The Abuse of Beauty - DANTO

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 23

The Abuse of Beauty

Author(s): Arthur C. Danto


Source: Daedalus , Fall, 2002, Vol. 131, No. 4, On Beauty (Fall, 2002), pp. 35-56
Published by: The MIT Press on behalf of American Academy of Arts & Sciences

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/20027805

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

American Academy of Arts & Sciences and The MIT Press are collaborating with JSTOR to
digitize, preserve and extend access to Daedalus

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur C. Danto

The abuse of beauty

It is self-evident that nothing concern For example, shortly after the terrorist
ing art is self-evident any more, not its attack on the World Trade Center in
inner life, not its relation to the world, New York in 2001, the composer Karl
not even its right to exist. heinz Stockhausen proclaimed it "the
greatest work of art ever. " Since his lan
- Theodor Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, 1969
guage conveyed extreme admiration, he
was instantly disgraced in the minds of
most. That such a claim could be made
1 at all underscores the total openness of
It is the mark of the contemporarythepericontemporary concept of art, how
od in the history of art that no conever monstrous the consequences of
straints govern the way works of visual
conceiving art in that way.
art should look. An artwork can look like
The philosophical history of art culmi
anything, and be made of anythingnates
- in the recognition that there is no
anything is possible. merit in asking any longer whether this
or that can be art, for the answer will al
ways be yes, noting that limits external
to the definition of art - moral consider
Arthur C. Danto, art critic for "The Nation"
ations
magazine and Emeritus Johnsonian Professor of above all - always remain. The de
finition
Philosophy at Columbia University, has been a of art must accordingly be con
sistent
Fellow of the American Academy since 1980. He with an absolute pluralism as far
is the author of numerous books, includingas"Niet
works of art are concerned. I am al
most certain that Adorno's cultural de
zsche as Philosopher" (1965), "The Transfigura
spair derived from this perception,
tion of the Commonplace" (19Si), and "Encoun
though
ters and Reflections : Art in the Historical Pre not even that paradigmatically
sent," a collection of art criticism that won pessimistic
the thinker, whose thought was
darkened
National Book Critics Circle Prize for Criticism inby the Holocaust, would have
been
1990. "The abuse of beauty" is based on the able to imagine a statement like
Stockhausen's, let alone the horror that
Cams Lectures presented to the American Philo
sophical Association in December of 2001.occasioned
Danto it.
is currently preparing a revised and greatly ex
panded version of these lectures that will be pub A he publication of Adorno ' s Aesthetic
lished as a book by Open Court Press in 2003. Theory in 1969 coincided with the end of
a decade of remarkably intense inquiry,

D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur c. conducted by artists as well as philoso against either the standards of ordinary
Danto phers, though largely in independence of discourse - where we know whereof we
beauty one another. Indeed, an essay with speak - or of a scientific discourse gov
which the decade properly began - erned by strict considerations of verifi
Clement Greenberg's i960 "Modernist ability and confirmability. It is difficult
Painting" - remarked upon a parallel be to resist the impulse to see a cultural
tween modernist art and a certain form equivalence between the canonization of
of philosophical practice. Comparing ordinary language cultivated by the Ox
contemporary art with a form of self ford School of Linguistic phenomenolo
criticism exemplified in the Critique of gy and the studied aesthetic of everyday
Pure Reason, Greenberg called Kant the objects in Warhol's Factory or Claes
first modernist. Self-criticism in the arts, Oldenberg's 1962 Store on East Second
as understood by Greenberg, consisted Street in Manhattan, where one could
in purifying the relevant medium of the buy painted effigies of gym shoes, auto
art form. Thus three-dimensionality was mobile tires, and women's underpants.
extrinsic to painting, which was essen
tially flat, in Greenberg's view. AAow much of any of this fell within
Accordingly, he believed painting should the horizons of official aesthetics is his
be purged of illusionism of any kind, and torically problematic, but some philoso
depth given over by right to sculpture. phers certainly grasped that the defini
Greenberg's agenda was one of art de tion of art was at issue as never before.
fining itself from within, and there can In 1965, the British philosopher Richard
be no question that this quasi-Kantian Wollheim published an important essay
endeavor was pursued, often with a cer on "Minimal Art." Though Wollheim
tain puritanical fervor, by a number of was subsequently credited with coining
artists bent on making art in its concep the term 'minimalism,' he admits to
tually purified condition. This was par having known nothing of the works that
ticularly the case with the so-called min finally became so designated. His con
imalists. But in truth, philosophy and cern in his essay, rather, was whether
avant-garde art shared a great many atti there are minimal criteria for something
tudes in the 1960s. being designated art. His paradigms
One aim of pop, for example, was to were monochrome painting, which was
ironize the distinction between high and generally regarded as a mere philosophi
vernacular art - between the heroized cal joke until perhaps 1915, and the
painting of the previous generation of ready-mades that Marcel Duchamp put
artists, the Abstract Expressionists, and forward as art at about that same time.
the popular imagery of the comic strip In addressing this concern, Wollheim
and commercial advertisements - the followed the official philosophical mod
'High and Low' of a controversial exhi el according to which having a concept
bition at the Museum of Modern Art in
requires criteria for picking out its in
1992. But comparably, it was an effort of stances. It was a Wittgensteinian com
analytical philosophy to overcome the monplace that instances can be culled
pretensions of what we might call 'high' out successfully without benefit of defi
philosophy - the cosmo-tragical visions nitions, as in the case of games. In fact
of the Existentialists or of the towering there can be no criteria for distinguish
titans of metaphysics who loomed be ing a ready-made metal grooming comb
hind them - by criticizing its language by Duchamp from an indiscernible met

