Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

KALLE PUOLAKKA

Public Art and Dewey’s Democratic Experience: The


Case of John Adams’s On the Transmigration of Souls

abstract
The aesthetic and political sides of public art have recently been examined from different theoretical vantage points. Pragmatist
accounts, however, have been largely absent from the discussion. This article develops a theory of public art on some central
ideas of John Dewey’s aesthetics and social philosophy. From a pragmatist perspective, the best cases of public art turn out to
have high social significance, for they are means of promoting the sense of community, which Dewey saw as foundational for
well-functioning democracies. The Deweyan account of public art developed in this article is set against theories that explain
its social value by public artworks’ ability to disrupt people’s everyday routines and beliefs, as well as by the political alertness
they often raise. Diana Boros’s recent treatment of what she calls “visionary public art” serves as the main specimen of this
approach. The Deweyan understanding of public art is illuminated and defended with the help of a reading of John Adams’s
On the Transmigration of Souls—a piece composed in memory of the victims of 9/11—that highlights its capacity to generate
such communal experiences that have a fundamental role in Dewey’s theory of democracy.

i. introduction Bamiyan Buddhas (Hein 2006, 50), or even


further back.
Public art is a somewhat fluid term that has been It is easy to associate public art simply with art
invented only recently, and there have been far that is located in public places, such as parks and
fewer serious attempts to define it than has been squares. This definition, however, is simplistic
the case in defining the concept of art itself. Some and misses some important aspects concerning
points of emphasis, however, do run through what makes some art genuinely public. Hilde
the relevant literature. One such point is that Hein makes an illuminating distinction between
public art is not solely an aesthetic phenomenon, “public art” and “art in public places” (Hein 2006,
but has an ulterior purpose beyond eliciting 53). In her view, the place of exhibition or the
an aesthetic reaction valued for its own sake fact that a great number of people are exposed
(Carroll 2005, Knight 2014). Typically, this extra to an artwork on a daily basis are not essential
aesthetic element has been thought to be of a features of public art. What makes a work public
social character, ranging from commemoration is a specific kind of relationship between the
to celebration (Hein 2006, 50). Yet despite its artwork and the audience. Its audience does not
short history as a concept, some scholars have consist of some indeterminate generic group of
considered public art a much older phenomenon unrelated individuals. Instead public art “sets
than art itself. It not only encompasses the recent out to forge a specific public by means of an
happenings and environmental works erected in aesthetic interaction” (Hein 2006, 49). True public
public spaces and buildings, like those of Christo, artworks draw in the audience in a particular
but its earliest examples have been traced back way, collecting people together, almost like “a
to Roman monumental sculpture (Boros 2012, congregation” (Hein 2006, 49). This does not
91–95; Knight 2014, 313), the now destroyed necessarily mean that the work would address
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 74:4 Fall 2016

C 2016 The American Society for Aesthetics
372 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

a specific group, but that the collectivity of the an aesthetic naturalism which regards art as an
experience would be built in to its reception. “extension of the power of rites and ceremonies
This aspect is absent from the experience of to unite men, through a shared celebration, to all
what Hein calls “private art,” such as traditional incidents and scenes of life” (Dewey 1980a, 271).
painting or symphonic music, which elicits “an But if social aspects are an important part
intimate exchange” between artist and recipient of Dewey’s aesthetic philosophy, his social
(2006, 49). In the case of public artworks, the fact philosophy, in turn, includes strong aesthetic
that the work is intended to gather together the undercurrents, especially in his reflections on
public to reflect on an issue of common concern democracy. For Dewey, the right to vote at certain
by means of an aesthetic interaction is a consti- intervals captures only part of the idea of democ-
tutive part of the experience. Not all artworks racy. Democracy does not merely refer to an
exhibited in public places embody this type of abstract principle governing the relationship be-
relationship to their audience, and their social tween citizens and those in power, but what holds
content is, consequently, thinner as well. Some democratic societies together and guarantees
may have a merely decorative function, while their well-being has more to do with how people
the representational and expressive contents of interact and communicate with one another, as
many artworks situated in public places may well as with the sense of community reigning
lack the communal aspects Hein sees essential between them. Dewey, thereby, promotes an
to public art, hence not qualifying as public art experientialist notion of democracy, and the
in her sense of the term. Henry Moore’s massive interactions of societies and communities that
Reclining Figure at New York’s Lincoln Center is live up to Deweyan democratic ideals involve
one example of this type of art. Following Hein’s features that Dewey sees as aesthetic.3
analysis, it is possible to see some paintings as Though these aspects of Dewey’s work are im-
public artworks as well. Picasso’s Guernica, for portant considerations in the philosophical and
example, seems like a potential candidate for such aesthetic questions related to public art, his more
a status. The painting is a response to a major explicit reflections on the topic are very scarce,
historical event (as public artworks usually are): being basically limited to a grieving over the “ter-
the Spanish Civil War. Its experience arguably has rible civil-war monuments” and “municipal stat-
a powerful collective sphere; the painting in a way uaries” of his country (Dewey 1980a, 206). Nei-
pleads to the audience as a collective and attempts ther have contemporary pragmatist aestheticians,
to draw people together, if only on an imaginative such as Richard Shusterman, taken up the issue
level, to reflect on the absurdity of war.1 extensively.4 The primary purpose of this article
The social value of public art and how the aes- is to develop a pragmatist account of the function
thetic and the social come together in public art- and value of public art based on some fundamen-
works has increasingly come under the spotlight tal elements of Dewey’s aesthetics and social phi-
in different traditions of aesthetics.2 One voice losophy and to show its significance for the cur-
that has been largely absent from the discussion, rent discussion on the aesthetic and social sides
however, is that of pragmatist aesthetics. This is of public art. As an alternative approach, I intro-
surprising, given the central place that the em- duce Diana Boros’s recent defense of what she
phasis on social aspects of art and other aesthetic terms “visionary public art.” From the views on
phenomena has had in this tradition. This aspect offer in contemporary aesthetics and art theory,
can be seen, for example, in a vital stage of John I have chosen to discuss hers for two reasons: it
Dewey’s well-known critique of the “museum con- includes a very systematic defense of a particular
ception of art,” which argues that the concept of type of aesthetic theory as the best background
art bears no essential connection to the modern in- for explaining the social value of public art, and
stitutions of art. In order to show that the origins her understanding differs in decisive ways from
of art and of the aesthetic lie elsewhere, Dewey the ideas I draw from pragmatism in the article.
refers to different cultures in which the arts are Boros’s theory is thus an ideal test case for the
considered essential parts of “the significant life pragmatist account of public art’s function that I
of an organized community,” as well as “the rites develop.
and ceremonies” that bring the members of the The distinctions present in Hein’s analysis—
community together (Dewey 1980a, 7). He posits public art versus art in public places, public art
Puolakka Public Art and Dewey’s Democratic Experience 373

