Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 15

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/259454700

The Development of Joke and Irony Understanding: A Study With 3-to 6-


Year-Old Children

Article  in  Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology · December 2013


DOI: 10.1037/cep0000011 · Source: PubMed

CITATIONS READS
50 4,702

2 authors, including:

Gabriella Airenti
Università degli Studi di Torino
23 PUBLICATIONS   407 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

THE COGNITIVE UNDERPINNINGS OF ANTHROPOMORPHISM View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Gabriella Airenti on 04 February 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology / Revue canadienne de psychologie expérimentale © 2013 Canadian Psychological Association
2014, Vol. 68, No. 2, 133–146 1196-1961/14/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/cep0000011

The Development of Joke and Irony Understanding:


A Study With 3- to 6-Year-Old Children
Romina Angeleri and Gabriella Airenti
University of Turin

Previous research suggests that comprehending ironic utterances is a relatively late-developing skill,
emerging around 5– 6 years of age. This study investigated whether younger children might show an
earlier understanding when ironic utterances are performed in familiar communicative situations, and
investigated the relationships among irony comprehension, language, and theory of mind (ToM) abilities.
A group of 100 children aged 3.0 – 6.5 years was presented with 4 types of puppet scenarios depicting
different communicative interactions: control, joke, contingent irony and background irony stories.
Results suggested that (a) even younger children easily understand jokes, and may sometimes understand
ironies; (b) children’s comprehension of irony continues to develop across early childhood; and (c)
receptive vocabulary scores had simultaneous effects on irony comprehension and ToM performance.

Keywords: verbal irony, theory of mind, communication, developmental pragmatics

Supplemental materials: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cep0000011.supp

Verbal irony is a form of nonliteral communication and many clusion of most studies is that children’s comprehension of
different definitions have been provided in the literature (Attardo, irony starts between the age of 5 and 6 years (e.g., Dews &
2000; Clark & Gerrig, 1984; Kreuz & Glucksberg, 1989; Kumon- Winner, 1997) and continues developing over time.
Nakamura, Glucksberg, & Brown, 1995; Wilson & Sperber, 1992). The particular difficulty in interpreting ironic utterances has
Developmental research has shown that the comprehension of often been attributed to the complexity of the inferences involved
ironic utterances is a particularly complex task for children in comprehension, which are assumed to require a full-fledged
(Capelli, Nakagawa, & Madden, 1990; Filippova & Astington, theory of mind (ToM). Several studies have shown that children’s
2008; Winner, 1988). A number of studies have focused on the inability to grasp the meaning of ironic phrases may be connected
different aspects connected with the development of children’s with their difficulties in inferring the speaker’s beliefs and inten-
understanding of this communicative act (for a review see tions (Sullivan, Winner, & Hopfield, 1995; Winner, Brownell,
Creusere, 2000; Pexman & Glenwright, 2007). In particular, irony Happé, Blum, & Pincus, 1998; Winner & Leekam, 1991). Accord-
comprehension has been compared with deceit and metaphor. ing to Winner (1988), in order to understand irony, the child has to
Some studies have investigated children’s difficulties in under- be able to detect incongruity or falsehood, infer motivation, and
standing intentional falsehood, which is typical of deceit, polite- attribute second-order beliefs to the speaker. Ackerman (1983)
ness, and irony (Ackerman, 1981; Airenti & Angeleri, 2011; suggested that in children’s comprehension of irony two indepen-
Peterson, Peterson, & Seeto, 1983). It has been shown that children dent processes can be distinguished, that is, the detection of the
as old as 13 years of age often fail to distinguish irony from nonliteral form cued by contextual discrepancy and the process
deception (Demorest, Meyer, Phelps, Gardner, & Winner, 1984; of inferring the speaker’s intent cued by intonation. Hancock,
Demorest, Silberstein, Gardner, & Winner, 1983). Data from Dunham, and Purdy (2000) confirmed this dissociation and
other studies indicate much earlier competence (e.g., Andrews, attributed it to the fact that detection demands first-order rea-
Rosenblatt, Malkus, Gardner, & Winner, 1986), and the con- soning about the speaker’s beliefs while inferring the speaker’s
intent requires inferences on the speaker’s beliefs about the
listener’s beliefs, that is, second-order reasoning.
The same developmental sequence has been confirmed by
This article was published Online First December 23, 2013. Filippova and Astington (2008) in a study comparing children and
Romina Angeleri and Gabriella Airenti, Center for Cognitive Science, adults. These authors stress the fact that interpreting irony is
Department of Psychology, University of Turin, Turin, Italy. difficult for children and that this ability improves with age. In fact
This research was supported by PRIN Project 2008 (No. 2008N9KF5K) even the 9-year-old participants in their study did not reach adult
from Ministero dell’Istruzione, dell’Università e della Ricerca (MIUR). skill levels. The progression was correlated with understanding of
We thank Valentina Berti, Miryam Donzelli, Andrea Dulicchio, and
mind and linguistic abilities. Filippova and Astington (2010) con-
Marika Tigani for their contribution in data collecting and coding, and Dr.
Marco Del Giudice for his valuable advice on the statistical analysis of the
firmed that the interpretation of complex mental states implied in
results. irony (i.e., speaker’s intention, motivation, and attitude) was dif-
Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Romina ficult for children and developed beyond middle-school years.
Angeleri, Department of Psychology, University of Turin, Via Po 14, However, they also found that for children interpreting the func-
10123 Turin, Italy. E-mail: romina.angeleri@unito.it tion of ironic utterances (i.e., how nice, mean, funny they are) was

133
134 ANGELERI AND AIRENTI

easier. This was viewed again in terms of theory of mind. One’s jects, revealing that they consider ironic utterances funnier than
own evaluation of the communicative effect of irony demands an literal ones (e.g., Colston & Keller, 1998; Gibbs, 2000; Kreuz,
intuitive judgment on a situation while inferring a speaker’s com- Long, & Church, 1991). As regards children, it has been suggested
plex mental states demands metarepresentational reasoning. that it is not before 7– 8 years of age that children start appreciating
In another study focused on the detection of verbal irony, the humorous aspect of irony (Dews et al., 1996; Harris & Pexman,
Nilsen, Glenwright, and Huyder (2011) presented children with 2003). Pexman, Glenwright, Krol, and James (2005) have tried to
video recordings where two puppets interacted in different com- find an explanation of this result. They suggested that children do
municative contexts (literal criticism, ironic criticism, and literal not appreciate the humor function of verbal irony in the same way
compliment), and then asked them questions about the listener’s that adults do, as they are only beginning to share adults’ percep-
interpretations and beliefs. They found that 8- to 10-year-old tions that ironic utterances (in particular, in case of ironic criti-
children were able to consider the listener’s knowledge state when cism) are intended to be funnier than literal remarks. In their study,
they had to interpret verbal irony. In particular, children of that age children tended to identify themselves with the victims of criti-
performed similarly to adults when answering questions about the cism, and had difficulties in dealing with conflicting representa-
listener’s beliefs, showing their ability to represent the listener’s tions of emotions and intentions.
knowledge state and the listener’s interpretation of the speaker’s From a theoretical point of view, in the pragmatics literature a
statement, while younger children (6- to 7-year-olds) had difficul- number of authors have tried to clarify the relation between irony
ties understanding the listener’s interpretation. Thus, in line with and humor (Attardo, 2002; Giora, 1995; Ritchie, 2005). Despite
previous research, they found that children’s second-order theory the definitional problems, due to the partial overlapping of differ-
of mind skills are related to their ability to interpret verbal irony, ent categories, irony is generally included in the broad category of
allowing children to be more flexible in their interpretations. conversational humor (Attardo, 2002; Norrick, 2003). However,
Although several developmental studies have assessed chil- little research has spanned both humor and irony (Attardo, 2002).
dren’s understanding of irony during middle and late childhood, With respect to development, even if it seems useful to study
there is still a need for data regarding irony comprehension in irony in connection with other forms of humor, this aim may be
younger children. To the best of our knowledge, there is only one difficult to achieve, given that while most studies on irony are
study that has shown an initial comprehension of irony in young
experimental and focused on comprehension, empirical work on
children (Loukusa & Leinonen, 2008). This study involved chil-
the development of humor in young children is mostly based on
dren aged 3 to 9 years, and showed that even if the majority of
naturalistic observations of interactions in family, daily care, and
children could correctly interpret verbal irony only between 6 and
nursery school (Bergen, 1989; Cameron, Kennedy, & Cameron,
7 years of age, some 3- and 4-year-olds showed an emerging
2008; Groch, 1974; Hoicka & Akhtar, 2012; Loizou, 2005; Reddy,
ability to recognise the communicative intent in simple ironic
2008). Therefore, the heterogeneity of both methods and commu-
utterances. It is interesting that this study was conducted on Finn-
nicative contexts makes comparing their results arduous.
ish children, opening a window on cultural settings and languages
However, we assume that considering irony on the background
other than English.
of the wider phenomenon of humor can be suitable to understand
All the results reported above are based on experimental studies
how children deal with different aspects of playful communication
focused on the comprehension of ironic language, where children
had to understand and evaluate dialogues presented within stories, since a young age.
cartoons, or puppet shows. Recently some works have tried to Studies on young children have shown that simple forms of
address the issue of when and how children begin to produce irony, humor appear very early in child development, reflecting how
examining various forms of irony during interactions in the family important these emotional responses become in the interactions
context. Pexman, Zdrazilova, McConnachie, Deater-Deckard, and with adults (Dunn, 1988). Laughter appears in infants at about 4
Petrill (2009) studied the use of ironic gestures and utterances in months (Sroufe & Piccard Wunsch, 1972) and at around 10 months
family triads of one parent and two children recorded while they children both respond to humorous situations and produce humor-
completed a cooperative dominos task. Their conclusion was that ous acts themselves such as clowning and teasing (Reddy, 1991).
irony production might begin at the same age as irony compre- From a cognitive point of view, humor has been defined as the
hension (the age of the youngest child to use verbal irony was 5.34 discovery of some incongruity with respect to reality (McGhee,
years). In a similar way, Recchia, Howe, Ross, and Alexander 1979; Shultz, 1976). From this perspective, the development of the
(2010) examined the use of irony in conversations between parents capacity of understanding and producing humor is related to chil-
and their 4- and 6-year-old children at home. Their results showed dren’s ability to construct symbolic representations of reality,
that even 4-year-old children occasionally used verbal irony, usu- which emerges at around 18 months of age, when children become
ally hyperbole, even if less frequently than their older siblings. able to deal with fantasy and pretend play suggesting some abili-
Thus, there is some evidence that children can begin to produce ties to separate representations and realities. The relation between
ironic utterances at around 4 years of age. children’s symbolic play and verbal humor has been supported by
Besides considering irony as a form of nonliteral communica- a case study in which all the productions of verbal humor in a child
tion, it is also possible to examine the discourse goals that are from 15 to 30 months of age have been systematically documented
accomplished by its use. In many cases, irony is used with humor- as a function of conceptual complexity (Johnson & Mervis, 1997).
ous intent (e.g., Long & Graesser, 1988; Roberts & Kreuz, 1994); According to Shultz (1976), the real appreciation of humor de-
thus another possibility is to study the development of irony with mands that children are able not only to represent incongruities,
respect to the development of humor. The relationship between but also to resolve them, and this ability emerges not before 6 years
irony and humor arises from studies conducted among adult sub- of age.
CHILDREN’S UNDERSTANDING OF JOKE AND IRONY 135

