Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

DOI: 10.1002/sres.

2597

RESEARCH PAPER

A note on Ludwig von Bertalanffy and the form problem


of life

Dirk Baecker

Culture Theory and Management, Witten/


Abstract
Herdecke University, Witten, Germany
The paper looks at two early books written and edited, respectively, by Ludwig
Correspondence von Bertalanffy, both published in 1928. They share an interest in the individ-
Dirk Baecker, Culture Theory and
Management, Witten/Herdecke
uality of individual things and living beings and thus are both skeptical of a
University, Alfred‐Herrhausen‐Str. 50, general substance able to explain existence and life. The first book is
58448 Witten, Germany. Bertalanffy's Critical Theory of Form Formation; the second, a small collection
Email: dirk.baecker@uni‐wh.de
of texts written by Nicholas von Cusa and preceded by an introduction by
Bertalanffy, which is as admiring of the Cardinal and Bishops diplomatic life
as it is impressed by his philosophy containing many ideas which only later,
and differently, became prominent by writers like Leibniz, Pascal, or Luther.
Von Bertalanffy calls von Cusa the first philosopher with a notion of infinity,
which proves to be pertinent both theologically and mathematically. The paper
discusses the problem of the individuality of individual living beings within the
context of the so‐called philosophy of organism, in which Plato is fascinated by
the question of how organisms manage to distinguish themselves from a sur-
rounding they at the same time depend on. The paper introduces Fritz Heider's
notion of medium and George Spencer‐Brown's notion of form to show how a
possible calculus of indications doubling as operations of reflexive negation
relate to a medium of life which consists, among other things, of decaying
forms of life.

KEYWORDS
form, life, medium, organism

1 | TWO EARLY BOOKS latter's interest in the individuality of individual things


and his interest in the alterity of the unity of any individ-
In 1928 Ludwig von Bertalanffy published two books, a ual thing. The “form” problem von Bertalanffy was after
Kritische Theorie der Formbildung (1928a) and a small col- is the problem of how to handle the question of negation
lection of texts by Cardinal and Bishop of Brixen Nicholas in living beings as well as in other entities which for
of Cusa, which he edited and preceded by an introduction instance in the sphere of meaning live a “life” of their
(1928b). This paper will look at a connection between own. The paper brings in Fritz Heider's (1959) notion of
those two books, which may shed some light on a prob- medium and George Spencer‐Brown's (1969) concept of
lem of theoretical biology, which von Bertalanffy pursued form to show that there are ways to follow up on von
in his later work yet formulated perhaps more radically in Bertalanffy's interest in von Cusa, which may even be
these early essays. The main idea is that von Bertalanffy's compatible with the idea of “open” systems being charac-
interest in von Cusa may well be triggered by both the terized by a steady state far from equilibrium.
Syst Res Behav Sci. 2019;36:1–10. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/sres © 2019 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. 1
2 BAECKER

2 | T H E I N D I VI D U A L I T Y O F not sufficient. There is something they adhere to, be it


LIVING BEINGS AND I NDIVIDUAL nothing more than their dependency on their interdepen-
THINGS dency. Their individual independence, important as it is,
can only be appreciated in the context of a dependency
The problem the two books of 1928 pose is the same. In whose status is unclear.
the Kritische Theorie der Formbildung, von Bertalanffy Let it be understood right from the beginning that von
confronts the “form problem” (1928a: 10) of life in the fol- Bertalanffy as well as von Cusa and Aristotle may well
lowing words: “We know the phenomenon of life only of refer to conditions of life, which since the nineteenth cen-
well‐individualized, more or less complicated natural tury were called “thermodynamic.” Living beings evi-
bodies with a certain shape, which we call ‘organisms’ dently consume energy in both material and immaterial
and which, of course, are extraordinarily different from form. But this is not the enigma all three of them and
one another: slime mold, amoeba, oak tree, fish, man” many others are reasoning about. Living beings owe their
(ibid.: 67; transl. DeepL). And from von Cusa he draws life to themselves while being dependent on energy they
the insight: “All our knowledge refers only to the individ- take up and release. How do they owe something to
ual things we see around us” (1928b: 17; transl. DeepL). themselves? This is von Bertalanffy's form problem.
The correlate of the latter thesis is: “There is no ‘living The concept of life von Bertalanffy was trying to come
substance’ in our experience, only living beings, organ- up with is not a generalization that would be guilty of the
isms” (1928a: 68; transl. DeepL). There is no life “as such” “fallacy of misplaced concreteness” (Whitehead, 1967:
apart from individual living beings. There is no possibility 51 f), but a generalization that identifies as the real prob-
to think about a more general structure explaining indi- lem of living beings their dependency as a prerequisite for
vidual living beings. The whole enigma of life resides in independency, and vice versa. The concept of life does not
those individual lives, and nowhere else. Yet, did anybody only describe the individual living beings in their isolated
at any time think differently? Has anybody at any time condition as self‐contained organisms, but at the same
been successful in delineating and proving a “substance” time as organisms in a self‐referential if not also self‐con-
of life? Is there nothing the noun of life could possibly taining exchange with other organisms and their environ-
refer to? ment. How is this exchange to be conceived of if it is not a
Von Bertalanffy may have been interested in von Cusa thermodynamic exchange but an exchange defining life,
because the position the latter assumes is not just that of taking order from order, as Ernst Schrödinger (1944)
a helpless positivist indicating, as a matter of fact, the evi- would have it, or order from noise, as von Foerster
dence of those individual living beings. For von Cusa (2003a) insinuated?
there is something more general than those individuals.
There is God's creation, of course. But this is not the prob-
lem. God's creation could well have been the creation of 3 | R HENISH H UM OR
nothing but individuals, being born and dying. There is
something else which cannot be reduced to any of those Von Cusa seems to follow two rather separate ideas when
individuals, let alone to all of them. As von Cusa's famous delving into questions of this kind, relating individuals to
sentence, quoted by von Bertalanffy, reads: “Ex omnibus a whole which shines in them. One is to express an over-
partibus relucet totum”; in all parts the whole shines whelming awe when considering the wholeness, great-
(1928b: 24). What is the status of this “whole”? What does ness, indeed infinity of God. And the other is to get God
it consists of? Surely, it is not just the aggregate of all indi- and his creation completely out of the way when trying
viduals, for how would this shine? Is it the emergent to explain anything proving itself before our very eyes.
“more” which, as Aristotle (Aristotle, 2002: 1041b) alleg- Being born near Trier in Germany not far from the
edly would have it, is more than the sum of the parts? Rhineland there is something peculiarly Rhenish in his
Aristotle, anyhow, was more interested in the question deep philosophical humour. God is way too infinite to
of what it is to be as it is (to ti ên einai; Metaphysics, be able to explain whatsoever. Calling God inconceivable
1029b ff), which may be read as a question relating more means to be able to call all the more attention to His liv-
to a possible self‐reference of being than to some external, ing creatures. Von Cusa even endows the individuals
transcendent, or substantial reference lending and with some participation in God, thus honouring Him
guaranteeing its existence. There is a whole which while all the same appreciating every one individual. Liv-
becomes almost visible—“it shines”—in any individual. ing beings are not parts of a whole, but the whole and the
The forms of life participate with this whole, just as the part as much as the general and the special, are unfolded
whole in a way participates in them. An additive and pos- from, and folded into, one another (von Kues, 1982b:
itive, let alone positivist, exploration of living beings is 47ff.).
BAECKER 3

