Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

The Law and Economics Movement

Author(s): Richard A. Posner


Source: The American Economic Review , May, 1987, Vol. 77, No. 2, Papers and
Proceedings of the Ninety-Ninth Annual Meeting of the American Economic
Association (May, 1987), pp. 1-13
Published by: American Economic Association

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1805421

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/1805421?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Economic
Review

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
RICHARD T. ELY LECTURE

The Law and Economics Movement

By RICHARD A. POSNER*

In the last thirty years, the scope of eco- fined by reference to other concepts, just as
nomics has expanded dramatically beyond numbers are; but (again like numbers) there
its traditional domain of explicit market is no observable object in the real world that
transactions.' Today there is an economic it names. (Try finding a firm's marginal costs
theory of property rights, of corporate and on its books of account!) The second type of
other organizations, of government and word, illustrated by "rabbit," refers to a set
politics, of education, of the family, of crime of real-world objects. Few such words are
and punishment, of anthropology, of history, purely referential; one can speak of a pink
of information, of racial and sexual dis- rabbit or a rabbit the size of a man without
crimination, of privacy, even of the behavior misusing the word, even though one is no
of animals-and, overlapping all these but longer using it to describe anything that
the last, of law.2 exists. Nevertheless, the referential function
Some economists oppose this expansion, dominates. Finally, there are words like
in whole or (more commonly) in part.3 There " law," ' "religion," "literature" -and "eco-
are a number of bad reasons, all I think nomics" -which are neither conceptual nor
closely related, for such opposition, and one referential. Such words resist all efforts at
slightly better one. definition. They have, in fact, no fixed mean-
1) One bad reason is the idea that eco- ing, and their dictionary definitions are cir-
nomics means the study of markets, so that cular. They can be used but not defined.4
nonmarket behavior is simply outside its One cannot say that economics is what
scope. This type of argument owes nothing economists do, because many noneconomists
really to economics, but instead reflects a do economics. One cannot call economics
common misconception about language the science of rational choice, either. The
more specifically a failure to distinguish word "rational" lacks a clear definition; and,
among three different types of word or con- passing that difficulty, there can be noneco-
cept. The first type, illustrated by the term nomic theories of rational choice, in which
"marginal cost," is purely conceptual. The few predictions of ordinary economics may
term is rigorously and unambiguously de- hold; for example, because the theory as-
sumes that people's preferences are unstable.
There can also be nonrational economic
theories; an example is the type of survival
*Judge, U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh Cir-
theory in industrial organization in which
cuit; Senior Lecturer, University of Chicago Law School,
1111 E. 60th St., Chicago, IL 60637. I thank Gary
firms that randomly hit on methods of
Becker, Frank Easterbrook, William Landes, Geoffrey lowering their costs expand vis-a-vis their
Miller, Richard Porter, George Stigler, Geoffrey Stone, rivals; another example is Marxism. One
and Alan Sykes for comments on a previous draft and cannot call economics the study of markets
Nir Yarden for research assistance.
either, not only because that characterization
'See, for example, Gary Becker (1976); Jack Hirsh-
leifer (1985, p. 53); George Stigler (1984); Gerard resolves the question of the domain of eco-
Radnitzky and Peter Bernholz (1986).
2 For a recent conspectus of economic analysis of
law, see my book (1986).
3See, for example, Ronald Coase (1978). Coase is of
course a leading figure in the economics of property 4For an excellent discussion, see John Ellis (1974,
rights, so his opposition is far from total. ch. 2).

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MA Y 1987

nomics by an arbitrary definitional stop but with a Ph.D. in economics. It may be easier
also because other disciplines, notably soci- for an anthropologist to learn economics
ology, anthropology, and psychology, also than for an economist to learn anthropology.
study markets. About the best one can say is Maybe the fraction of one's training in eco-
that there is an open-ended set of concepts nomics that is irrelevant to the economic
(such concepts as perfect competition, utility analysis of anthropological phenomena is
maximization, equilibrium, marginal cost, larger than the fraction of anthropological
consumers' surplus, elasticity of demand, and training that is irrelevant; or maybe eco-
opportunity cost), most of which are derived nomic theory is more compact than the body
from a common set of assumptions about of knowledge we call anthropology. (It prob-
individual behavior and can be used to make ably is easier to learn economics well than to
predictions about social behavior; and that learn Chinese well.) Or it might simply be
when used in sufficient density these con- (this has happened in law and economics)
cepts make a work of scholarship "eco- that a given anthropologist had more of a
nomic" regardless of its subject matter or its knack for economics than a given economist
author's degree. When economics is "de- had a knack for anthropology. It is only by
fined" in this way, there is nothing that defining economics, in rather a medieval way,
makes the study of marriage and divorce less as the work done by members of a particular
suitable a priori for economics than the study guild (the guild of economics Ph.D.s) that
of the automobile industry or the inflation one will be led to conclude that if the er -
rate. nomics of law is done by lawyers, or the
2) The "extension" of economics from economics of history by historians, it cannot
market to nonmarket behavior is sometimes be "real" economics. The emergence of non-
thought to be premature until the main market economics may have resulted in a
problems in the study of explicit markets vast but unrecognized increase in the num-
have been solved. How can economists hope ber of economists!
to explain the divorce rate when they can't The idea that nonmarket economics is
explain behavior under oligopoly? But this somehow peripheral to economics is con-
rhetorical question is just a variation on the nected with the fact that there has been little
first point, that economics has a fixed subject fruitful analysis of explicit markets besides
matter, a predefined domain. The tools of economics, though admirers of Max Weber's
economics may be no good for solving a analysis of the role of Protestantism in the
number of important problems in under- rise of capitalism may want to challenge this
standing explicit markets; that is no reason assertion. Almost by default, explicit markets
to keep hitting one's head against the wall. became thought of as the natural subject
Economics does not have a predestined mis- matter of economics. But the fact that other
sion to dispel all the mysteries of the market. areas of social behavior, such as law, have
Maybe it will do better with some types of been extensively studied from other angles
nonmarket behavior than with some types of than the economic is no reason for conclud-
market behavior. ing that these areas cannot be studied profit-
3) Next is the idea that to do economics ably with the tools of modern economic the-
in fields that have their own scholarly tradi- ory.
tions, such as history or law, an economist 4) Still another bad reason for hostility
must master so much noneconomic learning to nonmarket economics is fear that it will
that his total educational investment will be bring economics into disrepute by associat-
disproportionate to the likely fruits of "in- ing the economist with politically and mor-
terdisciplinary" research; hence economists ally distasteful, bizarre, or controversial
should steer clear of these fields. Besides practices (such as capital punishment, po-
disregarding the possibility of collaboration lygamy, or slavery before the Civil War) and
between economists and practitioners of proposals-whether specific policy pro-
other disciplines, this argument assumes that posals such as education vouchers, or the
economics means something done by people idea, which is basic to nonmarket economics,