However, the necessity of representation and resolution of in- identify a utterance as ironic, that is, to explicitly explain their
congruity for humor appreciation remains controversial. Some understanding in terms of others’ mental states. Children could
other authors have maintained that even very young children may directly access the communicative intent before being able to
experience humor as far as they are able to detect incongruities in attribute second-order beliefs. Actually, we try to depart from the
reality, and to adopt a playful attitude. In this perspective it is an procedure utilized in most of the cited studies, in which children
expectancy violation in reality, like the mother failing to reappear were asked to evaluate utterances so as to judge the speaker’s
in a peek-a-boo game or someone slipping on a banana peel that is intentions and motivations, or to rank utterances on the basis of
perceived as funny (Pien & Rothbart, 1976). The playful attitude how mean, or teasing, or funny they are. We move from the
makes possible for children to respond to incongruity with humor, assumption that young children could understand these aspects of
without confounding it with other emotions, as for example aston- ironic utterances while being unable to verbally explain them. In
ishment or fear (Bariaud, 1989). The playful attitude of humor may the Finnish study (Loukusa & Leinonen, 2008), children who
be in effect mingled with an aggressive component or be perceived initially gave correct answers were not always able to subsequently
as aggressive (Veatch, 1998). provide an explanation. This might clarify the discrepancy be-
From an analysis of the literature we can conclude that irony tween the findings of experimental and observational studies; in
shares with other forms of humor some basic mechanisms: the latter, even young children appear to understand and produce
a) They are all based on some form of incongruity or contrast humorous and ironic sentences in the context of everyday interac-
(Colston & O’Brien, 2000), as what the humorist does or says goes tions. In this respect, Gibbs and O’Brien (1991) in their discussion
against expectations in a funny way. With respect to irony, the of the psychological understanding of irony made an interesting
simplest situation is that of an utterance blatantly contradicting point, arguing that people do not need to recognise irony to
reality as when someone says “Another gorgeous day!” while it is comprehend what the speakers mean by their ironic utterances.
raining heavily. There are several other kinds of irony forms but all This conclusion was based on the finding that adults were able to
have in common the use of incongruity shared between the inter- give correct paraphrase judgments for ironic expressions even if
locutors to suggest a discrepancy between reality and expectation they were not always conscious of their ironic character (Gibbs,
(Gibbs, 1994). 1986).
b) Moreover, in humor as well as in irony there is often a latent Children are precociously involved in humorous interactions
aggressive component. With respect to humor, teasing is the typ- with parents. This develops children’s communicative abilities and
ical example (Keltner, Capps, Kring, Young, & Heerey, 2001), but facilitates the construction of a common ground for comprehen-
this is also the case of laughing at someone sliding on a banana sion. It is on this aspect that the present study is based.
peel. Irony often implies criticism even if sometimes, but in fact Thus we proposed to distinguish between the ability to compre-
rather rarely, also compliments are expressed in an ironic form. In hend the communicative intent of ironic utterances—which, in our
fact there is a controversy about the function of irony with respect perspective, relies on basic communicative abilities—and the abil-
to criticism. According to the tinge hypothesis, one function of ity to explicitly acknowledge the components and features of
irony is precisely to decrease the negativity of criticisms (Dews, irony—which demands second-order ToM abilities and only de-
Kaplan, & Winner, 1995). Other authors have found that on the velops later in childhood.
contrary irony enhances criticism (Colston, 1997; Toplak & Katz, Taking the standpoint that irony is a form of humor involves the
2000). question of what distinguishes one form of humor from another. A
c) Finally, understanding the effects of humor and irony, re- theoretical analysis of all the different forms of humor goes be-
quires one to consider the expansion of the common ground yond the scope of this paper. Actually, the boundaries between the
between the interlocutors (Clark, 1996). Adults and children share subcategories are fuzzy, no clear distinctions have been established
the ability to detect “affordances for funniness” (Reddy, 2008). in the literature, and it is even unclear if providing definitions of
This is what allows perceiving or constructing together humorous the different humorous phenomena is an attainable task (Attardo,
situations and sharing amusement. As regards irony, the only way 1994, 2002; Norrick, 1993). Distinctions may involve the opposi-
to distinguish between ironic and serious utterances is by focusing tion between literal and nonliteral or the different degrees of
on shared attitudes and expectations (Airenti, Bara, & Colombetti, knowledge constituting the common ground requested for com-
1993). At the core of different theories of irony is the consideration prehension or how teasing they are. Moreover, different configu-
that irony is the reminder of (Kreuz & Glucksberg, 1989), the echo rations of these aspects can make the comprehension of some
of (Wilson & Sperber, 1992), the allusion to (Kumon-Nakamura et forms more difficult than others.
al., 1995) something that interlocutors are supposed to share. Our standpoint that irony is a form of humor allowed us to
In conclusion, there are different definitions of irony, which compare in a single study young children’s comprehension of
focus on different aspects of irony and its pragmatic function. We irony and joke. We have used the term joke as dictionaries define
consider that, instead of adopting one of them, we can operate it: something said or done for cause amusement or a trick played
relying on a simplified definition that includes the main features for fun. Jokes result from the fact that what is said or done is
that the different models present in the literature have identified: unexpected and then incongruous with respect to reality and are in
irony is a nonliteral utterance which demands to be understood general mildly teasing. We considered that simple literal jokes
sharing a common ground, is focused on an unexpected incongru- could be good instances of unsophisticated humor. As regards
ity, and has a teasing aspect. irony, the traditional definition of Grice considered only the case
Starting from this simplified definition of irony we make the in which an utterance is taken to have a meaning opposite to its
general hypothesis that young children may understand the com- literal content (Grice, 1975, 1978). Most post-Gricean theories
municative intent of ironic utterances even if they are unable to adopt the point of view of Sperber and Wilson (1981), who argued
136 ANGELERI AND AIRENTI

