.
doubts or con arguments during the process of We propose that a higher number of con argu-
adoption and institutionalization. Put succinctly, ments reflects an increase in the scrutiny and in-
practices that initially face a favorable as opposed terrogation of these practices and thus indicates
to critical presumptive tilt face less contestation a decrease in the chance that actors will evaluate
during the adoption and institutionalization process. these practices as performing poorly in the future.
This is important if one considers that at any In sum, Proposition 4 suggests that if pre-
given time a community or social field will have sumptions shape the amount of interrogation and
a set of established and institutionalized prac- diligent analysis of decision makers, and the
tices. These institutionalized practices reflect amount of interrogation and diligent analysis
knowledge about what the community believes shapes the production of decision errors, then
and judges as true. However, history suggests presumptions should shape the production of
that there is always some percentage of insti- decision errors. The practical implication of this
tutionalized practices the community believes are proposition is potentially powerful if we connect
true today that the community will believe are not this idea to insights from Donaldson and Lorsch
true in the future. (1983), who suggest that managers can benefit
from periodically auditing or assessing their be-
Proposition 4: Social actors are more
liefs or judgments. For example, imagine a new
likely to evaluate practices that were
CEO who is assuming the leadership of a large
institutionalized with strong presump-
and complex business organization. Once in this
tive support (i.e., faced less contestation)
leadership position, the CEO faces many daunt-
as performing poorly in the future than
ing and challenging tasks. One common and im-
practices that were institutionalized
portant task the new CEO and his/her executive
with weak presumptive support (i.e.,
team face is assessing the effectiveness and risks
faced more contestation).
of the firm’s established institutional practices.
Proposition 4 allows us to assess the perfor- Within the set of established practices inherited
mance risks of institutionalized practices. In par- from the previous CEO and leadership team
ticular, the proposition suggests that a historical are practices that are good and effective for the
analysis of the presumptive context and argument firm. The new leadership team should keep and
2016 Hoefer and Green 145

maintain these practices. However, there are also granted, they cease to evaluate and interrogate
some practices that are bad and ineffective, and, their beliefs or judgments about the insti-
thus, the new leadership team should reject and tutionalized practice. Consequently, this un-
discard these practices. The institutional decision questioned belief increases the probability that
problem is discovering and identifying which in- actors will believe an institutional practice is le-
stitutional practices to keep and which to discard. gitimate or efficacious today that they will per-
Our rhetorical model of institutional decision ceive as performing poorly in the future.
making recognizes the informational and time
constraints of the new leadership team and thus
The Formation of Legitimacy Judgments
proposes one strategy to efficiently address this
challenge. Specifically, if a history of the com- Our model contributes to the literature on the
munication surrounding the adoption of the formation of legitimacy judgments. Scholars
established practices exists, the leadership team working from this perspective often focus on the
should examine this communication, identify psychological and social psychological factors
those practices that had strong presumptive that shape legitimacy judgments or evaluations
support during their adoption and institutionali- of desirability and appropriateness (Bitektine,
zation, and spend more of their limited time and 2011; George, Chattopadhyay, Sitkin, & Barden,
resources interrogating these practices as op- 2006; Kennedy & Fiss, 2009; Tost, 2011). Building on
posed to those practices that were institutionalized these seminal efforts, our rhetorical model de-
with low or unfavorable presumptive support. If lineates the fundamental role of communication
our model is correct, those practices that were in- in the persuasive and interpretive processes that
stitutionalized in the face of high presumptive social actors as both listeners and speakers use
support should have more errors than those prac- to shape their own as well as others’ cognitive
tices that were institutionalized in the face of low or legitimacy judgments. For instance, our model
unfavorable presumptive support. builds on primarily one-sided explanations from
listeners’ perspectives (Bitektine, 2011; Bitektine &
Haack, 2015; Tost, 2011) to develop a more bal-
DISCUSSION AND CONCLUSION anced explanation of when and how legitimacy
forms between speakers and listeners. Further-
Argumentation, Presumption, and Institutional
more, our model provides insight into the “need”
Decision Making
(Bitektine, 2011)—what drives or motivates
Our purpose in this article was to develop an people—to form or change legitimacy judgments.
