Ethical Challenges in The New World of Maternal - Fetal Surgery

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

SE M I N A R S I N P E R I N A T O L O G Y ] (2015) ]]]–]]]

Available online at www.sciencedirect.com

Seminars in Perinatology

www.seminperinat.com

Ethical challenges in the new world of


maternal–fetal surgery
Ryan M. Antiel, MD, MA
Department of Medical Ethics and Health Policy, Perelman School of Medicine at the University of Pennsylvania, 423
Guardian Dr, FL 14 Market St, Suite 320, Philadelphia, PA 19104

article info abstra ct

Keywords: This article explores some of the complex ethical challenges that exist in the field of fetal
Fetal diagnosis diagnosis and treatment, especially surrounding maternal–fetal surgery. The rise of these
Fetal treatment new treatments force us to reconsider who or what is the fetus, what are our obligations to
Maternal–fetal surgery the fetus, and what are the limits to those obligations. In addition, we will consider
Ethics provider and professional biases, disability issues, and how maternal–fetal surgery has, for
a select group of women, changed the very experience of motherhood.
& 2015 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.

Fetal diagnosis has always been medically complex and advancements, a new set of ethical challenges has surfaced.
ethically controversial. Rapid advances in molecular genetics For what is both morally important and problematic, is
and advanced imaging technologies have given clinicians an precisely that the procedure is not, properly understood,
unprecedented look into the womb. Until recently, however, “fetal” surgery. It is more appropriately termed “maternal–
advanced diagnostics were used primarily for decision- fetal” surgery: both the fetus and the mother undergo
making around pregnancy termination and preparing for surgery. Significantly, such a surgery poses physical harm
postnatal treatment. But now a selected group of women and offers no direct physical benefits to the mother.
have a third option. What was once considered, science The purpose of this article is not to provide an overarching
fiction has become a reality—surgery on the fetus. Harrison ethical framework to guide prenatal decision-making.
et al.1 at the University of California, San Francisco pioneered Instead, my aim is far less ambitious: to provide an overview
open fetal surgery in the 1980s. The theory was simple: if an of some of the major ethical questions that underlie the
intervention for congenital anomalies took place prior to challenges for the physicians face when caring for pregnant
birth, one might be able to cure, or at least mitigate, the women and ill fetuses. Questions such as: who is the patient
negative consequences that would be inevitable if surgery (the pregnant woman, the fetus, or both) and how ought we
was delayed until the fetus was delivered. navigate the tradeoffs, which invasive procedures yield each
The pace of medical and social developments in this arena individual? Are there specialty-specific biases and commit-
is dizzying. Consider that in the early 1980s standard treat- ments that unduly influence the counseling process? How
ment was withheld from more than half of infants with a have fetal diagnostics and interventions changed the very
myelomeningocele.2 After the Baby-Doe controversy, postna- experience of motherhood? Is the risk of fetal death associ-
tal treatment of spina bifida came to be understood as ated with maternal–fetal surgery for nonlethal conditions
mandatory.3 And today eligible women are offered prenatal discriminatory against people with disabilities? And finally,
repair of their fetus’ myelomeningocele.4 In the wake of should pregnant women be obligated to undergo surgery in
these rapid societal shifts precipitated by technological order to benefit their fetuses?

E-mail address: antiel@mail.med.upenn.edu

http://dx.doi.org/10.1053/j.semperi.2015.12.012
0146-0005/& 2015 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
2 SE M I N A R S I N P E R I N A T O L O G Y ] (2015) ]]]–]]]