versus private art—will not be further examined participation. The health of a democratic system,
in depth in this article, nor will I provide any more however, is founded on a more participatory
specific definition of public art based on Hein’s idea of citizen involvement, to which such an
work. This article is primarily about the function autopilot-like attitude toward public issues poses
and value of public art, not its definition, and a threat. In other words, democracy makes
the distinctions Hein puts forward are compati- possible an attitude which ultimately is in danger
ble with the different positions on the value of of undermining its foundation (Boros 2012, 2–3).
public art examined below. The primary role of Boros sees public art as one possible remedy for
the aforementioned distinctions in the article is the inactivity threatening democracy, since it can
that, in showing how misconceived it is to identify create a setting for increasing people’s awareness
public art simply with the works situated in public of their society’s problems as well as inspire them
places, they help to see its major case example, to initiate change. She writes: “Art that is housed
John Adams’s memorial piece for the victims of and experienced in our public spaces presents a
9/11, On the Transmigration of Souls (2002), as great opportunity—it can freely access the public
a public artwork.5 Many of the Deweyan ideas I at large, in the midst of their daily lives, and put
introduce below emerge from my interpretation before them, or involve them, in challenging ac-
of this work. It might seem counterintuitive to tivities and dialogues” (Boros 2012, 95). Not all
give a key role to a musical work in an article on types of public art, however, exemplify the qual-
public art, especially one that is intended to be ities Boros seeks in politically revitalizing public
performed in a concert hall, and not in an outdoor art. It has to shake people’s everyday routines and
public place that intersects with people’s everyday to encourage “new ways of feeling and thinking
lives. However, as my Deweyan reading shows, On about that with which [they] are already familiar”
the Transmigration is characterized by a relation- (Boros 2012, 81). In short, to be politically activat-
ship between work and audience similar to that ing, public art has to be “visionary.”
which Hein claims is essential to public art. The In her book Creative Rebellion, Boros presents
public character of On the Transmigration has al- numerous powerful descriptions of visionary pub-
ready been emphasized in the piece’s reception lic art and the galvanized experiences she believes
(Schiff 2006, 193), and one critic places it among it can generate. She even regards visionary public
Adams’s “public pieces” (Rich 2006, 64). My in- art as a means of recreating in a contemporary
terpretation gives further insight into the public context the powerful Dionysian rites Nietzsche
dimensions of the work as well as illuminating the describes in his book The Birth of Tragedy. Along
primary question of the article, which is the value with Nietzsche, other important background the-
of public art. orists to her account include Albert Camus,
Marquis de Sade, and Herbert Marcuse. Boros
says these theorists all emphasize the rebellious
ii. diana boros on the political significance of potential of artworks and see art and the aesthetic
public art as potential sources of social transformation. Vi-
sionary art, in other words, “has to excite people
Boros’s view on the social value of public art and encourage them to be critical” as well as “em-
stems from her highly pessimistic assessment of power the individual and motivate their desire
the current state of American democracy. In her to participate and create change in the public”
view, democracy is threatened by people’s in- (Boros 2012, 72). While Boros’s favorite exam-
creasing lack of interest in public affairs as well as ples of visionary public art are performances and
by their unwillingness to take part in its processes, happenings in public spaces that direct attention
all of which has an effect on the state of their to social problems like homelessness, she also in-
society and community. Boros considers this an cludes permanent sculptures within this category
example of what in political theory is called “the (Boros 2012, 156). A work of performance art ex-
free-rider problem,” which points to a paradox ecuted by Filip Noterdaeme in the Bowery in the
inherent in democracy that makes it possible for Lower East Side of Manhattan in 2008, included
citizens to leave deliberation on public issues in in Boros’s large collection of examples (2012, 144–
the hands of the people who have been voted into 145), illuminates her concept of visionary public
office. Things get done even without direct citizen art. The performance centered around a wooden
374 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

