Reuther

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 15

Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology © 2013 American Psychological Association

2014, Vol. 34, No. 2, 101–115 1068-8471/14/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0033040

On Our Everyday Being: Heidegger and Attachment Theory

Bryan T. Reuther
Nova Southeastern University

Each of us acquires a sense of everyday being implicitly through our engagement with
the social milieu. Understanding this being from the usual individualistic psychological
perspective suggests it originates from a subjective, internal private world. This
position, descended from Cartesian dualism, bifurcates human experience, rendering an
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

isolated subject and a decontextualized external world. Martin Heidegger rejected this
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

idea and contended that our sense of being springs from a more basic and primordial
engagement with the social world as a meaningful totality of being-in-the-world.
However, he did not explain how human beings develop this everyday being. Attach-
ment theory, espoused by John Bowlby, positions human beings from birth with the
innate ability to form close relationships with others, which serve critical roles in early
development and throughout the life span. This article integrates Heidegger’s social
ontology with Bowlby’s attachment theory to establish a nondualistic theoretical
grounding for human relational development, and provides the beginnings of an
existentially based developmental ontology of human being that fits within the current
movement of post-Cartesian thought.

Keywords: Heidegger, Bowlby, being-in-the-world, attachment theory, human development

We are all born into a social world of human of understanding this being? Where does it orig-
construction. At some point during our devel- inate and how does it develop? If we start from
opment, we literally discover ourselves as ac- an individualistic psychological perspective,
tive members of human sociocultural groups this framework will suggest that our everyday
already engaging in certain ways of interacting being originates from a subjective, internal
with others, interpreting situations, and making private world. This position, descended from
sense of experiences. In our experience of ev- Cartesian dualism, bifurcates human experi-
eryday life as members of the social milieu, we ence, rendering an isolated subject and a de-
come to absorb, rather implicitly, ways to feel contextualized external world. While on a
and behave in certain contexts. This process certain reflective level, we can surely per-
subsequently brings into focus our sense of our ceive objects and other people in the world as
potentials and limitations within our social con- seemingly “subjective” entities to fulfill the
text, and most centrally how things are mean- dichotomy, parting off experience in such a
ingful— essentially what can be considered our way, as Rollo May (1983/1994) suggested,
way of being. Given this, what is the best way loses the richness of the living, existing hu-
man being’s relationship to and engagement
in the world. Consequently, this dualistic po-
sition cannot be the fundamental starting
This article was published Online First July 29, 2013.
Many thanks to Steve Gold, Geoff Pfeiffer, and Eugene place if we are to understand human being,
May for the many conversations and endless support, which subsequently calling for an understanding that
helped me develop the ideas in this article. I also thank three collapses this duality in pursuit of the depth
anonymous reviewers, whose helpful comments and sug-
gestions on previous drafts undoubtedly improved this arti-
and robustness of being grounded in human
cle. This article is a much expanded version of a poster existence.
presented at the 120th Annual American Psychological As- A steward of this line of thought, the philos-
sociation Convention in Orlando, Florida, in August 2012. opher Martin Heidegger (1927/1962) rejected
Correspondence concerning this article should be ad-
dressed to Bryan T. Reuther, Center for Psychological Stud-
the idea of everyday being as derived from a
ies, Nova Southeastern University, 3301 College Avenue, privatized, internal realm of subjectivity.
Davie, FL 33314. E-mail: btreuther@gmail.com Heidegger repositioned the usual assumptions
101
102 REUTHER

of a dualistic starting place as a derivative ontology to help elucidate how we arrive at a


mode, one that springs from a more basic, pri- sense of everyday being?
mordial, and practical engagement with the Given that Heidegger positioned others as the
world as a meaningful totality—what he called primary source of social possibilities, to under-
“being-in-the-world.” This is a theoretical move stand a person’s being-in-the-world, this article
with ontological significance that depicts a hu- will demonstrate how the affectively laden
man being, or Dasein, before any internal sub- activity in attachment relationships fit within
jective mind and external objective world is Heideggerian thought. Moreover, using
abstracted. He contextualized human existence Heidegger’s conception of mood, this article
through embedded, mutually constitutive activ- will also establish how the inherent emotional
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

ity that is given through immersion in the so- and affective value held in these early attach-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

ciocultural practices. Within his conception of ment relationships help attune us to the world,
being-in-the-world, Heidegger forwarded a set the tone for future experiences, and gener-
unique view of emotional life that is existen- ally provide a source of sense of our everyday
tially grounded in Befindlichkeit,1 which is ex- being. Relevant supportive research in develop-
perienced as “moods.” For Heidegger, moods mental psychology and psychoanalysis will also
are inundated with meanings and are responsi- be woven into this analysis. The main goal of
ble for attuning us to our being-in-the-world. this article is to evince the relevancy and appro-
In situating human beings as being-in-the- priateness of Heidegger’s work, especially his
world, Heidegger contended that we take up our unique social ontology and collapsing of Carte-
everyday being via our absorptive immersion in sian-based dualities, as a philosophical and the-
the sociocultural milieu. This occurs rather im- oretical grounding for developmental and rela-
plicitly through our practical activity with oth- tional psychological theory. It will also seek to
ers, grounded in another existential structure, provide the beginnings of a developmental ap-
designated as Verfallen, or falling. In other proach to Heidegger’s philosophy of Dasein
words, through our absorption, we “fall” into and being-in-the-world, with the intent of work-
certain ways of being-in-the-world that are al- ing toward an existentially based developmental
ready always possibilities available to us given ontology, which may have conceptual and prac-
by our sociocultural times and situation. He tical implications on how we view human
offered a rich ontological backdrop for the irre- being. The following sections introduce
ducibility and context specificity of human so- Heidegger’s philosophical ideas and Bowlby’s
cial life and the constitution of being. However, psychologically based attachment theory.
he did not explain how human beings, at least
developmentally, come to this everyday being.
The psychoanalyst John Bowlby’s (1969/ Heidegger’s Thought
1982) attachment theory suggests that relation-
ships, particularly those involving emotional In Being and Time, Heidegger introduced the
and affective engagements with primary care- nature of Dasein and the structure of being-in-
givers, have an enormous impact on how a the-world. The introduction of these terms was
person develops perceptions and understand- intended to deliver a fresh perspective for the
ings of themselves, others, and the world. More analysis of the human being. Dasein, which
specifically, attachment theory positions human literally translates as “being-there,” is essen-
beings from birth with the innate ability to form tially Heidegger’s (1927/1962) name for all of
close relationships with other human beings. us as human beings: “Dasein is not only close to
These ongoing “attachment relationships,” ac- us— even that which is closest: we are it, each
cording to Bowlby, are the hub around which a of us, we ourselves” (p. 36). He continued,
person’s life revolves and, in many ways, pro- “Dasein is an entity which in each case I am
vide structures for engendering a sense of how myself” (p. 78). As Hubert Dreyfus (1991)
a human being behaves in and experiences a stated, Dasein “can refer to a way of being that
particular interpersonal or social situations. is characteristic of all people or to a specific
Given the aforementioned positions, can the
relationally based developmental perspective of 1
Befindlichkeit is a complex Heideggerian term that will
attachment theory fit within Heidegger’s social be defined and addressed later in this article.
ON OUR EVERYDAY BEING 103

person—a human being” (p. 14). Dasein, how- with others presupposes an existential structure
ever, is not to be understood as a subject with a of being-with. Our mere existence places us in a
consciousness; instead, it is assigned as the on- position to always be with others, even when
tological character of human beings as contex- alone, as we are always experiencing a human
tualized and embedded in the world with others, world. Dasein’s ontological being-with and on-
as a part of the irreducible totality of existence. tic2 being-with others are central features of
Being-in-the-world is an ontological struc- being-in-the-world. It is through our practical
ture, which supplies the grounding for Dasein’s engagements with others that we take up these
existential character. Dasein is essentially be- humanly possibilities according to context.
ing-in-the-world. Being-in-the-world is the Given the primacy of our engagement with oth-
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

most basic, primordial structure, which, as ers in a social world, Heidegger was clear on
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