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 77 NO. 2 RICHARD T. ELYLECTURE 3

that human beings are rational maximizers racial and sexual wage differentials, the inci-
throughout the whole, or at least a very dence and control of crime, and (I shall
broad, range of their social interactions. If argue) the common law rules governing
economics becomes associated with highly property, torts, and contracts5 -successful
sensitive topics, it may lose some of the enough at any rate to establish nonmarket
appearance of scientific objectivity that economics as a legitimate branch of econom-
economists have worked so hard to cultivate ics and to counsel at least a temporary sus-
in the face of obvious difficulties including pension of disbelief by the skeptics and
the fact that much of traditional microeco- doubters. Indeed, so familiar have some of
nomics and macroeconomics is already polit- these areas of nonmarket economics become
ically and ethically controversial, as is evi- in recent years (for example, education
dent from current debates over free trade, viewed through the lens of human capital
deregulation, and deficit spending. But this theory) that many young economists no
complaint, too, is part of the fallacious idea longer think of them as being outside the
that there is a fixed domain for economics. If traditional boundaries of economics. The
there were, it would be natural to recoil from distinction between "market" and "non-
economic ventures at once peripheral and market" economics is fraying.
controversial. But if I am right that there is
no fixed, preordained, or natural domain for I
economics -that politics, punishment, and
exploitation are, at least a priori, as ap- A
propriate subjects for economics as the oper-
ation of the wheat market-then it is pusil- The particular area of nonmarket econom-
lanimous to counsel avoidance of particular ics that I want to focus on is the economics
topics because they happen to be politically of law, or "law and economics" as it is often
or ethically (are these different?) contro- called. Because of the enormous range of
versial at the present time. behavior regulated by the legal system, law
5) A slightly better reason for question- and economics could be defined so broadly
ing the expansion of economics beyond its as to be virtually coextensive with econom-
traditional boundaries is skepticism that eco- ics. This would not be a useful definition.
nomic tools will work well in the new fields Yet to exclude bodies of law that regulate
or that adequate data will be available in explicit markets-such as contract and
them to test economic hypotheses. Maybe property law, labor, antitrust and corporate
these are domains where emotion dominates law, public utility and common carrier regu-
reason, and maybe economists can't say lation, and taxation-would be cripplingly
much about emotion. And explicit markets narrow. But if these bodies are included, in
generate substantial quantitative data (prices, what sense is law and economics a branch of
costs, output, employment, etc.), which nonmarket economics? (I do not suggest that
greatly facilitate empirical research- though this is an important question; it may, indeed,
only a small fraction of economists actually be an argument for discarding an increas-
do empirical research. These points suggest a ingly uninteresting distinction.)
functional as distinct from a definitional As with any nonreferential, nonconceptual
answer to the question of the appropriate term, the only possible criterion for a defini-
bounds of economics: economics is the set of tion of law and economics is utility-not
fruitful applications of economic theory. But accuracy. The purpose of carving out a sep-
a detailed survey of nonmarket economics is arate field and calling it law and economics
not necessary in order to make the point that
the economic approach has been shown to
be fruitful in dealing with such diverse non-
5For a few examples see Becker (1981; 1975); Orley
market subjects as education, economic his-
Ashenfelter and Albert Rees (1973); Robert Fogel and
tory, the causes of regulatory legislation, the Stanley Engerman (1971); Isaac Ehrlich (1974); David
behavior of nonprofit institutions, divorce, Pyle (1983); Stigler (1971).

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
4 A EA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MA Y 1987

