Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

Received: 19 October 2021 | Revised: 1 December 2021 | Accepted: 16 December 2021

DOI: 10.1111/dewb.12342

ORIGINAL ARTICLE

Global sharing of COVID‐19 vaccines: A duty of justice,


not charity

Nancy S. Jecker

Correspondence
Nancy S. Jecker, PhD, Department of Abstract
Bioethics and Humanities, School of Medicine,
Global scarcity of COVID‐19 vaccines raises ethical questions about their fair allo-
University of Washington, Seattle,
Washington, USA. cation between nations. Section I introduces the question and proposes that wealthy
Email: nsjecker@uw.edu
nations have a duty of justice to share globally scarce COVID‐19 vaccines. Section II
distinguishes justice from charity and argues that beneficiaries of unjust structures
incur duties of justice when they are systematically advantaged at others expense.
Section III gives a case‐based argument describing three upstream structural in-
justices that systematically advantaged wealthy countries and disadvantaged poorer
countries, contributing to global disparities of COVID‐19 vaccines. Section IV ex-
amines more closely the duties of justice owed, including a duty to relinquish
holdings, restitute victims, and restore relationships. Section V concludes that
wealthy nations have a duty of justice to share COVID‐19 vaccines with poor na-
tions and to restore relationships damaged by injustice. All nations should take steps
to transform unjust structures.

KEYWORDS
Africa, bioethics, ethics, international justice, justice, resource allocation

1 | INTRODUCTION young citizens, while healthcare workers and other high risk groups in
poorer countries are unprotected,3 ignoring an appeal by the
After witnessing highly effective vaccines against the SARS‐CoV‐2 Director‐General of the World Health Organization (WHO) to delay
virus develop at break‐neck speed, the world is now witnessing the booster shots until 10% of people in every nation receive first shots.4
sluggish pace at which globally scarce vaccines are being shared From a humanitarian standpoint this lopsided state of affairs is
around the world. As of December 23, 2021, just 8.1% of people in clearly a disaster. It prolongs the pandemic and increases the human
low‐income countries had received at least one dose of vaccine.1 By toll of disease, death, and suffering. Yet this paper argues that lack of
contrast, many wealthy countries have accumulated doses to vacci- access to COVID‐19 vaccines in poorer countries is not only a hu-
nate their citizens many times over. Canada, for example, pre‐ordered manitarian failure, but deeply unjust. The argument I give in support
enough vaccines to inoculate its citizens six times over; the UK and of this claim shows that the present‐day allocation comes about
US enough to do so four times over; in the European Union and through structural injustices that placed wealthy nations at an
2
Australia, pre‐orders are sufficient to protect each citizen twice.
Many high‐income countries are offering booster shots to healthy
3
Jecker, N.S., & Lederman, Z. (2021). Three for Me and None for You? An Ethical Argument
for Delaying COVID‐19 Boosters. Journal of Medical Ethics, 1‐4. https://doi.org/10.1136/
medethics-2021-107824
1 4
Our World in Data. (2021, December 22). Coronavirus (COVID‐19) Vaccinations. Retrieved World Health Organization. (2021). WHO Director‐General's Opening Remarks at the
December 23, 2021, from https://ourworldindata.org/covid-vaccinations Media Briefing on COVID‐19. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from https://www.who.int/
2
Allison, S. (2021, January 30). Bill Gates, Big Pharma and Entrenching the Vaccine director-general/speeches/detail/who-director-general-s-opening-remarks-at-the-media-
Apartheid. Mail and Guardian. briefing-on-covid-4-august-2021

Developing World Bioethics. 2022;1–10. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/dewb © 2022 John Wiley & Sons Ltd | 1
2 | JECKER