Heidegger (1927/1962) wrote, “stands for a uni- presenting a source, or the “who,” of everyday
tary phenomenon” and “must be seen as a being, which is the society and culture in which
whole” (p. 78). In this way, he closed the onto- we exist.
logical gap between dualistic conceptions of The “who” of everydayness, constitutes what
subject/object, inner/outer, and individual/ Heidegger called das Man, or the they.
world, with the implication that one must be Heidegger (1927/1962) indicated that “[t]he
understood in context of the other as a process- ‘they’ has its own ways to be. . .that concerns
oriented, meaning embedded whole. Heidegger itself as such with averageness, which is the
continued by saying that “’[b]eing-in’ is thus existential character of the ‘they’” (p. 164). He
the formal existential expression for the being added that “[t]he self of everyday Dasein is
of Dasein, which has being-in-the-world as its the ‘they-self’” (p. 167). That is to say, who we
existential state” (p. 80). Given this, being-in are as a self-identity, as Dasein, is held in the
the world is not to be understood spatially as societies and cultures in which we live. It is
liquid is in a cup, but rather to refer to each of through the existential structure of Verfallen,
our existences as a relational primacy of prere- translated as falling, that we “fall” into the
flective, practical action with the world. We world of what the “they” or sociocultural milieu
simply go about our everyday lives, doing what does in any particular context. He indicated that
we do without any indication of a mind relating this “fallenness into the world means an absorp-
to others and the world. Primordially, we are a tion in being-with-one-another” (p. 220). Our
part of the overall process of each social event. falling occurs rather implicitly and prereflec-
Along with this, Heidegger assigned Dasein as tively, and can be understood as a kind of con-
being-in-the-world as Lichtung, which refers to forming. Whether we are aware of it or not, we
both a light and a clearing (as in a clearing in all subscribe to different sociocultural entities to
the forest). Dasein is the type of being that is define who we are; these include peer groups,
open to and illuminates the world, allowing the occupations, religious entities, cultures, and so
world to be revealed and be known. For exam- on. Each of these entities has their own partic-
ple, consider the world as a dark room and the ular systems of meaning, modes of interacting,
human being, as Dasein, as a sort of brightness possibilities, limitations, and ways of being af-
or illumination. As the human being moves fected by the world. In our everydayness, we
through the darkness, the surrounding area be- comport ourselves as context-dependent expres-
comes illuminated or cleared, revealing this
sions of the being provided by our societies and
openness to the possibilities of a human world.
cultures. As consequence to this, Heidegger
Simultaneously, Dasein will always be con-
mentioned that considering the averageness of
stricted or “darkened” to certain other possibil-
the “they,” conforming to these customs, tradi-
ities of the world. In all, Dasein will always be
in a struggle with simultaneous openness and
constrictiveness to possibilities in its world dis- 2
Heidegger made the distinction between “ontological”
closure. and “ontic” in his analysis. Ontological refers to the nature
Moreover, Heidegger (1927/1962) situated of our existence and being, while ontic refers to the way in
which, for example psychologically, we experience our
“the world of Dasein is a with-world (Mitwelt). being. Accordingly, Heidegger (1927/1962) stated “Dasein
Being-in is being-with others” (p. 155). Expe- is ontically distinctive in that it is ontological” (p. 32,
riencing other people in everyday life as being- emphasis in original).
104 REUTHER

tions, and practices is a “‘leveling down’ of all they are not cognitive phenomena, at least at the
possibilities of being” (p. 165). primordial level, but rather are the tacitly sensed
Within being-in-the-world, Heidegger and felt total experience that attunes us to the
assigned Befindlichkeit, which is roughly trans- world. Simply put, moods are always there to
lated to affectedness or attunement, as the par- disclose how we are in our everydayness as
ticular mode of existence that provides the being-in-the-world.
possibility of the world as “always already”
mattering in some way. It is one of four exis-
tential structures of being-in-the-world, which Bowlby’s Attachment Theory
also includes understanding (Verstehen), discur-
Bowlby’s attachment theory is a relationally
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

siveness (Rede), and falling (Verfallen). Al-


This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

though these structures are equiprimordial, in based psychological theory grounded in ethnol-
the revealing of Dasein’s world disclosure, this ogy, human development, and evolutionary the-
analysis will focus mostly on Befindlichkeit as ory. He contended that, from birth, human
our primordial affectedness and Verfallen as beings form attachment relationships to adult
falling, because both of these structures are of humans that are in close proximity, typically
particular relevance to the aim of this article. ones that have the most contact, such as care-
Befindlichkeit is the existential possibility for a givers (e.g., parents or parental surrogates).4
meaning disclosing world that reveals being-in- Attachment theory positions human infants with
the world as a whole (Heidegger, 1927/1962; the innate, biologically “programmed” ability to
Gendlin, 1988). This structure is ontically ex- engage in certain attachment behaviors, such as
perienced through mood. For Heidegger (1927/ clinging, sucking, grasping, and following, as
1962), mood “comes from neither ‘outside’ nor well as signaling behaviors of crying and smil-
from ‘inside,’ but arises out of being-in-the- ing (Bowlby, 1969/1982; Bretherton, 1992).
world, as a way of such being” (p. 176). Moods Moreover, adult humans will also have special
are, therefore, neither internally derived (sub- ways of responding to infants and children,
jective) concepts nor ones that are received which are oftentimes the result of their own
wholly from the external (objective). Instead, experiences with attachment figures (Bowlby,
they arise from mutually constituted practical 1969/1982). From an evolutionary perspective,
activity with others within certain sociocultural attachment-seeking and signaling behaviors op-
contexts. Along with moods, the disclosing erated to ensure the survival of the child due to
modes of Befindlichkeit may also be expressed the variety of environmental hazards and pred-
experientially as emotions, feelings, and affects ators human ancestors faced. Given the com-
(Boss, 1979/1994; Gendlin, 1988). plexities of human social life, intimate bonds
According to Heidegger, moods reveal our form from the interaction of the infant and care-
inherent thrownness, orientation to the possibil- giver and provide the foundation for the infant’s
ities in a social world, and how things matter. future socioemotional development (Bowlby,
Thrownness is the fact that we fundamentally 1969/1982, 1988; Thompson, 1993).
exist in a world and have to be one thing or
another—we are always affected by the world 3
and we can never be without some relation to it. This is a good example of how Befindlichkeit as affect-
edness is equiprimordial to understanding in the constitution
Our orientation to possibilities is our orientation of everyday being. In this case, the ontically or psycholog-
to a social world with potentials that are avail- ically experienced mood discloses how Dasein is in a par-
able. He held that “by way of having a mood, ticular situation. Dasein’s ability to “see” possibilities rep-
Dasein ‘sees’ possibilities” and “in the projec- resents having implicit knowledge or “know how” given
tive disclosure of possibilities, it already has a their attunement (mood) and, therefore, an understanding of
the situation.
mood” (Heidegger, 1927/1962, p. 188). This 4
It should be noted that, although mothers have histori-
orientation allows for the discovery of others in cally been viewed as the primary attachment figure, attach-
the world and the possibilities therein.3 Finally, ments can include fathers and other human beings to a
moods reveal how the world matters in a certain greater or lesser extent. Infants and children often form
multiple attachments; however, the primary attachment fig-
way. They saturate the world with meanings by ure tends to be the one who spends the most time with the
unveiling situations as frustrating, anxious, infant and therefore has the greatest impact on his or her
pleasant, joyful, and so forth. Consequently, development.
ON OUR EVERYDAY BEING 105