booth which the artist had named “The Home- example, unity, order, development, and closing
less Museum of Art.” The booth also included the fulfillment—in the disruptive terminology with
ironic tag “The director is IN.” The goal of the which Boros characterizes visionary public art and
performance was to get passersby to stop and dis- its experience. The qualities Nietzsche attributes
cuss with “the director” played by Noterdaeme. to the Dionysian rituals are also very different
What Boros thinks is significant in this work is from the qualities appearing in Dewey’s analysis
its location in the vicinity of the New Museum of aesthetic experience.
of Contemporary Art and the long-serving home- Despite these differences, I argue that Dewey’s
less shelter, the Bowery Mission. The impressive aesthetic theory forms a promising framework for
new building of the museum opened in the begin- explaining the social value of public artworks and
ning of the century radically changed the urban that pragmatism as a whole can even be consid-
scene of the area as well as made it more middle ered the preferable option. The interpretation of
class and brought commercial interests more in- Adams’s On the Transmigration, articulating its
tently into its development. With his performance Deweyan aspects, will be a cornerstone of my ar-
Noterdaeme wanted to make people realize how gument. What in particular it seeks to show is that
difficult it is for places like the Bowery Mission the sense of communality that Dewey sees as the
to survive under the pressure of this sort of devel- bedrock of well-functioning democracies is an es-
opment. The discussions with the director were sential feature of the artwork’s proper experience.
precisely intended to raise peoples’ awareness of The work’s capacity to create this sort of expe-
the different worlds that met in the Bowery at the rience forms the core of its public character and
time. value. But Adams’s role in the article is not limited
The contrast between visionary and “main- to this particular piece of music. Also of impor-
stream” or “plastic” public art forms an important tance are his reflections on the elitist character of
part of Boros’s investigation into the revolu- modernist music. In the later parts of the article, I
tionary potential of public art. While visionary combine them with Richard Shusterman’s critique
public art “challenges the overarching status quo of modernist aesthetics. Together they reveal
understanding of how we live and relate to society, that Boros’s analysis of visionary public art con-
by provoking deeper individual engagement with tains some problematic assumptions concerning
the world,” works belonging to mainstream art aesthetic experience and the power of art.
are “supportive, of both the content and form that
defines the boundaries of our daily existence, and
enables us . . . to delay or even entirely avoid, a iii. early fears and the shaping of on the
truly independent critical examination of how and transmigration
why mechanisms in our lives function as they do”
(2012, 121). Boros singles out Ancient Roman John Adams occupies a unique position in con-
sculpture, whose purpose was to impress upon temporary classical music, for he has combined the
its citizens a sense of imperial power in the midst seemingly irreconcilable achievements of being
of their everyday lives, as a notable example of highly acknowledged by critics and having a large
plastic art (2012, 91–95). Contemporary examples group of fans among the general classical music
of this type of public art, in turn, represent for public. Given his reputation as a vivid portrayer
her a hopeless and even questionable attempt to of the American way of life through his music,
create harmony and order in a disordered and it is no surprise that the New York Philharmonic
fractured world. Orchestra commissioned Adams to compose a
From the point of view of pragmatist aesthet- work to commemorate the victims of 9/11. At
ics, Boros’s analysis sees the political and social first, Adams was reluctant to accept, saying he
challenges that contemporary America is facing had “difficulty in imagining anything ‘commemo-
as the very same ones that troubled Dewey in rating’ 9/11 that would not be an embarrassment”
his views on democracy: how to make democracy (Adams 2008, 263). After realizing that, despite
more participatory (2012, 54). Yet, the two differ its rich past, America had not produced a musical
widely as to how art and other aesthetic phenom- work “that could satisfy the need for collective
ena could promote this goal. There is no room emotional experience that a seriously traumatized
for the core concepts of Deweyan aesthetics—for public maintained in those jarring days after the
Puolakka Public Art and Dewey’s Democratic Experience 375