advantage and poorer nations at a disadvantage. As beneficiaries of governments in other countries; (2) the duty is enforceable and those
these unjust systems, wealthy nations incur a duty to relinquish who owe it are morally required to meet it; (3) the duty holds irre-
holdings, in this case vaccines, and restitute poorer nations. All na- spective of factors considered morally arbitrary, such as ability to pay;
tions have a duty to help create fairer structures. Section II distin- and (4) there is a responsibility to help establish the institutional
guishes duties of justice from duties of charity and argues that those structures to realize this duty. Practically speaking, it matters then,
who benefit from structural injustices incur duties of justice to those whether making COVID‐19 vaccines available to people in low‐
made worse off. Section III gives a case‐based argument describing income countries counts as a duty of justice or not. If it is a duty of
three upstream examples of injustices that contributed to global justice, this would show that the charitable giving of governments or
vaccine inequalities: concessionary lending in sub‐Saharan Africa by the voluntary offerings of philanthropic groups are not enough to
the World Bank and International Monetary Fund (IMF); the agree- meet ethical duties to people in low‐income countries. To the extent
ment on Trade‐Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights that charitable acts postpone or impede attempts to strengthen just
(TRIPS) enacted by the World Trade Organization (WTO); and systems, they may in fact do great harm in the long run, even if they
COVAX, the WHO co‐led effort to equitably distribute COVID‐19 help in the short‐term.
vaccines. Section IV examines more closely the duties of justice Duties of justice are often thought to arise from people's choices
owed, including a duty to relinquish holdings, restitute victims, and as free and rational agents. Consent‐based accounts, such as those
restore relationships damaged by injustice. Section V concludes that associated with Rawls,9 reflect the Kantian tradition, and the general
wealthier nations have a duty of justice to share COVID‐19 vaccines view that legitimate moral principles are those we choose to impose
and to repair relationships damaged by injustices. All nations should upon ourselves as free and rational agents. When obstacles to free
take steps to transform unjust structures. rational choice are pervasive and embedded in background condi-
tions affecting many people and groups systematically, they may
point to injustices that are structural. Kant himself recognized the
2 | D U T I E S O F J U S T I C E AN D C H A R I T Y problem. Even while Kant emphasized a normative framework fo-
cused on rational choice as a source of moral duty, he suggested in
Duties of justice are usually marked off from duties of charity by various writings that people in positions of wealth and privilege are
virtue of four distinguishing features.5 First, they are grounded in often ignorant about and may misjudge the many ways in which they
what others are due and can legitimately claim, as opposed to what benefit from, and owe recompense for, what he called, “general in-
would be benevolent but not mandatory to deliver. For this reason, justices.”10 In Lectures on Ethics Kant states, when people “take pity
failing to do what justice requires is generally considered blame- on another” they “render back the benefits they have previously
worthy or a violation of what one owes. Second, duties of justice are snatched away, though they are not aware of any injustice; the
usually regarded as enforceable and non‐elective. In this sense, “we reason being that they do not rightly examine the matter.”11 On
6
demand justice, but we beg for charity.” Third, duties of justice re- examination, Kant contends, do‐gooders would frequently find that
flect an impartial requirement of morality in which 'like cases are to they previously partook of a “general injustice” that renders their
be treated alike'. Thus, we do not except ourselves or those we present acts of kindness to an unfortunate person, not a “free gift,”
personally favor from justice standards unless we can show that but repayment for what they previously appropriated through a
there are morally relevant differences that justify this. Lastly, duties general injustice.12 Kant judges that in these cases, what appears as
of justice are ordinarily thought to relate to agency and what is within kindness is in truth, “duty and indebtedness, arising from the rights of
our power to do or refrain from doing. In the case of structural in- others.”13 Elsewhere, Kant comments, “One need only reflect a little
justices, agency is involved indirectly because we could have avoided and he will always find a debt that he has by some means incurred
a bad outcome by establishing institutional structures to avert it. towards the human race.”14 Finally, Kant argues that possessing
While there are variations in how the justice‐charity distinction is ample resources to afford beneficence itself often depends on “cer-
rendered,7 and some reject the distinction altogether,8 I bracket tain human beings being favored through the injustice of the gov-
these debates and use the fourfold analysis described here as a ernment;” and concludes rhetorically, “Under such circumstances,
working definition. does a rich man's help to the needy, on which he so readily prides
In the case of COVID‐19 vaccines, to say that making reasonable
efforts to share with people in low‐income countries is a duty of 9
Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Belknap Press.
justice entails (1) that people in low‐income countries can advance a 10
Kant, I. (1997/1784‐1785). Of Duties Towards Other People. In P. Heath & J. B.
Schneewind (Eds.), P. Heath (Transl.), Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics (pp. 177‐182). New
right or claim to access these vaccines which holds against
York, NY: Cambridge University Press, p. 179.
11
Ibid: 179.
12
Ibid: 179.
13
Ibid: 179.
5 14
Miller, D. (2021). Justice. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved Kant, I. (2015/1788). The Critique of Practical Reason. In T. K. Abbott & W. Hastie (Transl.),
December 1, 2021, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/justice/ The Ethics of Immanuel Kant: Metaphysics of Morals ‐ Philosophy of Law & The Doctrine
6
Ibid. of Virtue + The Critique of Practical Reason: Theory of Moral Reasoning + Perpetual
7
Goodin, R. (2017). Duties of Charity, Duties of Justice. Political Studies, 65(2), 268‐283; Peace (Kindle locations 5378‐7943). Prague, Czech Republic: e‐artnow ebooks: Kindle
8
Buchanan, A. (1987). Justice and Charity. Ethics, 97(3), 558‐575. location 7900).
JECKER | 3

himself as something meritorious, really deserve to be called bene- What light can these suggestions shed on the unequal access to
ficence at all?”15 Kant goes so far as to consider that a tendency COVID‐19 vaccines between rich and poor nations? It suggests that
toward benevolence might be implanted in us to rectify a common the duty to share COVID‐19 vaccines qualifies as a duty of justice if
epistemic deficiency, namely our failure to know the multitude of the benefits wealthier nations enjoy are the outcome of general in-
injustices in which we unwittingly partake. While we call such acts justices. One way this may have occurred is if the upstream processes
‘beneficence,’ they are not truly acts of beneficence, but payment of and structures that led to unequal distribution were themselves un-
debts owed. just. The argument can be specified in skeletal form as follows.
Contemporary scholars also appeal to epistemic deficiency to The Bare Bones Argument for Vaccine Sharing as a Duty of Justice
support the general claim that wealthy nations have duties to make 1. The Kantian Principle: beneficiaries of general injustices incur
amends to poorer nations. For example, Pogge argues wealthy na- duties of justice toward those disadvantaged by them.
tions owe recompense for harms they inflicted upon the global poor 2. The privileged access to vaccines wealthy nations enjoy resulted
during the colonial era.16 Waldron refers to the “contagion of in- from structural injustices that benefitted them while disadvanta-
justice” to explain interdependencies between domestic and inter- ging low‐income nations.
national parties that make it plausible to say that wealthy nations owe 3. Then wealthy nations incur a general duty of justice to share
recompense to poorer ones.17 Others, including Shklar,18 Young,19 vaccines with people in low‐income nations.
and Sangiovanni20 also comment on the more general tendency to
mistake restitution for charity. The remainder of the paper will explore this argument in greater
A difficulty all such suggestions encounter is that it is challenging detail. Aside from what has been suggested already, I will not further
to say exactly what a duty of justice arising in this way requires, examine the Kantian principle (premise 1), but instead assume it is a
because people may not know who they owe recompense to or even plausible principle to hold and focus attention on premises 2 and 3.
what exactly they owe recompense for. Waldron sees the difficulty Section III will make the case that upstream structures that con-
as wide‐ranging, arguing that it is always possible when attempting to tributed to COVID‐19 vaccine distribution were unjust in ways that
address a particular injustice to raise the question “why stop there?” gave rich nations privileged access to vaccines while giving poor
and inquire about other injustices in the vicinity.21 One solution, nations reduced access. Section IV will identify the duty of justice
which Kant suggests, is treating debts that arise from general in- that follows and what is required to discharge it.
justice as if they were duties of beneficence to give back to the least
advantaged members of a group. According to this proposal, even
though duties of recompense are in truth of a more stringent class, 3 | UPSTREAM STRUCTURAL INJUSTICES
i.e., duties of justice, not charity, we make good on them by bene-
fitting the least well off. Moran characterizes Kant's suggestion Structural injustice exists “when social processes put large groups of
this way: persons under systematic threat of domination or deprivation of
the means to develop and exercise their capacities and, at the same
facts about structural injustice should figure into a time … these processes enable others to dominate or to have a wide
privileged agent's assessment of her various obliga- range of opportunities for developing and exercising capacities
tions… Unlike other acts of beneficence…these acts available to them.”23 This section will argue that the structures that
warrant neither merit nor gratitude…agents should underlie the global distribution of COVID‐19 vaccines have put
avoid any hint of self‐congratulations for performing people in low‐income countries under systemic threat of domination
acts of beneficence in these circumstances. Rather or deprivation in this way. The structures in question can be thought
they should humble themselves in recognition of the of in terms of what Buchanan terms, a ‘global basic structure.’24
debt they owe…simply to acknowledge the diffuse, A global basic structure refers to “a set of economic and political
systematic, and entrenched nature of past injustice.22 institutions that has profound and enduring effects on the distribu-
tion of burdens and benefits among peoples and individuals around
the world.”25 It includes, for example, international economic agree-
ments, such as the WTO and North American Free Trade Alliance;
15
Kant, I. (1996/1797). Metaphysics of Morals. In McGregor, M. (Transl). The Metaphysics of
international financial regimes, such as the IMF and World Bank; and
Morals, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, (2nd ed.), New York, NY: Cambridge
University Press, p. 454. the global system of private property rights, including intellectual
16
Pogge, T. W. (2002). World Poverty and Human Rights. New York, NY: Cambridge
property rights. In the examples below, I pay particular attention to
University Press.
17
Waldron, J. (1992). Superseding Historic Injustice. Ethics, 103(1), 4‐28.
18
Shklar, N. J. (1992). The Faces of Injustice. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
19
Young, I. M. (2011). Responsibility for Justice. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
20 23
Sangiovanni, A. (2018). Structural Injustice and Individual Responsibility. Journal of Social Young, I. M. (2011). Responsibility for Justice. New York, NY: Oxford University
Philosophy, 49(3), 461‐483. Press, p. 51.
21 24
Waldron, op. cit. note 17. Buchanan, A. (2004). Justice, Legitimacy, and Self‐Determination. New York, NY: Oxford
22
Moran, K. A. (2016). Neither Justice Nor Charity? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 47(4), University Press.
25
477‐498. Ibid: 213.
4 | JECKER