integrated rhetorical model of institutional de- In particular, in previous work researchers tended
cision making in order to show how communica- to equate cognitive legitimacy judgments with
tion and cognition interrelate among active and a lack of content. For instance, Tost argued that
passive speakers and listeners to shape legiti- legitimacy judgments are initially formed with
macy judgment formation and institutional de- substantive justifications or content; however,
cision making. Our first goal and contribution over time this content dissipates and cognitive
was to show that judgment formation and de- legitimacy or taken-for-grantedness emerges
cision making are products and processes of (Tost, 2011: 697-698). We argue that describing
argumentation. We developed a model that de- cognitive legitimacy as the absence of questions
scribes how institutional actors manage the or lack of substantive content hinders us from
blessing and curse of institutionalization through explaining what it is “that leads individuals to
the arguments and presumptions they deploy that begin to actively interrogate an existing social
shape and weigh the perceived risk of believing entity and to imagine possible alternatives” (Tost,
versus the perceived risk of doubting the effec- 2011: 700) or what factors “lead people to move out
tiveness or legitimacy of institutional practices. of the use stage, where institutional arrange-
Actors use argumentation to manage the bless- ments are passively accepted, and into the judg-
ing of institutions by economizing limited cog- ment reassessment stage, where institutional
nitive resources. However, argumentation and arrangements are actively interrogated” (Tost,
presumptions also shape the curse of institu- 2011: 700).
tions, because when actors take the effectiveness Our model suggests that the formation of cog-
or legitimacy of an institutionalized practice for nitive legitimacy often leaves substantive content
146 Academy of Management Review January

or binds on the rationality or communication identifying and explaining when and how actors
patterns of speakers and listeners. Specifically, as speakers and listeners use persuasion and
for recurring classes of institutional decisions, interpretation processes to manage the risk of
speakers and listeners will construct presump- believing or doubting the legitimacy of organi-
tions or rules regarding the burden of proof for one zations, events, or practices. For example, we ar-
side of a legitimacy judgment versus the other gued that the formation of legitimacy judgments
side of the legitimacy judgment. Speakers and occurs when cognitively limited speakers and
listeners establish these binds on rationality for listeners exchange public and private arguments
particular reasons, and these binds have sub- between themselves (i.e., ontic) and within them-
stantive content (e.g., pathos, logos, ethos) and selves (i.e., ontologically) to manage the risks in-
thus reflect the emotions, logic, and values of volved with forming legitimacy judgments about
these actors. Presumptions represent a mecha- practices. Within this framework, argumentation
nism for describing how substantive content is both a concrete mechanism actors use to
shapes the formation of legitimacy judgments, as manage their limited cognitive resources and
well as reflects the emotions, logic, and values of an important indicator of how automatic and
speakers and listeners. Moreover, presumptions deliberate cognitive processes interrelate in
as burdens of proof provide us with a lens to use in decision-making processes. Our model shows
explaining when actors will passively accept how automatic cognitive processes via the de-
a judgment or actively interrogate and reassess ployment and use of presumptions evolve and
that judgment. develop out of deliberate cognitive processes.
This is a much-needed improvement over pre-
sent models of institutional decision making
Practice Adoption and Implementation Literature
that often create caricatures of human rea-
We also believe that this rhetorical model of soning as under- or overrationalized (Powell &
how argumentation affects institutional judg- Colyvas, 2008).
ments and decisions extends and complements
institutional theorists’ focus on practice adoption
Procedural and Substantive Rationality
and implementation literature (e.g., Gondo &
Amis, 2013). Specifically, Proposition 1 through 4 Finally, our rhetorical model of institutional
describe how presumption and rhetorical appeals decision making provides a framework for con-
interrelate to shape the way organizational de- ceptualizing an institutional rationality that
cision makers weigh the benefits and risks of combines both procedural and substantive
forming judgments that shape the adoption and elements. Specifically, a rhetorical model of in-
rejection of institutional practices. We believe stitutional decision making describes how logos/
these propositions extend the practice adoption logic, pathos/emotions, and ethos/values shape
literature by detailing how adoption discourse presumptions and thus integrates the substance
shapes perceptions of risk. In addition, Proposi- and content of rationality with the procedural
tion 4 describes how presumption influences ac- deployment and operation of rationality. Within
tors’ evaluation of practice performance. We this framework, presumptions reflect a dual con-
believe Proposition 4 complements the practice ception of reason as both communicative and
implementation literature by highlighting how cognitive, revealing how logic, emotions, and
adoption discourse can shape not only the im- values interrelate to shape institutional action.