attack” (Adams 2008, 262), he decided to take up the Transmigration was premiered in New York at
the challenge even though he had no clear picture Avery Fisher Hall on the 19th of September 2002.
of the final composition. The only thing he was
sure about at this stage was that he would in every iv. recollection and on the transmigration as
way try to avoid writing a piece that “yanked or public art
tugged the heartstrings” (Colvard 2006, 197).
After a period of research, Adams became Even though on the face of it On the Transmigra-
inspired by the idea of incorporating pieces of tion does not bear the obvious marks of a work of
text into the work that victims’ loved ones had left public art, it nevertheless has a communal dimen-
at Ground Zero, giving vital details of the missing sion that makes it as rightful a member of this
person and which usually concluded with a per- category as some of its more traditional examples.
sonal note to them. Here is one example: “Louis In fact, On the Transmigration can be seen to
Anthony Williams. One World Trade Center. belong to the growing number of public artworks
Port Authority, 66th Floor. ‘We love you, Louis. that take healing and consoling, instead of the
Come home.’” Adams found similar material glorification of the events or figures portrayed, as
from among the short obituaries dedicated to the their extra-aesthetic goal (Hein 2006, 94–95).
victims that appeared in the “Portraits in Grief” On the Transmigration has been fittingly called
section in The New York Times. An obituary of a a “musical memorial” (Schmidt 2010), along with
young man that Adams included goes as follows: pieces such as Arnold Schönberg’s A Survivor
“He was tall, extremely good-looking, and girls from Warsaw. Noël Carroll’s (2005) close exami-
never talked to me when he was around.” For nation of the effectual mechanism of memorial art
Adams, these personal reminiscences were not proves illuminating in this context. He posits that
mere textual fragments, but “emotionally charged besides their aesthetic intentions, it is equally im-
cues that stood for larger, longer personal narra- portant that memorial artworks serve as vehicles
tives that one could never completely know but of recollection. In other words, memorial artworks
might imagine” (Adams 2008, 264). The choral seek “to commemorate the past for the present—
parts of the work are put together mainly from to recall to mind exemplary events and persons
these personal reminiscences, while the contents and to limn their significance to the ongoing cul-
of the notes left at Ground Zero are mostly ture” (Carroll 2005, 5). He says that in many cases
recorded on tape. Adams believed that with the memorial art performs this recollective function
help of these very personal texts he could create a “exceedingly well,” and in some cases “the [social]
work which would not make the piece an embar- functions performed by memorial art at least ri-
rassment and would instead give it a very specific vals and arguably surpasses the aesthetic function
tone that would set it apart from the appalling way of art” (Carroll 2005, 5–6). What makes memo-
he thought that parts of the mass media had dealt rial art into a powerful medium of recollection, he
with the attack. Adams writes: “I decided that the continues, is that it addresses not just perception,
only way to approach this theme [of 9/11] was to but “imagination, memory, emotions, and cogni-
make it about the most intimate experiences of tion” (Carroll 2005, 6). This is precisely what in my
the people involved” (Adams 2008, 264). view takes place in the case of On the Transmigra-
A taped, mantra-like recitation of the victims’ tion, and the way it engages the listener largely
names forms another important element of the explains its social value.
work. The piece begins with sounds of street Because it includes powerful extra-musical
noise—cars accelerating, brakes squealing, fleet- elements, Adams—instead of describing On the
ing laughter, shoes scuffling, sounds of distant Transmigration as a musical work—has called it “a
sirens—recorded by the composer in New York memory space,” where “you can go and be alone
at nighttime. Then, a young boy is heard recit- with your thoughts and emotions” (Tommasini
ing on tape the words “missing, missing,” giving 2006, 365), a kind of cathedral, for he found
the piece “a verbal heartbeat” (Schiff 2006, 194). the atmosphere reigning inside great cathedrals
The work also includes a veil-like orchestral ele- deeply moving and inspiring. Adams explains:
ment. Apart from a few climaxes, the work consists
of twenty-five minutes of highly static music, cre- What I remember [from my visit to Notre Dame in
ating an intensively meditative atmosphere. On Paris] was that there was always sound. Even though
376 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

they forbid people to talk—they still do. And there are v. the democratic experience in on the
noises. Any large public space with several hundred peo- transmigration
ple walking around is going to have a sort of constant
level of ambient noise . . . [of whispered voices, children Emphasizing the social functions of memorial
whimpering, shoes scuffling on the stone floor]. . . . To art is also an important part of Carroll’s anal-
be in that space itself is intensely moving, because you ysis, and his perspective on them interestingly
feel that you’re in the midst of many, many souls—not overlaps with the Deweyan idea of democracy.
just the people in the building, but all the souls that have Carroll claims that the best examples of memorial
been there before. It was an image that I had in my mind art have the capacity “to enculturate and reinforce
when I was composing the piece, that we would be in this the ethos of social groups in a way that promotes
space, and that there would be this constant, low-level their cohesion and continuance,” all which con-
noise . . . of humanity. It might be the boy just saying curs with Dewey’s views on democracy (Carroll
the word “missing, missing,” or people reading names, 2005, 6). However, it can be argued that with the
or traffic sounds, or what life is like. (Colvard 2006, 200) help of Dewey’s pragmatism it is possible to go
deeper into the social functions of memorial works
like Adams’s On the Transmigration.
This description shows why this work can be un- While Dewey is very aware of the dangers in-
derstood as public art. It forms an artistic setting herent in overly communitarian attitudes, such as
which brings the public together collectively to the suppressing of individuality, he nevertheless
reflect on an issue of common concern in a way finds communal bonds a key ingredient of good
that Adams’s traditional orchestral pieces, such societal life. Gregory Pappas in particular empha-
as The Chairman Dances, do not. In this respect, sizes the importance of these communal experi-
On the Transmigration can even be considered a ences for Dewey’s theory of democracy, which
more genuine example of public art than many of he understands “as a complex array of transac-
the artworks situated in public places which only tions where each individual has a high quality of
call for the sort of “intimate exchange” Hein finds shared experiences,” which are, in turn, achieved
characteristic of private art, such as those having “through participation and interaction in common
a mere decorative function. The collective sphere rituals and practices” (Pappas 2008, 219, 232). In
of the experience is of course at its strongest in a ideal cases, these communal happenings “provide
live performance. However, I see no reason why an order and stability that is not rigid or oppres-
this collectivity could not figure in a performance sive to individuality”; instead, “the participation
heard from a recording in the privacy of one’s of individuals is aesthetic and not mechanically
home; even then the work’s public character can imposed” (232). Given the social character of its
constitute an important background to the experi- reception, public art seems an especially fitting
ence, even though the memory space, in this case, medium for creating the types of participation and
is only present metaphorically.6 interaction that further Deweyan democratic ide-
Dewey is an important figure in Hein’s investi- als. By drawing on “common materials of memory
gation of public art, even though she does not rely and experience” public artworks can strengthen
on his aesthetic theory in any systematic way. Her the experience of communality between people or
reading of Dewey, however, does not take into ac- even give rise to “a sense of relatedness that might
count the great social significance he attributes to not have existed before” (Mattern 1999, 62).
the sorts of collective experiences that public art Carroll mentions 9/11 as an important impetus
can create. In a similar vein, Lambert Zuidervaart for his reflections on the connection between art
claims that Hein fails to give a proper account of and recollection. In his view, this tragedy requires
the social input of public art (Zuidervaart 2011, us to examine closely “war memorials and mon-
126–127, 297). I shall bridge this gap by showing uments” in particular, for he thinks they inspired
that the memory space of On the Transmigration “the iconography” of what he calls “the media
promotes the kinds of communal experiences memorials to the police and firefighters of 9/11.”
Dewey places at the very heart of democracy. The recollections they incite also have a direct so-
This experience forms the core of the pragmatist cial function, for these memorials are intended to
view of the value of public art developed in this “transmit cultural values” by celebrating the vir-
article. tuous and courageous actions of the remembered
Puolakka Public Art and Dewey’s Democratic Experience 377