Africa, because the continent lags far behind any other region in referring not to the pecuniary debts of African nations, but the moral
vaccination: as of December 22, 2021, Africa had fully vaccinated just debts incurred by wealthy nations who benefitted. During the
8.6% of its 1.3 billion people. By comparison, rates of vaccination in COVID‐19 pandemic, the legacy of concessionary lending policies is
Europe were 60%, North America 58%, Asia 55%, and South evident. Prior cutbacks in health, education, and infrastructure added
America 63%.26 to the region's pandemic challenges related to developing, manu-
Pre‐pandemic, myriad upstream factors fed present‐day global facturing, transporting and administering vaccines. The continent not
vaccine disparities. Three examples serve to illustrate: concessionary only has a large unmet need for COVID‐19 vaccines, it also manu-
lending programs offered to African nations during the 1980s and factures less than 1% of all the vaccines it uses.30 According to Ri-
1990s; the 1995 WTO agreement on Trade‐Related Aspects of In- chardson, an advisor to the African Centres for Disease Control and
tellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) that governs patent rights for Prevention, concessionary lending policies “eviscerated safety nets and
COVID‐19 vaccines; and the 2020 formation of COVAX, which public health infrastructures across the Global South. They privatised
aimed to accelerate development and equitable global distribution of public assets, cut spending on healthcare, food and farm subsidies, and
vaccines. deregulated trade rules, such that illicit financial flows to the Global
North currently dwarf what is sent to the Global South in ‘aid’.”31
What implications do these concessionary lending practices have
3.1 | Concessionary lending in sub‐Saharan Africa for how we think about the duties of high‐income countries toward
people in low‐income countries in Africa during the COVID‐19
The health and social structures prevalent across much of Africa today pandemic? At a minimum, we can say that they raise the bar on what
trace to the twentieth century, when newly independent African na- wealthy nations owe and make their obligation to share vaccines
tions were making substantial public sector investments in education, stronger. Do the duties of wealthy nations rise to the level of justice?
healthcare, infrastructure and industrialization. During the 1980s and One way of bolstering a claim that they do is to appeal to the
1990s, these domestic investments were sharply curtailed when the Rawlsian view that that a just distribution must be the result of fair
World Bank and IMF began offering African governments conces- terms of negotiation.32 To the extent that the IMF and World Bank
sionary loans that reshaped their domestic policies. In exchange for methods for arriving at concessionary lending agreements fell short
credit, they required governments to implement a package of domestic of fair negotiations, they implicate the subsequent distribution of
reforms prescribed by the IMF and World Bank aimed at promoting benefits and burdens resulting from them. Furthermore, they suggest
free‐market trade and foreign investment and integrating African na- that wealthy nations who were beneficiaries of these practices incur
tions within dominant structures of global trade, finance and produc- a duty of justice to set things right, not only by sharing vaccines and
tion.27 Loans were conditioned on liberalizing trade by eliminating assisting with getting shots in arms but by supporting efforts to build
tariffs, lowering wages and reducing government spending on do- Africa's vaccine manufacturing capacity for COVID‐19 and future
mestic programs, such as education and healthcare, to ensure African pandemics. Africa is currently taking the initiative in ramping up its
governments could meet loan repayment schedules. By 1982, 19 vaccine manufacturing capacities; for example, the African Union has
African countries had taken IMF loans involving conditionality and 19 unveiled plans to accelerate local vaccine production sufficient to
had accepted conditional World Bank loans. meet 60% of Africa's routine immunization needs by 2040.33
While African governments accepted the terms of concessionary It might be objected that the duty to share vaccines and build
loans, they were disadvantaged in negotiating these terms. As Hodd vaccine manufacturing capacity falls narrowly on wealthy nations
notes, control of the IMF and World Bank at the time was in the who participated in IMF and World Bank decisions during the 1980s
hands of wealthy industrialized nations who held the majority of and 1990s, rather than on every wealthy nation. Yet, the Kantian
voting rights. For example, in 1984, 18 wealthy industrial nations held analysis from Section II suggests otherwise. It nudges privileged
67.5% of IMF votes, compared with 5.2% of votes held by 43 African people to acknowledge their own ‘epistemic deficiency’ or limited
countries.28 In this respect, the terms of loans were not freely chosen capacity to know the myriad ways in which their privilege accrues
by African nations but instead driven by institutional decisions that from unjust structures. Accepting a general duty to help the least well
subjected African nations to domination, exploitation, and exclusion. off is for Kant, a way out of this morass.
These historical patterns are reproduced in contemporary social
structures and relations, creating what Lu calls “unpaid debts,”29
30
Editorial staff. (2021). Africa's Vaccines Revolution Must Have Research at its Core. Nature,
592, 487‐488.
31
Ritchie, H. (2021, May 13). Western Countries Prevented African Nations From Having
26
Our World in Data. (2021). People Fully Vaccinated Per 100 hundred percent. Retrieved Their Own Vaccine. Vice World News. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from https://www.vice.
December 23, 2021, from https://ourworldindata.org/grapher/share-people-fully- com/en/article/epnxd7/africa-covid-vaccine-blocked-by-western-countries
32
vaccinated-covid?tab=table&country=OWID_WRL~Europe~South+America~Asia~North Rawls, op. cit note 9.
33
+America African Union. (2021). African Union and African CDC Launch Partnerships for African
27
Hodd, M. (1987). Africa, the IMF and the World Bank. African Affairs, 86(344), 331‐342. Vaccine Manufacturing (PAVM), Framework to Achieve it and Signs 2 MoUs. Retrieved
28
Ibid. December 1, 2021, from https://africacdc.org/news-item/african-union-and-africa-cdc-
29
Lu, C. (2017). Justice and Reconciliation in World Politics. New York, NY: Cambridge launches-partnerships-for-african-vaccine-manufacturing-pavm-framework-to-achieve-it-
University Press, p. 148. and-signs-2-mous/
JECKER | 5