Nothing is evident just as it is. It is not just scepticism developed much later by Louis Dumont in the context
von Cusa is interested in. It is trivial to say that the eyes of a theory of modern individualization (Dumont, 1983:
can be deceived, and the mind can err. Instead, there is 244f., omitted in Dumont, 1986): Here each individual is
something insensible which is not God but which must understood as an element of a not necessarily closed
be accounted for when trying to understand the individu- whole exactly in so far, as it can simultaneously set itself
ality of individual living beings. in opposition to this wholeness.
That comes very close to the thought that von Cusa
tries to think insisting, as it were, on the individuality of
4 | A P RO BL EM OF individual things. God permeating all individual things
PARTICIPAT I ON does not spare them their distinction from everything
else. The same goes for von Bertalanffy. All living being
Although the whole cannot be experienced by the mind sharing the feature of life does not spare them the need
(sensus) it is accessible for reason (ratio; von Kues, to produce and reproduce their life as a distinction from
1982a, 1982b). This is von Cusa's doctrine of ignorance. everything else. Individual things as individual living
One knows by admitting one's ignorance. One's igno- beings owe their existence to a primordial closure, a self.
rance is the first step toward relating one's self to some- Thus, the conundrum is how to conceive of a sharing
thing else one does not know but is dependent on. God which relies on distinction. Participation is von Cusa's
may know but He will not tell and it is blasphemy to concept, and participation becomes von Bertalanffy's idea
try to know what He may know. God is the inconceivable he tries to come to grips with.
infinity of the largest and the smallest at the same time Both von Bertalanffy and von Cusa are part of the tra-
(coincidentia oppositorum). Yet, there is something dition of a “philosophy of the organism,” which, accord-
beyond the individual. The individual is never left alone, ing to Alfred North Whitehead, was developed by Plato
as solitary as it may be. It has a life of its own consisting and ever since was continued by European philosophy
in some peculiar reliance on itself and the way this is as a series of “footnotes to Plato” (Whitehead, 1979,
dealt with. This is why von Bertalanffy speaks of a form 39f.). This philosophy deals with the problem of “partici-
problem of life. He cannot completely take the side of pation” (methexis) of the part in the whole, and the whole
the individual organisms but realizes that they are depen- in the part, without being able, and without having, to
dent on something beyond them. Rightly, however, he decide beforehand in which hierarchical relationship, if
rejects the assumption that this general has a real exis- at all, the one to the other stands. The form problem of
tence, whether as a platonic idea, a divine creation, or a life continues to fascinate even when no cosmos, God,
thermodynamic field miraculously bringing it about. Its nature, history, or reason is providing us with an address
infinity escapes any possible indication. Von Bertalanffy that idea of a whole may refer to. Instead, ecologies
may have been more interested in the mathematical incli- abound (Bateson, 1972), and problems of closure, fold,
nations of the notion of infinity than its theological ones. and boundary remain all of them sitting rather uneasily
Von Cusa develops a monadic doctrine that tries to with questions about the defining feature of a self.
view dependency and independency, the double fold of
the parts into the whole and of the whole into the parts,
as two sides of one coin. In a similar way Leibniz pro- 5 | PHYSICS, TELEOLOGY, A ND
posed to think of the relationship of the mutually closed DE SC E NDE NC E
monads to each other as a relationship of each individual
to the divine within and outside of it (Leibniz, 2014; cf. Von Bertalanffy's Kritische Theorie der Formbildung is
Serres, 1968). Jacob Böhme, Pascal, Luther, even Kant, “critical” in the sense that it renounces a formulated “the-
and Hegel will pursue that distinguished Gnostic and ory” of form formation. Instead, it provides an intensive
then Christian idea of conceiving of an individual self and dismissive examination of mechanistic and vitalistic
by first of all calling it empty with respect to God by explanations of life and discusses sympathizing efforts to
His inexhaustible mercy filling it (Jonas, 1958; Rossbach, develop a theory of biology, for example, by Hans
1996). A similar yet different thought fascinates von Driesch, Wilhelm Roux, and Jakob von Uexküll. And it
Bertalanffy in von Cusa: Infinity (of God or number) is provides “considerations” that can be related to the form
outside everything, inside everything, and permeating problem of life in the sense that although renouncing a
everything (von Bertalanffy, 1928b: 19). This idea goes substance of life, they trace the “immanent Gestalt princi-
beyond an empty self, and it is inconceivable vis‐à‐vis. It ple” of life (von Bertalanffy, 1928a: 221), that is, the
is a conjecture about a complex kind of relationship. If dependency of each individual living being on the solu-
anything, it is a doctrine of hierarchical opposition, as tion of the form problem. Any individual living being
4 BAECKER