36 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
al grooming comb that was not a ready vanced art of the 1960s, but from the ad- The abuse
made, nor a monochrome white paint vanced philosophy of art of that decade ?f beauty
ing from a panel all over which white as well. Nor could it be part of the defi
paint had been slathered - so the ques nition of art if anything can be an art
tion of definition became urgent after work, since it is certainly not true that
all. anything is beautiful.
Indeed, with the advent of conceptual Not long after the John Simon Gug
art at the end of the 1960s, the material genheim Memorial Foundation was
object was no longer required - nor did established in 1925, the founders saw as
it necessarily have to be made by the art its immediate beneficiaries "Men and
ist. "I've stopped making objects," the women devoted to pushing forward the
artist Douglas Huebner said in a 1969 in boundaries of knowledge and to the cre
terview. "And I'm not trying to take any ation of beauty." Art in that era was tac
thing away from the world. Nor am I try itly defined in terms of creating beauty,
ing to restructure the world. I'm not try and that creation was in turn put on
ing to tell the world anything, really. I'm equal footing with efforts at expanding
not trying to tell the world that it could the boundaries of knowledge.
be better by being this or that. I'm just, Forty years later, reference to the cre
you know, touching the world by doing ation of beauty was omitted from the
these things, and leaving it pretty much enabling language for the National
the way it is. " Leaving the world as we Endowment for the Arts, presumably
found it, we had been told by Wittgen because beauty had largely disappeared
stein, is the way it is with philosophy, from the artistic agenda in 1965. But
too. beauty still played a role in the thinking
What follows from this history of con of the era's politicians, many of whom
ceptual erasure - and the concomitant dismissed modern art as depraved and
pluralism I began by remarking - is not destructive. Congressman George A.
that art is indefinable, but that the con Dondero of Michigan wrote that "Mod
ditions necessary for something to be art ern art is communistic because it is dis
will have to be fairly abstract to fit all torted and ugly, because it does not glo
imaginable cases, and in particular that rify our beautiful country, our cheerful
very little remains of 'our concept of art' and smiling people, and our material
that the framer of a real definition can progress. Art which does not beautify
rely on. In The Transfiguration of the Com our country in plain simple terms that
monplace (1981) I came up with two con everyone can understand breeds dissat
ditions, condensed as "x is an art work if isfaction. It is therefore opposed to our
it embodies a meaning." The chief merit government and those who create and
of this definition lay in its weakness. promote it are our enemies."
Missing from my proto-definition, as The newspaper magnate William Ran
from all the philosophical definitions of dolph Hearst "equated any form of artis
art put forth during the 1960s that I can tic radicalism with communism, and
recall, was any reference to beauty, assumed that the work produced in a
which would surely have been among non-traditional manner was a disguised
the first conditions to have been ad means of communist propaganda. " This
vanced by a conceptual analyst at the is but one instance, as we shall see, of the
turn of the twentieth century. Beauty politicization of beauty.
had disappeared not only from the ad In the early 1990s, the art critic Dave

D dalus Fall 2002 37

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur C. Hickey was asked what he thought the guage regarding the fate of Metaphysics,
0?nt0 central issue of the decade would be. "brings beauty only scorn ; a matron out
beauty "Snatched from my reverie, I said 'Beau cast and forsaken."
ty,' and then, more firmly, 'The issue of
the nineties will be beauty. ' " This was A he twentieth century did not begin
greeted, he recalls, with a "total uncom with such disdain for the concept of
prehending silence. ... I had wandered beauty. In a letter to Thomas Monro in
into this dead zone, this silent abyss." 1927, George Santayana wrote of his gen
eration that "We were not very much
?-jet me begin to put this silence into a later than Ruskin, Pater, Swinburne, and
certain perspective by considering the Matthew Arnold. Our atmosphere was
photography of Robert Mapplethorpe, that of poets and persons touched with
who had become notorious in 1989 when religious enthusiasm or religious sad
his exhibition The Perfect Moment was ness. Beauty (which mustn't be men
cancelled by the Corcoran Museum of tioned now) was then a living presence,
Art in an ill-advised preemptive move or an aching absence, day and night." It
against the danger that funding for the was precisely its beauty that justified the
National Endowment for the Arts might esteem in which art was held in San
be voted down if our legislators saw tayana's time. Here, for example, are
what the fund was supporting. The fear some thoughts that are almost unintelli
was based on the charged sexual content gible today, from the early writing of
of his signature images - though it was Santayana's contemporary G. E. Moore:
central to his achievement that his work "I cannot see but what that which is
was self-consciously beautiful as well. It meant by beautiful is simply and solely
was this, rather than its content, that that which is an end in itself. The object
alienated the photographic avant-garde of art would then be that to which the
against him. objects of Morals are means, and the
When I was writing my book on Map only thing to which they are means. The
plethorpe, I asked an artist who was at only reason for having virtues would be
the time experimenting with pinhole to produce works of art. "
cameras what he thought of him. He dis In his early text Art, Morals, and Reli
missed Mapplethorpe as a pompier-an gion, Moore wrote, "Religion is merely a
artist so concerned with elegance as to subdivision of art," which he explicated
have lost touch with the limits of his me this way: "Every valuable purpose which
dium. The imperatives of modernism, as religion serves is also served by Art; and
defined by Greenberg, tended to make Art perhaps serves more if we are to say
the simple grainy snapshot the paradigm that its range of good objects and emo
of photographic purity. And the charge tions is wider." There can be no doubt
against Mapplethorpe was that his work that Moore believed that art can take re
was too beautiful to qualify for critical ligion's purposes over because of the
endorsement. Gerhard Richter recalls, beauty it essentially possesses.
"One writer claimed that if I painted sex
and violence, it would have been okay, JLNow I would like to offer a historical
but one isn't allowed to paint anything speculation. It is that the immense es
beautiful." teem in which art continues to be held
"The changed fashion of the time," if I today is an inheritance of this exalted
may appropriate Kant's mournful Ian view of beauty. It is widely and some

38 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
times cynically said that art has replaced place in virtue of a conceptual error. The abuse
religion in contemporary consciousness. Once we are in a position to perceive ?* eauty
My speculation is that these Edwardian that mistake, we should be able to re
attitudes have survived the abjuration of deem beauty for artistic use once again.
beauty itself. I will go even further to But conceptual analysis by itself, with
suggest that if there is a place for beauty out the reinforcement of a kind of Fou
in art today, it is connected with these cauldian archeology, is insufficiently
survivals, which are deeply embedded in powerful to help us in this task. Had it
human consciousness. not, for example, been for the artistic
Beauty's place is not in the definition avant-garde in the twentieth century,
or - to use the somewhat discredited idi philosophers almost certainly would
om - the essence of art, from which the continue to teach that the connection
avant-garde has rightly removed it. That between art and beauty is conceptually
removal, however, was not merely the tight.
result of a conceptual but, as I shall ar
gue, a political determination. And it is An the latter sections of Principia Ethica,
the residue of aesthetic politics that lin first published in 1903, Moore wrote,
gers on in the negativity we find in atti "By far the most valuable things we
tudes toward beauty in art today. The know or can imagine, are certain states
idea of beauty, the poet Bill Berkson of consciousness, which may roughly be
wrote me recently, is a "mangled sodden described as the pleasures of human
thing." intercourse and the enjoyment of beauti
But the fact of beauty is quite another ful objects." Moore thought the point
matter. "so obvious that it runs the risk of seem
In a passage near the beginning of ing to be a platitude." No one, Moore
Proust's Within a Budding Grove, Marcel claims, "has ever doubted that personal
(the Narrator), traveling by train to Bal affection and the appreciation of what is
bec, sees a peasant girl approaching the beautiful in Art or Nature, are good in
station in the early morning, offering themselves." Nor, he continues, "does it
coffee and milk. "I felt on seeing her that appear probable that any one will think
desire to live which is reborn in us when that anything else has nearly so great a
ever we become conscious anew of value as the things which are included
beauty and of happiness. " under these two heads."
I believe Proust's psychology profound Moore's confident appeals seem al
in connecting the consciousness of most shockingly parochial, but I'll sup
beauty with happiness - providing we pose they were commonplace in his
are not conflicted because of a negativity world. What would not have been com
that had yet to inflect the idea of beauty monplace, however, is what he next goes
in the generation of Proust, Moore, and on to claim, namely that "this is the ulti
Santayana. mate and fundamental truth of Moral
I would like to press this further. It was Philosophy," and that these two values
the moral weight that was assigned to "form the rational ultimate end of hu
beauty that helps us understand why the man action and the sole criterion of
first generation of the twentieth-century social progress." People might come to
avant-garde found it so urgent to dis accept these as truths, but they appear,
lodge beauty from its mistaken place in Moore said, to be "truths which have
the philosophy of art. It occupied that been generally overlooked."