a way may protect the normative asymmetry Lyerly is


But who is the patient? arguing for—the primacy of the clinician’s duties to the
pregnant woman—yet the definition itself is problematic.
The majority of fetuses prenatally diagnosed with congenital The concept of the patient as a self-sufficient, independent,
anomalies now have a physician monitoring them before and fully autonomous being is an illusion, the byproduct of a
they are born. With evolving technology, many diagnosed post-enlightenment, patriarchal American culture. What
fetuses are not just monitored but also undergo treatment in makes certain decisions in medicine so difficult and often
utero. These treatments vary from minimally invasive blood heartrending—whether parents should stop life-sustaining
transfusions for fetal anemia to more invasive fetoscopic treatment for their baby in the NICU, whether a sister should
procedures for twin-to-twin transfusion syndrome to open donate a kidney to her younger sister, or whether your father
surgical repairs for spina bifida. In this current age of with advanced Alzheimer’s disease should undergo surgery
medicine, most would argue that the fetus has become a for his newly diagnosed cancer—is that we are intimately
patient.5 connected to others. Yet, the overarching framework of
McCullough and Chervenak6 explicate the fetus as patient discussions on personhood, and now patienthood, is obses-
idea.7,8 They strategically bypass any discussion about fetal sively individualistic. The particular emphasis on separate-
personhood given the deep-seated metaphysical disagree- ness does violence to the moral and emotional commitments
ments surrounding the moral status of the fetus. Instead, that arise out of intimate relationships.
they focus on the concept of patienthood. The previable fetus Debates over personhood, and now patienthood, are con-
becomes a patient, they argue, when (1) the mother presents troversial because they are often seen as the basis of morality.
her to the physician and (2) when there exists a clinical We believe that persons, and patients, deserve to be treated in
intervention to benefit the fetus. They argue that the fetus certain ways. It is thought that if we can determine the
has no intrinsic moral status but rather a “dependent moral capacities or criteria that constitute personhood (or patient-
status,” which is conferred upon the fetus only when the hood), then we will know who is worthy of fundamental rights
pregnant woman presents the fetus to the physician. In this and our moral respect. Lindemann15 takes the opposite
paradigm, the status of the fetus as patient is only ever approach. She argues that personhood is something that we
contingent: if the mother desires the fetus to be viewed as a do. Someone is not a person because I think she is a person, but
patient, her “thinking makes it so.”9 The physician does have rather because I treat her as a person. Thus, personhood, and I
beneficence-based obligations to protect and to promote the would argue patienthood, is dependent on a moral community
best interest of the fetus but only if it is brought to her. They recognizing and responding to the other. And for many
reject that fetal patienthood necessarily implies that the women, pregnancy is the very active process of beginning to
pregnant woman and fetus are separate patients. initiate the fetus into personhood. Lindemann writes:
On the other hand, Lyerly et al.10 argue that fetal patient-
hood will encourage viewing the pregnant woman as simply In nonhuman animals, for all we can tell, pregnancy is a
the fetal environment, thus obliterating her own identity. The process that, occurs in the female without any purposive
authors acknowledge that both physicians and pregnant contributions on her part: she passively suffers the fetus
women have beneficence-based obligations toward the fetus. to grow in her rather than actively, shaping it, so the
They cite taking prenatal vitamins to prevent birth defects as relationship that ensues is a purely biological one. In
one example. Yet, they believe that the “concept of fetus as human pregnancies, by contrast, what begins as a purely
patient” will animate conceptualizations of the fetus and biological, relationship is transformed into a recognizably
pregnant woman as two separate patients. This could result human one because, by what the woman does in word,
in physicians regarding “their obligations to and the value of deed, and imagination, she calls, her fetus into person-
each of their patients as equal.” Instead, Lyerly et al. argue for hood. She now not only bears the identity of a pregnant
a single patient, the pregnant woman. woman but also becomes a particular kind of pregnant
This emphasis on symbiosis is helpful for a field marred woman: she is an expectant mother.
with a feto-centric history.11 Fetuses are not separable from The decision to undergo maternal–fetal surgery is not prem-
pregnant women. Yet, the fetus is also not reducible to the ised on whether the fetus is a person, but rather it depends on
pregnant woman—not merely an extension of her flesh our attitude toward the fetus, perceptions of ourselves as
analogous to a kidney. Rich12 describes the fetus as “some- parents, and the belief that medical interventions are one form
thing inside and of me, yet becoming hourly and daily more of caring for children and even our future children. Hauerwas16
separate.” Young13 recollects fetal movements as “belonging writes, “We seldom decide to treat or not treat (someone)
to another, another that is nevertheless my body.” Under- because they have or have not yet passed some line that makes
standing pregnancy as a separate existence or as a single them a person or nonperson. Rather, we care or do not care for
existence fails to accurately account for the phenomenon at them because they are Uncle Charlie, or my father, or a good
hand. Pregnancy is experienced as “the splitting of the friend.” A fetus is a patient because we treat her as a patient.
subject: redoubling up of the body, separation and coexistence
of the self and another.”14
Lyerly et al.10 take a surprising turn when they insist on Tradeoffs
self-sufficiency and detachment as prerequisites for patient-
hood. The “paradigmatic patient” is one who is “fully sepa- Despite great advances in obstetrical care, pregnancy is risky.
rate from others.” Defining the “paradigmatic patient” in such Pregnant women are at increased risk for both morbidity and
SEM I N A R S I N P E R I N A T O L O G Y ] (2015) ]]]–]]] 3