people and by making them something to live up course of which one’s everyday beliefs and val-
to for future generations (Carroll 2005, 8). ues are put into question. Instead it involves a
However, the memorial aspects of On the distinctive kind of concentrative unity and coher-
Transmigration have a much more personal tone, ence that does not preclude the intensity of the
and its social goals are less grandiose than those experience. A reworking of beliefs and values can
Carroll attributes to the media memorials of 9/11. take place without the substantial shaking of their
Adams explains his intentions: “The piece is not foundations that Boros sees in visionary works of
about the towers falling, or politics, or who did public art. In Dewey’s pragmatism the experience
it, or the violence. It’s really just about loss, and of public art can be likened to a ritual, but it is a
about the mother who lost a son, the wife who ritual of a very different kind from the Dionysian
lost a husband, the daughter who lost a father” gatherings described by Nietzsche that Boros
(Colvard 2006, 201). Here there are parallels with references.
Pappas’s interpretation of Dewey’s conception of My reading of Dewey’s aesthetics shows that
democracy. According to Pappas, the idea of com- a viable account for explaining the social value of
munality at the heart of Dewey’s account requires public art can be built on a very different aesthetic
that people have “an emotional readiness to as- foundation from the one underlying Boros’s view.
similate the experiences of others” (Pappas 2008, My aim is not to present any detailed argument to
271). Dewey refers to this capacity with the term show the pragmatist understanding of public art
“sympathy,” and a democratic society should pro- superior to hers. However, there are some ques-
vide a setting in which it can flourish, that is, tionable assumptions in her view regarding the
a moral life “where the interests, demands, and effectiveness of public art which are relevant to
needs of others are vital and moving realities in this discussion.
one’s moral deliberation” (Pappas 2008, 200–201). Boros regards visionary public art as a successor
Dewey sees that the relationship between sym- to modernist and avant-gardist art (Boros 2012,
pathy and sense of community—as a condition 149–150), and at times she contrasts this aesthetic
of a well-functioning democracy—is, in the end, conception with the idea of harmonious beauty
reciprocal; for achieving a sense of togetherness contained in classical conceptions of art (2012,
with other members of one’s community requires 123). This theoretical setting is already apparent
the capacity to engage sympathetically with their from her sources of inspiration: Camus, de Sade,
situations, but the sympathetic traits of a person Nietzsche, and Marcuse—theorists who share a
themselves can “only grow out of having certain rebellious attitude toward society similar to that
communal experiences” (Pappas 2008, 201). of avant-garde movements and who believe that
By engaging the listener in the fates and aesthetic resistance and challenging the classical,
losses of others in an imaginative and emotional harmonious conception of beauty can serve as fuel
way, the memory space afforded by On the for social change and revolution (Boros 2012, 66,
Transmigration creates a promising setting for 110, 121).
the emergence of these kinds of communal A similar attitude can be seen in Boros’s
experiences. Like all great public art, this work many flamboyant descriptions of the Dionysian
contributes to “the development of community experiences she believes visionary public art can
as individuals acquire and maintain an awareness engender. For example, she states:
of common experiences, memories, beliefs, and
commitments” (Mattern 1999, 62).
Artistic experiences, particularly social and public vi-
sionary creative encounters, are vital sources of life, of
quiet thoughtful moments, of chaotic rearrangements,
vi. the elitism of visionary experiences
of confrontations with taboos and fears, of affirmations
of innate unity and interconnectivity among humans,
Such an interpretation of On the Transmigration
and of nature. These opportunities to create our own
gives insight into the constitutive elements of the
“realities” in the creative realm, however temporarily,
Deweyan conception of public art. As can be seen,
make possible true liberation. (2012, 72)
it is built on a very different aesthetic terminology
from the visionary understanding of public art that
Boros promotes as a Dionysian bacchanal in the And to take another example:
378 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