The main goal of attachment systems is to adulthood. It is important to note that general
provide the infant or child with a sense of felt attachment behaviors and the formation of inti-
security; that others can be relied on for protec- mate relationships are fairly universal; however,
tion and support when needed. Early in human the way in which these behaviors manifest over
development, separation from an attachment time and the forms they take may vary based on
figure will often evoke distress, fear, and pro- sociocultural practices.
test, which are seen as manifestations of what is
called separation anxiety (Bowlby, 1988). The Everyday Being and Attachment Theory
way in which separation is handled is critical to
the developing human being. If the attachment The preceding sections provided a general
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

figure consistently attends to the child when overview of both Heidegger’s and Bowlby’s
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

needed or in distress, the child learns that safety thought. Before continuing, it should be noted
and security is possible. As a result, the child is that implied in Bowlby’s developmental frame-
able to handle separation more effectively and work are deterministic and linear conceptions of
is able to develop adaptive strategies to cope, development, with the most poignant example
such as find it in others (e.g., teachers, intimate being internal working models. Yet, this aspect
partners). With the establishment of security of his theory is not necessarily a burden to the
through the attachment relationship, infants and present analysis because the actual phenomena
children can explore their environment from Bowlby described can be grounded and recast
this secure “base” and gain experiences and using Heidegger’s social ontology. As such,
move toward autonomy. Moreover, Bowlby viewing internal working models through a
noted that if the child is inconsistently re- Heideggerian lens dramatically contextualizes
sponded to or rejected outright, insecure attach- them while also collapsing their dualistic struc-
ments can form, impairing the child’s emotional ture. The “internal” aspect of the working
development and ability to explore the world. model implies something that was internalized
These positions have a profound and long- and now resides inside the person—as inside a
standing impact on the development of the per- type of cognitive container, isolated and closed
son and the way in which the social world is off from the world. The allocation of these
revealed. models as decontextualized stored “things” is
These intimate relational bonds with attach- misleading when understanding their embedded
ments provide people with models for future practical and social function. Even Bowlby
social interactions and interpersonal relation- (1988) acknowledged that “the forms they take,
ships, which Bowlby (1988) called “internal as the evidence strongly suggests, are based on
working models.” More specifically, internal the child’s real-life experience of day-to-day
working models are a species of cognitive sche- interactions with the parents” (pp. 129 –130). In
mata that govern the way a person interprets a person’s everydayness, these patterns are pre-
oneself, others, and the world that impact social reflective, active modes of existence that in-
expectations, socioemotional understandings, volve an embodied person in a contextual
and personality (Thompson, 2008a). Bowlby’s world, not a static set of rules that exist “inside”
notion of internal working models—along with a cognitive container consulted prior to action
their concomitant content—which are generated or behavior. Furthermore, the relational psycho-
from secure or insecure attachments, greatly analyst Stephen Mitchell (2000) stated:
direct experiences and understandings of self
and others (Thompson, 2008b). Earlier experi- We might speculate that the residue of attachment
experiences, both early on and through later life, in-
ences, particularly with caregivers, provide an cludes not simply cognitive working models of the
initial framework, which remains consistent interpersonal world, but affective states of undifferen-
throughout life, even though it is possible that tiated connection with attachment figures, organized
later experiences with other attachment figures around both positive affects, like euphoria or soothing
can alter and “revise” these “models.” Attach- calm, and negative affects, like depression, anxiety, or
terror. (pp. 90 –91)
ments eventually expand beyond caregivers and
close family members to include peer groups in Therefore, it can be said that different possi-
adolescence, as well as occupations, intimate bilities and interpretations are disclosed through
partners, and religious and cultural figures in these emotionally saturated lived relationships,
106 REUTHER

which illuminate various ways of being to the thoughts and activities at all” (p. 145). With this
developing human being. This perspective cuts analysis, it only makes sense to talk about Da-
much deeper than the cognitive⫺subjective em- sein as already having a “stand” on its exis-
phasis to more of the primordial affectedness tence. It is to this extent that Dasein is already
(Befindlichkeit) of human existence that individuated (Letteri, 2009); that is, having its
Heidegger discussed. At the very basic level, own “distinct” being, grounded in the inherent
these relational patterns are out there in-the- relational and social connectedness offered in
world, residing in the fundamental and indivis- being-with and being-in-the-world. Undoubt-
ible human relational world saturated and con- edly, the Dasein Heidegger used as the basis for
textualized through affectivity. Consequently, his existential investigation is the type of being
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

Bowlby’s conception of internal working mod- that exists as we would expect an adult human
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