D dalus Fall 2002 39

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur C. I think Moore must have been correct aim in this is to "release the people of his
^anto thsit if truths, these were generally over native state from the bondage of ugli
beauty looked, since they were perceived as ness. " There would be no way - or no
having the force of revelation by the easy way - to transform Detroit or Pitts
Bloomsbury circle, whose entire philos burgh into the Catskills or the Grand
ophy of art and of life were derived from Canyon. But artistic beauty was porta
Moore's teaching. "A great new freedom ble, so if the aesthetically deprived citi
seemed about to come," according to zenry of American City could be put in
Vanessa Bell. Love and friendship, on the the presence of "treasures sifted to posi
one hand, and what Moore speaks of "as tive sanctity," it would benefit immense
the proper appreciation of a beautiful ly from the contemplation of beautiful
object" were to suffice, without the need objects, which Moore endorsed as the
for religion, in satisfying the main moral highest moral good.
needs of modern human beings.
With the exception of Hume and A he problem was that modernist paint
Hegel, the classical aestheticians drew ing, in the period James's novel was first
no crucial distinction between art and
published, was beginning to veer, some
nature in regard to the appreciation of what starkly, away from the mimetic
beauty, and it must be borne in mind model. In 1910 and 1912, modernist
that that indifference was but rarely con painter and critic Roger Fry organized
tested in philosophical aesthetics nor in two notorious postimpressionist exhibi
artistic practice itself when Moore com tions at the Graf ton Gallery in London.
posed Principia Ethica. If anything, I As it happens, the Bloomsbury circle,
think, Moore supposed the appreciation and Moore himself, praised the objective
of natural beauty superior to the appre beauty of the unprecedented works on
ciation of artistic beauty, largely because display in these exhibitions. But a great
"We do think that the emotional con
many professional art critics disagreed.
templation of a natural scene, supposing The artistic representations so deviated
its qualities equally beautiful, is in some from the motifs they transcribed that
way a better state of things than that of a many viewers saw no way of dealing
painted landscape ; we would think that with them. "One gentleman," wrote Fry,
the world would be improved if we "is so put to it to account for his own in
could substitute for the best works of
ability to understand these pictures that
representative art real objects equally he is driven to the conclusion that it is a
beautiful." colossal hoax on the part of the organiz
Moore believed that so far as the picto ers of the exhibition and myself in par
rial arts are concerned, a beautiful paint ticular."
ing is a painting of a beautiful subject. Attempting to explain the incapacity
And this I think gave a certain impor of such gentlemen to appreciate objec
tance to the museum of fine arts as a site
tive beauty, Fry blamed ignorance and
in which to experience beauty in those unfamiliarity:
years. In Henry James's The Golden Bowl
(1905), his character Adam Verver, a Almost without exception, they tacitly as
sume that the aim of art is imitative repre
man of immense wealth living abroad,
sentation, yet none of them has tried to
has conceived the idea of building a
"museum of museums" for American show any reason for such a curious propo
sition. A great deal has been said about
City, where he amassed his fortune. His

40 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
these artists searching for the ugly instead How does this happen ? Fry believed The abuse
of consoling us with beauty. They forget that it happens through critical explana- ?* eauty
that every new work of creative design is tion. People have to be brought to un
ugly until it becomes beautiful ; that we derstand the work, and the way in which
usually apply the word beautiful to those it is actually beautiful. That, more than
works of art in which familiarity has en the actual explanations Fry gave, is his
abled us to grasp the unity easily, and that great achievement. For it makes clear
we find ugly those works in which we still that artistic beauty often requires expla
perceive beauty only by an effort. nation if it is to be appreciated, some
thing that Hume understood completely.
The perception of these artworks as ugly
"In many orders of beauty, particularly
was, in effect, the projection onto them
those of the finer arts," Hume writes in
of a mental confusion that a course in
aesthetic education will remove. Postim the Enquiry Concerning the Principles of
Morals, "it is requisite to employ much
pressionist painters, Fry goes on to say,
reasoning in order to feel the proper sen
affirm "the paramount importance of
timent ; and a false relish may frequently
design, which necessarily places the imi
be corrected by argument and reflec
tative side of art in a secondary place."
tion." Hume is eager to point out that
This is the basis of Fry's formalism.
"moral beauty partakes much of this lat
But Fry himself made a mistake even
ter species."
more profound than those critics who
supposed it was the aim of painting to
imitate nature. His mistake was suppos With qualification, I accept Fry's
point, as well as the spirit of Hume's
ing it was the aim of painting to be beau marvelous observation. What I want to
tiful.
deny, however, is that the history of ap
I give Fry great credit for recognizing
preciation always culminates in the ap
that something needed to be explained
preciation o? beauty. That, as I see it, is
in order that those who scoffed might
the assumption of Edwardian aesthetics,
perceive the beauty of postimpressionist which the kind of art selected for the
painting, but I draw special attention to
Grafton Gallery exhibitions ought to
the a priori view that the painting in
have called into question. The Edwar
question really was beautiful, if only
viewers knew how to look at it. dians, for example, were entirely right to
begin to appreciate African art. They
Since Fry, it has become a common
were even right in thinking that, on for
place that the history of modernism is
mal grounds, it could be seen as beauti
the history of acceptance. This story is
ful. The Victorians had thought that
told over and over by docents and lectur
'primitive peoples' were, in making art,
ers in art appreciation. In this view, the
trying to make beautiful objects, only
history of art always has a happy ending.
they did not know exactly how - hence
Manet's Olympia, vilified in 1865, became
their 'primitivity.' The Edwardians
a world treasure two generations later:
in The Guermantes Way, Proust writes of
thought themselves advanced because
formalism enabled them to see what Fry
the way "the unbridgeable gulf between
called "Negro sculpture" as beautiful.
what they considered a masterpiece by
But they were wrong in thinking that
Ingres and what they supposed must for
they had learned through formalism to
ever remain a 'horror' (Manet's Olympia,
see the beauty that was the point of
for example) shrank until the two can African art.
vases seemed like twins."