that there are several forms of irony where the intended meaning mances in the experimental situations should be more similar
is not simply the opposite of the literal one. With respect to to the ones observed in everyday life.
development it is possible that not all the forms of irony present
the same level of difficulty (Bosco & Bucciarelli, 2008). In our 3) Joke and irony understanding would show different stages of
study, we have distinguished two forms, contingent irony and development. We predicted that joke is the easiest form,
background irony, which we have supposed to be of different followed in turn by contingent irony, and finally by back-
difficulty with respect to comprehension due to the different access ground irony. The basis of this prediction was the assump-
to common ground they involve. tion that jokes make a very early part of young children
We assessed understanding presenting to 3.0- to 6.5-year-old interactions with adults and are based on incongruities im-
children a number of scenarios in which two puppets handled by mediately perceived while irony is constructed on the basis
two experimenters were involved in four types of simple commu- of more elaborated knowledge. In turn, the common ground
nicative interactions: (1) literal factual serious communicative acts shared by the participants in the contingent situation is more
that can be conceived as control items (e.g., one puppet plays ball direct than in the background situation, which appears more
and the other says: “I like playing ball too”), (2) joke, that is, demanding.
nonserious utterances (e.g., the puppets laughed at the experi-
4) Finally, in order to investigate the critical factors involved in
menter making funny faces and one puppet said to the other “Look,
irony understanding, we explored its relationship with ToM
what funny faces!”), (3) contingent irony, the most simple case of
abilities and child receptive vocabulary as a measure of
irony, based on what we call a form of manifest sharedness. The
language development, two aspects that the literature has
irony in this case derives from the negation of something that is
shown as strongly related (e.g., Lewis & Osborne, 1990;
directly perceived by the interlocutors, (e.g., one puppet fails to
Milligan, Astington, & Dack, 2007; O’Neill, 2005).
score a basket and the other says: “Your shot was pretty good!”),
and finally (4) background irony, a different case of irony, based
on what we can call a form of previously acquired sharedness (e.g., Method
one puppet breaks a plate and the other says: “Your mommy will
be happy!”), where irony is based on something that the interloc- Participants
utors are supposed to share but which is not directly perceived or
mentioned (in this case, the fact that the mother is not happy when A total of 100 Italian children (50 girls, 50 boys) were tested.
her child breaks something). All children were recruited through kindergarten centers and ele-
It is important to note that children were presented with simple mentary schools from the greater Turin area. The mean age for
interactions depicting familiar situations (e.g., puppets playing children was 4.77 years (SD ! 1.14 years). The global sample was
with sand, playing with a basket, and so on), and we asked them divided into the following four age groups: 25 3.0- to 3.5-year-olds
open questions with the purpose of creating a relatively naturalistic (M ! 3.34 years; SD ! 2.1 month), 25 4.0- to 4.5-year-olds (M !
communicative situation, which offered the opportunity to provide 4.25 years; SD ! 1.8 months), 25 5.0- to 5.5-year-olds (M ! 5.19
expansive and comprehensive answers. Our objective was to have years; SD ! 3.88 months) and 25 6.0- to 6.5-year-olds (M ! 6.32
children providing their interpretation of the communicative acts years; SD ! 2.88 months). For the sake of simplicity, we will refer
instead of orienting them to give judgments using predefined to the four age groups as 3-year-olds, 4-year-olds, 5-year-olds and
aspects of irony. Moreover, we proposed to put forward the hu- 6-year-olds. Each age group included an equal number of boys and
morous component of irony placing side-by-side ironic utterances girls. Criteria for inclusion were that participants had no history of
and joking situations. In particular we focused on common ground, speech and language difficulties, were Italian native speakers, and
that is, shared knowledge that constitutes the basis for comprehen- had no known significant medical or neurological condition. Par-
sion (Clark, 1996). We considered that in situations where the ents were informed about the research details and provided in-
common ground is easy to deal with, even young children would formed consent for their children to participate in our study.
be able to understand jokes, and probably also some forms of In order to check the consistency of language ability in each age
irony. group, children were administered the Peabody Picture Vocabulary
Our expectations were the following: Test–Revised (PPVT-R; Dunn & Dunn, 1981; Italian adaptation:
Stella, Pizzioli, & Tressoldi, 2000). The mean scores for each
1) All children— even the younger ones—would be able to group are reported with other participants’ details in Table 1. All
understand the humorous intent underlying joke situations. children were within the normal range. Moreover, to ensure ho-
mogeneity of linguistic ability within each age group, Grubb’s test
2) At least some children in the younger groups would succeed was used in the statistical evaluation of the data to identify outliers.
in the irony comprehension task. We suggest that children For the PPVT-R, no outliers were detected at the 95% significance
are able to participate in communicative interactions in level within each age group, consequently we did not exclude any
which irony is in place not because they understand the exact participants from the sample. As it will be clear in the Result
nature of the ironic utterances (i.e., the use of nonliteral section, the scores obtained using the PPVT-R were further anal-
language, the ironic intentions of the speaker, and so on), but ysed to examine the contribution of verbal skills in irony under-
because they participate in a wide range of communicative standing.
interactions, becoming more and more familiar with the use Socioeconomic status (SES) was measured by family composi-
of communicative practices and activities. Thus, if the chil- tion, parental education level and occupation, and was obtained
dren are presented with familiar interactions, their perfor- using the Two-Factor Index of Social Position (ISP) developed by
CHILDREN’S UNDERSTANDING OF JOKE AND IRONY 137

Table 1
Sample Description: Demographic Details and Peabody Scores of Participants

Sex Age (years) Peabody score


Age group No. of children Female Male M SD M SD

3-yr-olds 25 12 13 3.34 .17 38.20 9.65


4-yr-olds 25 13 12 4.25 .15 55.56 13.71
5-yr-olds 25 13 12 5.19 .32 80.88 19.16
6-yr-olds 25 12 13 6.32 .24 95.48 18.93
Total 100 50 50 Mean 4.77 .22 67.53 15.36

Hollingshead (1975), combining information about parents’ jobs children are involved from very early on and therefore
and educational attainment. Parents were free to decide whether familiar and shared among all young children.
they would complete the SES questionnaires; nine families did not
return the questionnaire. According to the parent reports of the Theory of mind tasks. Three ToM tasks were used in the
remaining 91 families, the majority of children were from the present study. These tasks examined the ability to understand first-
middle social class (47.2%), but other classes were also repre- and second-order false belief. First-order false belief tasks required
sented (lower: 9.7%; lower-middle: 25%; upper-middle: 13.9%; a child to make an inference concerning a false belief about a state
and upper: 4.2%). Only 4.2% of children lived with one single of the world; to examine this ability we used the following two
parents, while 95.8% of children lived with two married or cohab- tasks: the Smarties task (Perner, Leekam, & Wimmer, 1987), and
iting parents. the Sally-Ann task (Wimmer & Perner, 1983).
In the Smarties task, children were shown a familiar container
(in this case, a Pringles box, due to the fact that Smarties boxes are
Materials
no longer familiar to Italian children) and were asked to indicate
Irony task. Sixteen puppet show scenarios were depicted; we what it held. Then the unusual contents were revealed (i.e., a
created scenarios that were likely to be familiar to the 3.0- to pencil) and the children were asked what a person who had not
6.5-year-old children (e.g., playing with sand, eating cakes, going seen the pencil would have said was inside the container.
for a bike ride). Some examples of the puppet scenarios are given For the Sally-Ann task, we followed the experimental procedure
in the Appendix (available online as supplemental material). In suggested by Baron-Cohen, Leslie, and Frith (1985). We presented
each scenario, two puppets were involved in a communicative children with two dolls, Sally and Ann, and first we asked children
interaction; the speaker puppet did not perform any action but the naming question (“Who is this doll? And this one?”) in order
produced an utterance in response to the other puppet’s behaviour. to check that the children knew which doll was which. Then Sally
The utterance might have been a simple and common comment placed a ball into her basket, and left the scene; the ball was
(control situation), a joke, or an ironic utterance; the utterances transferred by Ann and hidden in her box. When Sally returned,
were equivalent in terms of length and syntactical difficulties. In the experimenter asked the critical belief question: “Where will
more detail, there were four different types of scenarios (four Sally look for her ball?” If the children replied/pointed to the
scenarios for each type): previous location of the ball, then they correctly responded to the
belief question by appreciating Sally’s present false belief. If they
1) Control stories, where the speaker puppet produced a literal, replied/pointed to the ball’s current location, then they failed the
factual, and serious comment spoken with matter-of-fact belief question by not taking into account the doll’s belief. These
tone in response to the other puppet’s behaviour (contextual conclusions were warranted if two control questions were an-
cues present); swered correctly: “Where is the marble really?” (reality question);
“Where was the marble in the beginning?” (memory question).
2) Joke, where the speaker puppet produced an utterance spo-
Second-order stories investigate the ability to understand a false
ken with joking tone to evoke laughter or amusement (con-
belief about another character’s belief; to examine this ability we
textual cue present);
used the Ice-cream van story task (Baron-Cohen, 1989). The story
3) Contingent irony, where the speaker puppet produced an was read to the children who were shown a paperboard model
ironic utterance spoken with joking tone that implied the scenario presenting the action sequences involved in the story.
negation of something directly perceived by the interlocutors John and Mary are together in the park. Along comes the ice-cream
(contextual cue present); man. John would like to buy an ice cream but has no money with
him. The ice-cream man tells him to go home and get his money.
4) Background irony, where the speaker puppet produced an In the meantime he will be staying in the park. When John comes
ironic utterance spoken with joking tone that could be com- home to get the money, the ice-cream man moves to the church.
prehended only referring to shared knowledge; for example, Later John meets the ice-cream man in front of the church, but
normally children don’t like spinach, any mom tries to stop Mary does not know about that because she came back home
sibling squabbles, and so on (contextual cue absent). The before. Children were then asked: “Where does Mary think that
proposed situations are expected to refer to contexts in which John has gone to buy an ice-cream?”
138 ANGELERI AND AIRENTI