els, with their dualistic underpinnings and cog- to exist. If Dasein is reserved for an adult hu-
nitive basis, if to be used at all, can only be cast man being, where do infants and children fit in
as abstractions posteriori to the embedded ac- the conception of Dasein? How can the early,
tivity of being-in-the-world. With this contex- postbirth experiences, such as in infancy and
tual grounding in being-in-the-world, the con- childhood, contribute to the understanding of
cept of “internal working models” can be set Dasein and everyday being?
aside without losing Bowlby’s core point. Invariably, from the moment of birth, infants
The following sections will further explore are affected by a human world (this is clear by
how our fundamental activity within these at- the innate, basic disposition revealing attach-
tachment relationships is situated in the struc- ment behaviors of crying, smiling, etc.), and,
tures of being-in-the-world and being-with. Us- most importantly, are positioned to be affected
ing Heidegger’s conception of Befindlichkeit by other human beings and human social events
(through mood), it will be shown how the lived in very special ways (Stern, 2000). It is to this
experiences of these emotionally laden attach- extent that infants are thrown into the human
ment relationships attune us to the world and social world. Although they are not considered
others, structuring our existence, and revealing Dasein in the same way as adults, the activities,
it in certain meaningful ways. Moreover, possibilities, and ways of understanding a hu-
Heidegger’s structure of Verfallen (falling) manly constructed world, which infants and
grounds these attachments to serve a critical children certainly acquire and express as they
function in our inherent insecure natures. To develop, would not be possible if they did not
this end, our experience with attachments, in already exist in a shared human world, engaging
their various forms, can be considered an im- in practices with other human beings within
portant source of being and part of the back- sociocultural systems.
ground conditions responsible for disclosing an Parents (as caregivers), which are typically
intelligible and knowable world in everyday the first and primary attachment figures, are also
life. the first and most significant engagement in-
fants have with the social world. Phenomenol-
Dasein and Human Development ogist Maurice Merleau-Ponty (2010) empha-
sized that the relations with parents are always
To connect the developmental insights of at- relations with the larger sociocultural world. He
tachment theory with Heideggerian thought, a stated that, “[d]ue to the behavior of the parents
more in depth analysis of Dasein is needed. As toward the child, the child immediately finds
previously mentioned, Heidegger allocates the himself [sic] in contact with cultural phenome-
ontological source of Dasein’s everyday being non” (p. 304). As such, events and phenomena
(everydayness) to the sociocultural milieu (das that occur on the social and cultural levels will
Man).5 In this way, Dasein is considered to have
already taken up a shared world of norms and
5
customs, as well as ways to interpret and feel; This article focuses on the sociocultural milieu (das
that is, practical working knowledge of the Man) as the constituting aspect of Dasein’s everyday un-
derstanding; however, Dasein’s everyday understanding
world. Dreyfus (1991) contended that socializa- and the sociocultural milieu are primordially constituted by
tion and interpersonal understanding are to “be temporality (Zeitlichkeit) itself, understood through the dy-
taken over before there can be any Dasein with namics of historical movements and time periods.
ON OUR EVERYDAY BEING 107

arise within and further contextualize the par- ization is an always “sensing” of how to feel
ent⫺infant interactions (Sameroff, 1983). in situations, as according to Heidegger, we
These include things like belief systems, cul- can never be without our primordial affected-
tural and religious practices, economic hard- ness (Befindlichkeit) as mood. As such,
ships, and anything that involves the shared through the lived experiences with others, the
social world. From our earliest days, we are infant or child must therefore feel into his or
always already immersed in and can never be her Dasein when developing into adolescence
separate from the shared cultural conditions, and adulthood in order to take up the mean-
phenomena, and practices that make up our ings of the world.
existence. This inherent relational situation ex- From the initial absorption in a parent’s
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

poses how our possibilities of comportment are Dasein and being-in-the-world, such as a
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

always a result of being-with others, which pre- mother (Boss, 1979/1994), the infant can be-
supposes the existential structure of being-with.
gin to press into his or her own Dasein and
In this way, an infant is a being-in-the-world.
way of being. As people advance from in-
Given this primordial position, Dasein is always
an ontological possibility, just not his or her fancy through childhood and adolescence to
own at that point. Medard Boss (1979/1994) adulthood, relationships with others typically
stated that because the infant “is not yet an increase in number and complexity. In all,
independent Dasein capable of carrying out its further pressing into his or her own Dasein
own being” (p. 243), the infant’s fledgling Dasein means taking up different modes of being by
remains fully absorbed in the primary caregiver’s way of lived experience from the myriad re-
Dasein and way of being-in-the-world. Absorbed lationships within the sociocultural milieu,
and anchored in this relational position, they lack with attachment relationships as an important
the contextual “individuated” stance present in specific source. In regard to this position, it is
Dasein. So, how does an infant or child press into important to note that, due to the inherent
Dasein and carry out its own being? This question uncertainty of the world, we always already
becomes the central topic for the rest of this anal- maintain an implicit readiness to become ab-
ysis. sorbed in order to take-up these modes of
Given that the infant is a being-in-the- being. Our falling (Verfallen) into the “they,”
world who possesses Dasein as its own-most starting from initial absorption in the primary
ontological possibility, there is an innate, ex- caregiver’s Dasein and continuing to other
istential motivation toward discovering and sociocultural attachments (e.g., peer groups,
experiencing the possibilities offered by the intimate partners, religions) through lifetime
human Dasein’s attunement to the world and development, facilitates the striving for security
others as being-in-the-world. Heidegger and safety in established worldly understand-
(1927/1962) stated that this everyday being is ings and sociocultural systems of meanings. We
“precisely that being which is ’between’ birth “fall” into the modes of being provided by at-
and death” (p. 276). That is to say, to account tachments to cope with our thrownness.
for the everyday being of Dasein, we must
Still, Dasein is not to be considered a devel-
look at the entire history, from birth forward.
opmental milestone like adolescence or adult-
Boss (1963, 1979/1994) contended that we
extract our Dasein from or fundamental be- hood (although developmental milestones can
ing-with others. Similarly, Dreyfus (1991) as- be considered one component of human exis-
serted the “human organism starts Daseining tence), but rather as a moving toward apprehen-
gradually” (pp. 187–188), starting from birth sion of his or her Lichtung over time, by way of
and taking “a stand on itself by pressing into being-with others through sociocultural con-
human possibilities” (p. 187). To press into texts. For example, it would be akin to increas-
and subsequently to take up these possibili- ing the brightness of a light set on a dimmer
ties, the infant “must be socialized into switch in a dark room, illuminating more pos-
shared, ongoing activities by imitating people sibilities of the world to apprehend. The forth-
and accumulating the necessary experiences coming sections will address how attachment
until it begins to do what [the] one does” (p. activity is situated in being-in-the-world and
187). Fundamentally saturated in this social- how it is a source of everyday being.
108 REUTHER

Attachment Activity and Emotional tual “expressive and receptive sociability” (p.
Experience as Being-in-the-World 236) that allows for the discovery of experi-
ences that are uniquely human. Always present
Attachment theory positions human beings as and saturated in this activity are underlying
always attuned and oriented in some way to the affective and emotional tones that reveal how
social world, which Heidegger would affirm. the activity is meaningful. Merleau-Ponty sup-
Bowlby (1969/1982) stated that, from birth, the portively added that this affectivity is funda-
infant has a discriminative favor toward the mentally embodied, in that it always involves
actions of other human beings, including the corporeal body. This can easily be seen in an
“marked bias to respond in special ways to infant’s use of hands, arms, and mouth when
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

several kinds of stimuli that commonly emanate interacting with others and the world. These
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