plementation of a practice but also the evaluation Presumptions are often the ontic traces and fos-
of that practice’s performance. sils of ontological persuasion and interpreta-
tion processes. As such, they potentially provide
the best empirical window into the contours
Communication, Cognition, and the
and processes of how actors ontologically form
Microfoundations of Institutions
legitimacy judgments. Hence, presumption as
Another of our goals was to describe the an ontic or communicative and cognitive mech-
entwinement of communication and cognition in anism by which values, emotions, and logic
the institutional decision-making process. To bind procedural rationality extends the Carnegie
this end, in our rhetorical model of institutional perspective’s emphasis on satisficing as the
decision making, we provided a framework for primary cognitive and ontological interpretive
2016 Hoefer and Green 147

process organizations and institutions use to Conclusion


make decisions. As a result, we believe this
Our rhetorical model of institutional decision
model reflects a broader and therefore more
making emphasizes a broad conception of human
realistic conception of human reasoning and
reasoning as rhetorical cognition. Rhetoric and,
institutional decision making built on more than
thus, reasoning are emotional, logical, and con-
just logic—built on emotions and values as well.
cerned with values. A rhetorical approach recog-
nizes that cognition is limited and, thus, sometimes
Future Research automatic, as well as sometimes consciously de-
liberate. Within this framework actors rhetori-
A rhetorical model of institutional decision
cally manage their limited cognitive resources
making resonates with and extends recent trends
and the associated risks and errors these limita-
in institutional research focused on the cognitive
tions bring about in order to best navigate a prob-
(e.g., Bitektine, 2011; George et al., 2006; Kennedy
lematic and uncertain world. We hope our model
& Fiss, 2009; Powell & Colyvas, 2008; Tost, 2011)
provides more insight into how researchers might
and communicative (e.g., Cornelissen et al., 2015;
examine the communicative and cognitive factors
Gondo & Amis, 2013; Lammers, 2011; Lammers &
shaping the creation, maintenance, and perfor-
Barbour, 2006) underpinnings of institutions.
mance evaluations of institutions, and into how
However, the model we propose also has limits
managers might deploy and analyze their argu-
and potentially raises as many questions as it
ments to more effectively manage the blessing and
answers. We hope that future research can vary
curse of institutions.
important factors, such as initial argument char-
acteristics (e.g., pathos, logos, and ethos) or bur- REFERENCES
den of proof, to predict future argumentation,
Abrahamson, E. 1996. Management fashion. Academy of
institutionalization, and institutional performance. Management Review, 21: 254–285.
Researchers should examine how variations in
Alvesson, M. 1993. Organizations as rhetoric: Knowledge-
appeals to pathos, logos, and ethos shape how intensive firms and the struggle with ambiguity. Journal
automatic and deliberate cognitive processes in- of Management Studies, 30: 997–1015.
terrelate. Will pathos appeals more likely trigger Argote, L., & Greve, H. R. 2007. A behavioral theory of the
automatic responses or deliberate responses? firm—40 years and counting: Introduction and impact.
How do various aspects of human reason—that is, Organization Science, 18: 337–349.
emotion, logic, and values—instantiate and tran- Aristotle. 1992. The art of rhetoric. (Translated by H. Lawson-
sition between automatic and deliberate cognitive Tancred.) New York: Penguin Books.
processes? Aristotle. 2001. The basic works of Aristotle. (Translated by R. P.
From a formal organizational perspective, fu- McKeon-Tancred.) New York: Modern Library.
ture research should continue to explicate the role Barber, B. M., Heath, C., & Odean, T. 2003. Good reasons sell:
of managers as rhetors in institutional processes Reason-based choice among group and individual investors
(Alvesson, 1993; Green, 2004; Mintzberg, 1973). in the stock market. Management Science, 49: 1636–1652.