3.2 | The TRIPS agreement and to the transfer and dissemination of technology to
the mutual advantage of producers and users of
Consider next the patent protections enjoyed by for‐profit pharma- technological knowledge and in a manner conducive
ceutical companies that sell and set prices for COVID‐19 vaccines. to social and economic welfare, and to a balance of
These protections are governed by the WTO's 1995 TRIPS agreement, rights and obligations.39
which made compulsory the enforcement of intellectual property
rights by WTO member states. In the process, it limited access to However, even if profit is essential to incentivize innovation,
pharmaceutical products for low‐income nations whose governments unlimited profits are not.40 Pharmaceutical companies that developed
cannot afford to pay the prices for‐profit pharmaceutical companies COVID‐19 vaccines have already enjoyed substantial profits:, in 2021,
set for patent‐protected products. Prior to TRIPS, countries enjoyed Pfizer/BioNTech is forecast to make between 15 and 30 billion US
wide latitude in enforcing patents in developing nations and could dollars in COVID‐19 vaccine sales, while Moderna is expected to make
exclude whole sectors from patent protections; pharmaceuticals 18 to 20 billion US dollars and Johnson & Johnson 10 billion US dollars.41
were frequently excluded from patentability in developing countries. Arguably, this is sufficient to keep intact the incentive to innovate.
TRIPS represented a major shift that benefitted the pharmaceutical Finally, while the public good is served by innovation, it is also
industry because it increased patent protection for their products; served by the diffusion of products, such as essential medicines.
simultaneously, it represented a major loss for low‐income countries. Thus, the merits of granting exclusive rights to intellectual property
According to Correa, the overall effect for poorer nations was to limit owners must be balanced against the prospect of excluding from the
their ability to “discharge their obligations in public health rights in- market “competitors who may be able to imitate or adapt the in-
cluding those subsumed under the right to health.”34 The reason this vention in such a way that its social value is increased.”42 Vaccine
occurred was that the vast majority of economically developing dissemination stands out from dissemination of other essential
countries consume rather than produce intellectual property and im- medicines in this regard because vaccines benefit public health to a
port rather than export intellectual property.35 TRIPS thus favored much greater extent. While other essential medicines enhance in-
industrialized countries that “built economic prowess by appropriating dividual health, vaccines also protect population health by preventing
others' intellectual property” because it foreclosed such an option for infectious diseases from spreading.
later industrializers.”36 Setting aside the debate over TRIPS, it is widely agreed that
According to Sell et al., when developing countries initially signed during a pandemic, ‘business as usual’ is not ethically supported.
onto TRIPS, they did not fully realize the future impact of TRIPS and Emanuel et al. observe that many pharmaceutical companies and
they were strong‐armed into agreeing: “they were subjected to governments recognize the need to suspend business as usual, as
pronounced economic coercion leading up to and during the nego- evidenced by their willingness to donate vaccines and waive patent
tiations. Furthermore, they assented to an IP agreement in exchange protections.43 The problem has been coordinating their efforts to
for Organization of Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD) achieve a fair global distribution of COVID‐19 vaccines, defined as a
commitments to expand market access for developing countries' distribution based on need, not wealth:
agricultural and textile exports.”37
It could be countered that TRIPS is a fair system for allocating Fairness requires that vaccine allocation should appro-
patent rights because pharmaceutical companies own the products of priately prioritise countries in great need, not those with
their labor. Shouldn't they be free to set whatever prices they wish? great wealth; fairness also requires not leaving people
In response, critics challenge this claim, noting that public tax dollars who are in need at the back of the queue, and instead
contributed substantially to the development of COVID‐19 and other ensuring that they receive the vaccine in a timely man-
38
vaccines and to the basic science on which vaccines are based. ner; no segment of the world's population should be left
Yet, it could also be claimed that the protection of intellectual behind because of inability to afford vaccines.44
property that TRIPS afforded was necessary to encourage innovation.
According to the original TRIPS Agreement, The TRIPS agreement has in fact met resistance during the
pandemic on grounds of fairness. Two petitions currently before the
protections and enforcement of IP rights should con-
tribute to the promotion of technological innovation
39
World Trade Organization. (1994). Agreement on Trade‐Related Aspects of Intellectual
Property Rights (TRIPS), Article 7. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from https://www.wto.org/
34
Correa, C. M. (2009). Intellectual Property Rights and Inequalities in Health Outcomes. In english/docs_e/legal_e/27-trips_01_
40
R. Labonte & T. Schrecker (Eds.), Globalization and Health: Pathways, Evidence and Policy. Sell, Ikenberry, & Smith, op. cit. note 35.
41
(pp. 263‐288). New York, NY: Routledge. Kollewe, J. (2021, March 6). From Pfizer to Moderna: Who's Making Billions from
35
Sell, S. K., Ikenberry, G. J., & Smith, S., et al. (2003). Private Power, Public Law: The COVID‐19 Vaccines? The Guardian.
42
Globalization of Intellectual Property Rights. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Trebilcock, M., & Howse, R. (1995). The Regulation of International Trade. New York, NY:
36
Ibid: 9. Routledge, p. 250.
37 43
Ibid: 9. Emanuel, E. J., Buchanan, A., Chan, S. Y., et al. (2021). What are the Obligations of
38
Jecker, N. S. & Atuire, C. A. (2021). What Yours is Ours: Waiving Intellectual Property Pharmaceutical Companies in a Global Health Emergency? Lancet, 398(10304), P1015‐1020.
44
Protections for COVID‐19 Vaccines. Journal of Medical Ethics, 47, 595‐598. Ibid: 2.
6 | JECKER