from a human being” (p. 265). These include actions are part of, and embedded in, this affec-
human facial patterns, environmental move- tive expressivity. In this way, the infant’s rela-
ment, and higher pitched voices. Moreover, at- tions to others and the world are not to be
tachment behaviors are engaged, such as crying, understood as minds and extended body-
smiling, clinging and following, which increase objects, but rather as embodied lived experi-
the likelihood of others responding and main- ences. Accordingly, these affective experiences
taining proximity to the infant. From the mo- are not isolative “things” that reside in the
ment of birth, infants are open to and are active minds. This activity is, therefore, an interactive,
seekers within a human social world, orienting transpersonal process (Mitchell, 2000) that is
toward others to engage with them (Stern, situated in and “coconstituted within ongoing
1977). Consider, for example, a crying infant relational systems” (Stolorow, 2011, p. 26).
due to separation from the caregiver. The care- Even with the development of language to sym-
giver may, in response to the crying, pick up the bolize experiences, affects and emotions remain
infant, allowing for embrace, which will prompt the “principal feature of intimate relationships
other attachment behaviors. This will further throughout life” (Bowlby, 1988, p. 121). In
elicit a response from the caregiver, and so on. sum, the experiences are shared and mutually
Here, infants are not only born into being af- constitutive, with the affect emerging from the
fected by a human social world, but their mere between of infant and attachment figure, within
presence and activity also affects the world and the social contexts of the engagement and par-
people around them. Occurring in an already ticipants’ relational histories. Our oftentimes
present intersubjective world, these engage- “internal,” overly cognitive ways of understand-
ments increase in sophistication (Trevarthen, ing how we feel in the world is, therefore, not
1979, 2003) over time, facilitating the rapid how we truly relate at the most basic level.
forming and tacit “figuring out” of relationships This position fits within Heidegger’s concep-
in the human world. Mitchell (2000) support- tion of moods and other revealing modes of
ively suggested that through this often repetitive Befindlichkeit, such as emotions, feelings, and
and “complex choreography of behaviors in affects. In support of Heidegger, Charles Gui-
which participants cyclically cue and respond to gnon (1984) wrote that these moods and similar
each other in turn” (p. 60), intimate relation- affective experiences “are discovered not by
ships and ways to handle situations are formed. looking inward, but rather by getting a feel for
These basic exchanges between the infant and the entire situation” (p. 236). Taken this way,
caregiver, therefore, always consist in this in- human beings are always accessing meaning-
tersubjective, reciprocal and mutually constitut- disclosing emotions by looking outward toward
ing activity, as each member constitutes the their involvement in social activity—in which
other’s actions. Consequently, the full meaning their first and arguably most important experi-
of the experience is only revealed in its contex- ences are with the affective and emotionally
tual totality. laden engagements with attachment figures.
However, given that infants lack organized Continuing with the previous example, when a
verbal language, the primary means of commu- caregiver smiles and displays positive affect
nication is through affective expression. This toward the infant, and the infant responds with
affective expressivity is quite powerful, and is a smile, cooing, and positive affect, the infant’s
central to what Trevarthen (2003) called a mu- emotional experience is not something that re-
ON OUR EVERYDAY BEING 109

sides solely in the infant, but rather arises from safety and security (Bowlby, 1969/1982, 1980,
the engagement with the caregiver. Moreover, 1988). In this way, the infant or child will look
the caregiver’s positive affect was not some- or move toward the attachment figure for vali-
thing that resides solely in them, but emerges dation and regulation of his or her experience.
in the context of their attunement to the infant. Consequently, the attachment’s affective attun-
Using Heidegger’s framework, the infant is “in” ement is critical to how the child will subse-
the world with others; that is, involved in the quently respond and proceed. This separation
embedded affective activity with attachment anxiety exposes the infant’s reliance on attach-
figures as being-in-the-world. ment figures for navigating and developing a
It is important to consider that being-in the grasping of how to relate to and feel about the
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

embedded activity of these attachment relation- world. Bowlby (1988) viewed this form of anx-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

ships is a type of being-with others. There is no iety as a fundamental “human disposition” and
way of understanding a person without some the process of how it is handled as an important
relation to the human world and, more specifi- aspect of early human life.
cally, the others of that world. We not only look Anxiety and fear are both emphasized by
to our sociocultural system to find what things Heidegger as central to human existence.
mean and how they matter, but we also engage Heidegger (1927/1962) stated the difference
with specific people and groups, particularly our “phenomenally” between anxiety and fear is
attachments, to provide the specific ways of “that in the face of which one has anxiety is not
attuning to and understanding the human world. an entity within-the-world” (p. 231), while fear,
Affective experiences with attachments are the in contrast, has directedness toward something
first within the sociocultural system to provide a in the world—it has been objectified. Further,
grasping of our thrownness as well as exposing the pervasive uncertainty and unknown nature
and articulating various modes of being-in-the- of anxiety confirms our enduring dependency
world throughout life. Thus, resulting attach- on the public “they-self” for systems of mean-
ment relationships can be viewed as a special ing and significance. Consequently, Heidegger
type of being-with others that disclose the given viewed anxiety as the primordial orientation
possibilities of being. that exposes our Dasein as fundamentally inse-
At the most basic level, these modes of hu- cure, “unsettled,” and unknown; we, as Daseins,
man being are not to be seen as individualistic are the source of anxiety due to our existential
assemblies constructed within isolative subjec- predicament. When confronted with anxiety,
tive minds from external impositions; instead, “[e]veryday familiarity collapses” (Heidegger,
they arise from embodied coconstitutive em- 1927/1962, p. 233), rendering a “world col-
bedded engagements of existing together in be- lapse.” In these ways, anxiety is more terrifying
ing-in-the-world. They are out there in the and primal than fear, and, as a result, we seek to
world, embedded in the “between” of people, displace this anxiety with fear.
saturated in the relational fabric of human life. Although Heidegger and Bowlby discussed
Seen in this way, subjective minds and external anxiety and fear in different ways, in both their
worlds only figure into a person’s experiential writings they remain core human emotional ex-
understandings as derivative and reflective con- periences. Given this, how can Bowlby’s treat-
cepts arising from the “background milieu or ment of separation anxiety fit existentially
situation” of being-in the world (Carman, within Heideggerian thought? On this note, Ir-
2003). vin Yalom (1980) has suggested that “at the
level prior to thought and language the child
Attachments as Sources for Everyday Being may experience the inchoate anxiety of nonbe-
ing; and that anxiety, in the child as in the adult,
Attachments, Establishing Security, and the seeks to become fear” (p. 102). Perhaps the
Existential Role of Anxiety and Fear separation anxiety experienced during the con-
frontation with an unfamiliar situation without
Separation in the presence of a stressor or the proximal support of the attachment can be
unfamiliar situation often provokes distress in interpreted as confrontation with the uncertainty
the form of fear, anxiety, and protest, which and “the unknown” of the world. When this
prompts the seeking of attachment figures for occurs, the infant or child will cease exploring
110 REUTHER

the environment and react in anxious protest: by terrifying to face directly in early development.
in large, the world “breaks down,” rendering the Several theorists (Vandenberg, 1991; Yalom,
infant anxiously seeking the attachment figure. 1980; Maurer, 1966) have mentioned how sep-
However, because the infant or child lacks a aration anxiety may be seen as an early mani-
fully constituted self-identity (Dasein) and con- festation of existential anxiety. The account
sidering the reaction is directed toward the ab- provided in this section may be understood as
sence of an attachment figure, separation anxi- one way to connect them.
ety is to be considered a manifest form of fear When conceptualized in this fashion, attach-
rather than anxiety, at least in the sense ments can be viewed not only to serve a critical
Heidegger has described. Additionally, separa- existential purpose of survival, but also in how
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

tion anxiety is an ontic experience, while the (and in what ways) our affectedness (Befind-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