(or better, because clearer, "economics of mercial law; corporate law and securities
law") is to identify the area of economic regulation; and taxation, including state
inquiry to which a substantial knowledge of taxation of interstate commerce, an area that
law in both its doctrinal and institutional the courts regulate under the commerce
aspects is relevant. Many economic prob- clause of the Constitution.6 In none of these
lems in such areas of law as taxation and areas is participation by economists, or (if
labor do not require much legal knowledge we insist on guild distinctions) by econom-
to solve. Although taxes can be imposed ics-minded lawyers, particularly controver-
only by laws, often the details of the tax law sial any more, though some die-hard lawyers
either are not relevant to the analyst, as continue to resist the encroachments of eco-
where he is asking what the effect on charita- nomics and of course there is disagreement
ble giving of reducing the marginal income among economists over many particular is-
tax rate is likely to be, or are transparent sues; this is notable in antitrust. An area of
and unproblematic. legal regulation of explicit markets that is
Similarly, in the field of labor, you can just beginning to ripen for economics is in-
study the effects of unemployment insurance tellectual property, with special reference to
on unemployment without knowing a great copyrights and trademarks. Patents have long
deal about the state and federal laws govern- been an object of economic study.
ing unemployment insurance, though you The areas of law and economics about
must know something. But suppose you which economists and lawyers display con-
wanted to study the consequences of al- siderable unease are the (sometimes arbi-
lowing the defendant in an employment dis- trarily classified as) nonmarket areas-crime,
crimination case to deduct from the lost torts, and contracts; the environment; the
wages awarded the plaintiff (if the plaintiff family; the legislative and administrative
succeeds in proving that he was fired because processes; constitutional law; jurisprudence
of race or sex or some other forbidden crite- and legal process; legal history; primitive
rion), any unemployment benefits that the law; and so on. All the reasons that I gave at
plaintiff might have received after being fired. the outset for why some economists resist
You could not get far in such a study with- the extension of economics beyond its tradi-
out knowing a fair amount of nonobvious tional domain of explicit market behavior
employment discrimination law: Is there a coalesce in regard to these areas. And be-
uniform judicial rule on deduction or non- cause they are also close to the heart of what
deduction of such benefits? Could the bene- lawyers think distinctive about law-of
fits be deducted but then be ordered paid to what they think makes it something more
the state or the federal government rather than a method of economic regulation-this
than kept by the employer? Does the law branch of economic analysis of law dismays
insist that the employee who wants damages many lawyers. Furthermore, lawyers tend to
for employment discrimination search for have more rigid, stereotyped ideas of the
work? How are those damages computed? boundaries of economics than economists
The economics of law is the set of economic do, in part because most lawyers are not
studies that build on a detailed knowledge of aware of the extension (which is recent,
some area of law; whether the study is done though its roots go back to Adam Smith and
by a "lawyer," an "economist," someone Jeremy Bentham) of economics to non-
with both degrees, or a lawyer-economist market behavior. Indeed, a demarcation
team has little significance.
The law and economics movement has
made progress in a number of areas of legal
regulation of explicit markets. These include
antitrust law, and the regulation of public 6The work in these areas is summarized in my book
(pts. 3-5 and ch. 26). It is of some interest to note
utilities and common carriers; fraud and un-
that the economic analysis of secured financing is
fair competition; corporate bankruptcy, se- now dominated by economically inclined lawyers. See
cured transactions, and other areas of com- Robert Scott (1986) and references cited there.

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 77 NO. 2 RICHARD T. ELY LECTURE 5

which places secured financing on one side the crime rate, that making the losing party
of the divide and contract law on the other in a lawsuit pay the winner's attorney's fees
seems entirely artificial. The distinction be- will not reduce the amount of litigation, that
tween market and nonmarket economics may abolition of the reserve clause in baseball did
be as arbitrary as it is uninteresting. not affect the mobility of baseball players
(the Coase theorem, restated as a hypothesis),
B that the 1978 revision of the bankruptcy
laws led to more personal-bankruptcy filings
I want to try to convey some sense of the and higher interest rates, and that abolishing
economic analysis of "nonmarket" law. Its the laws that forbid the sale of babies for
basic premises are two: adoption would reduce rather than increase
1) People act as rational maximizers of the full price of babies.
their satisfactions in making such nonmarket I have given a mixture of obvious and
decisions as whether to marry or divorce, nonobvious hypotheses derived from my
commit or refrain from committing crimes, basic premises. Notice that I do not say
make an arrest, litigate or settle a lawsuit, intuitive and counterintuitive hypotheses,
drive a car carefully or carelessly, pollute (a because all are counterintuitive to people
nonmarket activity because pollution is not who believe, as many economists and most
traded in the market), refuse to associate lawyers do, that people are not rational
with people of a different race, fix a manda- maximizers except when transacting in ex-
tory retirement age for employees. plicit markets, or that legal rules do not have
2) Rules of law operate to impose prices substantial incentive effects, perhaps because
on (sometimes subsidize) these nonmarket the rules are poorly communicated or the
activities, thereby altering the amount or sanctions for violating them are infrequently
character of the activity. or irregularly imposed.
A third premise, discussed at greater length
later, guides some research in the economics C
of nonmarket law:
3) Common law (i.e., judge-made) rules Thus far in my discussion of the econonic
are often best explained as efforts, whether analysis of legal regulation of nonmarket
or not conscious, to bring about either Pareto behavior I have focused on the effects of
or Kaldor-Hicks efficient outcomes. legal change on behavior. One can reverse
The first two premises lead to such predic- the sequence and ask how changes in behav-
tions as that an increase in a court's trial ior affect law. To make this reversal, though,
queue will lead to a reduction (other things one needs a theory of law, parallel to the
being equal-a qualification applicable to all rational-maximization theory of behavior.
my examples) in the number of cases tried, The economic theory of the common law,
that awarding prejudgment interest to a pre- defined broadly as law made by judges rather
vailing plaintiff will reduce settlement rates, than by legislatures or constitutional conven-
that "no-fault" divorce will redistribute tions or other nonjudicial bodies, is that the
wealth from women to men, that no-fault common law is best understood not merely
automobile accident compensation laws will as a pricing mechanism but as a pricing
increase the number of fatal accidents even mechanism designed to bring about an effi-
if the laws are not applicable to such acci- cient allocation of resources, in the Kaldor-
dents, that substituting comparative for con- Hicks sense of efficiency.7 This theory im-
tributory negligence will raise liability and plies that when behavior changes, law will
accident insurance premium rates but will
not change the accident rate (except insofar
as the increase in the price of liability in-
surance results in fewer drivers or less driv-
ing), that increasing the severity as well as 7See my book (pt. 2); and William Landes and
certainty of criminal punishment will reduce myself (1987).