WTO seek to temporarily waive patent rights,45 and seek to require purchase options and highly reliant on ad‐hoc charitable donations of
pharmaceutical companies to share licenses to manufacture COVID‐ doses.”50
46
19 vaccines. While these petitions have are not received sufficient Second, COVAX lacks independent powers of enforcement. This
backing to pass, there are other steps countries can undertake. not only made participation purely voluntary but meant that promises
Emanuel et al. propose tiered pricing and limiting the proportion of could be routinely broken with impunity. Pharmaceutical companies
vaccines sold through bilateral deals to offset market influences.47 were incentivized to prioritize delivering vaccines to the most profit-
Such efforts are critical to prevent gaps between rich and poor na- able markets. As of October 9, 2021, Moderna had not shipped any of
tions from widening and becoming even more entrenched. The IMF's the 34 million doses it promised COVAX.51 In tandem, many wealthy
2021 World Economic Outlook offers a longer‐run perspective on the countries broke promises to COVAX and prioritized their own citizens.
impact of slower vaccine rollouts in developing economies, fore- According to Dr. Christian Happi, a professor at Redeemer University
casting that they will deepen global economic inequalities absent in Nigeria and Harvard School of Public Health, “donations from
multilateral efforts to accelerate vaccine access and provide debt wealthy countries are completely unreliable, as they have already
relief.48 hoarded the global supply and are now moving on to inoculating
children and planning booster shots.”52 In September 2021, the UN
reported COVAX had secured legally binding commitments for 4.5
3.3 | COVAX billion doses but expected to secure just 1.4 billion doses in 2021.53
While multiple factors contribute to supply shortfalls, the failure of
A third example of an upstream structural injustice relates to the wealthy countries is a significant part of the supply problem.
design and execution of COVAX. COVAX is the co‐led partnership Third, while COVAX produced the social good of making vaccines
between two international philanthropic organizations, CEPI and available to poorer countries, it simultaneously thwarted an historic
Gavi, and the WHO. Its initial goal was delivering two billion doses of opportunity. Early in the pandemic, governments, pharmaceutical
vaccines by the end of 2021, with each participating country re- companies, the National Institutes of Health, and the WHO were at-
ceiving sufficient doses to vaccinate its highest priority populations tempting to put in place a just system for distributing vaccines that
and 20% of its general population. COVAX initially functioned like an would curb the profits of pharmaceutical companies and reign in the
insurance plan, enticing wealthier countries to invest in its efforts in power of wealthy purchasers by establishing a pooled resource of
exchange for priority access to a portfolio of vaccine candidates it COVID‐19 products that would “override a global drug system based
was purchasing by pooling resources from many countries. While on proprietary science and market monopolies.”54 The effect of forming
COVID‐19 vaccine candidates were still being studied, wealthy COVAX was that these efforts lost steam and never materialized.
countries had no idea if the vaccine candidates they had paid for Finally, baked into COVAX's model is a form of philanthropy that
would wind up being effective; overall, just 20% of clinical trials of has been termed, philanthrocapitalism, because it emulates the way
pharmaceutical products result in a marketable product.49 Against business is done in the capitalist world.55 Through COVAX, rich na-
this backdrop, many high‐income nations were persuaded to join tions essentially became “rivals” with COVAX in “a vaccine‐buying
COVAX. Simultaneously, they were completing their own bilateral race,” bidding up vaccine prices and creating supply shortages.56
advance purchase deals directly with pharmaceutical companies. Meanwhile, poorer countries were left to rely on loans to finance
COVAX fell short of is aspirations in ways that reveal structural debt in order to pay pharmaceutical companies for lifesaving vac-
injustices in its design and execution. First, during the critical period cines. Philanthrocapitalism concentrates power in the hands of a
when COVAX was signing participants, raising funds, and pooling small group of wealthy philanthropreneurs. Both CEPI and Gavi were
demand to advance purchases vaccines, its efforts were stymied by founded by the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation, which is also the
wealthy nations buying up most of the initial global vaccine supply.
According to Christos Christou, President of Médecins Sans Fron-
tières, “by pre‐booking billions of doses of COVID‐19 vaccines out- 50
Christou, C. (2021, September 15). More Empty Promises about Global Vaccine Equity.
side of COVAX, the EU and other high‐income countries have side‐ Quoted in Médecins Sans Frontières & European Union. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from
https://www.msf.org/european-union-more-empty-promises-about-global-covid-19-
lined the mechanism. As a result, COVAX has been left without vaccine-equity
51
Robbins, R. (2021, October 9, Updated November 9). Moderna, Racing for Profits, Keeps
Covid Vaccine Out of Reach of Poor. New York Times.
52
Cheng, M. & Hinnant, L. (2021, August 14). Back of the Line: Charity Only Goes So Far. AP
45
World Trade Organization. (2020, October 2). Waiver from Certain Provisions of the TRIPS News. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from https://apnews.com/article/joe-biden-middle-
Agreement for the Prevention, Containment and Treatment of COVID‐19, Communication east-canada-health-coronavirus-pandemic-4581a4ac07631e66f9db8fd0dd02942a
from India and South Africa. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from https://docs.wto.org/ 53
United Nations. (2021, September 8). COVID‐19: ‘Unacceptable’ Deals and Delays,
dol2fe/Pages/SS/directdoc.aspx?filename=q:/IP/C/W669.pdf&Open=True Hampering Lifesaving COVAX Deliveries. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from https://news.
46
Josephs, J. (2021, February 16). New WTO Boss Warns Against Vaccine Nationalism. BBC un.org/en/story/2021/09/1099422
54
News. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from https://www.bbc.com/news/business-56079088 Zaitchik, I. (2021, April 12). How Bill Gates Impeded Global Access to Covid Vaccines. New
47
Trebilcock, & Howse, op. cit. note 42. Republic. Retrieved December 1, 2021.
48 55
International Monetary Fund. (2021, October). World Economic Outlook: Recovery During a Bishop, M., & Green, M. (2010). Philanthrocapitalism: How Giving Can Save the World.
Pandemic. Washington, D.C.: International Monetary Fund. Bloomsbury Publishing USA.
49 56
Wong, C. H., Siah, K. W., & Lo, A. W. (2019). Estimation of Clinical Trial Success Rates and Mueller, B. & Robbins, R. (2021, August 2). Where a Vast Global Vaccination Program
Related Parameters. Biostatistics, 20(2), 273‐286. Went Wrong. New York Times.
JECKER | 7