mortality. The most common causes of morbidity in preg- proportional to the potential benefit for the future child. And
nancy are pregnancy-induced hypertension, hemorrhage, we must also weigh the potential morbidity benefits for the
and pulmonary embolism.17 Furthermore, over 20% of preg- future child with both the risk of death and the risks of
nant women are hospitalized before delivery due to a com- prematurity. Is it preferable to have a full term baby with
plication.17 Fortunately in most circumstances, the well-being hydrocephalus or a 24-week premature infant without
of the pregnant woman and the fetus overlap. Yet there are hydrocephalus?
extreme circumstances where divergences do occur. Specifi- The risk of a surgery may be worthwhile if the benefit is
cally, fetal interventions can create situations where the commensurable with the risk, but what scale can accurately
clinical best interests of the fetus and the mother are not weigh and measure such things? When two things are said to
aligned, where potential benefits for the fetus are attainable be commensurable, there exists a common criterion to
only by risking serious morbidity for the mother. measure them by.22,23 Commensurable items can be ranked.
Significant short-term and long-term maternal risks are John is 5 in taller than Bill. In contrast, things that are
involved with open fetal surgery.4 When a woman undergoes incommensurable lack a common unit of measure. They
fetal surgery, she must have two operations: the first to repair may be comparable—for example, I can compare jazz music
the fetal defect and the second to deliver the fetus. She has with Baroque music. But what calculus exists to rank these
committed herself to future cesarean sections for all subse- genres? In a similar way, the choice to undergo maternal–
quent pregnancies, as the hysterotomy puts her at risk for fetal surgery cannot simply be decided by a scale weighing
uterine dehiscence or rupture, either of which could be fatal. the risks and benefits. McIntyre writes:
If a woman has an amniotic leak from the incision, she is
The characteristic temptation of the modern world is
required to undergo strict bed rest for the remainder of the
utilitarianism. For utilitarianism in all its versions aspires
pregnancy. In addition to complications from the hysterot-
to provide a criterion, a way of judging between rival and
omy, there are also side effects from the medications
conflicting goods to maximize utility. But the goods and
attempting to prevent premature labor after surgery. Fortu-
rights, which define our contemporary conflicts are
nately, there have been no maternal deaths after open
incommensurable. There is no higher criterion. There is
maternal–fetal surgery, although it is a theoretical risk. No
no neutral concept of utility.24
good studies currently exist on the long-term reproductive
health of women who undergo maternal–fetal surgery. In a Given the incommensurability of competing factors, we
recent survey of 93 patients who had undergone open fetal should expect a broad spectrum of prioritization by individual
surgery, of which only half of the women responded (47 of women and individual physicians.
the 93 women), 27 (57%) reported one or more subsequent
pregnancies after open maternal–fetal surgery.18 Among
these 27 women, 10 (37%) had uterine rupture or dehiscence Does who counsels matter?
and 2 (7%) had excessive bleeding. One cesarean hysterec-
tomy was reported. Reported infertility rates were not above A specific patient is cared for by a specific provider who
baseline population rates. However, these results are subject brings her own values, knowledge, and practices to the care
to selection bias. of patients; these factors shape the care that is provided. This
The benefits to the future child are of course dependent on clinical reality raises the concern that a pediatric-based
what disease is being treated. Fetal hydrops secondary to model of fetal care, in contrast to an obstetrics-based model,
congenital cystic adenomatoid malformation or sacrococcygeal will be primarily concerned with the health and well-being of
teratomas can be fatal. So in these cases, the possible benefit to the fetus in contrast to the well-being of the pregnant
the fetus is life. In the case of maternal–fetal surgery for spina woman.25 It has been assumed that high risk obstetricians
bifida, the benefit is decreased disability. The Management of will primarily focus on maternal risks, whereas pediatric
Myelomeningocele Study (MOMS) was a multi-center, random- neurosurgeons will focus on shunt rates and neonatologists
ized controlled trial that compared prenatal repair with stand- will focus on prematurity to the exclusion of other consid-
ard postnatal repair of myelomeningocele.4 Prenatal repair erations. This may be true and simply a function of the
reduced the need for a cerebrospinal fluid shunt at 12 months specialization and niche expertise common in medicine
and improved motor function at 30 months. today. Neurosurgeons have no experience with the side
During open fetal surgery, significant risks for the fetus are effects of tocolytics, and obstetricians have never taken care
also posed. Even in the most experienced hands, the risk of of a child with spina bifida or managed a cerebrospinal fluid
fetal death is between 3% and 6%.4,19 And most fetuses will be shunt. In short, our specialization precludes us from seeing
born prematurely. One neonatologist has commented that we the whole picture. Additionally, some are concerned that
have in essence developed a device to create prematurity.20 pediatric-based models of fetal care will not present termi-
The risks associated with prematurity include respiratory nation as a viable option and encourage women to bring to
distress, cardiovascular disease, injury to the bowels, immu- term pregnancies with disabilities.25 In contrast, others have
nologic compromise, hearing and vision problems, and neu- argued that obstetric-based counseling for congenital defects
rological insult.21 In the MOMS trial, 33% of the prenatal group like spina bifida is grossly slanted against disability and in
were born between 30 and 34 weeks, and 13% were born less favor of termination.26 They argue that obstetricians, who
than 30 weeks.4 have no experience caring for any children with disabilities,
But how are pregnant women to weigh these tradeoffs? We present inaccurate and worst case scenarios to the
generally think that the risks to the pregnant woman must be pregnant woman.
4 SE M I N A R S I N P E R I N A T O L O G Y ] (2015) ]]]–]]]