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
6 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MA Y 1987

change. Suppose that at first people live in states fencing in. Many similar examples
very close proximity to each other. Natural could be given.8
light will be a scarce commodity in these Two objections to this branch of economic
circumstances, so its value in exchange may analysis of law must be considered:
well exceed the cost of enforcing a property 1) One is that a theory of law is not
right in it. Later, people spread out, so that testable, because when one is examining the
the value of natural light (in the economic effects of behavior on law rather than of law
sense of value-exchange value rather than on behavior, the dependent variable tends
use value) falls; then the net social value of not to be quantitative: it is not a price or
the property right (i.e., the value of the right output figure but a pattern of rules. How-
minus the cost of enforcing it) may be nega- ever, the scientific study of social rules is not
tive. These two states of the world corre- impossible; what else is linguistics? Fencing
spond roughly to the situations in England in vs. fencing out (or ancient lights vs. no
and America in the eighteenth century. The ancient lights, or riparian vs. appropriative
English recognized a limited right to natural water rights) is a dichotomous dependent
light; they called this right "ancient lights." variable, which modern methods of statis-
When American courts after independence tical analysis can handle. And if a continu-
decided which parts of the English common ous variable is desired, it can be created by
law to adopt, they rejected the doctrine of using the year in which the particular law
ancient lights-as the economic theory of was adopted (earlier adoption implying a
the common law predicts they would. more strongly supported law), the severity of
Another example is the adoption of the the sanctions, or the expenditures on en-
appropriation system of water rights in the forcement, to distribute states or nations
arid American West. In wet England and the along a continuum.
wet eastern United States, the riparian 2) James Buchanan (1974), along with a
system prevailed. This was a system of com- number of neo-Austrian economists, holds
munal rights, which is a kind of halfway that law should not be an instrumental vari-
house between individual rights and no able designed to maximize wealth. Judges
rights, and is inefficient for scarce goods. should not be entrusted with economic deci-
The appropriation system is one of individ- sions--they lack the training and informa-
ual rights, and was and is more efficient for tion to make them wisely. They should use
areas that are dry (i.e., where water is scarce custom and precedent to construct a stable
rather than plentiful)-which is where we but distinctly background framework for
find the appropriation system, as the eco- market and nonmarket behavior. But this is
nomic theory of common law predicts. Or an objection to normative economic analysis
consider the different responses of the east- of law- to urging, for example, that the
ern and the western states to the problem of common law (and perhaps other law) be
fencing out vs. fencing in. Fencing out refers changed to make it approximate the eco-
to a property rights system in which damage nomic model of efficient law better-and the
caused by straying cattle is actionable at law more interesting and promising aspect of
only if the owner of the crops or other goods economic analysis of law is the positive. I
damaged by the cattle has made reasonable say this not because of a general preference
efforts to fence. Fencing in refers to a system for positive to normative inquiry, but be-
where this duty is not imposed, so that the cause so little of a systematic nature is known
owner of the cattle must fence them in if he about law. Law is not so well understood
wants to avoid liability. The former system is that one can hold a confident opinion about
more efficient if the ratio of crops to cattle is whether the right way to improve it is to
low, for then it is cheaper for the farmer
than the rancher to fence. If the ratio is
reversed, fencing in is a more efficient sys-
tem. In fact, the cattle states tended to adopt 8See sources cited in fn. 7, from which the above
fencing out, and England and the eastern examples are taken.

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 77 NO. 2 RICHARD T. ELY LECTURE 7

make the judges more sophisticated eco- on radio and television. Although Americans
nomically or more obedient to precedent appear to enjoy greater freedom of speech
and tradition. than citizens of the Western European na-
tions, Japan, and other democratic nations
II at an equivalent level of development to the
United States, the gap appears to have nar-
Much of what I have said so far is old hat, rowed, not broadened, since the Supreme
at least to those familiar with the law and Court began to take an aggressive stance
economics movement, so let me turn to some toward protection of free speech in the
novel applications of economic analysis to 1940's. It may be that as nations become
law: applications to free speech and religious wealthier and their people better educated
freedom, respectively. and more leisured, the gains from restricting
free speech-gains that have to do mainly
A with preserving social and political stability
-decline relative to the costs in hampering
It has long been recognized that the pro- further progress and in reducing the welfare
cess by which truth emerges from a welter of of producers and consumers of ideas. These
competing ideas resembles competition in a trends, I conjecture, are sufficiently pro-
market for ordinary goods and services: nounced to bring about (save possibly in
hence the influential metaphor of the "mar- totalitarian counties) dramatic increases in
ketplace of ideas." It is also well known that free speech regardless of the specifics of
because of the incompleteness of patent and free-speech law.
copyright law as a system of property rights The American law9 has several interesting
in ideas, the production of ideas frequently economic characteristics.
generates external benefits. Aaron Director 1) In the evolution of free-speech law,
(1964) and Ronald Coase (1974) have em- the first mode of regulation to go is censor-
phasized the peculiarity of the modern ship of books and other reading matter; the
"liberal" preference for freedom in the law's greater antagonism to censorship than
market for ideas to freedom in markets for to criminal punishment or other ex post reg-
ordinary goods and services (both freedoms ulation (for example, suits for defamation)
having been part of the nineteenth-century being expressed in the rule that "prior re-
concept of liberty), and have attributed this straints" on speech are specially disfavored.
preference to the self-interest of intellectuals. Censorship is a form of ex ante regulation,
Economists have paid scant attention, like a speed limit. The less common the
however, to the details of legal regulation in substantive evil (the costs resulting from an
this area. Over the past seventy years or so, accident due to carelessness, in the case of
the courts have developed an elaborate body the speed limit, or the costs resulting from a
of doctrine through interpretation of the First treasonable or defamatory newspaper article,
Amendment's guarantee of free speech. Both in the case of censorship), and also the more
the effects of this body of doctrine on the solvent the potential injurer,10 the weaker
marketplace of ideas and the economic logic the case for ex ante regulation is. With the
(if any) of the doctrines present interesting growth of education and political stability,
issues for economic analysis. the social dangers of free speech have de-
So far as effects are concerned, I suspect
they have been few. Despite the high-flown
rhetoric in which our courts discuss the right
of free speech, they have countenanced a 9Well summarized, and in a form accessible to non-
large number of restrictions-on picketing, lawyers, in Geoffrey Stone et al. (1986, pt. 7).
on obscenity, on employer speech in collec- 1?4f the probability of apprehension and punishment
is substantially less than one, the expected punishment
tive bargaining representation elections, on
may not deter wrongdoing even if the punishment,
commercial advertising, on threats, on de- when imposed, takes away the offender's entire wealth
famatory matter, and on materials broadcast and utility.