largest funder of the WHO. CEPI and Gavi are accountable only to 4 | PRACTICAL I MPLICA TIONS
their shareholders; to the extent that the WHO becomes reliant on
private donors, this conflicts with its duty to member states. Building on the analysis throughout the paper, I turn next to examine
Stepping back from the analysis of this section, the examples of more closely the practical duties of justice wealthy nations owe as
concessionary lending, TRIPS, and COVAX illustrate injustices that are beneficiaries of structural injustices. As noted previously (Section II),
structural in the sense that the social structural positions that poorer the debts incurred by benefitting from general injustice are diffuse,
states occupy put them at a disadvantage relative to others. In the first i.e., it is unclear how much is owed and to whom. The Kantian
case, concessionary lending demonstrated structural injustice because principle stated that a duty of recompense might be paid as a general
it deprived poorer nations of the means to develop their own capacities duty to the least well off. Yet one worry with this strategy is that it
through domestic programs and infrastructures. In the second example, places victims of injustice at a disadvantage twice over: first, from the
TRIPS strengthened the hand of for‐profit pharmaceutical companies original injustice and second, because the duty can be discharged at
by enabling them to protect profits in sales of pharmaceuticals to low‐ the timing and manner of the benefactors' choosing.59 Is there more
and middle‐income nations; it simultaneously excluded these nations that we can say? This section explores practical ways of spelling out
from timely access to lifesaving vaccines and thwarted their ability to the duty beneficiaries of injustice owe.
meet their citizens' basic health needs. Finally, COVAX kept in place
market structures and vaccine monopolies, reinforcing a business
model and putting down initial efforts to reform these structures. 4.1 | Relinquishing holdings and restituting victims
Taken together, these examples of upstream structural injustices
show that wealthy countries benefitted from injustices and incurred a One alternative is to emphasize the objects of gain and loss. It holds
duty of recompense. The Kantian analysis (from section II) suggests that parties benefitting from unjust structures should relinquish the
that as a consequence of benefitting from such injustice, wealthy benefits/advantages gained and restitute the harms/disadvantages
nations incur a duty of recompense to people in poorer nations that lost. Notably, advantages and disadvantages often accrue to people
lost out. Kant thought the best way to repay in such case was often other than (or in addition to) the original perpetrators and victims. For
helping the least well off. If that is right, rather than regarding nations example, TRIPS benefitted future generations of stockholders at
that share vaccines as altruistic do‐gooders, they are more aptly seen Pfizer, Moderna, and Johnson & Johnson during the COVID‐19
as setting things right. Thinking of vaccine sharing as an act of charity pandemic, as well as citizens of wealthy nations who accessed
wrongly positions poorer nations as akin to beggars, pleading for globally scarce vaccines before poorer nations. On this interpretation,
favors. Kant adamantly opposed begging, regarding it as “depreciat- the requirement to relinquish ill‐gotten gains applies irrespective of
ing” and “abasing,”57 because it forces some citizens to become de- whether the beneficiary took part in the original wrongdoing or did
pendent on the choices and will of others. anything to solicit the benefit.60 The idea is simply that those hold-
An objection to the case‐based argument is that duties arising ings are illegitimate. Goodin puts the point this way: “People
out of individuals' acts at a particular historical moment do not wrongfully in possession of goods should acknowledge that they
transfer from individuals to nations. In response, nations routinely have no legitimate claim to them and should be prepared to give
incur responsibilities for actions performed by individuals when those them up.”61
individuals act in official capacities on behalf of their governments. In Unlike relinquishing holdings, which focuses on perpetrators,
the cases discussed, when government officials negotiated and voted restitution foregrounds victims. Restitution claims that people who
on international financial regimes, such as concessionary lending have lost something that was rightfully theirs deserve something
programs and TRIPS, or when government leaders joined COVAX, back. With restitution, the point is not a particular victim's welfare,
they were acting in official roles. Their actions embedded injustices in but more generally putting objects in the hands of a group of people
the global basic structure, for which governments bear responsibility. who rightfully hold them. This involves attending to the overall pat-
Another possible concern is that the cases selected are drawn tern of exchange that injustice disrupts and making amends through
from the recent past; perhaps, considering the more distant past social schemes that restore objects to persons or groups.
would weaken the argument. In reply, considering the more distant A pragmatic advantage of a restitution strategy is that in order to
past is apt to strengthen, not weaken, the argument, since it would establish a duty, it is sufficient to know that holdings are substantially
include the long history of colonialism, in which European‐led colonial tainted; it is not necessary to know more, e.g., the identities of par-
and imperial expansion was marked by “conquest, dispossession, legal ticular perpetrators that merit punishment, or the identities of par-
exclusion and unequal treaties, not to mention enslavement, political ticular victims that merit compensation. In the case of COVID‐19
subjugation, forced labor, violence, and even genocide.”58