anxiety Heidegger discussed is clearly ontolog- lichkeit) and falling (Verfallen) manifest as any
ical. The infant or child is not yet (existentially) sense of relational stability, structure, security,
able to take on the inchoate anxiety, because, and belonging to handle the anxiety from an
according to Heidegger, Dasein is the source of inherently uncertain existence. These early ex-
anxiety, and without his or her own Dasein, periences of finding safety and security in at-
there is no way of confrontation—which ac- tachments have been seen as early manifesta-
counts for the looking-to and immersion in the tions of our ongoing struggle to invest trustingly
other’s Dasein and being-in-the-world. Just as in close bonds with other people, such as friends
the infant or child is unable fully to care for and intimate partners (Mikulincer, Florian, &
itself in the world, he or she is not fully pre- Hirschberger, 2004) as well as larger sociocul-
pared to confront his or her owner-most anxiety. tural entities, including peer groups, religions,
Nevertheless, despite Heidegger’s likely in- cultures, and the like (Vandenberg, 1991)—all
terpretation of Bowlby’s separation anxiety as of which are entities that constitute who we are
fear, there is clear existential grounding. The and what matters in specific contexts. Conse-
structure of falling (Verfallen) comes into focus quently, early activity with attachments will
in ontological development such that the phe- have deep and long-lasting implications for our
nomenology of separation can be viewed as the contextualized world disclosure.
beginnings of how we “fall” into our own Da-
sein by fleeing into the “they.” Through this Attachment Experiences and Accounts for
means, the fledgling Dasein is able to literally the Basis of Everyday Being
put a “face” to the disruption, and within that
mutual contextual engagement an unfolding of How attachment figures respond to the
how the situation matters is revealed. There is a child’s affective experiences, and what tran-
looking-to-the-other for affective regulation in spires during this activity, largely provide the
that situation, and, from the way in which it is early foundation for how safe and secure the
handled, a way to be emerges. It is essentially world is, with implications for how the child
through the relational context with the other will feel, respond to, and function in it, as well
Dasein (attachment figure) that existential anx- as supply the context for various emotional ex-
iety is immediately displaced to a fear reaction. periences and their meanings to arise. In one
Thus, the motivation to be reunited with the particular case, if the attachment figure is reli-
other to quell the fear is, to this scale, cast as the ably available to address the child’s needs and
first coping with our existential predicament by consistently responding in caring and support-
absorbing or falling into the “they” for a way to ive ways when distressed, a secure base will
be in the world. As Heidegger (1927/1962) likely form. For example, when encountering
pointed out, “the turning-away of falling is new surroundings, a child might venture from
grounded rather in anxiety, which in turn is the secure base and periodically look back and
what first makes fear possible” (p. 230, empha- orient to the attachment figure with a look of
sis in original). Here, rather than the “no” thing caution. If met with encouragement by the at-
of anxiety, it becomes directed at a less terrify- tachment figure, he or she may reciprocate the
ing “some” thing of fear—in this case, the at- affect and continue the exploration of the world
tachment figure’s absence. Anxiety remains under the affective safety and support that arose
prima facie in human existence, even if it is too from the engagement. Once learned that stres-
ON OUR EVERYDAY BEING 111

sors can be resolved and “anxiety” can be man- pensatory behaviors in response to the
aged through the availability and attunement of attachment in an attempt to create some type of
early attachments, it opens up the possibility of relational structure and displace anxiety. For
a world in which safety and security can be example, in the case of inconsistent or delayed
established. It is through this experience that a responsiveness, the child may manifest in anx-
safe and secure world becomes an ontological ious obedience and preoccupation with attach-
possibility. Children with a secure base are bet- ments, with a general lack of concern for others
ter able to focus on further discovering and (Bowlby, 1988). Furthermore, in the case of
exploring their world, and can become increas- open rejection, the child may develop ambiva-
ingly self-reliant, engage cooperatively with lent attitudes toward attachments; that is, he or
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

others, and provide sympathy and support to she may display anxious possessive behavior
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

others in distress (Bowlby, 1988)—all essential mixed with anger toward the attachment figure
traits to operate effectively and adaptively in the (Bowlby, 1973, 1988). These behavioral re-
social world. Moreover, research has shown, sponses are a general attempt to maintain the
rather consistently, that “a more positive and relational bond with the attachment figure, and
open self-concept” is related to secure attach- are a full result of the coconstitutive activity that
ment (particularly mother⫺infant), which is demonstrates a particular way of functioning
“revealed not only in explicit self-descriptions, within these systems. From the activity, patterns
but also in implicit self-concept” (Goodvin, emerge, which reveal a type of relational struc-
Meyer, Thompson, & Hayes, 2008, p. 435). As ture that discloses meanings of how to feel and
a result, children will have the ability to dis- get along in the human social world.
cover it in the world beyond the primary attach- Unrecognized, invalidated, and unacceptable
ment, such as through other sociocultural enti- feelings are subsequently dimmed out of being-
ties, including teachers, peer groups, intimate in-the-world, and, as a result, there is a narrow-
partners, and others. ing, constricting, distorting, and inflexible ren-
Generally, consistent and reliable presences dering of potential modes of being. Clearly, if
of attachments engender structure in the chaotic certain experiences were never recognized, val-
and unpredictable world, helping orient the idated, or inconsistently responded to, the child
child toward a flexible and resilient existence. had no access to them and would be subse-
This sense of belongingness will project to the quently closed off to those modes of being. This
disclosure of future situations. The exploration could take the form of emotions in general
and exposure to experience different facets of (most likely positive emotions) or emotionally
the sociocultural world illuminate a general “felt” experiences, such as trust. As such, these
openness of possibilities for the Dasein he or experiences would simply not be a factor in the
she takes up. person’s world disclosure. Moreover, according
If the primary attachment is inconsistent, to Boss (1979/1994), “unacceptable emotions”
generally aloof, responds with delay or even (i.e., negative emotions that might jeopardize
outright rejects the child, a general struggle for the bond, such as anger toward the attachment
a felt sense of security and safety emerges. figure) that are dimmed out of a person’s being-
Without the consistent attunement to the child’s in-the-world can become “obtrusive” in every-
affective states, separation anxiety is experi- day life. That is to say, we can still be affected
enced quite strongly and persistently, resulting by them. Take, for example, a person exploring
in crippling anxiety and fear. Largely, the lack a darkened office; just because a desk cannot be
of responsiveness or utter rejection to the in- seen does not mean the person cannot knock
fant’s or child’s emotional needs results in in- into and be affected by it. Similarly, although a
secure attachments. To this end, the child re- person has pushed away an experience, espe-
mains consumed with the unpredictability and cially an early one with an attachment, does not
uncertainty of the attachment’s presence, which mean that it may not have an impact on the
limits the exploration of the world. The world projective disclosure of events in everyday life.
that is revealed is one drenched in anxiety, fear, Quite clearly, the actual loss of an attach-
and incoherence. Because consistent and pre- ment, whether through prolonged or permanent
dictable safety and security may not be onto- departure or death, will have a significant im-
logically available, the child will perform com- pact on the child’s development. According to
112 REUTHER

Bowlby (1980), in this relational loss, the child 1986) that disclose the possibilities of a social
will proceed from experiencing the anxious pro- world and how things matter (Heidegger, 1927/
test of separation to experiencing despair, rep- 1962), the affective-saturated activity with the
resented by sadness and withdrawal from en- various forms of attachments (e.g., parents, peer
gaging the social world. As wrapped up in the groups) will reveal certain sociocultural prac-
lost attachment figure’s Dasein, a serious lack- tices and ways of handling the world that are
ing emerges because quite literally part of his or also modeled and absorbed. This leads to the
her constitutive being is gone. Consequently, acquisition of differentiated and nuanced ways
the child is literally thrown into confrontation of apprehending a meaningful world. That said,
with his or her own annihilation or nonbeing. a person’s exact understanding and behavior
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