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
8 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MA Y 1987

clined; and suppose the fraction of books victims of defamation cannot spread the costs
and magazine articles that contain seriously of being defamed to other members of the
harmful matter is today very small. Then the community. The costs are concentrated on a
costs of a scheme in which a publisher must narrow group, resulting in a deadweight loss
obtain a license from the public censor to if risk aversion is assumed. Moreover, public
publish each book are likely to swamp the service is made less desirable, resulting in a
benefits in weeding out the occasional pro- decline in the quality of government. It would
hibitable idea, especially since publishers be difficult to prevent the decline by raising
have sufficient resources to pay fines or government salaries. The salary increase
damage judgments for any injuries they in- would have to be large enough to cover not
flict. It makes more economic sense in these only the expected cost of uncompensated
circumstances to rely on ex post regulation defamation, but also the risk premium that
(through criminal punishment or tort suits) risk-averse people would demand because
of those ideas that turn out to be punishable. they cannot buy insurance. Even if salaries
Censorship is retained, however, in areas, are raised, the composition of public service
such as that of classified government docu- will shift in favor of risk preferrers and
ments, where the probability of harm is high people with little reputation capital. Finally,
and where in addition the magnitude of the the difficulty of monitoring government out-
harm if it occurs may be so great (for exam- puts leads to heavy emphasis on economiz-
ple, from disclosing sensitive military secrets) ing on visible inputs, for example by paying
that the threat of punishment will not deter low salaries to government officials; and the
adequately because the wrongdoer will lack problem of false economies is aggravated if
sufficient resources. the costs of government service are raised by
Many of these arguments could of course curtailing the right of government officials to
be made against ex ante regulation of safety, protect their reputations through suits for
as by the Food and Drug Administration defamation.
and OSHA. One difference is that while the 3) The Supreme Court has distinguished
First Amendment forbids overregulating the between public and private figures, giving
marketplace of ideas (and also, as we are private figures a broader right to sue for
about to see, the religious marketplace), no defamation than public ones. This distinc-
constitutional provision seems directed at tion may make economic sense. The external
forbidding overregulation of markets in con- benefits of information about public figures
ventional goods and services. are greater than those of information about
2) Consider now the onerous limitations private figures, and therefore the argument
that the Supreme Court has placed on efforts for allowing some of the costs to be external-
to sue the media for defamation. If we as- ized is stronger. Moreover, a public figure,
sume that news confers external benefits, being by definition newsworthy, has some
then, since a newspaper or television station substitute for legal action: he can tell his
cannot obtain a significant property right in side of the story, which the news media will
news, there is an argument for subsidizing pick up.
the production of news. A direct subsidy, 4) A related point is that if the main
however, would involve political risks- reason for limiting efforts by government to
though we have run them occasionally, as in regulate the marketplace of ideas is to foster
the establishment of the Corporation for the provision of external benefits, we would
Public Broadcasting. A form of indirect sub- expect, and to a certain extent find, that the
sidy is to make the victims of defamation limitations on regulation are more severe the
bear some of the costs of defamation that greater the likelihood of such benefits. Con-
the tort system would otherwise shift to the sider: Maximum protection for freedom of
defamer. Notice, however, the curious effect speech is provided to scientific and political
of this method of subsidization, which may thought, in which property rights cannot be
make it on balance inefficient. Because it is obtained. Slightly less protection is given art,
impossible to insure one's reputation, the which enjoys a limited property right under

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 77 NO. 2 RICHARD T. ELYLECTURE 9