59
Moran, op. cit. note 22.
57 60
Kant, I. (1997/1793). Notes on the Lectures of Mr. Kant on the Metaphysics of Morals. In Pasternak, A. (2016). In K Lippert‐Rasmussen, K. Brownlee, & D. Coady (Eds.), Companion
P. Heath, & J. B. Schneewind (Eds.), P. Heath (Transl.), Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics. to Applied Philosophy (pp. 411‐423). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
61
(pp. 249‐452). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, pp. 421, 351. Goodin, R. (2013). Disgorging the Fruits of Historical Wrongdoing. American Political
58
Lu, op. cit. note 29, p. 143. Science Review, 107(3), 478‐491.
8 | JECKER

vaccines, this approach gives ground for saying that if the vaccines 4.2 | Restoring relationships
possessed by wealthy nations are tainted by structural injustices,
wealthy nations have a duty to give them up. The underlying ethical To understand more clearly how the sustaining harms principle
reason is that there is something wrong about enjoying the fruits of applies during the COVID‐19 crisis we need to say more about what
wrongdoing. More precisely stated, it means to ‘sustain harms.’ One way of spelling this out identifies
the kind of harm at stake as relational. On this rendering, the
Wrongful benefits principle: if one benefits from wrongfulness of retaining ill‐gotten gains is not just that the dis-
wrongdoing one incurs a moral duty to address the tribution that results from unfair negotiations is unjust, but also that
wrongdoing and/or disgorge the wrongful benefit.62 ill‐gotten gains damage relationships between nations. Building on
Barry and Wiens' analysis, a principle of right relations holds that
Yet a difficulty the wrongful benefits principle faces is that there beneficiaries incur a debt just in case their actions sustain harms and
are cases where benefits accrue from wrongdoing that are purely disrupt right relations.
happenstance. Barry gives the example of a terrorist bomb that leads
to a chance meeting between two individuals who subsequently form Principle of right relations: beneficiaries of wrongdoing
a lucrative partnership.63 Participants in the lucrative partnership incur a duty to victims of wrongdoing just in case they
benefitted from the bombing in the sense that if it had not occurred, (1) receive and retain benefits and (2) doing so sustains
they may never have met; yet, they did nothing wrong and do not a wrongful harm and (3) this includes disrupting right
incur a duty to the bombing's victims. Thus, even if benefitting from relations.
wrongdoing is necessary, it seems not to be sufficient to incur a duty
of justice. Analogously, the mere fact that wealthy countries bene- Walker captures the crux of a relational account a duty to “repair
fitted from ill‐gotten access to vaccines is not sufficient to say they relations damaged by injustice,” distinguishing this from corrective
have a duty of justice to relinquish vaccines or share them with justice, which aims to return victims to a pre‐harm baseline.66 Walker
victims. Whether a duty to share arises depends on other con- notes that corrective justice, which stresses relinquishing holdings or
siderations. One additional consideration that seems salient is whe- restituting victims, does not always do enough, because it does not
ther the benefits people in wealthy nations gained enabled or assess the pre‐harm baseline or recognize that it might be tainted. By
reproduced injustices. Since the chance meeting that led to the lu- contrast, the aim of right relations is normative. It aspires to relations
crative partnership did not perpetuate terrorist bombings, it does not in which
yield any duties on the part of those who formed the partnership.
This leads Barry and Wiens to endorse a variation of the wrongful people are confident that they share… basic standards
benefits principle: for the treatment of each other. are able to trust each
other to abide by those standards or at least to ac-
Sustaining harms principle: beneficiaries incur knowledge fault if they (or others) do not.… [and] are
benefitting‐related duties to the victims of wrong- entitled to be hopeful that unacceptable treatment
doings…if and only if receiving and retaining the will not prevail, that unacceptable behavior will not be
benefits sustains wrongful harm.64 defended or ignored where it occurs, and that victims
will not be abandoned.67
In the cases explored in Section III, wealthy countries incurred
duties not just because they received ill‐gotten gains, but also be- On this analysis, relinquishing holdings and restituting victims is
cause they used their privileged status to perpetuate injustices. To necessary, not sufficient. Repairing relationships damaged by in-
take but one example, wealthy nations struck bilateral advance justice is also necessary. Combining corrective and relational
market deals to hoard vaccines, which drove down global vaccine approaches affords the better strategy, because it both gives up
supply and bid up prices. These deals were made possible by the ill‐gotten gains and examines the normative baseline.
patent protections TRIPS established for pharmaceutical companies.
In addition, wealthy nations perpetuated wrongful harms by offering
booster doses to their own citizens before ensuring people in 4.3 | Next Steps
low‐income nations could access first shots.65
Taking steps to remedy structural injustices is a duty that befalls all
nations who participated in them, but especially beneficiaries. In the
three cases discussed above (concessionary lending, TRIPS, and
62
Goodin, R. & Pasternak, A. (2016). Intending to Benefit from Wrongdoing. Politics,
Philosophy and Economics, 15(3), 280‐297.
63
Barry, C., & Wiens, D. (2016). Benefitting from Wrongdoing and Sustaining Wrongful
66
Harm. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 13(5), 530‐552, p. 532. Walker, M. U. (2006). Restorative Justice and Reparations. Journal of Social Philosophy,
64
Ibid: 533. 37(3), 377‐395, p. 377.
65 67
Jecker, & Lederman, op. cit. note 3. Ibid: 384.
JECKER | 9

TABLE 1 Structural Injustices in Global Vaccine Allocation and Steps to Rectify Them

Structural injustices Steps to rectify injustices

Concessionary lending • Undercuts domestic self‐determination Set standards for World Bank & IMF lending to support self‐
• Exploits economic inequalities determination & build health systems capacity
• Adversely affects health systems in poorer nations