must be able to solve the form problem of its life, just as self‐referential system, which, on the basis of “opera-
much as biology has to solve its form problem to become tional closure,” is preserved as a recursive sensory‐
a science and theoretical endeavour worthy of that name. motoric calculus of its own operations (von Foerster,
Three specific considerations are essential to von 2003b). Humberto R. Maturana and Francisco J. Varela
Bertalanffy (ibid.: 88): Each organism satisfies physical will develop the concept of “autopoiesis” on the basis of
and chemical conditions for the preservation of its life. a theory of self‐referential systems (Maturana & Varela,
Each organism is teleologically composed; that is, it seeks 1980), and already W. Ross Ashby, in his Introduction to
and sets itself goals which it pursues in different Cybernetics (Ashby, 1956: 4), speaks of “information‐
(“equifinal”) ways. And each organism is phylogeneti- tight” systems, which are “open to energy but closed to
cally and ontogenetically descending, that is, historically information and control.” It must be emphasized that clo-
determined. One immediately recognizes that these three sure, autopoiesis, and information‐tightness do not solve
conditions, which do not claim to be complete, are the form problem of life empirically, but axiomatically.
related to the form problem of life. Physics and chemistry They postulate self‐reference of systems on the basis of
can be found inside and outside the organism. The goals their ability to distinguish themselves from their environ-
of an organism are set internally but can only be realized ment and examine which empirical observations can be
externally. And also the history of an organism links it better explained by the means of this postulate than on
with itself and the conditions in which it has survived. the basis of other theories. We will have to look more
Note that the assumption of “teleology” does not refer closely at von Bertalanffy's concept of steady state to see
to a whole bounding of the organism to define its func- how it may contribute to the understanding and solution
tions and functioning but assumes instead that the organ- of the form problem.
ism must be able to orient itself towards goals and to
react to deviations from goals (Parsons, 1979;
Rosenblueth, Wiener, & Bigelow, 1943). In place of teleol-
ogy it might be better to speak of “teleonomy” to empha- 6 | A L T E R I T Y IN UN I T Y
size the internal rather than external functionality of
means and ends (Mayr, 1974). The telos is not given but Von Bertalanffy's interest in von Cusa may throw light on
must be sought, tested, and changed with respect to the some different idea, which avoids an axiomatic postulate
uncertainty itself of the relationship between organism of some boundary between system and environment yet
and environment. Teleonomy does not provide the organ- will prove as compatible with it as closure, autopoiesis,
ism with some higher kind of necessity but instead and and information‐tightness proved empirically fruitful.
quite to the contrary exposes it to all vicissitudes of its Consider again the individual being unfolded out, and
surroundings and its ideas and decisions to deal with folded into, the infinitely large and infinitely small. One
them. may think of Pascal's later idea of the “deux infinis,”
Von Bertalanffy is rightly skeptical about the possibil- the double infinity of the ever larger and ever smaller,
ity of already concluding from these specific consider- into which man is hooked in a precarious and fragile
ations, which are nothing but empirical observations of way (Pascal, 1954: 1105ff.). Yet, for von Cusa, it is not
circumstances and characteristics of life, that a theory of only the separation and interdependency of the individ-
Formbildung might already be possible. Completely lack- ual which is decisive but also the otherness, alterity of
ing are considerations, thoughts, or hypotheses on the each entity, which in the mode of negation, the nonpar-
question of boundary, that is, on the question of how ticipant, is responsible for the multiplicity of the individ-
the organism acquires and maintains the necessary indi- ual beings (von Kues, 1982b: 43f., 109 et seq.).
vidual independency despite its dependency on the cir- This alterity is presupposed as a condition not only of
cumstances of its life. No doubt the organism is the multiplicity of entities but also of the variety of the
participating. But what makes it securely distinct from unity they still participate in. Variety in unity will later
anything it is participating with? Bertalanffy will, in the be called complexity. Von Cusa makes sure that it already
further course of the development of his theory, speak applies to the symbolic archetype of all things, that is,
of the organism as an “open system” (von Bertalanffy, number: Each number consists of itself and of its differ-
1976), but it remains to be seen whether and how this ence to all other numbers. “Each number is composed
solution is compatible with the form problem. The ener- of opposites which differ from one another and are in
getic and material openness of the organism system does relation to one another, so that these are the number
not necessarily explain how this system simultaneously itself” (ibid.: 11). Only this inner contradiction, which
draws its own boundary, that is, realizes a closure. Heinz contains a reference to all other numbers, makes it a
von Foerster will therefore later describe the system as a number—and makes man, who is able to count, that is
BAECKER 5