D dalus Fall 2002 41

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur C. That was never its point, nor was in 1873, when Rimbaud published th
^an o beauty the point of most of the world's poem. In Fantin-Latour's group por
beauty great art. It is very rarely the point of art of the previous year, Un Coin de Tabl
today. Rimbaud is shown seated with Ver
Having lived through the Sensation ex and a number of other bohemians i
hibition at the Brooklyn Museum in group called Les Villains Bonhommes
1999, with its crude exploitation of what Bad Eggs - of whom Verlaine and R
might shock or offend, I can sympathize baud were, one might say, the 'badde
with Fry. The critics, pretty much to a The portrait of Rimbaud - the only
person, condemned the art, and were trait of him we possess - is of a sing
certain they were being put upon. But ly beautiful, almost angelic looking
some of us were ready to see it as a First youth, shown in a pensive state. He
Amendment rather than aesthetic mat eighteen, and a rakehell, and the d
ter, and in this we were perhaps more ty between his character and his ap
right than someone would have been ance, as in Dorian Grey, is a familiar
who hoped that through argument they ure of fit that has come to give beau
would see the beauty it was in some bad name. His badness extends even
measure the object of the art to injure. his aesthetic preferences, which he
This is not to say that beauty does not logs in the Delires section of his poem
have a role to play in the art of our own "Idiotic pictures, shop signs, stage se
day. But in order to find out what that backcloths for street-entertainers, b
role might be, we shall have to free our boards, vernacular images, old fash
selves from the Edwardian axiom that all stories, church Latin, badly spelt po
good art is categorically beautiful, if only nography, romance novels for elderl
we have learned to recognize how. We ladies, fairy tales, little books for ch
will have to find ways of justifying art dren, old operas, silly refrains, na?v
other than those with which my narra rhythms." What Rimbaud would n
tive of the decline of beauty began. It is have known was that his inventory
an achievement of the conceptual histo to become the substance of an alte
ry of art in the twentieth century that we tive aesthetic a century later.
have a much more complex idea of artis Though I have no wish to lose my
tic appreciation than the early modern in interpreting Rimbaud's poem, it
ists - or modernism in general, down to perhaps must, be read as a tribute to
its formulation in the writing of Clement power of beauty, the disparities not
Greenberg as late as the 1960s. standing. Having abused Beauty in
third line, it is as if the poet were se
tenced to madness - a season in hel
2 penalty. He explicitly titles the secti
the poem
Near the opening of Une Saison in which
en Enfer - he declares his
aesthetic
allegedly an allegorical account of preferences
his as Ravings. Th
section
tumultuous relationship with ends with what feels like Ri
the poet
Verlaine - Rimbaud writes : "One
baud eve to his senses, though
coming
ning, I sat Beauty on my knees ; and heavy
be read as I irony: "All that's
found her bitter, and I abused
hind her.
me"now. Today I know how t
down
The 'bitterness of beauty' before
became epi beauty."
demic in the avant-garde art Itof
is the
as iffol
Rimbaud intuited a thoug
lowing century, but it was can hardly
a rare suppose he could have r
thought

42 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Critique of Judgment - that "the iXant interestingly handled moral and The abuse
beautiful is the symbol of the morally aesthetic differences in systematically ?* eau y
good." Kant's thought is not entirely parallel ways. He learned about the
easy to follow, but he clearly wants to say South Seas from reading Captain Cook's
that finding something beautiful is more voyages, and clearly he was struck by the
than simply taking pleasure in experi otherness of the societies Cook de
encing it. The beautiful "gives pleasure scribes. The question comes up for him
with a claim for the agreement of every whether those other lives are ones we
one else." For this reason, "the mind is would morally be able to live. In the
made conscious of a certain ennoble schedule of cases in which he attempts
ment and elevation above the mere sen to illustrate the working of the categori
sibility of pleasure received through cal imperative, he considers a talented
sense, and the worth of others is esti individual in comfortable circumstances
mated in accordance with a like maxim who "prefers indulgence in pleasure to
of their judgment." And Kant goes on to troubling himself with broadening and
claim that "the subjective principle in improving his fortunate natural gifts." It
judging the beautiful is represented as would be entirely consistent with the
universal, i.e., valid for every man." The laws of nature that everyone should live
abuse of beauty in this view is the sym like "the inhabitants of the South Seas,"
bolic enactment of an offense against so by one formulation of the categorical
morality and hence, in effect, against hu imperative, it would be permissible that
manity. "I had armed myself against jus a man "should let his talents rust and re
tice," Rimbaud says just after confessing solve to dedicate his life only to idleness,
his crime. indulgence, and propagation." But we
It is not clear, even if it would have "cannot possibly will that this should
been possible for him to have imagined become a universal law of nature," for
it, that the abuse of beauty would be re "as a rational being, one necessarily wills
garded by Kant as ipso facto a moral evil, that all one's faculties should be devel
since beauty only symbolizes morality, oped inasmuch as they are given to one
and between moral and aesthetic judg for all sorts of possible purposes."
ments there is only the kind of analogy, The implication is that the South Sea
to use his example, that may hold be islanders are not quite rational, but even
tween a commonwealth and a living so ought to live in conformity with the
body. So aesthetic imperatives are moral Protestant ethic, and that is what we
imperatives only symbolically. Kant rec must teach them as moral missionaries.
ognizes that not everyone will agree, Kant was in no sense a moral relativist.
case by case, on questions of beauty, but What relativists regard as differences in
the analogy requires the belief that they culture Kant regarded as but differences
ought to, whatever the force of the in development, on the model of the dif
ought. There was an Enlightenment ten ferences between children and adults.
dency to believe that the same moral Kant similarly contests South Sea aes
principles - the golden rule for exam thetics, as he understands them. Pre
ple - were to be found in every society, sumably based on an anthropological
so universality must have seemed co illustration he must have seen, Kant was
extensive with humanity. Would there aware that there are parts of the world in
have been a parallel view in regard to which men are covered with a kind of
beauty? spiral tattoo : "We could adorn a figure