Interestingly, at fetal care centers, specialty bias seems to pregnancy into a production instead of a relationship.30 Many
diminish. Put another way, at fetal care centers, physicians women postpone bonding with their fetus until they have
from all specialties appear to be quite uniform in their been reassured that it is not defective—thus the “tentative
recommendations. In 2010, Brown et al.27 surveyed both pregnancy.” The sort of preparation and bonding that a
maternal–fetal medicine specialists as well as pediatric spe- pregnant woman actively engages into begin to welcome a
cialists who practiced at fetal care or fetal treatment centers. fetus into her familial and social narrative is put on hold. She
Although maternal–fetal medicine practitioners were more writes:
likely to support the termination of a pregnancy with spina
We ask the mother and her family to say, in essence,
bifida than pediatric specialists (54% versus 35%), there was
“These are my standards. If you meet these standards of
not a significant difference between the groups in the like-
acceptability, then you are mine and I will love and accept
lihood of recommending open maternal–fetal surgery. Why is
you totally. After you pass this test.”
this? It may be that fetal treatment centers self-select
physicians who collectively view maternal–fetal surgery pos- The pregnant woman and fetus are thus viewed as separate
itively. I would also argue that, in order for maternal–fetal individuals whose relationship is chosen and contingent. Yet
surgery to be successful, it requires highly specialized practi- these diagnostic tests only give the illusion of control. No test
tioners from multiple disciplines to work together as a team. can guarantee a perfect child. Rothman writes:
This team of obstetricians, surgeons, neonatologists, and
other healthcare providers meet together at the end of a One can rationally decide to abort a fetus with spina bifida
woman’s comprehensive evaluation to discuss the case and because life in a wheelchair is not acceptable—and then
will often meet as a team with the patient. The emphasis on have a baby’s back broken in a car accident … Does the
teamwork in medicine is not a new concept. In 1910 Mayo,28 conscious, deliberate emphasis on control and “standards
surgeon and cofounder of the Mayo Clinic, said, “In order that of acceptability” prepare us for the reality of parenthood?
the sick may have the benefit of advancing knowledge, a And, if developmental psychology has shown that uncondi-
union of forces is necessary.” Inter-specialty collaboration tional acceptance of a child is foundational for successful
will lead to a heightened awareness of factors one may not parenting, what implications does the “tentative pregnancy”
normally consider, temper individual bias, and result in more have for the future difficult and life-long task of parenting?
uniform recommendations. While the majority of women choose to terminate the
“diagnosed fetus,” others have turned to intrauterine treat-
ment, which may equally alter the meaning of motherhood.
How did we get here? If prenatal diagnosis and selective abortion have created
the “tentative pregnancy,” the option of fetal intervention
A striking dichotomy exists. For one pregnant woman, physi- does the opposite. The dramatic self-sacrifice we associate
cians go to extreme efforts and accept serious risks in hopes with parenthood begins much earlier for these women.
of improving the quality of life of the future child. On the Pregnant women who choose to undergo maternal–fetal
other hand, the majority of fetuses diagnosed with anomalies surgery are forced to make maternal decisions before birth.
such as spina bifida are terminated. A surgical colleague There may be disagreement about the type of sacrifices we
recently overheard a conversation I was having about a present to women and the societal pressures to make those
particular maternal–fetal surgery. She interjected that she sacrifices, but the new world of maternal–fetal surgery has,
could not figure out why anyone would go to such lengths for a select group of expectant mothers, accelerated
when they could simply abort and “start over.”20 motherhood.
As alluded to above, the evolution of maternal–fetal surgery
was contingent upon the ability to provide timely and
accurate prenatal diagnosis. Our ability to diagnose has Disability rights critique
dramatically improved due to technologies such as amnio-
centesis, chorionic villus sampling, high-resolution ultra- Fetal surgeon Alan Flake writes that “maternal–fetal surgery
sound, ultra-fast MRI, and fetal echocardiography. The is a specialty born of clinical necessity.”31 The first applica-
evolution of these technologies has provided women and tions of maternal–fetal surgery were to prevent prenatal or
their partners with new choices. But more choice yields neonatal death. But now maternal–fetal surgery has been
heavy burdens. Smajdor29 writes about the connection extended to nonlethal anomalies, such as myelomeningocele.
between ultrasound and maternal–fetal surgery and the more This raises an important question. What “clinical necessity”
general connection between data and the “urge to intervene.” exists in nonlethal cases to justify the considerable risks to
It is interesting to consider how this “urge to intervene” alters the healthy young mother and the small, but real, risk of fetal
the very nature of parenthood, in particular, motherhood. demise? The risks assumed are for the hope of decreasing
When our screening technologies catch an abnormality, our disability.
first instinct is to want to do something: to fix or treat the Disability rights scholars have criticized prenatal genetic
problem. screening and selective abortion as immoral and misin-
Historically, there has been only one “treatment” available formed.32 One argument critics make against aborting an
at the time of diagnosis: termination. In her important and otherwise desired fetus because she has spina bifida is that it
thought provoking book, The Tentative Pregnancy, Barbara Katz is insulting to people who currently live with spina bifida. The
Rothman argues that prenatal screening has turned message conveyed by aborting a fetus with a disability is that
SEM I N A R S I N P E R I N A T O L O G Y ] (2015) ]]]–]]] 5