[V]isionary artistic experience disorders, and this chaos Instead, Adams found the key inspiration for
produces a metaphorical clean slate within our inner his musical development from that pioneering fig-
selves that enables an expansion of the imagination and ure of American classical music Charles Ives. He
a space for new possibilities. . . . [O]nly truly transcen- was especially impressed by Ives’s ability to keep
dent visionary art opens the way to freedom of thought, “the vernacular roots of the art alive within the
real conceptual change, and an expanded worldview that context of his formal experimentation” as well as
extends individual concerns into concern for the greater the sensitive way with which he tried to accom-
human community. (2012, 142) modate the experience of “cultural connectivity”
within his works (Adams 2008, 228). The pragma-
Now, I have no intention of questioning the sig- tist qualities considered central to Ives’s work, like
nificance of these experiences as such. However, the critique of the dualism between vernacular and
I would suggest Boros’s account of them has high culture, are important underlying qualities of
some unfortunate consequences. Here, Richard Adams’s music too (Spurgeon Hall 2011).
Shusterman’s reservations about modernist Adams saw the value of musical minimalism,
aesthetics can be used to reveal particular limits when he began his career as a composer in the
in Boros’s visionary aesthetics, which suggest the early 1970s, as bringing the “pleasure principle”
need to develop supplementary views on the expe- back into classical music. In minimalism and in its
rience of public art for explicating its social value. understanding of tonality, he saw the possibility of
Shusterman accuses the different proponents of creating a new musical language which could over-
modernist aesthetics of excessive elitism: they turn the idea of contemporary music as inherently
equate genuine instances of the aesthetic with difficult and elitist as well as bringing back clas-
the radically new and the startling and regard all sical music’s ability to move people more widely
conceptions of the aesthetic that are understood (Adams 2008, 24).
in more traditional terms as backward-looking, The reservations Shusterman and Adams
both aesthetically and politically. In a very prag- have toward modernist aesthetics and musical
matist spirit, the danger Shusterman detects in modernism, respectively, point to some downsides
this approach to the aesthetic is that it looks down in understanding the social value of public art in
on or even ridicules the experience of a great terms of visionary experiences. Can a large group
number of people and turns genuine instances of of people indeed in the midst of their everyday
aesthetic experience into the sole property of a lives undergo the kinds of visionary experiences
small group of elitists (Shusterman 2000, 144–145, at the heart of Boros’s view, that is, “Dionysian
178–179, 186–187, 254). occasions,” during which they “experience
The discriminatory implications Shusterman transcendent feelings of freedom and mystical
sees in modernist aesthetics overlap with Adams’s understandings of human unity and wholeness,
critical view concerning musical modernism. An and oneness with nature” (Boros 2012, 58)?
important aspect of Adams’s work has been his Shusterman and Adams’s analyses of the short-
critical confrontation with the tradition of musical comings of modernist aesthetics show there
modernism—ranging from Arnold Schönberg’s to be a genuine danger that a large group of
atonalism to composers like Milton Babbitt, people will fail to form meaningful connections to
Iannis Xenakis, and Pierre Boulez.7 He has ar- visionary public art.8 In the worst case, visionary
gued that musical modernism put contemporary public art can become a mere playground of
music in danger of becoming a playground for a the cultural elite, as Adams thinks happened
circle of intellectuals, which had the unfortunate with modernist music. Even the more cultured
consequence of distancing classical music from members of the general public may have as much
“communal experience” (Ross 2006, 34). He is trouble engaging with this kind of music as they
also greatly puzzled by the almost hostile attitude have in engaging with much avant-garde art. As
adopted by modernist composers toward genres important as visionary experiences may be, their
of popular music like rock and jazz—genres that role in explicating the social value of public art
have greatly inspired him (May 2006, 10). Adams is arguably more limited than Boros presumes.
also found the image, inherent in modernism, of At least, it would be good to pursue alternative
the composer as a kind of “outsider” of the com- accounts of the experience of public art, which
munity off-putting (May 2006, 7). can add to the understanding concerning its social
Puolakka Public Art and Dewey’s Democratic Experience 379

value that Boros provides. The pragmatist view of Souls. It is precisely this type of experience
of aesthetic experience can, I believe, offer such a that is a key element of the Deweyan conception
supplementation. of the social and aesthetic dimensions of public
art.
The primary relevance of Dewey’s reinter-
vii. a new aesthetic for public art pretation of the traditional formula of beauty is
that it offers an opportunity to understand the
As we have seen, Boros’s conception of pub- experience of public art in a way that manages
lic art is based on a stark contrast between an to avoid both the criticism Boros levels against
avant-gardist visionary aesthetics and traditional mainstream public art, which exhibits the harmo-
accounts of harmonious beauty. Disrupting the nious conception of beauty, and the elitist charge
ideal of beauty serves as a means to challenge peo- Shusterman and Adams raise against modernist
ples’ mind-set and to inspire them to look at the aesthetics. Put bluntly, public art that inspires
surrounding world with more socially alert eyes. communal/aesthetic experiences of the Deweyan
Public art that is committed to the harmonious kind, like Adams’s On the Transmigration, is
conception of beauty does not shake viewers, and more easily approachable than the visionary
works of this kind, at least indirectly, merely sus- artworks of Boros’s theory and thereby can reach
tain established ways of thinking. a larger audience. Simultaneously, however, it
Situated between these opposing views is stimulates or even challenges the imaginative and
Dewey’s reinterpretation of the concept of beauty cognitive faculties of the recipient and thereby
in the light of his pragmatism. Dewey admits that does not uphold the kind of simple harmony that
in emphasizing unity, gradual development, and makes mainstream public art politically dubious
closing fulfillment as essential features of aesthetic in Boros’s eyes.10 Such communal/aesthetic ex-
experience, the key pillar of his aesthetic theory periences, I believe, can take place in connection
can be regarded as a successor of the classical idea with painting as well.11
of beauty as unity in variety. Yet, he says there are With these remarks my primary intention is not
some decisive differences. For Dewey emphasizes to call into question the significance of the ex-
the “dynamic” character of the unity he attributes periences Boros describes as visionary. Rather, it
to aesthetic experience. In other words, although raises the need to look for supplementary views
he places unity and order at the very heart of on how the social value of public art could be
aesthetic experience, his view of the relationship explained. Boros manages to single out only one
between the individual elements of the unity is dif- type of valuable experience, whose role, if my cri-
ferent from that present in classical conceptions of tique is accurate, may very well be more limited
beauty reigning in antiquity and the Renaissance. than she assumes. In my view, pragmatism offers a
Dewey’s idea of the relationship between the promising supplementation to her account as well
elements of aesthetic experience is not harmo- as an important addition to the current discussion
nious, but live and tension filled. The Deweyan on the social and aesthetic character of public art
aesthetic is an energetic unity: “There is unity as a whole.
only when the resistances create a suspense that
is resolved through cooperative interaction of the
opposed energies” (Dewey 1980a, 161). Aesthetic viii. closing notes on on the transmigration of
experience thus involves a more dynamic engage- souls
ment with the aesthetic object than it does in the
contemplative perception of harmonious beauty. Adams won the Pulitzer Prize in 2003 for On
It is characterized by a participation in which the the Transmigration of Souls, and its première
recipient’s mental faculties, like imagination, are recording received the Gramophone Prize in
actively engaged.9 The mental processes under- 2005 in three different categories. The piece
lying this type of experience are very similar to has been performed widely around the world,
those Noël Carroll attributes to the experience which, in part, shows that it is not too strictly
that he sees successful memorial art inspiring—a tied to its original context but has more universal
characterization that captures particularly well dimensions.12 Despite this success, the composer
the experience of Adams’s On the Transmigration was not unreservedly happy with it, explaining
380 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