Managers guide attention, beliefs, and meaning Baumol, W. J. 2004. On rational satisficing. In M. Augier & J. G.
by regulating the timing, framing, and flow of March (Eds.), Models of man: Essays in memory of Herbert
argumentation (Alvesson, 1993; Czarniawska & A. Simon: 57–66. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Joerges, 1996). For example, NASA program man- Benoit, W. L., & Smythe, M. J. 2003. Rhetorical theory as message
agers reversed the standard of proof of engineer- reception: A cognitive response approach to rhetorical
theory and criticism. Communication Studies, 54: 96–114.
ing teams, from proving that the Columbia Space
Bentham, J., & Dumont, E. 1981. A treatise on judicial evidence.
Shuttle was safe to fly to proving that it was un-
Littleton, CO: F. B. Rothman.
safe to fly, hampering the flow of arguments that
might otherwise have prevented the Columbia Berger, P., & Luckmann, T. 1966. The social construction of re-
ality: A treatise in the sociology of knowledge. New York:
fiasco (Weick, 2005). More process-based research Doubleday.
into how powerful actors control the flow and
Billig, M. 1996. Arguing and thinking: A rhetorical approach to
circulation of arguments (Sahlin & Wedlin, 2008) social psychology (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
could significantly elucidate our understanding versity Press.
of the process of institutional decision making, as Bitektine, A. 2011. Toward a theory of social judgments of or-
well as highlight the role of power in institutional ganizations: The case of legitimacy, reputation, and sta-
decision making. tus. Academy of Management Review, 36: 151–179.
148 Academy of Management Review January

Bitektine, A., & Haack, P. 2015. The “macro” and the “micro” of Etzion, D., & Ferraro, F. 2010. The role of analogy in the insti-
legitimacy: Toward a multilevel theory of the legitimacy tutionalization of sustainability reporting. Organization
process. Academy of Management Review, 40: 49–75. Science, 21: 1092–1107.
Bitzer, L. 1968. The rhetorical situation. Philosophy and Rheto- Evans, J. St. B. T. 2008. Dual-processing accounts of reasoning,
ric, 1: 1–14. judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psy-
chology, 59: 255–278.
Bizzell, P., & Herzberg, B. (Eds.). 2001. The rhetorical tradition:
Readings from classical times to the present (2nd ed.). Fiss, P. C., & Zajac, E. J. 2006. The symbolic management of
Boston: Bedford Books of St. Martin’s Press. strategic change: Sensegiving via framing and decou-
pling. Academy of Management Journal, 49: 1173–1193.
Block, P. 1978. Flawless consulting: A guide to getting your
expertise used. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Friedland, R., & Alford, R. R. 1991. Bringing society back in:
Symbols, practices, and institutional contradictions. In
Bonet, E. 2014. Exploring the boundaries of rhetoric. Journal of
W. W. Powell & P. J. DiMaggio (Eds.), The new institution-
Organizational Change Management, 27: 793–806.
alism in organizational analysis: 232–263. Chicago: Uni-
Booth, W. 1974. Modern dogma and the rhetoric of assent. versity of Chicago Press.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gadamer, H.-G. 1975. Truth and method. (Translated by G.
Brown, R. 1987. Reason as rhetorical: On relations among Barden & J. Cumming.) New York: Crossroad Publishing.
epistemology, discourse, and practice. In J. S. Nelson, A.
Garfinkel, H. 1967. Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood
Megill, & D. N. McCloskey (Eds.), The rhetoric of the human
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
sciences: Language and argument in scholarship and
public affairs: 184–197. Madison: University of Wisconsin Gavetti, G., Greve, H. R., Levinthal, D. A., & Ocasio, W. 2012. The
Press. behavioral theory of the firm: Assessment and prospects.
Academy of Management Annals, 6: 1–40.
Burke, K. 1969a. A rhetoric of motives. Berkeley: University of
California Press. Gavetti, G., Levinthal, D., & Ocasio, W. 2007. Neo-Carnegie: The
Carnegie School’s past, present, and reconstructing for the
Burke, K. 1969b. A grammar of motives. Berkeley: University of
future. Organization Science, 18: 523–536.
California Press.
George, E., Chattopadhyay, P., Sitkin, S., & Barden, J. 2006.
Burnstein, E., & Vinokur, A. 1977. Persuasive argumentation
Cognitive underpinnings of institutional persistence and
and social comparison as determinants of attitude polar-
change: A framing perspective. Academy of Management
ization. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 13:
Review, 31: 347–365.
315–332.