these individuals are unworthy of being born.33 It is an attack, have severe disability secondary to their CDH. Some physi-
however oblique or unintended, on the humanity of people cians have stated that it would be better not to intervene and
with spina bifida. Furthermore, critics argue that many simply let “nature take its course” than to ensure that the
pregnant women and the physicians who counsel them have child will live and suffer. As prenatal surgery continues to
misinformed views of what life with a disability is actually evolve, it is crucial for practitioners to work out appropriate
like. A study of parents of children with spina bifida and their limits to our technology. Knowing when to intervene and
pediatricians found that the pediatricians overestimated the when to let be is one of the most difficult decisions for
negative impacts while simultaneously underestimating the parents and practitioners to make.
positive impacts of caring for a child with a disability.34
It is beyond the scope of this article to adequately present
the various disability rights critique of prenatal genetic test- Obligatory or supererogatory
ing in full detail or to assess responses to those critiques.
Instead, I am interested in examining whether maternal–fetal While society understands parents to have an obligation and
surgery is subject to the same criticisms as selective abortion. responsibility to care for their children, oftentimes parents
Somewhat paradoxically, many women who are strongly exceed normative parental duties. The ethics of these super-
opposed to selective abortion have nevertheless risked fetal erogatory actions give rise to the debate over whether expect-
death by undergoing maternal–fetal surgery to decrease ant mothers who choose to continue their pregnancy are
disability in an otherwise nonlethal condition (i.e., spina obligated to undergo prenatal interventions for the good of
bifida). Lyerly11 argues that this is problematic. If prenatal their future child. Is it unfair to the future child to decline
genetic testing spawns the “urge to intervene,” is intervening prenatal surgery? These questions fall within a larger—and
through maternal–fetal surgery discriminatory in the same largely contentious—debate about obligations toward the
way many view selective abortion? fetus. Pregnant women who chose to continue their preg-
Lyerly raises a thought provoking consideration. I have nancy do have beneficence-based obligations toward the
witnessed women, albeit a minority, decline maternal–fetal fetus.10 But what becomes controversial is compulsory treat-
surgery because they viewed the risk of fetal demise to be too ment when a pregnant woman either refuses to undergo a
high. There is a theoretical risk of death with any surgery. treatment recommendation (cesarean delivery for fetal dis-
This begs the question, how high of a risk is too high? An tress) or rejects medical recommendations (continuing to use
individual’s assessment of risk is influenced by many biases illegal drugs). The American College of Obstetricians and
such as risk aversion, omission bias, and how the risk is Gynecologists (ACOG) Committee on Ethics argues strongly
framed. against the use of coercive or punitive means in these
But is the motivation for fetal intervention the same as that difficult situations.35 Regarding the use of force in the setting
for selective abortion? In other words, should we view of maternal–fetal surgery, a joint statement by ACOG Com-
maternal–fetal surgery as an attempt to “fix the broken gift,” mittee on Ethics and the American Academy of Pediatrics
reflective of a qualified acceptance of a child? Important Committee on Bioethics contends that “even the strongest
differences exist between selective abortion and maternal– evidence for fetal benefit would not be sufficient ethically to
fetal surgery. Selective abortion “treats” the disability by ever override a pregnant woman’s decision to forgo fetal
eliminating the diagnosed fetus. The mortality rate of selec- treatment.”36 Even if the vast majority of physicians and
tive abortion is 100%. In contrast, as cited above the fetal ethicists agree that forcing a woman to undergo maternal–
mortality rate for prenatal spina bifida repair is approxi- fetal surgery is never justifiable, it is important to explore
mately 5%. Suggesting that these two interventions are what internal or external pressures (from family, community,
equally discriminatory toward those with disability seems or even one’s physician) might make it nigh impossible to
very problematic. Yet, it remains debatable what constitutes forgo maternal–fetal surgery.
a justifiable mortality tradeoff for a morbidity benefit. Consider the following two examples: a mother pleads with
Furthermore, maternal–fetal surgery for spina bifida is not the doctors to allow her to undergo fetal surgery to repair a
a cure. Unless there is a fetal demise during or after the recently diagnosed spina bifida. “I would give my right arm if
surgery, the woman has accepted to care for a child with a it would help my baby,” she tells the doctors. But she is not a
disability. The disability may be lessened as a result of candidate—her BMI is too high. Another pregnant woman is
intervention, but the disability remains. One woman shared carrying a fetus with the same diagnosis. After two days of
her motivation to undergo maternal–fetal surgery stating that comprehensive testing and consultations, she is told the
her future child would face many difficulties because she had “good news”—she is a candidate; however, she hesitates.
spina bifida, should not she (the expectant mother) do every- After a few days of deliberation, she declines. She tells the
thing possible to make her child’s life just a little easier?20 nurse coordinator that she does not want a scar.
A related but different dilemma is the potential for mater- These two cases represent divergent views on motherhood
nal–fetal surgery to save the life of a fetus that would and the obligations that arise from the relationship. For the
otherwise die, resulting in the child living with severe first pregnant woman, there seemed to be no choice. In order
disability. The best example of this dilemma is prenatal to be a “good mother,” consistent with her understanding of
tracheal occlusion for congenital diaphragmatic hernia what that meant, she ought to sacrifice for her future child
(CDH). This treatment is currently under investigation for in this way. The fact that the gatekeepers would not offer her
fetuses with severe and likely fatal CDH. The problem is that, an operation infuriated her. She felt as though the medical
while the treatment offers a mortality benefit, these babies team was restricting her autonomy and denying her the
6 SE M I N A R S I N P E R I N A T O L O G Y ] (2015) ]]]–]]]