that his response fluctuated between “loathing KALLE PUOLAKKA


and loving,” and that, until he heard a particularly Department of Philosophy,
well-executed performance in 2007, it seemed to History, Culture, and Art Studies
him to be “compromised and uneven” (Adams FI-00014 University of Helsinki
2008, 267). Helsinki, Finland
Not many have shared Adams’s doubts about
internet: kalle.puolakka@helsinki.fi
the work. On the contrary, On the Transmigration
has been described as “a breakthrough” and a
great example of how contemporary classical references
music can speak to a wider audience. The critic Adams, John. 2008. Hallelujah Junction: Composing an
concerned hoped it would signify a more fun- American Life. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
damental “turning point” in American classical Boros, Diana. 2012. Creative Rebellion for the Twenty-First Cen-
tury: The Importance of Public and Interactive Art to Political
music (Schiff 2006, 189–191). The Deweyan Life in America. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
interpretation of the piece I have presented in Carroll, Noël. 2005. “Art and Recollection.” Journal of Aesthetic
this article supports these sorts of assessments: Education 39(2): 1–12.
Colvard, Daniel. 2006. “John Adams Discusses On the Transmi-
On the Transmigration gives a moving expression
gration of Souls. An Interview by Daniel Colvard.” In The
of collective sorrow as well as a unique collective John Adams Reader: Essential Writings on an American Com-
musical space for recollection. I am by no means poser, edited by Thomas May, 196–204. Pompton Plains, NJ:
claiming that the piece will cause in all listeners Amadeus Press.
Dewey, John. 1980a. Art as Experience. New York: Perigee
the sorts of experiences I have tried to explicate Books; originally published by Putnam’s, 1934.
with the help of Dewey’s aesthetics; some people . 1980b. Democracy and Education: An Introduction to
might gain those kinds experiences from a very the Philosophy of Education. In The Middle Works, 1899-
1924, Volume 9, 1916, edited by Jo Ann Boydston. Southern
different kind of work. Illinois University Press.
The function pragmatism assigns to public art . 1984. The Public and Its Problems. In The Later Works,
has a lot to do with building cohesion, overcoming 1925-1953, Volume 2, 1925–1927, edited by Jo Ann Boydston.
controversies, and disentangling opposites. There 235–371. Southern Illinois University Press.
Gracyk, Theodore. 2001. “‘Candle in the Wind 1997’ as an Anti-
might, of course, be other legitimate social dote to the Social Erasure of the Public.” Genre 34: 219–242.
aims that some other type of public art could Hein, Hilde. 2006. Public Art: Thinking Museums Differently.
serve better. In some situations, there might, for Lanham, MD: AltaMira Press.
Knight, Cher Krause. 2014. “Public Art.” In Encyclopedia of
example, be a need to shock the public, and the Aesthetics, vol. 5. 2nd edition. Edited by Michael Kelly, 312–
pragmatist framework, given its aspiration to 316. Oxford University Press.
coherence, might not give the best understand- Mattern, Mark. 1999. “John Dewey, Art and Public Life.” The
Journal of Politics 61: 54–75.
ing of how public art can serve these goals. I
May, Thomas. 2006. “John Adams Reflects on His Career.” In
nevertheless believe that On the Transmigration The John Adams Reader: Essential Writings on an American
is a great example of the social aspects Dewey Composer, edited by Thomas May, 2–28. Pompton Plains, NJ:
attributes to art and provides insight into the Amadeus Press.
Pappas, Gregory Fernando. 2008. John Dewey’s Ethics: Democ-
experiences where the social value of public art racy as Experience. Indiana University Press.
from the perspective of Dewey’s pragmatism Rich, Alan. 2006. “Life as Music: John Adams Goes Public.” In
lies. The following quotation from Dewey sums The John Adams Reader: Essential Writings on an American
Composer, edited by Thomas May, 63–66. Pompton Plains,
these up: NJ: Amadeus Press.
Ross, Alex. 2006. “The Harmonist.” In The John Adams Reader.
Essential Writings on an American Composer, edited by
Works of art that are not remote from common life, that Thomas May, 29–44. Pompton Plains, NJ: Amadeus Press.
Schiff, David. 2006. “Memory Spaces (On the Transmigration
are widely enjoyed in a community, are signs of a unified Souls).” In The John Adams Reader: Essential Writings on
collective life. But they are also marvelous aids in the an American Composer, edited by Thomas May, 189–195.
creation of such a life. The remaking of the material of Pompton Plains, NJ: Amadeus Press.
Schmidt, James. 2010. “Cenotaphs in Sound: Catastrophe, Mem-
experience in the act of expression is not an isolated ory, and Musical Memorials.” Proceedings of the European
event confined to the artist and to a person here and Society for Aesthetics 2: 454–478.
there who happens to enjoy the work. In the degree in Shusterman, Richard. 2000. Pragmatist Aesthetics: Living
which art exercises its office, it is also a remaking of the Beauty, Rethinking Art, 2nd edition. Lanham, MD: Rowman
& Littlefield.
experience of the community in the direction of greater Spurgeon, Hall. and Richard Anthony. 2011. “The Deweyan
order and unity. (Dewey 1980a, 81)13 Aesthetic of Charles Ives.” In The Continuing Relevance
Puolakka Public Art and Dewey’s Democratic Experience 381