Godden, D., & Walton, D. 2007. A theory of presumption for
Collins, H. M. 1992. Changing order: Replication and induction
everyday argumentation. Pragmatics & Cognition, 15:
in scientific practice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
313–346.
Cornelissen, J. P., Durand, R., Fiss, P. C., Lammers, J. C., &
Golant, B. D., & Sillince, J. A. 2007. The constitution of organi-
Vaara, E. 2015. Putting communication front and center in
zational legitimacy: A narrative perspective. Organization
institutional theory and analysis. Academy of Manage-
Studies, 28: 1149–1167.
ment Review, 40: 10–27.
Gondo, M. B., & Amis, J. M. 2013. Variations in practice adoption:
Crusius, T. W. 1991. A teacher’s introduction to philosophical
The roles of conscious reflection and discourse. Academy
hermeneutics. Urbana, IL: National Council of Teachers of
of Management Review, 38: 229–247.
English.
Goodnight, G. T. 1980. The liberal and the conservative pre-
Cyert, R. M., & March, J. G. 1963. A behavioral theory of the firm.
sumptions: On political philosophy and the foundation of
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
public argument. In J. Rhodes & S. Newell (Eds.), Proceedings
Czarniawska, B., & Joerges, B. 1996. Travel of ideas. In B. of the Summer Conference on Argumentation: 304–337. Falls
Czarniawska & G. Sevon (Eds.), Translating organi- Church, VA: Speech Communication Association.
zational change: 13–48. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Green, S. E. 2004. A rhetorical theory of diffusion. Academy of
DiMaggio, P. J., & Powell, W. W. 1991. Introduction. In W. W. Management Review, 29: 653–669.
Powell & P. J. DiMaggio (Eds.), The new institutionalism Green, S. E., & Li, Y. 2011. Rhetorical institutionalism: Language,
in organizational analysis: 1–38. Chicago: University of agency, and structure in institutional theory since Alvesson
Chicago Press. 1993. Journal of Management Studies, 48: 1662–1697.
Donaldson, G., & Lorsch, J. W. 1983. Decision making at the top: Green, S. E., Li, Y., & Nohria, N. 2009. Suspended in self-spun
The shaping of strategic direction. New York: Basic Books. webs of significance: A rhetorical model of institutionali-
Douglas, M. 1986. How institutions think. Syracuse, NY: Syr- zation and institutionally embedded agency. Academy of
acuse University Press. Management Journal, 52: 11–36.

Edmondson, A. C., Roberto, M. A., Bohmer, R. M. J., Ferlins, E. M., Habermas, J. 1984. The theory of communicative action. Boston:
& Feldman, L. R. 2005. The recovery window: Organiza- Beacon Press.
tional learning following ambiguous threats. In W. H. Harmon, D. J., Green, S. E., & Goodnight, G. T. 2015. A model of
Starbuck & M. Farjoun (Eds.), Organization at the limit: rhetorical legitimation: The structure of communication
Lessons from the Columbia disaster: 220–245. New York: and cognition underlying institutional maintenance and
Blackwell. change. Academy of Management Review, 40: 76–95.
2016 Hoefer and Green 149

Hartelius, E. J., & Browning, L. D. 2008. The application of rhe- Miller, C. R. 1990. The rhetoric of decision science, or Herbert A.
torical theory in managerial research: A literature review. Simon says. In H. W. Simons (Ed.), The rhetorical turn: In-
Management Communication Quarterly, 22: 13–39. vention and persuasion in the conduct of inquiry: 162–184.
Heracleous, L., & Barrett, M. 2001. Organizational change as Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
discourse: Communicative actions and deep structures in Mintzberg, H. 1973. The nature of managerial work. New York:
the context of information technology implementation. Harper & Row.
Academy of Management Journal, 44: 755–778.
Nienkamp, J. 2001. Internal rhetorics: Toward a history and
Hirschman, A. 1991. The rhetoric of reaction. Cambridge, MA: theory of self persuasion. Carbondale: Southern Illinois
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. State Press.
Hopper, R. 1981. The taken-for-granted. Human Communica- Paglieri, F., & Castelfranchi, C. 2010. Why argue? Towards
tion Research, 7: 195–211. a cost-benefit analysis of argumentation. Argument and
Hyde, M. J., & Smith, C. R. 1979. Hermeneutics and rhetoric: A Computation, 1: 71–91.
seen but unobserved relationship. Quarterly Journal of Paglieri, F., & Woods, J. 2011. Enthymematic parsimony. Syn-
Speech, 65: 347–363. these, 178: 461–501.