Procedure If the child replies “Because he has broken a plate” the examiner asks:
“And why did the puppet say that?”
Children were tested individually in a separate quiet room
outside of their classroom. The PPVT-R and all theory of mind If the child replies “The mommy will be happy,” the examiner asks:
tests were presented first. Then, two puppets were introduced to “Will mommy be happy?” If the child replies “No,” the examiner
asks: “And why did the puppet say that?”
the children. The various objects involved in the experimental
scenarios were all placed in a small bag; during the experimental Narratives for the puppet scenarios were told by two experi-
sessions, they were taken from the bag and put on the table in front menters who had been instructed to use the appropriate tone
of the children. After every puppet show, each child was asked: according to the situations. For prompts the experimenters were
“Why did the puppet say that?” Throughout the interviews, the instructed to use a neutral tone in order to exclude any cue toward
experimenter used some prompts to elucidate children’s responses a preferred response, and to stop after two prompts. The puppet
to the questions and/or to obtain explanations of the responses; the scenarios were presented in random order.
prompt questions were the same for each child, but they were used The order of the 16 scenarios was randomized across children.
only when the child was briefly distracted or the responses were The experimental sessions lasted approximately 40 minutes, per-
ambiguous, and they did not necessarily indicate a failure in the mitting pauses if needed. All sessions were audiotaped and chil-
comprehension task. dren’s responses verbatim were transcribed.
In order to further clarify the experimental protocol used in the Some more examples of experimental questions and children’s
present study, we report some examples of items: responses are given in the Appendix (available online as supple-
mental material).
(1) Control Story

Puppet A is drawing; puppet B says: “So nice you’re drawing!” Scoring Procedure
Examiner: “Why did puppet B say that?” Irony task. After every puppet scenario, there was a question
(“Why did the puppet say that?”) involving children’s understand-
If the child’s answer is not clear, ambiguous, or merely descriptive, ing of the communicative intent. Only in the case that children
the examiner gives a prompt. For example, if the child replies “He’s made ambiguous replies, the examiner posed a set of other ques-
drawing,” the examiner asks: “And why did the puppet say that?” tions aimed at clarifying children’s understanding. Children’s re-
(2) Joke plies obtained 1 point if they understood the joke/ironic commu-
nicative intent; otherwise, they obtained a score of 0. Responses
Puppet A makes funny faces; the two puppets are laughing. Puppet B were considered correct if the children identified the correct com-
says: “Look! What funny faces!” municative intention as resulting from the explicit reference to the
puppet’s utterance, in order to avoid the possibility that children
Examiner: “Why did Puppet B say that?”
were generically referring to the proposed situation.
If the child’s answer is not clear, ambiguous, or merely descriptive, We present here some examples of scoring.
the examiner gives a prompt. For example:
(1) Control Story
If the child replies “Because he makes funny faces,” the examiner
asks: “And why did the puppet say that?” Puppet A is drawing; puppet B says: “So nice you’re drawing!”

(3) Contingent Irony Example of child’s answer: “Because he likes drawing” (score ! 1)

Puppet A fails to score a basket; puppet B says: “Well done!” Comment: In the answer the child recognises the seriousness of the
utterance.
Examiner: “Why did puppet B say that?”
Example of child’s answer: “I don’t know why” (score ! 0)
If the child’s answer is not clear, ambiguous, or merely descriptive,
(2) Joke
the examiner gives a prompt. For example:
Puppet A makes funny faces; the two puppets are laughing. Puppet B
If the child replies: “Because they are playing,” the examiner asks:
says: “Look! What funny faces!”
“And why did the puppet say that?”
Example of child’s answer: “He said that because it is so fun”
If the child repeats: “Well done” the examiner asks: Was it well done?
(score ! 1)
If the child replies “No,” the examiner asks: “And why did the puppet
say that?” Comment: In the answer the child recognises that the puppet’s utter-
ance is supposed to evoke amusement.
(4) Background Irony
Example of child’s answer: “Because they are laughing” (score ! 0)
Puppet A broke a plate; puppet B says: “Your mom will be very
happy!” Comment: The child does not refer to the utterance but to the
situation.
Examiner: “Why did puppet B say that?”
(3) Contingent Irony
If the child’s answer is not clear, ambiguous, or merely descriptive,
the examiner gives a prompt. For example: Puppet a fails to score a basket; Puppet B says: “Well done!”
CHILDREN’S UNDERSTANDING OF JOKE AND IRONY 139

Example of child’s answer: “Because he wanted to make fun of him”


(score ! 1)

Comment: The child recognises that the puppet’s answer is nonliteral


and nonserious.

Example of child’s answer: “Because he was good at playing”


(score ! 0)

Comment: The child takes the puppet’s answer literally.

(4) Background Irony

Puppet A broke a plate; puppet B says: “Your mom will be very


happy!”

Example of child’s answer: “The mom will be mad!” (score ! 1)

Comment: The child recognises that the puppet’s answer is nonliteral.


Figure 1. Children’s performance on the control, joke, contingent, and
Example of child’s answer: “The mom will be happy” (Examiner: background irony stories by age group.
“Will mommy be happy?”) Child: Yes (score ! 0)

Comment: The child takes the puppet’s answer literally.

Two independent raters coded children’s responses. The Co- Analysis and Results
hen’s k value was .90, indicating almost perfect agreement (Landis
& Koch, 1977). Comparison Between Irony Scenarios
The Appendix (available online as supplemental material) dis-
plays some other examples of children’s answers, and scoring. First, children’s scores across irony scenarios and age groups
were compared to determine whether there was a difference among
Theory of mind tasks. The theory of mind tasks were coded
the tasks, and whether the ability to understand different types of
on the basis of the coding procedures normally used in the liter-
irony was characterised by an age-related improvement. Table 2
ature. In more detail, in the Smarties task children’s answers were
displays the mean proportions of correct responses for the four
coded as correct if they replied “Pringles!,” showing an appreci-
types of scenarios (control, joke, contingent irony, and background
ation of the mental state of the person involved in the task (Perner,
irony stories) in the four age groups and in the whole sample.
Leekam, & Wimmer, 1987). In the Sally-Ann task an error in ToM
To test the hypothesis that different tasks would show increasing
is revealed at the belief question if the child answers the wrong difficulty levels, we performed a repeated measures ANOVA on
location of the ball (i.e., the box), since Sally is unaware of Ann’s the whole sample (see the bottom line of Table 2). A linear contrast
covert action (Wimmer & Perner, 1983). To pass the task and was fitted to the data under the hypothesis that task difficulty
obtain 1 point at the belief question, the children had to pass all the would be ordered as follows: control stories " jokes " contingent
questions posed (naming, reality, and memory questions; Baron- irony " background irony. The analysis showed a significant
Cohen et al., 1985). In the Ice-cream van story task children effect of task difficulty in the predicted direction (F(1, 99) !
obtained 1 point if they passed test question and if they correctly 255.37, p " .001, #2 ! .72).
answered the control questions, following the procedure reported The effect of age on children’s performance was investigated
in Wimmer and Perner (1983). with a between-subjects ANOVA with four levels corresponding
To summarise, for each task a single score was given for to the four age groups, and average performance across tasks as the
children’s responses (0 –1). Also in this case, the responses of all dependent variable (rightmost column of Table 2). A linear con-
participants on every theory of mind task were coded by two trast was fitted to the data under the hypothesis that performance
independent judges; interrater agreement was almost perfect (Co- would increase linearly with age. Again, age showed a significant
hen’s k ! .94). effect on performance in the predicted direction (F(1, 98) ! 31.02,

Table 2
Mean (SD) of Correct Responses to the Different Types of Scenarios (Scoring Range 0 –1)

Background
Age group Control stories Joke Contingent irony irony Average score

3-yr-olds .97 (.08) .85 (.24) .57 (.33) .40 (.26) .70 (.16)
4-yr-olds 1.00 (.00) .87 (.21) .71 (.30) .52 (.25) .77 (.12)
5-yr-olds 1.00 (.00) 1.00 (.00) .87 (.22) .60 (.24) .87 (.09)
6-yr-olds .95 (.12) .97 (.09) .92 (.14) .63 (.23) .86 (.09)
Whole sample .98 (.08) .92 (.17) .77 (.29) .54 (.26) .80 (.14)
140 ANGELERI AND AIRENTI

Table 3 Table 4
Mean (SD) of Correct Responses to the Theory of Mind Tasks Correlations Between Irony and ToM Scores (Global Sample)
(Scoring Range 0 –1)
Variables 1 2 3 4 5 6 7
Sally & Smarties’ Ice-cream
Age group Ann task story Total 1. Sally & Ann —
2. Smarties’ task .35!! —
3-yr-olds .08 (.28) .20 (.41) .00 (.00) .09 .15 3. Ice-cream story .31!! .34!! —
4-yr-olds .40 (.50) .25 (.44) .04 (.20) .25 .29 4. Control stories $.07 $.03 $.14 —
5-yr-olds .64 (.49) .63 (.49) .28 (.46) .51 .33 5. Joke .14 .23! .12 $.12 —
!! !!
6-yr-olds .84 (.37) .72 (.46) .36 (.49) .64 .30 6. Contingent irony .34 .32 .21 $.01 .24! —
!