to simultaneously divide and combine, a “spiritual” from, and in, it (stêresis). The term periechon for “sur-
being. rounding” in Thomas Aquina's Aristotle translation was
Von Bertalanffy's considerations lack this thought of rendered by the Latin word “medium,” so that in the
inner alterity. It may be part of the distinction of system English translation the relevant passage reads as follows:
from environment yet immediately is lost again in the “For sight takes place through an affection of the sensi-
concept of the open system. My question is therefore tive faculty. Now it cannot be affected by that which is
whether and how the idea of inner alterity contains a ref- seen, the colour itself: therefore it can only be the inter-
erence to a continuation and solution of the form prob- vening medium [periechon, DB]: hence the existence of
lem of life. There might be a necessary concept of form some medium is necessary. But, if the intermediate space
preceding any consideration of systems and their became a void, so far from being seen distinctly, an object
environments. would not be visible at all” (De anima, 419a). The invisi-
ble medium is absent and present at the same time. It
permeates entities, organisms, individuals, while not
7 | ANOTHER L OOK A T G REEK being absorbed by them. Ever since Aquina's translation,
PHILOSOPHY there is a media theory which is dated back to Aristotle
(Hagen, 2008), although, as Spitzer (1948) pointed out,
In more recent systems theory, as it is proposed in Niklas the terms milieu and ambiance, that is, environment,
Luhmann's theory of social systems, the idea of an inner could also have been used as a translation of periechon.
alterity if not an ability of negation inherent in individual This ambivalence of medium and environment is an
living being is taken up from the point of view of the dis- indication that the living being itself, the alterity in unity,
tinction between form and medium (Luhmann, 2012: has still not been sufficiently understood. The problem of
113ff). This distinction combines several thoughts already form is unsolved because the relationship between form
known from Greek philosophy. The first is the idea in and medium is just as unclear as that between system
Plato (Plato, 2000: 51d‐52b) that there is a third genre, and environment.
which is not being or becoming but “receiving” (chôra).
Then there is in Aristotle (Aristotle, 1907: 419a) the
thought of a surrounding (periechon), which cannot be 8 | THE STEADY STATE
experienced sensually itself, yet makes every sensual
experience possible. And last not least there is in Aristotle Let us take up another thought of von Bertalanffy to make
(Aristotle, 1984: 191a) the idea of an apparently produc- some progress here. In his later work he thinks of the
tive role of lack or privation (stêresis). All three thoughts organism as an open system in some steady state far from
embed the philosophy of the organism into the even more equilibrium, which tries to achieve its goals or telos
general question of whether and how philosophy and sci- (“appropriate place” in cosmos) with interchangeable
ence can be understood as endeavours to deal only with (equifinal) means (von Bertalanffy, 1976: 139–154). “Far
the positively present or rather must also reckon with from equilibrium” can be read as a form of stêresis, as a
what is absent (i.e., receiving, surrounding, and lacking negation of thermodynamic equilibrium or maximum
at the same time). Moreover, it is not just the absent in entropy, insofar as this negation is to be understood not
itself which attracts attention. Philosophy and science as antinomy or opposition, but as a reflexive, inclusive,
are not playing the game of curiosity towards hidden enti- and exclusive opposition (cf. Luhmann, 1975). Self‐organi-
ties. It is the absent negating the self‐evidence of what is zation, as emphasized again by Heinz von Foerster, is at
present, which is thought about. The absent, for instance, the same time self‐disorganization, that is, the gain of
becomes important when not only reality but also the material (negative entropy) from the consumption of mate-
potential (dynamis) of a living being is to be understood rial (entropy; von Foerster, 2003a; cf. Atlan, 1974). Von
(Heidegger, 1981). Because the absent by definition is Bertalanffy speaks of “import and export, building‐up
not to be grasped by the positively sensual mind, a theory and breaking‐down” of components and “the system
must use not just “identifying” but also “speculative” remains constant in composition” (von Bertalanffy, 1976:
assertions, as Hegel in his considerations on what scien- 142). The steady state is defined in terms of kinetics and
tific thinking is about put it (Hegel, 2018: 40). thermodynamics “generalized” to include open systems.
The interesting question is whether, and how, some- In his later as well as in his earlier work von
thing absent as well as receiving may not only in‐form Bertalanffy refers to physics as a model of science, which
but underlie any entity being present. It is something sur- is as exemplary in its mathematical rigor as it is insuffi-
rounding an entity, an organism, an individual such that cient in its restriction to closed systems. In biology as well
any life is dependent on it while distinguishing itself as sociology open systems are the rule. They export
6 BAECKER