Irwin, J., & Davis, J. 1995. Choice/matching preference reversals Perelman, C. 1982. The realm of rhetoric. Notre Dame, IN: Uni-
in groups: Consensus processes and justification-based versity of Notre Dame Press.
reasoning. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. 1969. The new rhetoric: A
Processes, 64: 325–339. treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame, IN: University of
Isenberg, D. 1986. Group polarization: A critical review and Notre Dame Press.
meta-analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol-
Petty, R. E., & Cacioppo, J. T. 1986. Communication and per-
ogy, 50: 1141–1151. suasion: Central and peripheral routes to attitude change.
Janis, I. L. 1971. Groupthink. Psychology Today, 5: 43–46. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Janis, I. L. 1972. Victims of groupthink: A psychological study of Phillips, N., Lawrence, T. B., & Hardy, C. 2004. Discourse and
foreign-policy decisions and fiascoes. Boston: Houghton institutions. Academy of Management Review, 29:
Mifflin. 635–652.
Jasinski, J. 2001. Sourcebook on rhetoric: Key concepts in con- Potter, J. 1996. Representing reality: Discourse, rhetoric and
temporary rhetorical studies. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. social construction. London: Sage.
Kahneman, D. 2003. A perspective on judgment and choice: Powell, W. W., & Colyvas, J. A. 2008. Microfoundations of
Mapping bounded rationality. American Psychologist, 58: institutional theory. In R. Greenwood, C. Oliver, K. Sahlin-
697–720. Andersson, & R. Suddaby (Eds.), Sage handbook of organi-
Kennedy, M. T., & Fiss, P. C. 2009. Institutionalization, framing, zational institutionalism: 276–298. London: Sage.
and diffusion: The logic of TQM adoption and imple- Quine, W. V., & Ullian, J. S. 1978. The web of belief (2nd ed.).
mentation decisions among U.S. hospitals. Academy of New York: Random House.
Management Journal, 52: 897–918. Quinn, K. 1996. A rhetorical conception of practical rationality.
Lammers, J. C. 2011. How institutions communicate: In- Journal of Economic Issues, 30: 1127–1142.
stitutional messages, institutional logics, and organiza- Rawsthorn, A. 2011. The clunky PC that started it all. New York
tional communication. Management Communication Times, July 31: http://www.nytimes.com/2011/08/01/arts/
Quarterly, 25: 154–182. the-clunky-pc-that-started-it-all.html?_r50.
Lammers, J. C., & Barbour, J. 2006. An institutional theory of Rorty, R. 1980. Philosophy and the mirror of nature (2nd ed.).
organizational communication. Communication Theory, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
16: 356–377.
Sahlin, K., & Wedlin, L. 2008. Circulating ideas: Imitation,
Lerner, J., & Tetlock, P. 1999. Accounting for the effects of ac- translation and editing. In R. Greenwood, C. Oliver, K.
countability. Psychological Bulletin, 125: 225–275. Sahlin-Andersson, & R. Suddaby (Eds.), Sage handbook
Lonergan, B. J. F. 2005. Insight: A study of human understanding of organizational institutionalism: 218–242. London:
(5th ed.). Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Sage.

Lounsbury, M., & Ventresca, M. 2002. Social structure and or- Schein, E. 1996. Organizational culture and leadership (2nd
ganizations revisited. Research in the Sociology of Orga- ed.). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
nizations, 19: 3–36. Shafir, E., Simonson, I., & Tversky, A. 1993. Reason-based
Maguire, S., Hardy, C., & Lawrence, T. 2004. Institutional en- choice. Cognition, 49: 11–36.
trepreneurship in emerging fields: HIV/AIDS treatment Shapira, Z. 1995. Risk taking: A managerial perspective. New
advocacy in Canada. Academy of Management Journal, York: Russell Sage Foundation.
47: 657–679.
Sillince, J. A., & Suddaby, R. 2008. Organizational rhetoric:
Mailloux, S. 1990. Interpretation. In F. Lentricchia & T. Bridging management and communication scholarship.