Mean .49 (.50) .45 (.50) .17 (.38) .37 (.35) 7. Background irony .15 .27!! .11 .05 .23! .46!! —
! !!
p " .05. p " .01.

p " .001, #2 ! .24), indicating that children’s performance sig-


nificantly increased with increasing age (see Figure 1). hand, the whole pattern of correlations might be explained by age
differences between children. In order to disentangle these possi-
Correlations Between Irony, Language, and bilities and ascertain the specific effects of ToM and language on
ToM Scores humor comprehension, we fitted a series of path analysis models to
the data and employed formal model selection techniques to
First, in order to investigate the relation between children’s ToM choose the most appropriate among them.
development and their understanding of irony, correlational anal-
yses were performed. Children’s scores on the various ToM mea-
sures (Sally & Ann, Smarties’ task, and Ice-cream story) were Path Analysis: Effects of ToM, Language Abilities,
correlated with understanding of irony tasks (control, joke, con- and Age on Humor Comprehension
tingent irony, and background irony). Table 3 presents the descrip- To begin with, a set of four alternative path-analytic models
tive statistics for each ToM task in the sample. Table 4 displays (Models A$D in Figure 2) was constructed based on theoretical
correlations among ToM tasks and irony comprehension. considerations. In these models, various combinations of age,
Statistically significant correlations were found among the ToM ToM, and language ability (PPVT-R) predicted humor compre-
tasks (.31 " r " .35; p " .01), as well as among the irony tasks, hension, either directly or indirectly. In all models, age had direct
namely joke, contingent irony, and background irony (.23 " r " causal effects on language, ToM, and humor comprehension. In
.46; p " .05). No significant correlations were observed between Model A, both language and ToM had direct effects on humor
control stories and ToM tasks ($.14 " r " $.03; p % .05), and comprehension; moreover, language had a direct effect on ToM
with irony stories ($.12 " r " .05; p % .05). For this reason, in (and thus an additional indirect effect on humor comprehension).
the following analysis we collapsed the three ToM tasks into a Model B was the same as Model A without the effect of language
single ToM score, and the three pragmatic tasks (joke, contingent on ToM. In Model C, only ToM had a direct effect on humor
irony and background irony) into a single humor comprehension comprehension, while language had only an indirect effect through
score, while the control stories were excluded. While the three ToM. Finally, in Model D, language ability affected both humor
pragmatic tasks are conceptually distinct, collapsing them into a comprehension and ToM, and ToM had no independent causal
single score provides a more statistically robust measure of overall effect on humor comprehension.
pragmatic ability (Cronbach’s alpha ! .73), as well as more robust Models were fitted to the covariance matrix using maximum-
estimates of path coefficients. Indeed, running separate analyses likelihood estimation, and compared using the small-sample ver-
for each task (humor, contingent irony, and background irony) sion of Akaike’s AIC (AICC; see Burnham & Anderson, 2002).
yielded virtually identical patterns of results, supporting the deci- Models were fit with R 2.8.0 (R Development Core Team, 2008)
sion to employ the summary score in the main analysis. with the sem package version 3.0 (Fox, 2008). Fit indices are
In order to examine what factors contribute to success in irony shown in Figure 2. Model D achieved the best combination of fit
comprehension, the global humor comprehension score was then and parsimony, as shown by the lowest value of AICC, and was
correlated with children’s performance on PPVT-R (language therefore selected as the best model in the set. In order to test the
test), the global ToM score, chronological age, and sex. Table 5
shows correlations among these variables.
The humor score was significantly correlated with the ToM Table 5
score (r ! .37, p " .0001), with the PPVT-R score (r ! .56, p " Correlations of Irony Score, ToM Score, Peabody Score, Age,
.0001), and with children’s age (r ! .54, p " .0001); no significant and Sex (Global Sample)
correlations were found with the sex of participants. While this
pattern of correlations could imply a causal effects of both ToM Variables 1 2 3 4 5
and language abilities on humor comprehension, the interpretation 1. Irony score —
of these findings is complicated by the correlation between ToM 2. ToM score .37!! —
and language, and— even more importantly— between all the per- 3. PPVT-R .56!! .61!! —
formance variables and chronological age. On the one hand, indi- 4. Age .54!! .62!! .81!! —
vidual differences in language abilities might determine a spurious 5. Sex .10 .05 .01 .01 —
! !!
correlation between ToM and humor comprehension. On the other p " .05. p " .01.
CHILDREN’S UNDERSTANDING OF JOKE AND IRONY 141

Figure 2. Potential models among age, language skills, ToM ability, and irony comprehension.

possible effects of children’s sex, direct effects of sex on ToM, As expected, age significantly predicted both language ability
language, and humor comprehension were added to Model D, and ToM skills, while the direct effect of age on humor compre-
leading to Model E (see Figure 2). Model E failed to outperform hension was not significant. Language had simultaneous effects on
Model D, and sex was consequently dropped from the analysis. humor comprehension and ToM performance; however, ToM had
The standardized parameters of Model D are shown in Figure 3. no independent effect on humor comprehension. In other words, in
the selected model the correlation between ToM and humor un-
derstanding (see Table 5) was entirely spurious. Specifically, this
correlation was accounted for by (a) the shared direct effects of
language ability on ToM and humor, and (b) the shared indirect
effects of chronological age on language and ToM.

Discussion
The current study was designed to investigate the emergence of
humor and irony comprehension in young children. Our goal was
to examine the possibility of an early competence and a progres-
sive increment already during the preschool period; moreover, we
tried to clarify the role played by theory of mind and language
Figure 3. Standardized parameters of model D (see Figure 2). Variances, skills in children’s acquisition of these communicative acts.
disturbances, and measurement errors are omitted for clarity of presenta- A number of experimental studies have shown that irony is a
tion. communicative phenomenon that is difficult to grasp. The obser-
142 ANGELERI AND AIRENTI

vation of real life situations seems to contradict this fact: is it true authors related with a different use of irony in home environment.
that when a mother tells her child coming back dirty from the This is also consistent with our hypothesis that comprehension of
playroom “Here you are, ready for a visit to your grandmother!” irony is not dependent on the ability of making inferences on the
the child does not understand the real meaning intended by the other’s mind, but on the familiarity with these specific forms of
mother? A mother who utters such an utterance implies shared communicative interactions. While ToM abilities show a certain
knowledge about a familiar situation for the child, being washed degree of individual variability, they also increase strongly with
and changed clothes before a visit to grandmother. The general age. On the contrary, as Recchia and colleagues (2010) have
purpose of our study was to investigate whether the difficulty that found, there is a great deal of variability across families in their use
many children displayed in experimental situations might be as- of ironic language. As these authors suggest, to gain new insight
cribed to the fact that children were asked to judge communicative on this correlation future research should combine children’s ob-
acts and to make the comprehension of their ironic nature explicit. servation in family context and experimental assessment.
Actually, it has been shown that even adults may well understand Our results show that it is useful posing the distinction between
the communicative intent of irony without taking notice of the the comprehension of the communicative intent of an ironic utter-
specific ironic form used (Gibbs, 1986). We can then consider that ance and understanding of the ironic form. The fact that there are
this be true also for children. Understanding what is meant by two different steps in irony comprehension has been proposed in
ironic utterances should be assessed without asking children ex- the literature (Ackerman, 1983; Hancock et al., 2000) attributing
plicit judgments, which by definition imply second-order theory of these two steps to different levels of ToM abilities. Our point of
mind abilities. view is more radical. Children are involved since very young in
For that reason, we designed a task in which children had to communicative interactions, which imply shared knowledge
show their comprehension of the communicative intent of ironic (Airenti, 2010). It is on the background of this familiar knowledge
utterances—that is, what the speaker meant— by answering open- that children may have direct access to the speaker’s communica-
ended questions related to natural communicative contexts. We tive intent without elaborating the specific literal phrasing. In fact,
assumed that adopting such a flexible approach children would be people in general, even adults in everyday communicative inter-
able to demonstrate their emergent irony understanding. Moreover, actions, just limit to comprehend the “real meaning” of a commu-
as irony can be considered as a form of humor, we associated irony nicative act, which often is not the literal meaning. Adults are more
comprehension to simple joke situations. proficient with respect to children because in case of failure or
Children were required to deal with communicative situations uncertainty they may resort to more complex inferences while this
that are rather common in parent/children and peers interactions. is not the case for young children. Our approach is compatible with
These situations covered different forms of humor, including jokes those studies that have shown that young children are able to grasp
and two forms of irony, and some everyday serious interactions the communicative intentions of their interlocutors while having
used as control items. We considered that the knowledge necessary difficulties taking account of the specific linguistic form that has
for the comprehension of these situations could be assumed with a been used to convey them (Olson & Hildyard, 1981; Robinson,
reasonable probability. We expected that under these conditions Goelman & Olson, 1983). It has been suggested that the capacity
the task would be accessible also to young children, and that at of distinguishing literal meaning from communicative intent is a
least some of them would have been able to understand the general ability that develops between first and second grades (Beal
communicative intent even in the case of ironic utterances. & Flavell, 1984).
In the present study, the performance of children in all age In the literature about irony this issue has been summarised as
groups in jokes did not differ significantly from the performance in the contrast between one-stage and two-stage theories (Attardo,
control situations. As regards the comprehension of irony we 2000). On this matter a debate has opposed Gibbs (1984), who has
found an increasing trend of performance with children’s age; as contended that the comprehension of the real meaning is immedi-
expected the immediate access to shared knowledge on which ate and does not pass through the failure of the literal meaning, and
irony is based makes the understanding of contingent irony easier other authors assuming that there are reasons to think that speakers
than the understanding of background irony. From our point of have access also to the literal meaning (Dews & Winner, 1995;
view, the most interesting result regards irony understanding in the Giora, 1997). Recently this debate has been resumed by Gibbs and
younger groups of children. In fact, the 3- and 4-year-olds also Colston (2012), who argue against a principled distinction between
showed a good performance in the contingent irony tasks (.64 and literal and nonliteral language and maintain that figurative lan-
.75, respectively) and a reasonable comprehension of background guage does not represent any cognitive deviation. Actually, this is
irony (.45 and .55, respectively). Thus our results showed that even a general question regarding the link between language and com-
3- and 4-year-old children might comprehend the actual intent of munication. A great part of human communication is not literal
an ironic communicative act. An interesting element is that our and it is a fact that adults deal with it rather easily. Surely, there are
data show an important individual variability with regards partic- cases where the doubt arises if an utterance has to be taken for
ularly to the younger groups. It is in these groups that we find instance as a literal praise or as an ironic blame. What can make the
children who gave correct answers to all the items and others who doubt arise is a lack of shared knowledge. Think of someone saying
never showed comprehension. Different studies on the develop- “Paul is so brilliant!” The interlocutor may not be sure about the
ment of humor have shown a high degree of variability within knowledge and judgments possibly shared with the speaker, and so
groups of children (Brodzinsky & Righmyer, 1980; Masten, 1989; may be unable to decide if the utterance has to be taken as ironic
St. James & Tager-Flusberg, 1994; Varga, 2000). Moreover, this is or not. If the interlocutor, on the contrary, shares with the speaker
consistent with the Finnish study (Loukusa & Leinonen, 2008) that a negative judgment about Paul, the ironic interpretation is imme-
noted the same effect in children aged 3 to 6, an effect that the diately activated as the literal one would be in the case they shared
CHILDREN’S UNDERSTANDING OF JOKE AND IRONY 143