the copyright laws.'1 Even less constitutional women will spend more time in church than
protection is given to pornography and com- men because the cost to women in foregone
mercial advertising. And none is given to earnings is less, and that men will spend
threats and other utterances that manifestly more time in church as they get older be-
create net external costs. cause as they approach the end of their
Pornography appears to create no external working life it is optimal for them to switch
benefits (no one but the viewer or reader from investing further in their earning capac-
himself benefits-and he pays), and may ity to investing in the production of afterlife
create external costs. Commercial adver- utility. The authors find support in the data
tising, a particularly interesting case, also for their predictions."4 My focus is different.
creates few external benefits-since most I ask, what have been the effects on religious
such advertising is brand-specific and its belief and observance of the Supreme Court's
benefits are captured in higher sales of the enforcement of the First Amendment? To
advertised brand-and it creates some exter- avoid potential misunderstanding, I em-
nal costs: competitor A's advertising may go phasize that I am offering no opinion on
largely to offset B's, and vice versa. This either the validity of any religious belief or
analysis implies that if the logic of free- the legal soundness of any of the Court's
speech law is basically an economic logic, decisions.
commercial advertising that is not brand- Three major strands in the Court's mod-
specific, such as advertising extolling the ern decisions should be distinguished:
value of prunes as a laxative, would receive 1) In its school-prayer decisions, and
greater legal protection than brand-specific other decisions under the establishment
advertising. clause, the Court has interpreted the concept
of an "establishment" of religion very
B broadly, in effect forbidding the states and
the federal government to provide direct
The First Amendment also forbids the support, financial or even symbolic, for reli-
government to make any law (1) respecting gion. These decisions make a kind of eco-
an establishment of religion or (2) pro- nomic sense, though perhaps only super-
hibiting the free exercise of religion. The ficially. Public education (the principal arena
Supreme Court has enforced both clauses of modern disputes over establishment of re-
aggressively in recent years.'2 The economic ligion) involves the subsidizing of school-
effects of the Court's doctrines as well as children and their parents. Parents will-
their possible economic logic are interesting ing to pay the full costs of their children's
topics that economists (with the partial ex- education can and often do send their
ception of Adam Smith) have not addressed. children to private schools. If they choose a
There is, it is true, a nascent economic public school instead, this may be because
analysis of religion. Corry Azzi and Ronald some of the costs will be paid by others,
Ehrenberg (1975) have formulated a simple including persons who do not have school-
(maybe too simple, given the variety of reli- age children as well as taxpayers in other
gious beliefs) economic model of religion, parts of the state or nation. The principal
which assumes that people want to increase economic argument for externalizing some
their expected utility from a happy afterlife.'3
of the costs of education is that education
The model leads to such predictions as that (with possible exceptions, as for vocational
education and "phys. ed.") confers external
benefits; that we all (or most of us, anyway)
benefit from living in a nation whose popu-
11 Only the specific work of art is protected; an
artistic innovation (perspective, chiaroscuro, the sonnet,
blank verse, etc.) is not.
'2See Stone et al. (pt. 8).
'3See also Ehrenberg (1977); Paul Pautler (1977); 14For criticism of some of their results, see Holley
Barbara Redman (1980). Ulbrich and Myles Wallace (1984).

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
10 A EA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MA Y 1987

lation is educated. Therefore, to justify on receive public services for which they do not
economic grounds a public school's spending pay. This is fine if they generate benefits for
money on prayer and other religious activi- which they cannot charge, but the Court has
ties, either these activities would have to be not required that they show that. So here
shown to produce positive externalities also may be a large judicially sanctioned public
(as by making schoolchildren more moral, or subsidy of religion.
at least better behaved in school), or there 2) In its "free exercise" decisions, the
would have to be economies from combining Court has sometimes required public bodies
secular and religious instruction in the same to make costly accommodations to religious
facility, or private persons would have to observance. An example is forbidding the
volunteer to pay the incremental cost of the denial of unemployment benefits to a person
public school's religious activities, so that whose religion forbids him to accept a job
there would not be a subsidy. offer that would require working on Satur-
If the Supreme Court were willing to days. So the Court with one hand (establish-
accept any of these justifications-provided, ment clause cases) forbids the subsidizing of
of course, that they were adequately sup- religion and with the other (free-exercise
ported by evidence-then one might con- cases) requires such subsidies.
clude that the Court was taking an economic 3) In cases involving contraception,
approach to the issue in religion in the pub- abortion, illegitimacy, obscenity, and other
lic schools. But, in fact, the modern Court moral questions about which religious peo-
forbids virtually every public school religious ple tend to hold strong views, the Court in
activity, whether or not any of these justifi- recent years has almost always sided with
cations is present. If none is present, it can the secular against the religious point of
indeed be argued that religious persons view.
would be enjoying a public subsidy of reli- The decisions in both groups 1 and 2
gion if the activity were permitted. Parents favor religious rivalry or diversity (not com-
willing to pay the full costs of education in a petition in the economic sense: as we shall
school that conducts prayer or engages in see in a moment, to subsidize rivalry as in 2
other religious activities can always send theirretards rather than promotes competition in
children to a private school that offers such the economic sense). Any public establish-
activities, thereby bearing the full cost of ment of religion will tend to favor major
those activities rather than shifting a part of religious groups over minor ones and can
it to others in the community. Concern with thus be compared to government's placing
public subsidies of religion may explain the its thumb on the scales in a conventional
Court's insistence that Christmas nativity marketplace, by granting subsidies or oth-
scenes supported by public funds have a er benefits to politically influential firms.
secular purpose, that is, confer benefits on Refusing to accommodate fringe religious
nonreligious as well as religious persons. But groups will have effects similar to those of
the Court has not worried about the fact that establishing a religion because employment
the benefits may be greater for the latter policies, and other public policies and
persons, so that an element of subsidy re- customs, are chosen to minimize conflict with
mains. Nor has it explained its unwilling- the dominant religious groupings."5 It is no
ness to search for similar secular justifica- accident that the official day of rest in this
tions for public school religious activity-such country is the sabbath recognized by the
justifications as reducing the rowdiness of mainline Christian groups. Fringe groups will
schoolchildren. therefore benefit from a rule requiring
Further complicating the picture, the accommodation of their needs.
Supreme Court has declined to hold that the
exemption of church property from state
and local taxes is an unconstitutional estab-
lishment of religion. However, the conse-
quence of the exemption is that the churches "5As stressed in Michael McConnell (1985).