opportunity to help her future child. The second pregnant to exclude pregnant women from their place in that
woman felt differently. She verbalized feeling a similar intu- system by a system of paternalistic restrictions … Perhaps
ition to undergo the surgery. She acknowledged both internal this encroachment of paternalism is a subversion of
(a good mother would be willing to do this) and external (my medical ethics on a greater scale than the problem that
family might think poorly of me if I do not have the surgery) it is attempting to solve.
pressures to do so. She desired the pregnancy and was not
considering an abortion. Yet, surgery overwhelmed her. She While difficult theoretical work must be done to demarcate
was prepared to make sacrifices in the future for her child, yet the limits of what prenatal interventions we will offer and to
this seemed to be asking too much of her. Thus, we are whom, broadly dismissing the maternal desire to sacrifice for
presented with two women with divergent views of what was her future child as merely the influence of coercive forces,
required of them as expectant mothers. One woman felt the eradicates the human aspect of medicine. Yet, we must
obligation to do everything possible and the other understood maintain that fetal surgery, like organ donation or bearing a
there to be some limits to what was required of her. child in the first place, is an extraordinary sacrifice. What one
There are similar dilemmas in the field of living donor ought to do in these situations is at best unclear.
organ transplantation. Is a father obligated to donate a kidney
to his daughter in end stage renal failure? Or is a sister
obligated to donate bone marrow to her younger brother Conclusion
dying of leukemia? The transplant world’s response to these
dilemmas may be instructive to the field of maternal–fetal More than 30 years ago, the editor-in-chief of the Journal of the
surgery. First, the field has gone to great lengths to emphasize American Medical Association interviewed some of the leading
that organ donation is a supererogatory act. Physicians ethicists of the time, including theologian Richard McCor-
ensure that potential donors are given an “out.” In fact, some mick, about the ethics of maternal–fetal surgery.38 In partic-
physicians have even deceived families that a potential donor ular, McCormick was asked about the legitimacy of letting a
is not a biological match if the potential donor fears that her diagnosed pregnancy go to term without intervening. McCor-
unwillingness to donate an organ will be met with disap- mick replied, “One wonders, when a successful treatment is
proval and rejection. Although an ethical analysis of decep- available to the individual couple, whether that is any longer
tion in this circumstance is beyond the scope of this article, it an alternative.” For some pregnant women with a fetal
is crucial to emphasize that maternal–fetal surgery is also diagnosis of spina bifida, there is no alternative. And I wonder
supererogatory. Furthermore, the future child’s best interest if surgery will become more compelling over time as treat-
is not the only interest to be considered. Many pregnant ment becomes more successful: less invasive, better out-
women have other children or older parents that they care comes. Others argue that the compulsion is problematic—
for. Many pregnant women have demanding careers. It is another example of the undue pressures that society already
simply not feasible for every woman to move to another state places on women.
to be close to a given fetal center. Pregnant women and their As I conclude this article, I acknowledge that it offers little
families have the difficult task of evaluating their own caring help for those dealing with these difficult dilemmas. Instead
resources and making a decision that is best for the family of developing a framework to “solve” these dilemmas or
unit. These decisions require a great deal of prudence. articulating a public policy proposal to guide future research
The second lesson from the field of transplantation is to resist in the field, I have merely sketched out some of the funda-
the temptation to view a decision to sacrifice as pathologic or mental questions that underlie our debates: who or what is
coercive. With the rise of living donor transplantation, some the fetus, what are our obligations to the fetus, and what are
ethicists believe that we ask too much of parents.37 It was argued the limits to those obligations. In the absence of any ethical
that no parent could decline when presented with the option of consensus, we are reminded how dependent medicine is on
donating an organ to his or her child and that this was therefore underlying moral commitments. Divergent views exist
coercive at its core. Critics, in a similar fashion, have accused regarding parental decision-making, the purpose of having
maternal–fetal surgery of being coercive and undermining a children, the nature and perception of disability, and at what
woman’s autonomy. There are at least two reasons for this point human life merits protection. The tension between
viewpoint. First, modern ethical frameworks, obsessed with these perspectives—influenced by a plurality of moral tradi-
autonomy and free choice, have difficulty assimilating sacrificial tions and commitments—gets played out in the arena of fetal
actions not based on risk aversion or self promotion.29 Second, diagnosis and treatment.
society has and in many ways continues to place undue The “urge to intervene” is gripping. The alternative—to
demands on mothers and pregnant women generally. Smadjor termination on the one hand, maternal–fetal surgery on the
believes that these conditions have made ethicists and physi- other—has become less compelling to some. Yet, it is exactly
cians uncomfortable with open maternal–fetal surgery. However, this alternative that requires important moral reflection. For
the response to this discomfort has been problematic. Some within a society dominated by a technological imperative, we
have proposed that medicine ought to construct barriers to often lack the imagination to “do nothing gallantly.”39 We
access and to protect pregnant women from themselves, a must learn what kind of limits we should accept. Medicine
subtle but gross form of neo-paternalism. Smadjor writes: provides the opportunity for some parents to help their
children, and even future children, in extraordinary ways.
In essence, because our ideas of maternal altruism do not And the supererogatory maternal sacrifice of maternal–fetal
fit into an autonomy-based ethics system, we are tempted surgery, what some might call love, has certainly mitigated
SEM I N A R S I N P E R I N A T O L O G Y ] (2015) ]]]–]]] 7