TRIPS • Reduces capacities of poorer nations to meet duties to Waive intellectual property during pandemic emergencies
citizens
• Exploits political inequalities at WTO
• Adversely affects health access in poorer nations by
limiting diffusion of innovations

COVAX • Lacks funding & enforcement Empower global institutions to fund and enforce pandemic
• Thwarts efforts to establish alternative frameworks response
• Undermines democratic values & concentrates power
in the hands of private philanthropists

COVAX), the wealthiest nations incurred special duties by virtue of Another example of a transformative reparation is waiving in-
the privileged vaccine access they gained through unjust systems. tellectual property protections for vaccines and other pharmaceuticals
While there is not a single way to go about righting relations, a pri- and taking other steps to build drug manufacturing capacities, such as
mary goal should be transformative reparations. sharing knowhow, technology, and resources to expand drug manu-
An example that illustrates transformative reparations is re- facturing capacities. A concrete step toward realizing this during the
quiring World Bank and IMF lending to contribute to health systems COVID‐19 pandemic would be passing India and South Africa's peti-
development in economically developing nations in ways that avoid tion to the WTO to temporarily waive intellectual property rights for
creating financial hardship for those countries. Examples are lending medical products pertaining to preventing, containing, or treating
that supports domestic capacities for universal healthcare, health COVID‐19.71 Rather than viewing this as an act of charity given to
research, and manufacturing of pharmaceutical products. Ethically, poorer nations, the arguments throughout the paper suggest that it is
the rationale for imposing such a requirement on the World Bank more properly understood as a duty of justice.
and IMF is that a country's health care system is the first line of Finally, empowering the WHO and/or other global institutions with
defense during a pandemic emergency. Financing aimed to support funding and enforcement authorities needed to address global health
universal healthcare systems and build health system resilience is emergencies would enact transformative reparations. Many of the
transformative in the sense that it builds “the capacity of health structures that govern relations between nations date to 1945 and the
actors, institutions, and populations to prepare for and effectively aftermath of the Second World War, when the UN was created to
respond to crises, maintain core functions when a crisis hits; and, provide a forum for discussions and agreements between states. The UN
informed by lessons learned during the crisis, reorganize if condi- and the organizations under its sponsorship (such as the WHO, WTO,
tions require it.”68 Promising developments in this area include the IMF and World Bank) have no independent powers of enforcement or
WHO's establishment of mRNA vaccine technology transfer hub,69 sources of funding and serve at the behest of member states. Funding
and the WTO's expression of interest in creating regional vaccine for these global institutions could be established by creating an Inter-
70
manufacturing hubs in South Africa, Senegal, Rwanda, or Nigeria. national Pandemic Financing Facility capable of rapidly scaling up funding
Yet more is needed. The African Union has set a continent‐wide for pandemic response and require contributions based on countries'
goal of raising vaccine capacity from 1% to 60% by 2040 and ability to pay.72 Powers of enforcement for global institutions could be
expanding the fill and finish vaccine manufacturing capacities cur- established by harnessing the power of law to promote global health and
rently being established to encompass more stages up and down the sustainable development, as the Lancet Commission recommends.73
chain of vaccine development. Strengthening global institutions will be essential to overcoming barriers
to transformative change, such as short‐termism, nationalism, costs, and
‘capture’ by private for‐profit industries.74

68
Kruk, M., Myers, E. M., Varpilah, S. T., Dahn, B. T. (2015). What is a Resilient Health
71
System? Lessons from Ebola. Lancet, 385(9980), 1910‐1912. Sell, Ikenberry, & Smith, op. cit. note 35.
69 72
World Health Organization. (2021, April 16). Establishment of a COVID‐19 mRNA Vaccine Gostin, L. O. (2021). 9 Steps to End COVID‐19 and Prevent the Next Pandemic. JAMA
Technology Transfer Hub to Scale Up Global Manufacturing. Retrieved December 1, 2021, Health Forum, 2(6), e211852.
73
from https://www.who.int/news-room/articles-detail/establishment-of-a-covid-19-mrna- Gostin, L. O., Monahan, J. T., Kaldor, J., et al. (2019). The Legal Determinants of Health:
vaccine-technology-transfer-hub-to-scale-up-global-manufacturing Harnessing the Power of Law for Global Health and Sustainable Development. Lancet,
70
Miller, J. (2021, June 21). WTO Head Says South Africa, Senegal, Rwanda and Nigeria 393(10183), 1857‐1910.
74
Considered as Vaccine Production Hubs. Reuters. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from Goldin, I. (2020, September 1). Rethinking Global Resilience. IMF Finance and
https://www.reuters.com/world/wto-head-says-south-africa-senegal-rwanda-nigeria- Development Magazine. Retrieved December 1, 2021, from https://www.imf.org/external/
considered-vaccine-production-2021-06-21/ pubs/ft/fandd/2020/09/pdf/rethinking-global-resilience-ian-goldin.pdf
10 | JECKER

Table 1 displays the sources of structural injustice discussed in AUTHOR BIOGRAPHY


Section III and the possible steps to rectify them.
Nancy S. Jecker, PhD, is a Fulbright Scholar (2021‐22); Visiting
Professor, University of Johannesburg, Department of Philoso-
5 | C ONC LUS I ON phy; and Professor, University of Washington School of
Medicine. Dr. Jecker's research explores justice, human dignity
In conclusion, this paper argued that that the duty of wealthier na- and global bioethics, particularly in sub‐Saharan Africa and East
tions to share vaccines is a duty of justice, not charity. A case‐based Asia. Her most recent book is Ending Midlife Bias: New Values for
argument established that privileged access to COVID‐19 vaccines Old Age (Oxford University Press, 2020).
reflects upstream structural injustices. By benefitting from and sus-
taining structural injustices, wealthier nations incur a duty to restitute
victims and restore right relations. All nations have a duty to enact
How to cite this article: Jecker, N. S. (2022). Global sharing of
transformative change to create fairer structures.
COVID‐19 vaccines: A duty of justice, not charity. Developing
World Bioethics, 1–10. https://doi.org/10.1111/dewb.12342
ORCID
Nancy S. Jecker http://orcid.org/0000-0002-5642-748X

You might also like