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 77 NO. 2 RICHARD T. ELYLECTURE 11

But since the costs of accommodation are school in which teachers lead prayers or read
borne by employers, consumers, taxpayers, to students from the Bible is treated as a
other employees, etc., the group 2 cases actu- religious organization, but my concern is
ally subsidize fringe religious groups. And with the effect on private organizations. Sim-
since it is no more efficient for government ilarly, a government that rigorously re-
to subsidize weak competitors than strong pressed abortion might be thought of as the
ones, it may not be possible to defend the enforcement arm of the Christian sects that
accommodation cases by reference to no- regard abortion as immoral; but by thereby
tions of efficiency. In addition, the group 1 assuming one of the functions of private
cases may go further than necessary to pre- religious organizations, it would be compet-
vent public subsidies of established religious ing with those organizations and thus reduc-
groups, by neglecting the various justifica- ing the demand for the services provided by
tions that might be offered for public sup- them.
port of religion-although allowing the There is a further point. As Adam Smith
property-tax exemption may correct (or for pointed out (1937, pp. 740-50), the effective-
that matter, overcorrect) that tendency. The ness of a private group's monitoring and
most important point to note, however, is regulating the behavior of its members is apt
that the Supreme Court has required govern- to be greater, the smaller the group (this is
ment to subsidize fringe religious groups both the essence of cartel theory), from which
directly and by discouraging religious estab- Smith inferred that the more religious sects
lishments that inevitably would favor the there were, and hence the smaller each one
beliefs and practices of the dominant sects in was on average, the more effective would
the community. By doing these things, the religion be in regulating behavior. This im-
Court probably has increased religious di- plies that legal regulations which have the
versity and may therefore have promoted effect of atomizing rather than concentrating
religion, on balance, notwithstanding the religious organization may improve the
"antireligion" flavor of some of its establish- society's moral tone even if they diminish
ment cases. the role of government in inculcating moral
The group 3 decisions favor religion, too values directly.
-more precisely, private religious organiza- It may be hard to believe that the moral
tions-but in a subtler sense, which may be tone of our society has actually improved
entirely unintended, even unrecognized, by since the Supreme Court adopted its aggres-
the courts. By marking a powerful agency of sively secularist stance, but economic analy-
government (the federal judiciary) as sis suggests that the situation might be worse
secularist, and, more important, by under- rather than better if the Court had weakened
mining traditional values through invalida- private religious organizations by allowing
tion of regulations that express or enforce government to compete more effectively with
those values, these decisions increase the de- them in inculcating or requiring moral be-
mand for organized religion, viewed as a havior. Since government and organized reli-
preserver of traditional values. If the govern- gion are substitutes in promoting moral be-
ment enforced the value system of Christian- havior, an expansion in the government's
ity, as it used to do, people would have less role as moral teacher might reduce the de-
to gain from being Christian. The group 1 mand for the services of organized religion. I
cases have a similar effect. By forbidding say "might" rather than "would" because,
teachers paid by the state to inculcate reli- to the extent that the government's role as
gious values, the courts have increased the moral teacher is taken seriously, a govern-
demand for the services provided by reli- ment that seeks to promote religiously based
gious organizations. And allowing the prop- moral values may help "sell" religious val-
erty-tax exemption lowers the costs of these ues, and the organizations that promote
organizations. them, over their secular substitutes. But this
Of course, there may be no net increase in assumes what history suggests is unlikely:
the provision of religious services if a public that the government will find a way of sup-

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
12 A EA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MA Y 1987

porting religion on a genuinely nonsectarian No doubt the Supreme Court's causal role
basis rather than establishing a particular in all this is smaller than I have suggested.
sect and thereby weakening competing sects The tradition of religious diversity in the
and maybe religion as a whole. United States is very old, and the Court's
To prove, in the face of the conventional contribution to maintaining it may be slight.
wisdom to the contrary, that the Supreme Nevertheless, economic analysis suggests that
Court's apparently antireligious decisions the religious leaders who denounce the course
have promoted religion would be a formid- of the Court's decisions and the secular
able undertaking, and here I offer only two leaders who defend it may be arguing con-
fragments of evidence. The first is the rapid trary to their institutional self-interest.
growth in recent years of evangelical Chris-
tianity, formerly a fringe religious grouping
and one marked by emphatic adherence to C

traditional values.'6 The second is the star-


tling difference in religiosity between the My discussions of free speech and religion
United States and Western Europe. Not only can be connected as follows. One possible
does a far higher percentage of Americans reading of the First Amendment (I do not
believe in an afterlife than the population of suggest the only, or a complete one) is that it
any western European country other than forbids government to interfere with the free
Ireland,17 but this percentage has been rela- market in two particular "goods"-ideas,
tively constant in the United States since the and religion. Government may not regulate
1930's, while it has declined substantially in these markets beyond what is necessary to
Europe over the same interval."8 Almost all correct externalities and other impediments
Western European nations have an estab- to the efficient allocation of resources. This
lished (i.e., a taxpayer-supported and legally seems an appropriate description of how
privileged) church (or churches, as with the modern courts interpret the amendment; the
state churches of Germany), and some re- principal though not only exceptions are the
quire prayer in public schools.19 To the ex- cases that forbid what might be called "effi-
tent that establishment discourages the rise cient" establishments (establishments that do
of rival sects, it reduces the religious "prod- not involve a subsidy to religious persons
uct variety" offered to the population, and I beyond what can be justified on secular
would expect the demand for religion to be grounds) and the cases requiring accommo-
less. The American system fosters a wide dation of religion in the sense of subsidizing
variety of religious sects. Almost every per- fringe religious groups. There is no compel-
son can find a package of beliefs and ob- ling economic argument for such a subsidy
servances that fits his economic and psycho- unless something can be made of Adam
logical circumstances. And by preventing the Smith's point that the more separate reli-
government from playing a shaping role in gious sects there are, the more effective reli-
the moral sphere the Supreme Court in re- gion is in bringing about moral behavior-
cent years has, I have conjectured, increased and morals supplement law in correcting
the demand for religion as a substitute in- negative externalities such as crime and fos-
stitution for the regulation of morals. tering positive ones such as charity.
But a lecture is not the place to prove a
new economic theory. All that is feasible is
to suggest that a particular theory holds
promise and is thus worth pursuing. I hope I
16See The Gallup Report (1985, pp. 3, 11). have persuaded you that what may loosely
'7See The Gallup Report, p. 53. be called the economic theory of law has a
'8See The Gallup Report, pp. 9-10, 40, 42, 53. significant potential to alter received no-
190n the religious establishments of Western Europe,
see, for example, E. Jiirgen Moltman (1986); E. Garth
tions, generate testable hypotheses about a
Moore (1967); Franklin Scott (1977, pp. 571-75); variety of important social phenomena, and
Frederic Spotts (1973). in short enlarge our knowledge of the world.