D dalus Fall 2002 43

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur C with all kinds of spirals and light but reg are wrong. They just don't know what
ato uj jjnes as j.]^ ]sjew Zealanders do with beauty is, which he would have defined
on '
beauty their tattooing, if only it were not the
in terms of what we may as well term th
Protestant
figure of a human being," he writes. In aesthetic.
Even Hegel,
this same section of the Third Critique, he the first major philoso
says, "We could add much to apher actually to have gone out of his way
building,
which would immediately please the at
to look eyepaintings and listen to music -
and,"as we shall see, an extraordinary art
if only it were not to be a church.
critic
These are imperatives of taste, and -ithad
is a difficult time with other
striking that Kant considers thetraditions.
tattoo as "The Chinese," he writes in
merely a form of ornamentation, the like
Philosophy of History, "have as a gen
gilded statuary on a church, rathercharacteristic,
eral than a remarkable skill in
imitation,
a set of marks that may have nothing to which is exercised not merely
do with beautification, but serve rather
in daily life but in art. They have not yet
to connect the tattooed personsucceeded
with in representing the beautiful
as beautiful
some larger scheme of the world. The ; for in their painting, per
tattoo may conduce to admirationspective
of itsand shadow are wanting." (Ma
bearer - but not for aesthetic reasons
net, who so pushed shadows to the side, as
much as for whatever it is in aweperson
find thethem in photographs, inevitabl
flattened
tattoo signified - military prowess, say, his figures, which explains in
or cosmic rank. Similarly withsome measure the outcry against his
the brass
work.) The implication is that the Chi
neck coils affected by the Paduang
women of Burma. And something of the
nese have either no idea of beauty or a
wrongin
same sort may be true of ornament one. But Chinese culture had a
the German baroque church Kant very different
evi idea of visual truth than
dently finds offensive to tasteHegel
- as ifhad,
the and hence a different view of
passions of northern European
theicono
aims of representation. No one cou
clasm were merely expressions of aes
count their art as ugly, which is the oper
thetic revulsion. So it is with reference to
ative thought in Fry's dictum that thing
cognitive rather than aesthetic willjudg
be perceived as ugly until they are
perceived as beautiful. It was Hegel who
ments that both ought to be assessed.
I would hesitate to say that all cases ofaesthetic education, fixated as
required
so-called beautification can be
hedeflected
was on the Renaissance paradigm of
mimesis.
in this way, but the possibility suggests
that a universal beauty may be But Fry understood, as a modernist,
entirely
consistent with cultural differences, our between beauty and
that the ligature
mimetic
mistake consisting in regarding representation had been irre
certain
things as aesthetic when they versibly loosened in his time. He knew
have some
that one func
quite different and more cognitive could not argue his critical au
tion. The aesthetic diversity ofdiences
theinto agreeing that C?zanne or
world's art is consistent withPicasso
beauty showsas the world as we really see
such being everywhere the same, it. He if
had one
instead to argue that this is
cared to defend that thesis. not relevant, and that the emphasis must
If, on the other hand, tattooing
be notinon the
vision but on design - to use
South Seas really is beautiful "in the of
the terms his famous title. Then we
eye
of the South Sea Islander," Kant must
can see the beauty of African and Chi
nese that
feel himself entitled to the view art, having
theysurrendered the mis

44 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
leading mimetic criteria so compelling between art and morality, on another The abuse
to Hegel. plane Ruskin was right that "all great art ?* eau y
Loosening the beauty-mimesis liga is morality." In 1903, as we have seen,
ture made it possible for Fry to become a Moore seriously argued that the con
great formalist art critic, but because he sciousness of beauty was among the su
continued to see the ligature between art preme moral goods. We are safe, I think,
and beauty as a necessary connection, so in speaking of an atmosphere at the be
that of necessity art is always beautiful, ginning of the twentieth century in
it failed to occur to him, as a theorist, which Rimbaud's image of abusing
that whole artistic traditions have exist beauty could still have been seen as an
ed in which beauty was never the point abuse of morality.
at all. I can think of no more vivid a gesture
Beauty was not the rainbow that of abusing beauty by abusing great art
awaited us as the reward of sustained than Duchamp's 1919 work in which he
looking. It was never the case that the drew a moustache on a postcard of
only proper way to address art was that Mona Lisa, and scribbled a mild obscen
of aesthetic contemplation. To put it an ity beneath that paradigm of great art.
other way, it never occurred to Fry, any That work, like everything by Du
more than it had occurred to Ruskin, champ, is a field of fiercely competing
that the beauty that was incontestably interpretations, but I want to use it as a
present in, for example, the great cathe historical signpost of a deep change in
drals may have been a means rather than attitude that calls for a historical expla
an end. nation. I want to focus on an art-histori
The point was not to stand in front of cal episode in the course of which, great
the church and gape at its ornamenta ly to the benefit of the philosophical un
tion, but to enter the church, the beauty derstanding of art, a logical gap was de
being the bait, as it so often is in enter finitively opened between art and
ing into sexual relationships. beauty.
Fry's one contemporary who appears It was a gap that remained invisible to
to have understood this was Marcel the denizens of Bloomsbury, who re
Duchamp. "Since Courbet, it's been be mained, for all their modernist ideals,
lieved that painting is addressed to the late Edwardians. It was invisible to them
retina. That was everyone's error. The because they had the idea, expressed in
retinal shudder!" His argument, remark Fry's dictum, that works of art are per
ably overlooked by aesthetic theory, is ceived as ugly until they are perceived as
quite historical: "Before, painting had beautiful. It was a gap that remained in
other functions, it could be philosophi visible until the great conceptual efforts
cal, religious, moral. Our whole century of the 1960s to define art. That gap is the
is completely retinal, except for the contribution in my view of what I shall
Surrealists, who tried to go outside it term the intractable avant-garde.
somewhat." I want, in setting the scene for my his
torical explanation, briefly to return to
An 1905, ruminating on the somewhat Moore's philosophy - in particular to
farcical contest between Whistler and the connection between the two su
Ruskin, Proust wrote (in a letter to preme goods he holds up for examina
Marie Nordlinger) that while Whistler tion. Moore sees a clear connection be
had been right that there is a distinction tween goodness and beauty: "It appears