entropy and import “free energy” or negentropy (ibid.: steady state is defined in physical terms (even if general-
41). The problem is that the distinction of open from ized physical terms) issues of negation seem far off. Von
closed systems in model and mathematics may appear Bertalanffy defines steady states by a general transport
sharper than in reality. Von Bertalanffy is very interested equation describing the variation of an element Qi as a dif-
in some kind of a taxonomy of systems, distinguishing ferential function of the velocity of its transport, T i, and
open from closed as well as real from conceptual and the rate of its production, Pi (von Bertalanffy, 1976: 126).
abstract systems, only to notice that these distinctions That does not help us. Yet, his explanation may help. He
are conceptual in turn and that there is no “reality” describes those two variables as variables of “temporal
beyond our reckoning for the “viability” of our construc- cross” and “longitudinal sections,” respectively (ibid.:
tions. As he emphasizes in his 1976 preface to the revised 127). And he adds a third dimension, which is that of
edition of General System Theory even the objects of our “periodic changes,” or oscillation (ibid.). It is striking to
everyday world “by no means are simply ‘given’ as sense see that he comes up with exactly those two dimensions
data or simple perceptions, but actually are construed by defining any systems theory since its conceptualization
an enormity of ‘mental’ factors ranging from gestalt in Auguste Comte's work (Comte, 1853: 75f), if not earlier.
dynamics and learning processes to linguistic and cul- Those two dimensions are those of differentiation in mat-
tural factors largely determining what we actually ‘see’ ter or fact and reproduction in time, misleadingly called
or perceive” (ibid.: xxi). “static” and “dynamic” by Comte. Actually, Comte's static
The same may apply to von Bertalanffy's distinction of is nothing else but a description of a “steady state” main-
open systems theory focusing on concepts like “interac- tained by a phenomenon by being both differentiated from
tion, transaction, organization, teleology, etc.” (ibid.: other phenomena, and related to, or, with some later term,
xxii), on one hand, from cybernetics entertaining con- embedded within those other phenomena. It is fascinating
cepts like communication, including information, feed- to see that both Parsons' AGIL scheme and Luhmann in
back, and control, on the other (ibid.: 21f.). It is as his reconsideration of Parsons' project hold on to just two
conceptual as any other distinction. Even though von axes (internal/external and instrumental/consummatory)
Bertalanffy misses Talcott Parsons' importance for a as defining the core problem of sociological theory
sociological theory of systems by just taking note of a (Luhmann, 1982; Parsons, 1977).
once widespread criticism of the latter's alleged “conser- Steady states are to be maintained by differentiation
vatism and conformism” in rather defending the “sys- and reproduction. And in order to be able to do this, they
tem” by “conceptually neglecting hence obstructing oscillate. They oscillate between a consideration of the sys-
social change” (ibid.: 196), he acknowledges a world of tem and its environment, and they oscillate between a con-
“symbols, values, social entities and cultures” (ibid.: sideration of present states and past or future states. It may
xxiif.) any conceptual apparatus of science would be a well be possible to call such oscillations alternations (e.g.,
part of and emphasizes the need not just for systems sci- Lotman & Uspensky, 1978). And alternations are nega-
ence and systems technology but also for systems philos- tions working as both operators and operands. It may, of
ophy including systems epistemology to deal with course, be easier to see that kind of “considerations” of sys-
conceptual questions far from being solved.1 tem and environment, and of present, past, and future, in
My question is whether the concept of steady states may symbolic social systems which are able to not only do their
offer means to think alterity in unity. In fact, because the operations but also reflect on them or regulate them. Yet,
this only emphasizes that the “attempt to introduce the
1
It would be a fascinating research project to try to embed von notion of negative magnitudes into world wisdom” (Kant,
Bertalanffy's “general system theory” within the “paradigm of the 1992) is a still unfinished one. I therefore switch to a math-
human condition,” which Parsons (1978) was developing in the same ematical notion of a negational operator which may turn
time when von Bertalanffy prepared the revised edition of the collection out to be helpful here.
of his papers in General System Theory. A self‐application of Parsons'
action theory and his AGIL scheme (any action having to come up,
and highly dynamically so, as I would say, with solutions to the four
functional prerequisites of adaptation, goal‐attainment, integration, 9 | F ORM AND M EDIUM
and latent‐pattern maintenance and conflict regulation) to various gen-
eral and specific system theories remains a work not even envisioned, as George Spencer‐Brown in his Laws of Form (2008) sug-
far as I know, to this day. Not just system theories but any theory would gested an understanding of a concept of form, which con-
have to be considered an “action,” which seeks its adaptation to some
ceives of inner alterity or negation as a relation to
physical, chemical, and technological environment, must muster organ-
isms and personalities aligning their “goals” with it, should be inte- anything outside the boundary separating the entity from
grated in some wider field of societal concerns, and would have to rely everything else. He speaks of the form as a two‐sided dis-
on some values if questioned about its legitimation. tinction that includes what it excludes, and is thus to be
BAECKER 7