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 77 NO. 2 RICHARD T. ELYLECTURE 13

REFERENCES coming 1987.


McConnell, Michael, "Accommodation of Re-
Ashenfelter, Orley and Rees, Albert, Discrimina-
ligion," Supreme Court Review, Chicago:
tion in Labor Markets, Princeton: Prince- University of Chicago Press, 1985, 1-59.
ton University Press, 1973. Moltmann, E. Jurgen, "Religion and State in
Azzi, Corry and Ehrenberg, Ronald, "Household Germany; West and East," Annals of the
Allocation of Time and Church Atten- American Academy of Political and Social
dance," Journal of Political Economy, Science, January 1986, 483, 110-17.
February 1975, 83, 27-56. Moore, E. Garth, An Introduction to English
Becker, Gary S., The Economic Approach to Canon Law, Oxford: Clarendon Press,
Human Behavior, Chicago: University of 1967.
Chicago Press, 1976. Pautler, Paul A., "Religion and Relative
, Human Capital: A Theoretical and Prices," Atlantic Economic Journal, March
Empirical Analysis, With Specific Refer- 1977, 5, 69-73.
ence to Education, NBER, New York: Col- Posner, Richard A., Economic Analysis of Law,
umbia University Press, 2d ed., 1975. Boston: Little, Brown, 3d ed., 1986.
,_ A Treatise on the Family, Cam- Pyle, David J., The Economics of Crime and
bridge: Harvard University Press, 1981. Law Enforcement, New York: St. Martin's
Buchanan, James M., "Good Economics -Bad Press, 1983.
Law," Virginia Law Review, March 1974, Radnitzky, Gerard and Bernholz, Peter, Eco-
60, 483-92. nomic Imperialism: The Economic Ap-
Coase, Ronald H., "Economics and Contigu- proach Applied Outside the Field of Eco-
ous Disciplines," Journal of Legal Studies, nomics, New York: Paragon House, 1986.
June 1978, 7, 201-11. Redman, Barbara J., "An Economic Analysis
__ " The Market for Goods and the of Religious Choice," Review of Religious
Market for Ideas," American Economic Research, Summer 1980, 21, 330-42.
Review Proceedings, May 1974, 64, 384-91. Scott, Franklin D., Sweden: The Nation's His-
Director, Aaron, "The Parity of the Economic tory, Minneapolis: University of Min-
Market Place," Journal of Law and Eco- nesota Press, 1977.
nomics, October 1964, 7, 1-10. Scott, Robert E., "A Relational Theory of
Ehrenberg, Ronald G., "Household Allocation Secured Financing," Columbia Law Re-
of Time and Religiosity: Replication and view, June 1986, 86, 901-77.
Extension," Journal of Political Economy, Smith, Adam, in Edwin Cannan, ed., The
April 1977, 85, 415-23. Wealth of Nations, London: Methuen,
Ehrlich, Isaac, "Participation in Illegitimate 1937.
Activities: An Economic Analysis," in Spotts, Frederic, The Churches and Politics in
Gary S. Becker and William M. Landes, Germany, Middletown: Wesleyan Univer-
eds., Essays in the Economics of Crime and sity Press, 1973.
Punishment, NBER, New York: Columbia Stigler, George J., "Economics-The Imperial
University Press, 1974, 68-134. Science?," Scandinavian Journal of Eco-
Ellis, John M., The Theory of Literary Criti- nomics, No. 3, 1984, 86, 301-13.
cism: A Logical Analysis, Berkeley: Uni- , "The Theory of Economic Regu-
versity of California Press, 1974. lation," Bell Journal of Economics, Spring
Fogel, Robert W. and Engerman, Stanley L., The 1971, 2, 3-21.
Reinterpretation of American History, New Stone, Geoffrey R. et al., Constitutional Law,
York: Harper & Row, 1971. Boston: Little, Brown, 1986, pts. 7 and 8.
Hirshleifer, Jack, "The Expanding Domain of Ulbrich, Holley and Wallace, Myles, "Women's
Economics," American Economic Review, Work Force Status and Church Atten-
December 1985, Suppl., 75, 53-68. dance," Journal for the Scientific Study of
Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A., The Religion, December 1984, 23, 341-50.
Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cam- The Gallup Report, Report No. 236, Princeton:
bridge: Harvard University Press, forth- The Gallup Poll, May 1985.

This content downloaded from


49.207.195.101 on Thu, 27 Jan 2022 07:12:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like