D dalus Fall 2002 45

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur c. probable that the beautiful should be de It was with this question that the con
on" ? fined as that of which the admiring con cept of beauty became abruptly politi
beauty templation is good in itself. " The two cized by avant-garde artists around 1915,
values, Moore claims, are so related to which fell midway in the period of the
one another "that whatever is beautiful ready-mades in Duchamp's career.
is also good." He goes further: "To say
that a thing is beautiful is to say, not in A he 'abuse of beauty' became a device
deed that it is itself good, but that it is a
for dissociating the artists from the soci
necessary element in something which ety they held in contempt. Rimbaud be
is : to prove that something is truly beau came an artistic and moral hero - the po
tiful is to prove that a whole, to which it et everyone wanted to be.
bears a particular relation as a part, is "I believe in the genius of Rimbaud,"
truly good." So Moore sees some near the young Andre Breton wrote Tristan
entailments between art and beauty, and Tzara, the author of the dada manifesto
between beauty and goodness. And of 1918. It is dada to which I primarily re
beauty indeed was the principle on fer in the project of disconnecting beau
which Bloomsbury friendship was ty from art as an expression of moral re
based: It consisted almost entirely of vulsion against a society for whom beau
those who assigned to beauty the highest ty was a cherished value and which cher
moral priority. ished art itself because of beauty.
The Bloomsburys saw themselves as Here is a recollective account by Max
the true vessels of civilization. And they Ernst:
perhaps supposed it the mark of a civi
lization that it create individuals of the To us, Dada was above all a moral reac
tion. Our rage aimed at total subversion. A
sort they exemplified. In this, I think, horrible futile war had robbed us of five
they were not so far from Kant, in light
years of our existence. We had experi
of his concluding proposition that beau
enced the collapse into ridicule and shame
ty is the symbol of morality, even if con
of everything represented to us as just,
nected, in his view, by way of a kind of
true, and beautiful. My works of that peri
analogy. There is in aesthetic judgment
an entailed disinterestedness as well as a od were not meant to attract, but to make
people scream.
universality, which in Kant's philosophy
was sine qua non for moral conduct. The Ernst knew the war - he had been an ar
person who values aesthetic experience tilleryman - and his art was aggressive,
has a moral fineness in that she or he is as his perception of the war-makers as
ennobled through the disinterestedness. hateful required it to be.
Remember, further, that Kant defined In some measure this was true of Ger
the Enlightenment as mankind's coming man dada in general. The First Interna
tional Dada exhibition in Berlin had
of age - a cultural stage he would have
believed the South Sea Islanders have signs declaring that art was dead - "Der
not and perhaps for a long time will not Kunst ist Tot" - adding "Long life to the
have attained. maschinen Kunst Tatlins." Its members
And now the question was : how is it were not out to vilify German values ;
that those nations defined by civilized they were bent on destroying them by
high-mindedness should have made the forcing upon German consciousness an
most savage and protracted war that his art it could not swallow. Its means were
tory up to that point had known ? a kind of aggressive foolishness.

46 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The original spirit of dada was a kind He intended that his work be found The
of exaggerated play in the shadow of the disgusting, which was the one aestheti- ?*
war, a way of demonstrating its con cally unredeemable quality acknowl
tempt for the clashing patriotisms by in edged by Kant in the Critique of Aesthetic
fantile actions : the term itself was infan Judgment. Disgust was noticed by Kant as
tile for 'rocking horse,' and the Zurich a mode of ugliness resistant to the kind
dadaists registered their protests of pleasure that even the most displeas
through buffoonery against what Hans ing things - "the Furies, diseases, the
Arp called "the puerile mania for author devastations of war" - are capable of
itarianism which could use art itself for causing when represented as beautiful
the stultification of mankind" : by works of art. "That which excites dis
gust [Ekel],99 Kant writes, "cannot be rep
While the thunder of guns sounded in resented in accordance with nature
the distance, we pasted, we recited, we
without destroying all aesthetic satisfac
versified, we sang with all our soul. We
tion. " Since the purpose of art is taken to
searched for an elementary art that
be the production of pleasure, only the
would, we thought, save mankind from
most perverse of artists would under
the furious folly of these times. We
take to represent the disgusting, which
aspired to a new order.
cannot "in accordance with nature" pro
duce pleasure in normal viewers.
xVada art was vehemently ephemeral - There are, to be sure, those who derive
posters, book jackets, calligrams, pam a perverted pleasure in experiencing
phlets, recitations - as we would expect what the normal viewer finds disgust
from a movement made of poets as well ing: who have, one might say, 'special
as artists. These ephemera, in their very tastes.' Artists interested in representing
ephemerality, were what Tzara celebrat the disgusting would not have this spe
ed as "means of combat." cial audience in view. Their aim is pre
Dada refuses to be found beautiful, cisely to cause through their art sensa
even today, after the passage of time - tions that, in Kant's phrase, "we strive
and that is its great philosophical signifi against with all our might."
cance. Dada exemplifies the intractable The psychobiology of disgust is as yet
avant-garde, since its works are misper not well understood, but the early writ
ceived if perceived as beautiful. That is ers on it followed Darwin in thinking of
not its point or ambition. it as a product of evolution concerned
The narrative of aesthetic redemption "basically with the rejection of food. "
assures us that sooner or later we will see Evidence for the centrality of food "in
all art as beautiful, however ugly it ap cludes the facial expression, which fo
peared at first. Try to see this as beautiful ! cuses on oral expulsion and closing of
becomes a sort of imperative for those the nares, and the physiological con
who look at art that does not appear comitants of nausea and gagging." Re
beautiful at first at all. cent research has widened the scope of
Someone told me that she found beau "disgust elicitors," somewhat weaken
ty in the maggots infesting the severed ing the connection with survival - and it
and seemingly putrescent head of a cow, is with items in this augmented schedule
set in a vitrine by the Young British Art that disgust has become an artistic op
ist Damien Hirst. It gives me a certain portunity for those eager to hold beauty
wicked pleasure to imagine Hirst's frus at bay. Kant would have no recourse but
tration if hers were the received view. to regard this as the perversion of art. It
D dalus Fall 2002 47

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur c. would be of no value to the artists in Kant does make plain that the disgusting
^anto question if a taste for the disgusting is the antonym of the beautiful. So the
beauty were to be normalized. It is essential to disgusting is in any case not conceptual
their aims that the disgusting remain ly connected with the sublime. The ant
disgusting, not that audiences learn to onym of the sublime, he deliciously ob
take pleasure in it, or find it somehow serves, is the silly, which suggests that
beautiful. the effect of dada was less the abuse of
I have seen a sculpture from Nurem beauty than the rejection of the sublime.
berg from the late Gothic era of a figure
known as "The Prince of the World," Ajut just possibly the disgusting, as logi
which looks comely and strong from the cally connected with beauty, can also
front but is displayed in a state of wormy have the connection with morality that
decay from behind; the body is shown beauty does.
the way it would look decomposing in In the early 1990s, curators recognized
the grave. Such sights explain why we a genre of contemporary art they desig
actually bury the dead. There can be no nated 'abject art.' "The abject," writes
question of what is the intended func the art historian Joseph Koerner, "is a
tion of showing bodily decay with the novelty neither in the history of art nor
skill of a Nuremberg stone carver - it is in the attempts to write that history."
not to give the viewer pleasure : it is, Koerner cites, among other sources, a
rather, to disgust the viewer, and in so characteristically profound insight of
doing, to act as a vanitas, reminding us Hegel : "The novelty of Christian and
through presentation that the flesh is Romantic art consisted of taking the ab
corrupt, and its pleasures a distraction ject as its privileged object. Specifically,
from our higher aspirations - namely to the tortured and crucified Christ, that
achieve everlasting blessedness and ugliest of creatures in whom divine
avoid eternal punishment. To show the beauty became, through human evil,
human body as disgusting is certainly to basest abjection."
violate good taste, but Christian artists Rudolph Wittkower begins his great
were prepared to pay this price for what text on art and architecture in Italy after
Christianity regards as our highest moral the Council of Trent by recording the de
purpose. cision of that council to display the
Kant did of course have a concept of wounds and agonies of the martyred, in
the sublime, which I suppose has to tran order, through this display of affect, to
scend morality, because of the close par elicit the sympathy of viewers and
allels he insisted upon between moral through that to strengthen threatened
and aesthetic judgments, without so faith. "Even Christ must be shown 'af
much as asking whether and in what de flicted, bleeding, spat upon, with his
gree the production of beauty itself skin torn, wounded, deformed, pale and
serves or can serve some higher moral unsightly' if the subject calls for it." The
ends. It is quite as if beauty were its own tendency in the Renaissance to beautify
end, justifying the practice of art the crucified Christ was in effect a move
through its existence alone. to classicize Christianity by returning
Kant never asks what the purpose of the tortured body to a kind of athletic
the disgusting might be in a work of art, grace, denying the basic message of
or why the dereliction of beauty might Christian teaching that salvation is at
be a moral means. In a precritical text, tained through abject suffering.