understood as inner and outer opposites. This concept of as loosely coupled. For this, one needs (a) reflexive nega-
form organizes a calculus of indications, that is, a calcu- tion to treat each individual state as an alternative to
lus that operationally demonstrates and makes traceable other possible states, (b) a system that recursively derives
how a form is obtained and reproduced through indica- its operations from operations of the same system, and (c)
tions of its two sides in the mode of, first, a distinction with all this the self‐reference of the form that grasps its
between the two sides, and, then, the re‐entry of the dis- unity as alterity, or its “self‐identity” as “self‐diversity”
tinction into the form. An indication comes about by a in the sense of Whitehead (1979: xxii, 25f). One needs a
distinction “crossing” a boundary, which is produced by differential and certainly multivalued calculus that
that very operation. Considering the two sides of the dis- knows how to put every distinction (contexture) both
tinction means to “re‐enter” it into its very form. First‐ discontexturally and polycontexturally in relation to
order observation (a “cross”) becomes a second‐order other distinctions (contextures; Günther, 1979 and
observation (a form), thus watching inside its outside, 1972). The discontexture links the present to the absent,
indicating within the cross the very contingency of it. the actual to the potential, and, via negation, the current
The form, as emphasized by Spencer‐Brown, is not only distinction to an alternate one. It is an empirical question
memory of itself but also oscillation between the two which discontextures an organism or, for that matter, an
sides of the distinction (Spencer‐Brown, 2008: 50). It is action or communication have at their disposal. And it is
itself and its negation. Von Cusa might have enjoyed that an open question how a calculus of multi‐negational
idea and the calculus ensuing from it. polycontexturality may be able to conceive of, and
We may call anything a reflexive negation, set about describe, if at all, an ecology of life, action, and
by inner alterity, which is referring to the “medium” of communication.
a form. Medium, with Fritz Heider (1959), is the loose The precondition for any solution of the form problem
coupling of elements, and a form—Heider spoke of is the operation of an operator of general (in contrast to
“things”—brings those elements into a rigid or tight cou- binary) negation, which is able to memorize itself while
pling. A medium is not exactly the milieu, niche, or envi- oscillating between its two sides (Luhmann, 1997).
ronment of a form; rather it is an open, or endless, set of
alternative ways to realize a form. It may thus refer to
“homeostasis” (Cannon, 1929) as much as to “adapta- 10 | A C AL C UL US
tion” (Ashby, 1962). One might also think of Ludwig
Wittgenstein's (1953) concept of “life form” as a way to Using Spencer‐Brown's (1969) notation of his calculus of
describe the production of a life by conducting it and indications, we may call a any individual thing or living
exploring its possibilities within the surroundings it is organism. Without exactly knowing how it comes about
dependent on, yet is also received by. we know that it must distinguish itself, that is, cross the
Heider conceives of the medium very similar to boundary between nonexistence and existence:
Aristotle's idea of periechon as a set of loosely coupled ele-
ments or events (light waves and sound waves) that can-
not be experienced by the senses themselves, yet enable a
distant perception to be achieved by proximal causality. Within the form of a the cross is at the same time a
We do not see the excitation of the photons on our retina, general, that is, nonbinary, negational operator
but the image on the wall. Niklas Luhmann has expanded distinguishing a from, say, b:
and generalized this idea for the examples of the medium
of language, of distribution media of communication
(writing, book printing, and electronic media), and of
success media of communication (money, power, love,
truth, law, and art; Luhmann, 2012: 113–120). Here, This means that b, within the two‐sided form of dis-
too, what von Bertalanffy said for living beings and von tinction, takes part in the definition, or, better, determi-
Cusa said for individual things applies. There is no sub- nation of a. The unity of the form of a resided in its
stance of writing, printing, money, power, and so on, distinction from b:
but only texts, books, payments, orders, and so on, which
one can understand and describe with Heider as things or
forms in their medium.
The distinction between form and medium solves the
problem of form insofar as the form is a rigid coupling This expression is called the re‐entry of the distinction
of those elements, which are provided by the medium (between a and b) into the form (of a). Such a re‐entry,
8 BAECKER

being not just categorical (in watching the form) but varied. Without the incorporation of reflexive negation
operational (in bringing it forth) in cybernetics, may be into the units under consideration, this task cannot be
called closure. Note that it autopoetically produces its solved. I would assume that this was one of the reasons
own elements out of its own form once it comes about. von Bertalanffy was interested in von Cusa. And yet, his
Note as well that it is informationally tight while at the theory of open systems exactly avoids to ask the two deci-
same time containing, within the form, the unmarked sive questions of self‐reference and negation. There might
state on the outside of the form. Any re‐entry is distin- be reason enough to think “openness” in terms of closure.
guished itself from some further state, which remains Maybe, the distinction between form and medium and
unmarked as long as the form succeeds in (re)producing, a concept of a two‐sided form operating at its own reflex-
yet may be marked, say by c, to indicate it, thus moving ive negation do not solve Bertalanffy's form problem
the unmarked state one position further to the right. either. But they help to identify it a little better. Any tran-
The form, thus, elegantly contains von Cusa's infinity, scendence towards a whole gets dissolved into an alto-
or else, an indefinite (Jung, 2007: 258ff) indication of fur- gether empirical, yet not exactly positivist, reference to
ther elements qualifying as a possible or potential media providing the necessary elements to any form.
medium for (re)production.The form of a may also be And the individuality of individual things and living
called a Günther contexture. It determines a closure pos- beings resides in their ability to self‐negate in a way
sibly (re)producing. It is a discontexture as well, since b which relates their reproduction to an environment they
implying, by negating, a further c: have to be able to rely on and to withdraw from. The
unity of the difference of these two ideas consists in a
concept of life, or, for that matter, action and communi-
cation, which by producing and reproducing itself brings
forth the decay it is feeding on. Folded out of, and folded
may lead to another contexture: into, its debris life maintains itself. If that sounds too pes-
simistic, or even defeatist, one forgets the creativity of
negation bringing forth a new and splendid form.