a positive judgment. Thus, questioning about the kind of utterance This finding indicates that simple correlations between ToM, lan-
produced by the speaker, literal or nonliteral, is linked to a failure guage ability, and irony understanding should be interpreted with
of interpreting it on the background of shared knowledge (Airenti considerable caution, since at least some of the effects may be
et al., 1993). In conclusion, comprehension does not require fully partially or entirely spurious. In order to avoid misleading inter-
developed ToM abilities, while producing judgments on commu- pretations of research findings, explicit causal models should be
nicative acts is a ToM task. In the comprehension of the commu- constructed and tested; in particular, the independent effects of
nicative intent children, like adults, rely on other factors such as ToM and language should be assessed after controlling for their
their familiarity with the situation and the accessibility of the statistical overlap and for the indirect effects of chronological age.
knowledge that constitutes the background of the communicative Although the ToM abilities in our study seem to play a minor
act. This last aspect is particularly relevant for irony comprehen- role, these findings are in line with those by Filippova and
sion, as shared knowledge is the only element leading toward the Astington (2008) with respect to language development, and
nonliteral interpretation. In addition, children are able to coordi- with those of several other studies in showing the important role
nate multiple cues in order to interpret ironic utterance, including of language in the acquisition of theory of mind (see for
the literal statement itself, the speaker’s personality, and the type instance, Dunn & Brophy, 2005; Dunn, Brown, Slomkowski,
of statement, from very early (Climie & Pexman, 2008). The Tesla, & Youngblade, 1991; Nelson, 2005; Nelson et al., 2003;
variability of results especially among the younger children can Ruffman, Slade, & Crowe, 2002). Considering that the most
be considered as supporting this point of view. We found the same relevant aspect in irony understanding is the access to shared
variability in a study of ours presently in preparation in which we have knowledge, we can interpret this result considering that linguis-
used parent reports to give account of 2- to 7-year-old children’s tic proficiency allows a more active role in communicative
production of jokes, contingent irony, and background irony. Also, in interactions thus facilitating the acquisition of knowledge nec-
this case variability and a notable precocity in dealing with irony essary to comprehension. In conclusion, we can argue that when
shown by some of the children were associated. actively involved in communication, even young children may
The theoretical perspective and the experimental design that we implicitly understand the communicative intentions of their
have adopted— choosing to include in the same study both jokes interlocutors, before they acquire complete ToM skills, as mea-
and irony tasks—takes a stand on the relation between irony and sured by the well-known ToM tasks.
humor more in general. We believe that there is a strong link In the present study we introduced a distinction between irony
between these two phenomena. In fact, in the developmental based on directly perceived information and irony based on shared
literature such a link has been formulated mainly in terms of irony knowledge. While our findings support the usefulness of this
components, ascertaining the capacity to single out the humorous dichotomy, we intend it as a heuristic device rather than an
component of irony. Dews and colleagues (1996) and Harris and exhaustive taxonomy of ironic acts and we expect that future
Pexman (2003) showed that children appreciate rather late the research in this area will reveal other useful distinctions between
humorous aspect of irony, while Filippova and Astington (2010) related forms of humorous communication.
found that even adults did not find irony particularly funny under In our experimental procedure, children were not asked to
the same experimental conditions. Our results showed that if the provide explicit judgments on the nature of the communicative
problem is posed in terms of the comprehension of the communi- acts they observed. Clearly, a limitation of this approach is that we
cative intent, even young children could comprehend that the cannot know exactly how children interpreted those acts. It could
incongruity of an ironic utterance is intended for fun. This does not be that more specific questions would elicit more explicit infor-
entail that they find ironic utterances funny. As we mentioned in mation about the nature of children’s interpretations. However, our
the introduction, irony as humor in general has always a latent procedure was chosen to be as close as possible to real-life situa-
component of aggressiveness. Thus the perception of fun in humor tions, in which children are rarely if ever asked to precisely
depends on which side one is in real situations (the humorist or the explicate their understanding of a humorous event or interaction.
victim) or with which character one identifies in stories, as it has The novel contribution of the present study is that we were able
been shown by Pexman and colleagues (2005). Here we enter a to document young children’s ability to deal with irony, by dis-
very interesting field which goes beyond the simple comprehen- tinguishing between the ability to comprehend the speaker’s mean-
sion of communicative acts and which surely deserves further ing in communicative contexts from the ability to give explicit
work. judgments on the nature of his or her utterances. By focusing on
A fundamental point we intended to tackle in our study con- the former, we can begin to explain why young children appear
cerned the relations among theory of mind abilities, language way more proficient in real life than they do in most experimental
skills, and irony understanding, an issue that has received much settings.
attention in the current literature (Milligan et al., 2007). From the
present study, both language and ToM skills positively correlated Résumé
with irony understanding; while this picture could be consistent
with a causal effect of both cognitive abilities on irony understand- Les recherches antérieures suggèrent que la compréhension
ing, its interpretation is complicated by the fact that language and d’énoncés ironiques est une capacité qui se développe relativement
ToM skills are correlated to each other, and that both are related to tard, vers l’âge de 5 ou 6 ans. La présente étude cherchait à
chronological age. Our analyses suggested that the correlation déterminer si les enfants plus jeunes pouvaient témoigner d’une
between irony understanding and ToM was spurious, accounted by compréhension d’énoncés ironiques exprimés dans le cadre de
the shared effects of language ability on ToM and irony, and by the situations de communication familières. En outre, elle cherchait à
shared indirect effects of children’s age on language and ToM. déterminer les relations possibles entre la compréhension de
144 ANGELERI AND AIRENTI