48 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26fff on Thu, 01 Jan 1976 12:34:56 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
The aestheticism of the eighteenth Edwardian views we find in Moore and The abuse
century was a corollary of the rational Bloomsbury. ?fheauty
ism of natural religion. It was Kant's I regard the discovery that something
stunning achievement to situate aesthet can be good art without being beautiful
ics in the critical architectonic as a form one of the great conceptual clarifications
of judgment two small steps away from of twentieth-century philosophy of art,
pure reason. though it was made exclusively by art
In view of the vast human suffering ists, and it would have been seen as com
that was one salient aspect of the twenti monplace before the Enlightenment
eth century, it is astonishing how dispas gave beauty the primacy it has continued
sionate, how rational, how distancing, to enjoy. That clarification managed to
how abstract so much of twentieth-cen push reference to beauty out of any pro
tury art really was. How innocent dada posed definition of art, even if the new
was ! In its refusal to gratify the aesthetic situation dawned very slowly in artistic
sensibilities of those responsible for consciousness.
World War I, dada gave the world bab When a philosopher of art such as
bling in place of beauty, silliness instead Nelson Goodman sets aesthetics aside in
of sublimity. If it injured beauty, it was order to talk about representation and
through a kind of punitive clownishness. meaning, this is not done with the ex
What abject art, so pathetic in its inca pectation that we will return to the con
pacity finally to do much to deflect or di cept of beauty with an enhanced under
minish the degradations of the body that standing. It is done, rather, with the
the politics of our times has used as its awareness that beauty belongs neither to
means, has done is to seize upon the em the essence nor the definition of art.
blems of degradation as a way of crying
out in the name of humanity. "For many
in contemporary culture," Hal Foster 3
writes, "truth resides in the traumatic or On principles of Renaissance theory,
abject subject, in the diseased or dam paintings were windows on the world -
aged body. Thus body is the evidentiary pure, apparently transparent openings
basis of important witnessings to truth, through which one saw the world as if
of necessary witnessings against power. " from outside. So a picture drew its beau
My aim is not to judge the success or ty from the world, ideally having none of
failure of artistic abjection, but rather to its own to contribute to what one saw, as
emphasize that it is intended to resist it were, through it. (This of course over
the prediction that art is ugly until seen looks the contribution of the frame in
as beautiful. It is a misperception of art shaping the way the world presents itself
to see it as always and necessarily con to the eye in a painting.)
cerned with the creation and apprecia The stereotypical painter crooks the
tion of beauty. With dada, a deep con index finger against the thumb, framing
ceptual shift took place. This perhaps the world until it resolves into a picture
justifies the claim that I have often made - until it looks the way she wants her
that in the twentieth century, the artists picture to look - like Lily Briscoe in To
were carrying forward the philosophy of the Lighthouse, or, we imagine, any of the
art in a way that could not have been Bloomsbury painters scouting the south
achieved by philosophers themselves, of France for what the traditional art
whose intuitions were colored by the schools designated motifs.

D dalus Fall 2002 49

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur c. Kant was famously a stay-at-home, but eighteenth century, in France especially,
o?n ? he lived in an era of aesthetic tourism. a close parallel was drawn between
beauty The well-to-do went abroad to see the painting pictures and painting faces, so
sights : the Alps, the Bay of Naples, as that, in his portrait of Madame Pom
well, of course, as the Piazza San Marco, padour at her Vanity, which shows the
the Pantheon, the Leaning Tower, the great lady with her rouge-brush before a
Acropolis. A pictorial industry grew up mirror, Boucher is virtually saluting a
to provide souvenirs - objective memo fellow artist. With the made-up face,
ries - of what one took in. This I take to Kant's follow-up thought would be ex
be the background of Kant's somewhat act - "we are conscious of it as art while
surprising remark, at ?45 of the Critique yet it looks like nature."
of Judgment, that "Nature is beautiful Beautification has tended to incur a
because it looks like art," when one certain puritanical condemnation : it
would have expected the opposite asser traffics in causing the kind of false be
tion instead. Kant seems to be saying liefs that constitute the cognitive basis
that the world is beautiful when it looks for the great cosmetic fortunes of the
the way painters represent it. When one modern world. The French term for 'to
thinks an artist represented a scene be make up' is farder, or 'to color,' which
cause it was beautiful in the first place, explains in part why there was a tradi
one understands rightly the Renaissance tional mistrust of colors - why Descartes
idea that what one sees pictured on a went so far as to say we really did not
canvas or a panel is a transparent view of need our eyes to know what the world
a scene's beauty. was like, since the blind can feel the out
This cannot, however, have been the lines and know the shapes of things.
whole story, not even for Kant, who rec Ruskin appears to have had beautifica
ognized that art was capable of repre tion - or artifice - in mind when, in sup
senting as beautiful "things which may port of the British Pre-Raphaelites, he
be in nature ugly or displeasing. The Fu condemns pretty much the entire histo
ries, diseases, the devastations of war, ry of painting from the time of Raphael
etc. may even be regarded as calamitous, down.
be described as very beautiful, as they In the first of two letters to The Times
are represented in a picture." in 1851, Ruskin wrote that his young pro
So the picture in Kant's understanding teges
must contribute to the beauty, since
these motifs have none. It is here that desire to represent, irrespective of any
conventional rules of picture making; and
Kant makes his parenthetical observa
they have chosen their unfortunate
tion on disgust as the "one kind of ugli
though not inaccurate name because all
ness which cannot be represented in
artists did this before Raphael's time, and
accordance with nature without destroy
after Raphael's time did not do this, but
ing all aesthetic satisfaction, and conse
sought to paint fair pictures rather than
quently artificial beauty.99
represent stern facts, of which the conse
I emphasize 'artificial beauty.' It is
what we would call 'beautification' - quence has been that from Raphael's time
to this day historical art has been in
aesthetic sophism, making the worse ap
acknowledged decadence.
pear better, which involves cosmetics,
fashion, interior decoration, and the It did not incidentally matter that the
like, where we are not dealing with natu reality was only imagined - 'made up' by
ral but with enhanced beauty. In the the artist in the other sense of the ex