of John Dewey: Reflections on Aesthetics, Morality, Science, “Candle in the Wind,” a rewritten version of an earlier song
and Society, edited by Larry A. Hickman, Mathew Caleb by John dedicated to Marilyn Monroe, is an epitome of such
Flamm, Krzysztof Piotr Skowroński. and Jennifer A. Rea. a public cultural artifact.
Amsterdam: Rodopi. 6. Compare with Gracyk’s claim that it was not until
Steinberg, Michael. 2006. “Nixon in China.” In The John Adams a studio recording of “Candle in the Wind” brought the
Reader: Essential Writings on an American Composer, edited song within reach of a worldwide audience of millions that
by Thomas May, 110–119. Pompton Plains, NJ: Amadeus it became “truly public” (2001, 236).
Press.
7. This sort of critical attitude is especially important
Tommasini, Anthony. 2006. “Washed in the Sound of Souls
for Adams’s orchestral work Harmonielehre (1985), which
in Transit (On the Transmigration of Souls).” In The John
the composer has described as “a statement of belief in the
Adams Reader: Essential Writings on an American Com-
poser, edited by Thomas May, 365–367. Pompton Plains, NJ: power of tonality at a time when I was uncertain about its
Amadeus Press. future” (Adams 2008, 139).
Zuidervaart, Lambert. 2011. Art in Public: Politics, Economics, 8. Knight (2014, 314) sees similar problems in certain
and a Democratic Culture. Cambridge University Press. types of public art.
9. In Chapter 12 of Art as Experience, Dewey (1980a)
emphasizes the role played by imagination in aesthetic
1. Guernica’s first place of exhibition, the Spanish experience.
Pavilion at the Paris International Exposition of 1937, also 10. The following description of Adams’s music by
proves significant when considering the painting’s status. Michael Steinberg aptly captures the kind of experience I
The Exposition was surely in Picasso’s mind when making am after here: “Adams’s music enters the ear easily, but it
the work, for Guernica arose in response to a commission is not simple, certainly not simple-minded, and never pre-
Picasso got to compose a painting to this setting. It is very dictable. At no point, were the music suddenly to stop, could
likely that one of the reasons why Picasso settled on such a you foresee with certainty what comes next, even when
topic for his commission painting was a hope to gather, with the sense of pattern seems at its clearest” (Steinberg 2006,
the work, a great number of people together to reflect on 114).
the horrendousness of the events depicted in the painting. 11. Good examples include aesthetically interesting
2. Besides the already mentioned Carroll (2005), Hein paintings that attempt to lift national spirit. For example
(2006), and Boros (2012), see also Zuidervaart (2011, espe- Finnish art history of the turn of the twentieth century is
cially 78–81, 120–128). filled with such cases. Finland was then only a province of
3. Dewey’s key works on democracy include Democ- Russia, suffering from its motherland’s oppression. It was
racy and Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy of a goal of many great Finnish painters of this time, such as
Education (1980b) and The Public and Its Problems (1984). Akseli Gallen-Kallela and Albert Edelfelt, to increase the
Gregory Pappas (2008), in particular, has developed the ex- sense of togetherness of the Finnish people with their artis-
perientialist idea of democracy in Dewey’s footsteps. tic output and to inspire them to oppose Russia’s attempt to
4. Mattern (1999) touches upon questions related to get a tighter grip on Finland.
public art from the perspective of Dewey’s pragmatism. 12. Adams (2008, 265) explains that with On the Trans-
5. In a similar vein, Gracyk (2001) problematizes the migration he wanted to bring attention to the variety, both
idea of identifying public art solely with the physical statues ethnic and social, of the people who were killed in the WTC
and memorials located in public places and defends, against attack. The work has in fact been considered a homage to
the background of Hannah Arendt’s interpretation of Kant’s the variety and sense of community simultaneously reigning
aesthetics, the public art status of some products of popular in New York (Schiff 2006, 195).
culture distributed through the channels of mass production. 13. I would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers
For him, Elton John’s memorial piece for Princess Diana of the journal for very helpful comments.
Copyright of Journal of Aesthetics & Art Criticism is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its
content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the
copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email
articles for individual use.

You might also like