l’ironie, le langage et les processus cognitifs de la théorie de Burnham, K. P., & Anderson, D. R. (2002). Model selection and multi-
l’esprit. On a présenté à un groupe de 100 enfants, âgés de 3,0 à 6,5 model inference (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Springer-Verlag.
ans, 4 types de scénarios mettant en scène des marionnettes pour Cameron, E. L., Kennedy, K. M., & Cameron, C. A. (2008). “Let me show
illustrer différentes interactions communicationnelles : situation you a trick!: A toddler’s use of humor to explore, interpret, and negotiate
contrôle, blague, ironie contextuelle et ironie basée sur des con- her familial environment during a Day in the Life. Journal of Research
naissances antérieures. Les résultats obtenus suggèrent a) que les in Childhood Education, 23, 5–18. doi:10.1080/02568540809594642
Capelli, C. A., Nakagawa, N., & Madden, C. M. (1990). How children
enfants plus jeunes comprennent aisément les blagues et parfois
understand sarcasm: The role of context and intonation. Child Develop-
l’ironie; b) la compréhension de l’ironie se développe au cours de
ment, 61, 1824 –1841. doi:10.2307/1130840
la petite enfance; c) les scores pour les mots compris avaient des Clark, H. H. (1996). Using language. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
effets à la fois sur la compréhension de l’ironie et le rendement sur versity Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511620539
le plan de la théorie de l’esprit. Clark, H. H., & Gerrig, R. J. (1984). On the pretense theory of irony.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113, 121–126. doi:
Mots-clés : ironie verbale, théorie de l’esprit, communication, 10.1037/0096-3445.113.1.121
pragmatique développementale. Climie, E. A., & Pexman, P. M. (2008). Eye gaze provides a window on
children’s understanding of verbal irony. Journal of Cognition and
Development, 9, 257–285. doi:10.1080/15248370802247939
References Colston, H. L. (1997). Salting a wound or sugaring a pill: The pragmatic
Ackerman, B. (1981). Young children’s understanding of a speaker’s functions of ironic criticism. Discourse Processes, 23, 25– 45. doi:
intentional use of a false utterance. Developmental Psychology, 17, 10.1080/01638539709544980
472– 480. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.17.4.472 Colston, H. L., & Keller, S. B. (1998). You’ll never believe this: Irony and
Ackerman, B. (1983). Form and function in children’s understanding of hyperbole in expressing surprise. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research,
ironic utterances. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 35, 487– 27, 499 –513. doi:10.1023/A:1023229304509
508. doi:10.1016/0022-0965(83)90023-1 Colston, H. L., & O’Brien, J. (2000). Contrast and pragmatics in figurative
Airenti, G. (2010). Is a naturalistic theory of communication possible? language: Anything understatement can do, irony can do better. Journal
Cognitive Systems Research, 11, 165–180. doi:10.1016/j.cogsys.2009.03 of Pragmatics, 32, 1557–1583. doi:10.1016/S0378-2166(99)00110-1
.002 Creusere, M. A. (2000). A developmental test of theoretical perspectives
Airenti, G., & Angeleri, R. (2011). Dealing with sincerity: Pathways of on the understanding of verbal irony: Children’s recognition of allusion
communication in young children. British Journal of Developmental and pragmatic insincerity. Metaphor and Symbol, 15, 29 – 45. doi:
Psychology, 29, 765–782. doi:10.1348/2044-835X.002007 10.1207/S15327868MS151&2_3
Airenti, G., Bara, B. G., & Colombetti, M. (1993). Failures, exploitations Demorest, A., Meyer, C., Phelps, E., Gardner, H., & Winner, E. (1984).
and deceits in communication. Journal of Pragmatics, 20, 303–326. Words speak louder than actions: Understanding deliberately false re-
doi:10.1016/0378-2166(93)90055-T marks. Child Development, 55, 1527–1534. doi:10.2307/1130022
Andrews, J., Rosenblatt, E., Malkus, U., Gardner, H., & Winner, E. (1986). Demorest, A., Silberstein, L., Gardner, H., & Winner, E. (1983). Telling it
Children’s abilities to distinguish metaphoric and ironic utterances from as it isn’t: Children understanding of figurative language. British Journal
mistakes and lies. Communication & Cognition, 19, 281–297. of Developmental Psychology, 1, 121–134. doi:10.1111/j.2044-835X
Attardo, S. (1994). Linguistic theories of humor. Berlin, Germany: Mouton .1983.tb00550.x
de Gruyter. Dews, S., Kaplan, J., & Winner, E. (1995). Why not say it directly? The
Attardo, S. (2000). Irony as relevant inappropriateness. Journal of Prag- social functions of irony. Discourse Processes, 19, 347–367. doi:
matics, 32, 793– 826. doi:10.1016/S0378-2166(99)00070-3 10.1080/01638539509544922
Attardo, S. (2002). Humor and irony in interaction: From mode adoption to Dews, S., & Winner, E. (1995). Muting the meaning: A social function of
failure of detection. In L. Anolli, R. Ciceri, & G. Riva (Eds.), Say not to irony. Metaphor and Symbolic Activity, 10, 3–19. doi:10.1207/
say: New perspectives on miscommunication (pp. 159 –179). Amster-
s15327868ms1001_2
dam, Netherlands: IOS Press.
Dews, S., & Winner, E. (1997). Attributing meaning to deliberately false
Bariaud, F. (1989). Age differences in children’s humor. Journal of Chil-
utterances: The case of irony. In C. Mandell & A. McCabe (Eds.), The
dren in Contemporary Society, 20, 15– 45. doi:10.1300/J274v20n01_03
problem of meaning: Behavioral and cognitive perspectives (pp. 377–
Baron-Cohen, S. (1989). The autistic child’s theory of mind: A case of
414). Amsterdam, Netherlands: North-Holland/Elsevier Science. doi:
specific developmental delay. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychi-
10.1016/S0166-4115(97)80142-2
atry, 30, 285–297. doi:10.1111/j.1469-7610.1989.tb00241.x
Dews, S., Winner, E., Kaplan, J., Rosenblatt, E., Hunt, M., Lim, K., . . .
Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A. M., & Frith, U. (1985). Does the autistic child
have a “theory of mind”? Cognition, 21, 37– 46. doi:10.1016/0010- Smarsh, B. (1996). Children’s understanding of the meaning and func-
0277(85)90022-8 tions of verbal irony. Child Development, 67, 3071–3085. doi:10.2307/
Beal, C. R., & Flavell, J. H. (1984). Development of the ability to 1131767
distinguish communicative intention and literal message meaning. Child Dunn, J. (1988). The beginnings of social understanding. Cambridge, MA:
Development, 55, 920 –928. doi:10.2307/1130143 Harvard University Press.
Bergen, D. (1989). Characteristics of young children’s expression of hu- Dunn, J., & Brophy, M. (2005). Communication, relationships, and indi-
mour in home settings as observed by parents. International Journal of vidual differences in children’s understanding of mind. In J. W. Asting-
Educology, 3, 124 –135. ton & J. Baird (Eds.), Why language matters to theory of mind (pp.
Bosco, F. M., & Bucciarelli, M. (2008). Simple and complex deceits and 50 – 69). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/
ironies. Journal of Pragmatics, 40, 583– 603. doi:10.1016/j.pragma 9780195159912.003.0003
.2007.05.004 Dunn, J., Brown, J., Slomkowski, C., Tesla, C., & Youngblade, L. (1991).
Brodzinsky, D. M., & Righmyer, J. (1980). Individual differences in Young children’s understanding of other people’s feelings and beliefs:
children’s humour development. In P. McGhee & A. Chapman (Eds.), Individual differences and their antecedents. Child Development, 62,
Children’s humour (pp. 181–212). Chichester, UK: Wiley. 1352–1366. doi:10.2307/1130811
CHILDREN’S UNDERSTANDING OF JOKE AND IRONY 145