Moreover, Adah Maurer (1966) has suggested manifestations of happiness, anger, anxiety, and
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

that, at an implicit level “below true cognition,” so forth, and their contextual meanings, may
the child “knows” that this type of loss is es- vary from person to person and culture to cul-
sentially a loss to his or her connection with life. ture, because the functional expressions built
This is perhaps the starkest example of the into the affective experiences will differ de-
destabilization of the child’s world. The form- pending on parental, familiar, social, and cul-
less anxiety of nonbeing that arises from this tural engagements. Simply put, we learn from
loss situation is displaced to objective fears in our various attachments through our experi-
the child’s life, which can easily lead to with- ences of being-with them. These attachments, in
drawal from the social world and subsequent profoundly practical ways, are deeply con-
despair. From this, a kind of narrowing and nected to our existential predicament; that is,
constricting of his or her being-in-the-world is they furnish us with meaningful ways that, more
rendered, which may have long-term maladap- or less effectively, help us deal, compensate,
tive consequences for the handling of other and adjust to the uncertainty of the world and
stressors and anxiety-provoking situations in our own finitude (Becker, 1973/1997).
life (Yalom, 1980). In many ways— beginning from our original
The aforementioned positions, in many criti- parental caregiving relationships and forward—
cal ways, disclose the possibilities of the social ongoing attachments coconstitute the types of
world and shape a person’s (Dasein) openness. people we are and comport ourselves to be in
It is important to mention that these different everyday life. Bowlby (1973) noted that, due to
expressions of attachment activity reveal modes the complex networks these various types rela-
that still remain ways of encountering and ap- tionships form over time, the precise origin of
prehending a human world that arise from the the ways we feel and behave in the world in
primordial relational activity with the attach- various contexts are often unclear—not only to
ment figure as being-in-the-world—albeit some other people, but also to ourselves. It is to this
will consequent a more “open” existence, while extent that it can be said we often get on with
others a more constricted and limited one. things with little recollection or reflection to
The general examples based on Bowlby’s what we are feeling or doing, simply just having
work provided in this article demonstrate how ways of feeling about ourselves and dealing
vastly different a child’s world is initially dis- with others in the world. These modes are im-
closed than an adult’s. These early attachment plicit ways of making sense of our thrownness
relationships are important from a foundational into social world given a certain sociocultural
position for establishing a felt sense of safety background, which will project to future con-
and for providing the initial contexts for the texts and have active bearing on the Dasein a
emergence and articulation of specific affective person takes up and the available disclosive
experiences, which are carried forward in the modes of his or her own “individuated” Dasein
formation of and activity with attachments in and being-in-the-world. Although we can see
later life. Other attachment relationships, such how this might lead to different ways of living
as peer groups, intimate relationships, and so- in the world, according to Heidegger, it actually
ciocultural or religious entities, will also have discloses a different kind of world and therefore,
bearing on a person’s world disclosure. Further- in many ways, people will go about life in a
more, because affective experiences are active different world. It is through this ongoing social
in the negotiation of reality (Lutz & White, and developmental process with attachments
ON OUR EVERYDAY BEING 113

that a person distinguishes as a distinct entity Concluding Remarks


with his or her own Dasein. Attachment figures,
seen in this way, function as relational and Attachments take on a variety of forms and
affective references for the person’s projective move from the actual need for presence, which
disclosure, a type of existential vehicle for ways has been shown as critical in creating a safe and
of being. Even with the establishment of a per- secure world in infancy and childhood. The
son’s own Dasein, it is clear that attachments, anxiety-managing qualities provide the ground-
and specifically early ones, are carried forward, ing for early exploration of the world and sub-
thus remaining critical in the ongoing process of sequently the opening up, constriction, and dis-
tortions of future human potentialities. Our
disclosing the possibilities of things mattering.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

being is expressed through the contexts of these


Because we are constituted by our relationship
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

relationships; that is, they show up as a result of


to the human social world one way or another, what is publicly available, initially in early at-
attachments serve as one particular source. tachment relationships, and then within social
It is critical to note that these sociocultural activity with others as attachments in the socio-
attachments—in the various ways we are af- cultural milieu. Early and ongoing activity with
fected by them—provide ready-made modes of attachments, therefore, serves an ontologically
being into which we tacitly “feel” and “fall.” revelatory function; that is, through our ontic
Heidegger would contend that when attempting affective and emotional experiences with others
to cope with the terror, uncertainty, and dread as attachments that implicitly known ways to
that is ever-present in the world, which we do handle situations arise from the embedded ac-
continuously from birth, we fall into these par- tivity of everyday life, and through these means
ticular modes of the “they-self,” which are in- modes of being-in-the-world are able to be
authentic expressions of ourselves. They are grasped, extracted, and apprehended. Given
inauthentic insofar as they are not originally Heidegger’s view that the sociocultural world
ours. Their revealing of the world as mattering constitutes a person’s everyday being, and that
through affective engagements with attach- attachments are important members of this
ments are already always there as part of the world, attachments can be seen as particular
sociocultural milieu in which we rely—and it is sources of everyday being. Thus, grounded in
in exactly that way that they engender safety, as being-in-the-world, it is through the emotion-
what is known. Despite providing a protective ally saturated activity with attachments that we
barrier against anxiety, it is but a mere socio- take up our own modes of being and “individ-
cultural construction that, in a way, instills us uate” our Dasein; however, the ties to these
with a false sense of security and certitude in the constituting entities remain strong in our “fall-
world. This is because, ultimately, attachments enness.” This taking up of being as beings-in-
in their various forms can (and often do) even- the-world occurs before internal⫺external and
tually fail us, leading to a “world collapse” subject⫺object distinction. Therefore, we can
only talk about character organization, ego de-
(such as through the ending of an intimate
velopment, internalization, constructions of
relationship, traumatic event, or ostracism
schemas and the like as abstractions— consti-
from cultural or religious groups), exposing tuted from and secondary to—the fundamental
us to the chaotic abyss of the unknown. Al- relational and emotional primacy of being-in-
though attachments protect, they also simul- the-world.
taneous prevent; in other words, they prevent The present analysis has provided a sketch
us from taking on our freedom that can only of how our everyday being is generally con-
be grasped from the confrontation with anxi- stituted through these important sociocultural
ety. However, this is nothing to be alarmed or attachments over a person’s lifetime, mainly
surprised about, because our inauthentic ev- focused on the structures of Befindlichkeit and
erydayness, as different expressions of the Verfallen in being-in-the-world and the sig-
“they-self,” remain our primary mode of ex- nificance of anxiety, fear, and other moods
istence (Heidegger, 1927/1962), and are actu- and emotional experiences. Clearly, these at-
ally quite important and critical in everyday tachments serve a critical purpose in early
functioning. development to create a stable, albeit inau-
114 REUTHER

thentic, self-identity. Still, a more authentic References


existence can be discovered as an adult hu-
Becker, E. (1997). The denial of death. New York,
man being, as Dasein. Heidegger’s point is
NY: Free Press. (Original work published 1973)
that, instead of Dasein fleeing into these at- Boss, M. (1963). Psychoanalysis and Daseinsanaly-
tachments, accept inherent uncertainty and sis. New York, NY: Basic Books.
move past it. This is addressed through Boss, M. (1994). Existential foundations of medicine
Heidegger’s (1927/1962) concept of “liberat- & psychology (S. Conway & A. Cleaves, Trans.).
ing solicitude,” from which we care for the Northvale, NJ: Jason Aronson. (Original work
other by “freeing” or “emancipating” the published 1979)
other from the belief that these worldly at- Bowlby, J. (1973). Attachment and loss. Volume 2:
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

tachments are enduring, permanent, and se- Separation, anxiety and anger. New York, NY:
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

cure. By doing so, we open him or her up to Basic Books.