the suffering of many children. Yet, we must remember that 19. Moldenhauer JS, Soni S, Rintoul NE, et al. Fetal myelomenin-
the ability of a woman to undertake the anticipated morbid- gocele repair: the postMOMS experience at the Children’s
ities of maternal–fetal surgery is very much dependent on the Hospital of Philadelphia. Fetal Diagn Ther. 2015;37(3):235–240.
20. Personal communication.
larger family caring resources. There is no clear right or
21. Carlo WA. The high-risk pregnancy. In: Kliegman RM, Stanton
wrong thing to be done. Medicine, like every worthwhile part BF, St Geme JW, Schor NF, et al., eds. Nelson Textbook of
of our lives, involves tradeoffs. Maternal–fetal surgery is a Pediatrics, 20th ed. Philadelphia, PA: Elsevier; 2016.
formidable setting where we might learn to sacrifice, to love, 22. Chang R. Incommensurability (and incomparability). In:
and even to accept the limits that define the very nature of LaFollette H, ed, The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Oxford:
our existence, of our finitude—“the rest is silence.”9 Blackwell; 2013. 2591–2604.
23. Chang R. Value incomparability and incommensurability. In:
Hirose I, Olson J, et al., eds. Oxford Handbook of Value Theory.
re fe r en ces
Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014.
24. MacIntyre A. How virtues become vices. Encounter. 1975:11–17.
25. Brown SD, Lyerly AD, Little MO, Lantos JD. Paediatrics-based
1. Harrison MR, Golbus MS, Filly RA. Management of the fetus fetal care: unanswered ethical questions. Acad Pediatr. 2008;97
with a correctable congenital defect. J Am Med Assoc. 1981;246 (12):1617–1619.
(7):774–777. 26. Bruner JP, Tulipan N. Tell the truth about spina bifida. Ultra-
2. Gross RH, Cox A, Tatyrek R, Pollay M, Barnes WA. Early sound Obstet Gynecol. 2004;24(6):595–596.
management and decision making for the treatment of 27. Brown SD, Ecker JL, Ward JRM, et al. Prenatally diagnosed fetal
myelomeningocele. Pediatrics. 1983;72(4):450–458. conditions in the age of fetal care: does who counsels matter.
3. Fost N. Decisions regarding treatment of seriously ill new- Am J Obstet Gynecol. 2012;206(5):409.e1–409.e11.
borns. J Am Med Assoc. 1999;281(2):2041–2042. 28. Mayo WJ. The necessity of cooperation in the practice of medicine:
4. Adzick NS, Thom EA, Spong CY, et al. A randomized trial of address given June 15, 1910, Rush Medical College commencement.
prenatal versus postnatal repair of myelomeningocele. N Engl Collected Papers of Saint Mary’s Hospital Proceedings of the Staff
J Med. 2011;364(11):993–1004. Meetings of the Mayo Clinic. Philadelphia, PA: W.B. Saunders
5. Harrison MR, Golbus MS, Filly RA. The Unborn Patient, 2nd ed. Co.;557–566.
Philadelphia, PA: WB Saunders Company;1990. 29. Smajdor A. Ethical challenges in fetal surgery. J Med Ethics.
6. McCullough LB, Chervenak FA. Ethics in Obstetrics and Gynecol- 2011;37(2):88–91.
ogy. New York: Oxford University Press;1994. 30. Rothman BK. The Tentative Pregnancy, How Amniocentesis
7. Chervenak FA, McCullough LB. Ethics of maternal—fetal Changes the Experience of Motherhood. New York, NY: W.W.