letting a disappear. 12 | C ON C L US I ON
The procedure may be iterated at will without know-
ing whether moving within some hierarchy establishing The form problem of life cannot be solved. It can only be
itself or a heterarchy constantly coming up with new accounted for. It can be taken seriously in terms not of a
and interesting inconsistencies (McCulloch, 1989). whole and its parts nor of a general and its particulars but
Any third value, such as c, is called by Günther a rejec- in terms of a generic mechanism of closure. This closure
tion value oscillating, since negational as well, between produces a system which presupposes an environment it
rejection and acceptance the former distinction between can be distinguished, and distinguishes itself, from. This
a and b. A multinegational calculus of polycontexturality distinction is to be thought of as a general negator. By
consists of crosses and re‐entries producing, separating, negating, that is, reflecting, its environment the system
and linking contextures which all of them have two turns the environment into the medium of its reproduc-
binary values yet include a third embedding them within tion. The system becomes form, featuring an inside, an
a nexus of contextures calling on each other and standing outside, and a boundary linking both sides.
orthogonal to each other without, to this day, a way to Or else, by reading Aristotle's and Plato's, von Cusa's
write them down. and von Bertalanffy's, Heider's and Spencer‐Brown's,
and Parsons' and Luhmann's reflections on the paradox
of closure the paper opts for an understanding of entities,
1 1 | NECESSARY DECAY beings, and systems as operations in time. Systems and
environments, forms, and media are operational terms
Is there still a connection of this formulation to von describing both a space of possibilities they generate
Bertalanffy and his interest in Nicholas von Cusa? “Self‐ and a mode of reproduction which consists in relying
reference,” Kauffman (1987: 54) says, “is the infinite in on a self that is nothing but recursion, forward and back-
finite guise.” We are faced with the task of a form theory ward, between its operations.
of polycontexturality, that is, the question of what distinc- Is there a general lesson to be learned from the differ-
tion organisms, but also action and communication, use ent languages pursued to deal with the paradox of the
to create a contexture that can both be maintained and organism's closure? Perhaps, it is nothing more than once
BAECKER 9

again to emphasize the need to step from a substantial to Heider, F. (1959). Thing and medium. In idem, On Perception, Event
a functional description of living beings and other com- Structure, and Psychological Environment. Selected Papers. Psy-
plex entities (Cassirer, 2003). The form problem of life chological Issues, 1(3), 1–34.

cannot be solved because there is no other solution but Jonas, H. (1958). The Gnostic religion: The message of the Alien God
and the beginnings of Christianity. Beacon Hill/Boston: Beacon
the problem itself. Whatever the substance of life, its
Press.
reproduction is a function of itself referring it to anything
Jung, R 2007. Experience and action: Selected items in systems the-
else.
ory. Wien: Ed. Echoraum.
Translated with some help by DeepL (https://www.
Kant, I. (1992). Attempt to introduce the notion of negative magni-
deepl.com/translator).
tudes into philosophy (1763). In D. Walford (Ed.), Theoretical
philosophy, 1755–1770 (pp. 203–206). Cambridge: Cambridge
R EF E RE N C E S UP.
Kauffman, L. H. (1987). Self‐reference and recursive forms. Journal
Aristotle (1907). De Anima, transl. In Introd. and notes RD Hicks. of Social and Biological Structures: Studies in Human Sociobiol-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ogy, 10(1), 53–72. https://doi.org/10.1016/0140‐1750(87)90034‐0
Aristotle (1984). Physics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works Leibniz, G. W. (2014). In L. Strickland (Ed.), Leibniz's monadology:
(Vol. 2). Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP. A new translation and guide, transl. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP.
Aristotle (2002). Metaphysics, transl. In J. Sachs (Ed.), (2nd ed.). Lotman, Y., & Uspensky, B. A. (1978). On the semiotic mechanism
Santa Fe, NM: Green Lion. of culture. New Literary History, 9, 211–232. https://doi.org/
Ashby, W. R. (1956). An introduction to cybernetics. London: Wiley. 10.2307/468571
https://doi.org/10.5962/bhl.title.5851 Luhmann, N. (1975). Über die Funktion der Negation in
Ashby, W. R. (1962). Design for a brain: The origin of adaptive sinnkonstituierenden Systemen. In Positionen der Negativität.
behavior (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley. Poetik und Hermeneutik (Ed.), H Weinrich (Vol. VI) (pp.
201–218). München: Fink.
Atlan, H. (1974). On a formal definition of organization. Journal of
Luhmann, N. (1982). Talcott Parsons: The future of a theory. In S.
Theoretical Biology, 45, 295–304. https://doi.org/10.1016/0022‐
Holmes, & C. Larmore (Eds.), idem, The differentiation of society,
5193(74)90115‐5
transl (pp. 47–68). New York: Columbia UP.
Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind (Vol. 2000). New
Luhmann, N. (1997). The control of intransparency. Systems
York: Ballantine, Reprint Chicago: Chicago UP.
Research and Behavioral Science, 14(6), 359–371. https://doi.
Cannon, W. B. (1929). Organization for physiological homeostasis. org/10.1002/(SICI)1099‐1743(199711/12)14:6<359::AID‐
Physiological Reviews, 9(3), 399–431. https://doi.org/10.1152/ SRES160>3.0.CO;2‐R
physrev.1929.9.3.399 Luhmann, N. (2012). In R. Barrett (Ed.), Theory of society, transl
Cassirer, E. (2003). In W. C. Swabey, & M. C. Swabey (Eds.), (Vol. 1). Stanford, CA: Stanford UP.
reprintSubstance and function, and Einstein's theory of relativity, Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition:
transl. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications. The realization of the living. Dordrecht: Reidel. https://doi.org/
Comte, A. (1853). The positive philosophy. In H. Martineau (Ed.), 10.1007/978‐94‐009‐8947‐4
(Vol. 2). NewYork: Calvin Blanchard, Reprint Cambridge, MA: Mayr, E. (1974). Teleological and teleonomic: A new analysis. In R.
Cambridge UP. 2009 S. Cohen, & M. W. Wartofsky (Eds.), Methodological and histor-
Dumont, L. (1983). Essais sur l'individualisme: Une perspective ical essays in the natural and social science (Boston studies in the
anthropologique sur l'idéologie modern. Paris: Seuil. philosophy of science, vol. XIV) (pp. 91–117). Dordrecht: Reidel.
McCulloch, W. S. (1989). A heterarchy of values determined by the
Dumont, L. (1986). Essays on individualism: Modern ideology in
topology of nervous nets. In idem, Embodiments of mind, 2nd
anthropological perspective. Chicago: Chicago UP.
printing (pp. 40–45). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Günther, G 1972. A new approach to the logical theory of living sys-
Parsons, T. (1977). Some problems of general theory in sociology. In
tems. Unpubl. Ms., online https://www.vordenker.de/
Idem, Social systems and the evolution of action theory (pp.
ggphilosophy/gg_new_approach.pdf.
229–269). New York: Free Press.
Günther, G. (1979). Life as poly‐contexturality. In idem, Beiträge zur Parsons, T. (1978). A paradigm of the human condition. In Idem,
Grundlegung einer operationsfähigen Dialektik (Vol. 2) (pp. Action theory and the human condition (pp. 352–433). New
283–306). Hamburg: Meiner. York: Free Press.
Hagen, W. (2008). Metaxy: Eine historiosemantische Fußnote zum Parsons, T. (1979). Concrete systems and “abstracted” systems: Liv-
Medienbegriff. In S. Münker, & A. Roesler (Eds.), Was ist ein ing systems by James Grier Miller, a review. Contemporary
Medium? (pp. 13–29). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Sociology, 8(5), 696–705. https://doi.org/10.2307/2065421
Hegel, G. W. F. (2018). In T. Pinkard (Ed.), The phenomenology of Pascal, B. (1954). Pensées. Œuvres complètes, ed. J Chevalier (pp.
spirit. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 1079–1345). Paris: Gallimard.
Heidegger, M. (1981). Aristoteles, Metaphysik Theta 1–3: Von Wesen Plato (2000). In D. J. Zeyl (Ed.), Timaeus, transl. Indianapolis, IN:
und Wirklichkeit der Kraft. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. Hackett Publ.
10 BAECKER