being ontologically insecure and encourage Bowlby, J. (1980). Attachment and loss. Volume 3:
Loss, sadness and depression. New York: Basic
his or her confrontation with this anxiety
Books.
head-on, allowing for personal responsibility Bowlby, J. (1982). Attachment and loss. Volume 1:
for who he or she is, given the finite choices Attachment. New York, NY: Basic Books. (Orig-
there are to make. Although this concept de- inal work published 1969)
serves further attention, especially when con- Bowlby, J. (1988). A secure base: Parent-child at-
sidering authentic being, it is beyond the tachment and healthy human development. New
scope of the current analysis. York, NY: Basic Books.
The importance of attachment relationships Bretherton, I. (1992). The origins of attachment the-
in social and relational aspects of human growth ory: John Bowlby and Mary Ainsworth. Develop-
and development have been shown to be quite mental Psychology, 28, 759 –775.
clear. This is a continuation of the recent move- Carman, T. (2003). Heidegger’s analytic: Interpre-
tation, discourse, and authenticity in Being and
ment in psychology and psychoanalysis to Time. New York, NY: Cambridge University
move past Cartesian dualistic notions of iso- Press.
lated subjects and decontextualized external Dreyfus, H. L. (1991). Being-in-the-world: A com-
worlds in order to better fit with the embedded- mentary on Heidegger’s being and time, division I.
ness, context-dependency, and mutual constitu- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tion of our actions and social being (e.g., Stol- Frie, R. (2008). Fundamentally embodied: The expe-
orow, 2000, 2011; Frie, 2008). Casting human rience of psychological agency. Contemporary
development in this framework allows for a rich Psychoanalysis, 44, 367–376.
backdrop for further analysis that fits with con- Gendlin, E. T. (1988). Befindlichkeit: Heidegger
tinuously emerging post-Cartesian contextual, and the philosophy of psychology. In K. Hoeller
(Ed.), Heidegger & psychology (pp. 43–71). Se-
social, embodied, and action-oriented trends
attle, WA: Review of Existential Psychology and
in both theoretical and empirical psychology, Psychiatry.
with its greatest utility perhaps being in clin- Goodvin, R., Meyer, S., Thompson, R. A., & Hayes,
ical practice and psychotherapy. This article, R. (2008). Self-understanding in early childhood:
building on existing work, also establishes Associations with child attachment security and
groundwork for a developmental ontology of maternal negative affect. Attachment & Human
human being. Further directions also include Development, 10, 433– 450. doi:10.1080/
establishment of a more in-depth and com- 14616730802461466
plete account of the development of human Guignon, C. (1984). Heidegger on moods. In R. C.
being, specifically in Heidegger’s existential Solomon & C. Calhoun (Eds.), What is an emo-
analytic, which includes how sociocultural tion? Readings in philosophical psychology (pp.
230 –243). New York, NY: Oxford University
attachments and relational theories help to
Press.
elucidate the other existential structures of Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie
being-in-the-world, such as understanding & E. Robinson, Trans.). New York, NY: Harper
(Verstehen) and discursiveness (Rede), as and Row. (Original work published 1927)
well as developmentally based pathways to Letteri, M. (2009). Heidegger and the question of
inauthentic and authentic being across the psychology: Zollikon and beyond. New York, NY:
lifetime. Rodopi.
ON OUR EVERYDAY BEING 115

Lutz, C., & White, G. M. (1986). The anthropology of sey. American Journal of Psychotherapy, 54, 149 –
emotions. Annual Review of Anthropology, 15, 405– 151. Retrieved from http://www.ajp.org/
436. Retrieved from http://www.annualreviews.org/ Stolorow, R. D. (2011). World, affectivity, trauma:
journal/anthro Heidegger and post-Cartesian psychoanalysis
Maurer, A. (1966). Maturation of concepts of death. (Vol. 35). New York, NY: Routledge.
British Journal of Medical Psychology, 39, 35– 41. Thompson, R. A. (1993). Socioemotional develop-
Retrieved from http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com ment: Enduring issues and new challenges. Devel-
May, R. (1994). Discovery of being: Writings in opmental Review, 13, 372– 402. doi:10.1006/drev
existential psychology. New York, NY: Norton. .1993.1018
(Original work published 1983) Thompson, R. A. (2008a). Attachment-related mental
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010). Child psychology and representations: Introduction to the special issue.
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

pedagogy: The Sorbonne lectures 1949 –1952. Attachment & Human Development, 10, 347–358.
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Retrieved from http://www.tandfonline.com


Mikulincer, M., Florian, V., & Hirschberger, G. Thompson, R. A. (2008b). Early attachment and later
(2004). The terror of death and the quest for love: development: Familiar questions, new answers. In
An existential perspective on close relationships. J. Cassidy & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), Handbook on
In J. Greenberg, S. L. Koole, & T. Pyszczynski attachment (2nd ed., pp. 348 –365). New York,
(Eds.), Handbook of experimental existential psy- NY: Guilford Press.
chology (pp. 287–304). New York, NY: Guilford Trevarthen, C. (1979). Communication and coopera-
Press. tion in early infancy. A description of primary
Mitchell, S. A. (2000). Relationality: From attachment intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before
to intersubjectivity. New York, NY: Routledge. speech: The beginning of human communication
Sameroff, A. J. (1983). Developmental systems: (pp. 321–347). New York, NY: Cambridge Uni-
Context and evolution. In W. Kessen (Ed.), Hand- versity Press.
book of child psychology. Volume 1: History, the- Trevarthen, C. (2003). Infant psychology is an evolv-
ory, and methods (4th ed., pp. 237–294). New ing culture. Human Development, 46, 233–246.
York, NY: Wiley. Vandenberg, B. (1991). Is epistemology enough? An
Stern, D. N. (1977). The first relationship: Infant and existential consideration on development. Ameri-
mother. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University can Psychologist, 46, 1278 –1286.
Press. Yalom, I. D. (1980). Existential psychotherapy. New
Stern, D. N. (2000). The interpersonal world of the York, NY: Basic Books.
infant: A view from psychoanalysis and develop-
mental psychology (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Ba-
sic Books. Received September 8, 2012
Stolorow, R. D. (2000). From isolated minds to ex- Revision received April 8, 2013
periential worlds: An intersubjective space odys- Accepted April 10, 2013 䡲

You might also like