surgery. Semin Fetal Neonatal Med. 2007;12(6):426–431. Norton;1993.
8. Chervenak FA, McCullough LB. An ethically justified frame- 31. Flake A. Fetal surgery. In: Spitz L, Coran A, et al., eds. Operative
work for clinical investigation to benefit pregnant and fetal Pediatric Surgery, 7th ed. Boca Raton, Fl: Taylor and Francis
patients. Am J Bioeth. 2011;11(5):39–49. Group; 2013. 1037.
9. Shakespeare W. Hamlet. Oxford: Oxford University Press;2008. 32. Parens E, Asch A. The disability rights critique of prenatal
10. Lyerly AD, Little MO, Faden RR. A critique of the “fetus as genetic testing. Reflections and recommendations. Hastings
patient”. Am J Bioeth. 2008;8(7):42–44. Cent Rep. 1999;29(5):S1–S22.
11. Lyerly AD, Mahowald MB. Maternal–fetal surgery for treat- 33. Saxton M. Disability rights and selective abortion. In: Solinger
ment of myelomeningocele. Clin Perinatol. 2003;30(1):155–165. R, ed, Abortion Wars: A Half Century of Struggle, 1950–2000. Los
12. Rich A. Of Woman Born. NY: W.W. Norton;1976. Angeles, CA: University of California Press; 1997. 374–395.
13. Young IM. Pregnant embodiment: subjectivity and alienation. 34. Blaymore Bier JA, Liebling JA, Morales Y, Carlucci M. Parents’
In: On Female Body Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press;49. and pediatricians’ views of individuals with meningomyelo-
14. Kristeva J. Motherhood according to Giovanni Bellini. In: cele. Clin Pediatr. 1996;35(3):113–117.
Young IM, ed, Pregnant Embodiment: Subjectivity and Alienation. 35. ACOG Committee on Ethics. ACOG Committee Opinion #321:
On Female Body Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press; maternal decision making, ethics, and the law. Obstet Gynecol.
2005. 49. 2005;106(5):1127–1137.
15. Lindemann H. Holding and Letting Go—The Social Practice of 36. American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, Com-
Personal Identities. Oxford: Oxford University Press;2014. mittee on Ethics, American Academy of Pediatrics, Commit-
16. Hauerwas S. Must a patient be a person to be a patient, or my tee on Bioethics. Maternal–fetal intervention and fetal care
uncle Charlie is not much of a person but he is still my uncle centers. Pediatrics. 2011;128(2):e473–e478.
Charlie. Truthfulness and Tragedy. Indiana: Notre Dame Press;1977. 37. Kolata G. Lungs from parents fail to save girl, 9, and doctors
17. Grimes DA. The morbidity and mortality of pregnancy: still assess ethics. The New York Times. May 20, 1991.
risky business. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 1994;170(5):1489–1494. 38. Barclay WR, McCormick RA, Sidbury JB, et al. The ethics of in
18. Wilson RD, Lemerand K, Johnson MP, et al. Reproductive utero surgery. J Am Med Assoc. 1981;246(14):1550–1555.
outcomes in subsequent pregnancies after a pregnancy com- 39. Haueraws S, McKenny G. Doing nothing gallantly. In:
plicated by open maternal–fetal surgery (1996–2007). Am J Approaching the End: Eschatological Reflections on Church, Politics,
Obstet Gynecol. 2010;203(3):209.e1–209.e6. and Life. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans;2013.

You might also like