Rosenblueth, A., Wiener, N., & Bigelow, J. (1943). Behavior, pur- von Foerster, H. (2003b). On constructing a reality. In Idem, Under-
pose and tTeleology. Philosophy of Science, 10(1), 18–24. standing understanding: Essays on cybernetics and cognition (pp.
https://doi.org/10.1086/286788 211–227). New York: Springer.
Rossbach, S. (1996). Gnosis, science, and mysticism: A history of von Kues, N. (1982a). De docta ignorantia/Die wissende
self‐referential theory designs. Social Science Information, Unwissenheit. In L. Gabriel (Ed.), idem, Philosophisch‐
35(2), 233–255. https://doi.org/10.1177/053901896035002004 Theologische Schriften (Vol. I) (pp. 191–297). Wien: Herder.
Schrödinger, E. (1944). What is life? Cambridge: Cambridge UP. von Kues, N. (1982b). De coniecturis/Die Mut‐maßungen. In L.
Serres, M. (1968). La communication substantielle démontrée more Gabriel (Ed.), idem, Philosophisch‐Theologische Schriften (Vol.
mathematico. In idem, Hermès I: La communication (pp. II) (pp. 1–209). Wien: Herder.
154–164). Paris: Seuil. Whitehead, A. N. (1967). Science and the modern world: Lowell lec-
Spencer‐Brown, G. (2008). Laws of form (5th ed.). Leipzig: tures, 1925. New York: Free Press.
Bohmeier. Whitehead, A. N. (1979). Process and reality: An essay in cosmology,
Spitzer, L. (1948). Milieu and ambiance. In Idem, Essays in histori- eds. In DR Griffin and DW Sherburne. New York: Free Press.
cal semantics (pp. 179–316). New York: S. F. Vanni. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations, transl. GEM
von Bertalanffy, L. (1928a). Kritische Theorie der Formbildung. Ber- Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.
lin: Verlag von Gebrüder Borntraeger.
von Bertalanffy, L. (1928b). Einleitung. In N. von Kues (Ed.), in:
idem (pp. 5–28). München: Georg Müller.
How to cite this article: Baecker D. A note on
von Bertalanffy, L. (1976). General system theory: Foundations,
Ludwig von Bertalanffy and the form problem of
developments, applications, rev. New York: Braziller.
life. Syst Res Behav Sci. 2019;1–10. https://doi.org/
von Foerster, H. (2003a). On self‐organizing systems and their envi-
ronments. In idem, Understanding understanding: Essays on
10.1002/sres.2597
cybernetics and cognition (pp. 1–20). New York: Springer.

You might also like