Dunn, L. M., & Dunn, L. M. (1981). Peabody Picture Vocabulary Test- Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 124, 3–21. doi:10.1037/
Revised. Circle Pines, MN: American Guidance Service. 0096-3445.124.1.3
Filippova, E., & Astington, J. W. (2008). Further development in social Landis, J. R., & Koch, G. G. (1977). The measurement of observer
reasoning revealed in discourse irony understanding. Child Develop- agreement for categorical data. Biometrics, 33, 159 –174. doi:10.2307/
ment, 79, 126 –138. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8624.2007.01115.x 2529310
Filippova, E., & Astington, J. W. (2010). Children’s understanding of Lewis, C., & Osborne, A. (1990). Three-year-olds’ problems with false
social-cognitive and social-communicative aspects of discourse irony. belief: Conceptual deficit or linguistic artifact? Child Development, 61,
Child Development, 81, 913–928. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8624.2010 1514 –1519. doi:10.2307/1130760
.01442.x Loizou, E. (2005). Infant humor: The theory of the absurd and the em-
Fox, J. (2008). The SEM Package (Version 0.9 –13) [Software]. Retrieved powerment theory. International Journal of Early Years Education, 13,
from http://cran.r-project.org/ 43–53. doi:10.1080/09669760500048329
Gibbs, R. W. Jr. (1984). Literal meaning and psychological theory. Cog- Long, D. L., & Graesser, A. C. (1988). Wit and humor in discourse
nitive Science, 8, 275–304. doi:10.1207/s15516709cog0803_4 processing. Discourse Processes, 11, 35– 60. doi:10.1080/
Gibbs, R. W. Jr. (1986). On the psycholinguistics of sarcasm. Journal of 01638538809544690
Experimental Psychology: General, 115, 3–15. doi:10.1037/0096-3445 Loukusa, S., & Leinonen, E. (2008). Development of comprehension of
.115.1.3 ironic utterances in 3- to 9-year-old Finnish-speaking children. Psychol-
Gibbs, R. W. Jr. (1994). The poetics of mind. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge ogy of Language and Communication, 12, 55– 69. doi:10.2478/v10057-
University Press. 008-0003-0
Gibbs, R. W. Jr. (2000). Irony in talk among friends. Metaphor and Masten, A. S. (1989). Humor appreciation in children: Individual differ-
Symbol, 15, 5–27. doi:10.1080/10926488.2000.9678862 ences and response sets. Humor, 2, 365–384. doi:10.1515/humr.1989.2
Gibbs, R. W. Jr., & Colston, H. L. (2012). Interpreting figurative meaning. .4.365
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/ McGhee, P. (1979). Humor: Its origin and development. San Francisco,
CBO9781139168779 CA: Freeman and Company.
Gibbs, R. W. Jr., & O’Brien, J. (1991). Psychological aspects of irony Milligan, K., Astington, J. W., & Dack, L. A. (2007). Language and theory
understanding. Journal of Pragmatics, 16, 523–530. doi:10.1016/0378-
of mind: Meta-analysis of the relation between language ability and false
2166(91)90101-3
belief understanding. Child Development, 78, 622– 646. doi:10.1111/j
Giora, R. (1995). On irony and negation. Discourse Processes, 19, 239 –
.1467-8624.2007.01018.x
264. doi:10.1080/01638539509544916
Nelson, K. (2005). Language pathways into the community of mind. In
Giora, R. (1997). Understanding figurative and literal language: The
J. W. Astington & J. Baird (Eds.), Why language matters to theory of
graded salience hypothesis. Cognitive Linguistics, 8, 183–206.
mind (pp. 26 – 49). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/
Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan
acprof:oso/9780195159912.003.0002
(Eds.), Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts (pp. 41–58). New York,
Nelson, K., Skwerer, D. P., Goldman, S., Henseler, S., Presler, N., &
NY: Academic Press.
Walkenfeld, F. F. (2003). Entering a community of minds: An experi-
Grice, H. P. (1978). Further notes on logic and conversation. In P. Cole
ential approach to “theory of mind”. Human Development, 46, 24 – 46.
(Ed.), Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics (pp. 113–128). New York,
doi:10.1159/000067779
NY: Academic Press.
Nilsen, E. S., Glenwright, M., & Huyder, V. (2011). Children and adults
Groch, A. S. (1974). Joking and appreciation of humor in nursery school
understand that verbal irony interpretation depends on listener knowl-
children. Child Development, 45, 1098 –1102. doi:10.2307/1128101
edge. Journal of Cognition and Development, 12, 374 – 409. doi:
Hancock, J. T., Dunham, P. J., & Purdy, K. (2000). Children’s com-
prehension of critical and complimentary forms of verbal irony. 10.1080/15248372.2010.544693
Journal of Cognition and Development, 1, 227–248. doi:10.1207/ Norrick, N. R. (1993). Conversational joking. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
S15327647JCD010204 University Press.
Harris, M., & Pexman, P. M. (2003). Children’s perceptions of the social Norrick, N. R. (2003). Issues in conversational joking. Journal of Prag-
functions of verbal irony. Discourse Processes, 36, 147–165. doi: matics, 35, 1333–1359. doi:10.1016/S0378-2166(02)00180-7
10.1207/S15326950DP3603_1 Olson, D. R., & Hildyard, A. (1981). Assent and compliance in children’s
Hoicka, E., & Akhtar, N. (2012). Early humour production. British Journal language. In W. P. Dickson (Ed.), Children’s oral communication skills
of Developmental Psychology, 30, 586 – 603. doi:10.1111/j.2044-835X (pp. 313–335). New York, NY: Academic Press.
.2011.02075.x O’Neill, D. K. (2005). Talking about “new” information: The given/new
Hollingshead, A. B. (1975). Four factors index of social status. New distinction in children’s developing theory of mind. In J. W. Astington
Haven, CT: Yale University Press. & J. A. Baird (Eds.), Why language matters for theory of mind (pp.
Johnson, K. E., & Mervis, C. B. (1997). First steps in the emergence of 84 –105). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
verbal humor: A case study. Infant Behavior and Development, 20, Perner, J., Leekam, S. R., & Wimmer, H. (1987). Three-year-olds’ diffi-
187–196. doi:10.1016/S0163-6383(97)90021-7 culty with false belief: The case for a conceptual deficit. British Journal
Keltner, D., Capps, L., Kring, A. N., Young, R. C., & Heerey, E. A. (2001). of Developmental Psychology, 5, 125–137. doi:10.1111/j.2044-835X
Just teasing: A conceptual analysis and empirical review. Psychological .1987.tb01048.x
Bulletin, 127, 229 –248. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.127.2.229 Peterson, C. C., Peterson, J. L., & Seeto, D. (1983). Developmental
Kreuz, R. J., & Glucksberg, S. (1989). How to be sarcastic: The echoic changes in ideas about lying. Child Development, 54, 1529 –1535. doi:
reminder theory of verbal irony. Journal of Experimental Psychology: 10.2307/1129816
General, 118, 374 –386. doi:10.1037/0096-3445.118.4.374 Pexman, P. M., & Glenwright, M. (2007). How do typically developing
Kreuz, R. J., Long, D. L., & Church, M. B. (1991). On being ironic: children grasp the meaning of verbal irony? Journal of Neurolinguistics,
Pragmatic and mnemonic implications. Metaphor and Symbolic Activity, 20, 178 –196. doi:10.1016/j.jneuroling.2006.06.001
6, 149 –162. doi:10.1207/s15327868ms0603_1 Pexman, P. M., Glenwright, M., Krol, A., & James, T. (2005). An acquired
Kumon-Nakamura, S., Glucksberg, S., & Brown, M. (1995). How about taste: Children’s perceptions of humor and teasing in verbal irony.
another piece of pie: The allusional pretence theory of discourse irony. Discourse Processes, 40, 259 –288. doi:10.1207/s15326950dp4003_5
146 ANGELERI AND AIRENTI

Pexman, P. M., Zdrazilova, L., McConnachie, D., Deater-Deckard, K., & Sroufe, L. A., & Piccard Wunsch, J. (1972). The development of laughter
Petrill, S. A. (2009). “That was smooth, mom”: Children’s production of in the first year of life. Child Development, 43, 1326 –1344. doi:10.2307/
verbal and gestural irony. Metaphor and Symbol, 24, 237–248. doi: 1127519
10.1080/10926480903310286 Stella, G., Pizzioli, C., & Tressoldi, P. (2000). Peabody–Test di vocabo-
Pien, D., & Rothbart, M. K. (1976). Incongruity and resolution in chil- lario recettivo. Torino, Italy: Omega Edizioni.
dren’s humor: A re-examination. Child Development, 47, 966 –971. St. James, P. J., & Tager-Flusberg, H. (1994). An observational study of
doi:10.2307/1128432 humor in autism and Down Syndrome. Journal of Autism and Develop-
R Development Core Team. (2008). R: A language and environment for mental Disorders, 24, 603– 617. doi:10.1007/BF02172141
statistical computing (Software). Vienna, Austria: R Foundation for Sullivan, K., Winner, E., & Hopfield, N. (1995). How children tell a lie
Statistical Computing. Retrieved from http://www.R-project.org from a joke: The role of second-order mental state attributions. British
Recchia, H. E., Howe, N., Ross, H. S., & Alexander, S. (2010). Children’s Journal of Developmental Psychology, 13, 191–204. doi:10.1111/j
understanding and production of verbal irony in family conversations. .2044-835X.1995.tb00673.x
British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 28, 255–274. doi: Toplak, M., & Katz, A. N. (2000). On the uses of sarcastic irony. Journal
10.1348/026151008X401903 of Pragmatics, 32, 1467–1488. doi:10.1016/S0378-2166(99)00101-0
Reddy, V. (1991). Playing with others’ expectations: Teasing and mucking Varga, D. (2000). Hyperbole and humor in children’s language play.
about in the first year. In A. Whiten (Ed.), Natural theories of mind: Journal of Research in Childhood Education, 14, 142–151. doi:10.1080/
Evolution, development and simulation of everyday mindreading (pp. 02568540009594759
143–158). Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell. Veatch, T. C. (1998). A theory of humor. Humor, 11, 161–215. doi:
Reddy, V. (2008). How infants know minds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard 10.1515/humr.1998.11.2.161
University Press. Wilson, D., & Sperber, D. (1992). On verbal irony. Lingua, 87, 53–76.
Ritchie, D. (2005). Frame-shifting in humor and irony. Metaphor and doi:10.1016/0024-3841(92)90025-E
Symbol, 20, 275–294. doi:10.1207/s15327868ms2004_3 Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and
Roberts, R. M., & Kreuz, R. J. (1994). Why do people use figurative constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understand-
language? Psychological Science, 5, 159 –163. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280 ing of deception. Cognition, 13, 103–128. doi:10.1016/0010-
.1994.tb00653.x 0277(83)90004-5
Robinson, E. J., Goelman, H., & Olson, D. R. (1983). Children’s under- Winner, E. (1988). The point of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
standing of the relation between expressions (what was said) and inten- sity Press.
tions (what was meant). British Journal of Developmental Psychology, Winner, E., Brownell, H., Happé, F., Blum, A., & Pincus, D. (1998).
1, 75– 86. doi:10.1111/j.2044-835X.1983.tb00545.x Distinguishing lies from jokes: Theory of mind deficits and discourse
Ruffman, T., Slade, L., & Crowe, E. (2002). The relation between chil- interpretation in right hemisphere brain-damaged patients. Brain and
dren’s and mothers’ mental state language and theory-of-mind under- Language, 62, 89 –106. doi:10.1006/brln.1997.1889
standing. Child Development, 73, 734 –751. doi:10.1111/1467-8624 Winner, E., & Leekam, S. (1991). Distinguishing irony from deception:
.00435 Understanding the speaker’s second-order intention. British Journal of
Shultz, T. R. (1976). A cognitive developmental analysis of humor. In A. J. Developmental Psychology, 9, 257–270. doi:10.1111/j.2044-835X.1991
Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), Humor and laughter: Theory, research .tb00875.x
and applications (pp. 11–36). New York, NY: Wiley.
Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1981). Irony and the use-mention distinction. In
P. Cole (Ed.), Radical pragmatics (pp. 295–318). New York, NY: Received May 15, 2013
Academic Press. Accepted September 28, 2013 !

View publication stats

You might also like