McLaughlin (Eds.), Critical terms for literary study: Management Communication Quarterly, 22: 5–12.
121–134. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Simon, H. A. 1945. Administrative behavior. New York: Free
March, J. G., & Simon, H. 1958. Organizations. New York: Wiley. Press.
150 Academy of Management Review January

Simon, H. A. 1976. Administrative behavior: A study of Tost, L. P. 2011. An integrative model of legitimacy judgments.
decision-making processes in administrative organization Academy of Management Review, 36: 686–710.
(3rd ed.). New York: Free Press.
Toulmin, S. E. 1969. The uses of argument. New York: Cam-
Simon, H. A. 1978. Rationality as process and product of bridge University Press.
thought. American Economic Review, 68: 1–16.
Townley, B. 2008. Reason’s neglect: Rationality and organizing.
Simon, H. A. 1997. Models of bounded rationality: Empirically Oxford: Oxford University Press.
grounded economic reason. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Tversky, A., Sattath, S., & Slovic, P. 1988. Contingent weighting
Stanovich, K. E. 1999. Who is rational? Studies of individual in judgment and choice. Psychological Review, 95:
differences in reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum 371–384.
Associates.
Ullman-Margalit, E. 1983. On presumption. Journal of Philoso-
Suchman, M. C. 1995. Managing legitimacy: Strategic and phy, 80: 143–163.
institutional approaches. Academy of Management Re-
Vaara, E., & Monin, P. 2010. A recursive perspective on discur-
view, 20: 571–610.
sive legitimation and organizational action in mergers
Suddaby, R. 2010. Challenges for institutional theory. Journal and acquisitions. Organization Science, 21: 3–22.
of Management Inquiry, 19: 14–20.
Vinokur, A., & Burnstein, E. 1978. Novel argumentation and at-
Suddaby, R., & Greenwood, R. 2005. Rhetorical strategies of titude change: The case of polarization following group
legitimacy. Administrative Science Quarterly, 38: 35–67. discussion. European Journal of Social Psychology, 8:
Tetlock, P. 1992. The impact of accountability on judgment and 335–348.
choice: Toward a social contingency model. Advanced Wasserstein, B. 1998. Big deal. New York: Warner Books.
Experimental Social Psychology, 25: 331–376.
Weick, K. E. 1979. The social psychology of organizing (2nd ed.).
Tetlock, P. E., Peterson, R. S., McGuire, C., Chang, S. J., & Feld, P. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
1992. Assessing political group dynamics: A test of the
Weick, K. E. 2005. Making sense of blurred images: Mindful
groupthink model. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
organizing in Mission STS-107. In W. H. Starbuck & M.
chology, 63: 403–425.
Farjoun (Eds.), Organization at the limit: Lessons from the
Tompkins, E. V. B., Tompkins, P. K., & Cheney, G. 1989. Orga- Columbia disaster: 159–177. New York: Blackwell.
nizations as arguments: Discovering, expressing, and
Weick, K. E., & Browning, L. D. 1986. Argument and narration in
analyzing the premises for decisions. Journal of Manage-
organizational communication. Journal of Management,
ment Systems, 1: 35–48.
12: 243–259.
Tompkins, P. K., & Cheney, G. 1985. Communication and un-
Whately, R. 2009. Elements of rhetoric (7th ed.). New York: In-
obtrusive control in contemporary organizations. In R. D.
ternational Debate Education Association.
McPhee & P. K. Tompkins (Eds.), Organizational commu-
nication: Traditional themes and new directions: 179–210. Wittgenstein, L. 1963. Philosophical investigations. (Translated
Newbury Park, CA: Sage. by G. E. M. Anscombe.) Oxford: Blackwell.

Rolf L. Hoefer (rolf.hoefer@insead.edu) is a doctoral candidate in the Department of Or-


ganizational Behavior/Entrepreneurship at INSEAD. His current research focuses on im-
printing, cognition, communication, and learning in both entrepreneurial and
institutionalized settings.
Sandy E. Green, Jr. (sandy.green@csun.edu) is an associate professor of management at
California State University, Northridge. He received his Ph.D. from Harvard University
Graduate School of Business. His current research interests include neoinstitutional
theory, rhetorical theory, and corporate governance.

You might also like