50 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
pression - so long as it was not falsified the penalty, the humiliation, almost the The abuse
in the interests of beautification. squalor attendant upon being'made ?* eauty
I cannot help but feel that the aura of flesh' are marked." As enfleshed, God
falsification helps to explain some of the must begin as helplessly as we all be
suspicions aroused when beauty plays a gin - hungry, wet, soiled, confused, col
role in contemporary art. Consider again icky, crying, dribbling, babbling, drool
the case of Mapplethorpe. He tried to ing, and totally dependent. All that is
achieve the excitement of pornographic implicit in Mantegna's picture, and it is
images in artistic, that is, beautiful pho inconsistent with seeing the painting as
tographs. Freud observed that "the geni beautiful. The message transcends beau
tals themselves, the sight of which is al ty and ugliness. It is morally rather than
ways exciting, are hardly ever regarded visually true.
as beautiful." Yet at their most success I want one further example, which
ful, we can barely stand to look at some comes from Hegel, a great art critic,
of Mapplethorpe's pictures from which, writing about a masterpiece by the artist
because of the beauty with which he in the Pre-Raphaelites were to despise : "It
fused them, we cannot tear our eyes is a familiar and frequently repeated re
away. They paralyze the will, as in the proach against Raphael's Transfiguration
case cited by Socrates of a man who that it falls apart into two actions entire
"feasts his eyes" on the sight of corpses. ly devoid of any connection with one
To take a less complex case, Sabastao another," Hegel writes.
Salgado's photographs of suffering hu
And in fact this is true if this picture is
manity are beautiful - and hence, his
considered externally : above on the hill
critics would say, falsified - because suf
we see the transfiguration, below is the
fering of that order, being grim, ought
scene with the child possessed of an un
not to be seen as beautiful. Salgado pret
clean spirit. But if we look at the spirit of
tifies through photographic artifice what
the composition, a supreme connection is
ought to be shown in its true colors. If not to be missed. For, on the one hand,
there is to be art, it should not be beauti
Christ's visible transfiguration is precisely
ful, since the world does not deserve
his elevation above the earth, and his de
beauty. Artistic truth must accordingly
parture from his disciples, and this must
be as sad as human life itself, and art
be made visible too as a separation and a
leached of beauty serves in its own way
departure ; on the other hand, the sublimi
as a mirror of what human beings have
ty of Christ is here especially transfigured
done. Art, subtracted of the stigma of
in an actual simple case, namely in the fact
beauty, serves as what the world has
that the Disciples could not help the child
coming to it. Beautifiers are, so to speak,
collaborationists. without the help of the Lord. Thus here
the double action is motivated throughout
and the connection is displayed within
IVAost of the world's art is not beauti
and without in the fact that one disciple
ful at all, nor was the production of
expressly points to Christ who has depart
beauty part of its purpose. One of the
ed from them and thereby he hints at the
most marvelous pieces of art criticism I
true destiny of the Son of God to be at the
know was written by Fry himself about
same time on earth, so that the saying will
Mantegna's Simone Madonna in Berlin :
be true : Where two or three are gathered
"The wizened face, the creased and
in my name, there am I in the midst of
crumpled flesh of a new born babe... all them.

D dalus Fall 2002 51

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur c. To say design is as weak as beauty would ter to our taste and sentiment." It is in

^anto ke an inappropriate response to this regard to this sort of beauty that one
beauty tremendous work. The design inheres in might say there is no disputing taste. But
the meaning Raphael intends to convey, Hume, as a man of letters, had a vivid
Y effet of the event he has undertaken to sense of the transformative power of
depict visually, when the meaning of the critical reasoning:
event itself- the transfiguration - is not
In many orders of beauty, particularly
entirely visual. Ruskin would be right
those of the finer arts, it is requisite to
about Raphael: 'externally' it lacks visu
employ much reasoning in order to feel
al truth, but internally it conveys truth
the proper sentiment; and a false relish
of a profounder kind.
may frequently be corrected by argument
and reflection. There are just grounds to
V>Jne sees from this passage the re
conclude that moral beauty partakes
markable difference between a thinker
much of this latter species, and demands
like Hegel, who was deeply engaged by the assistance of our intellectual faculties
great art, and Kant, who was not, and for
in order to give it a suitable influence on
whom experiencing art was of a piece the human mind.
with experiencing natural beauty, like
that of flowers or sunsets or lovely wom This kind of reasoning is, I think, illus
en. And this is finally what is missing in trated in Fry on Mantegna, or Hegel on
Moore's way of thinking about art as Raphael. And I believe it is Hegel, more
than any other thinker, who draws the
well. He thought of artistic beauty on the
model of natural beauty, as we can see distinction most sharply. He is the first
from his belief that something beautiful in particular to distinguish, perhaps too
exists much more compellingly in reality sharply, between aesthetics and the phi
than in pictures. losophy of art. Aesthetics, he observes,
David Hume takes up the relationship is "the science of sensation or feeling,"
and concerns art "when works of art are
between natural and artistic beauty al
most as an aside, in order to point out an treated with regard to the feelings they
analogy between two views of moral were supposed to produce, as, for in
truths, namely "whether they be derived stance, the feeling of pleasure, admira
from Reason or Sentiment." Sentimen tion, fear, pity, and so on." This is a great
talists claim that "To virtue it belongs to advance over Kant, who more or less
be amiable, and vice odious. " The latter confines the relevant repertoire of ef
term evokes a distant echo to disgust, a fects to pleasure and pain, making an
moral revulsion that verges on physical important exception for sublimity. Hegel
recoil. By symmetry, the former evokes a insists artistic beauty is 'higher' than the
kind of natural attraction : we are drawn beauty of nature, and he writes with a
to what we perceive as good for us in marvelous thunder that "The beauty of
others. Hume allows that there is a kind art is beauty born of the spirit and born
of beauty of which the latter may be again. " What I am eager to stress is that
true: "Some species of beauty, especially art is, for Hegel, an intellectual product,
the natural kinds, on their first appear and that its beauty too must express the
ance command our affection and appro thought the art embodies.
bation ; and where they fail of this effect, All this said, Hegel cannot have
it is impossible for any reasoning to re thought of art as other than beautiful,
dress their influence, or adapt them bet and indeed he saw this as art's limita

52 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
tion, thinking as he does of beauty in place of ashes. I intend the examples, in The abuse
terms of a sensation, or what Hume calls brief, to help remove the stigma from ?* beauty
a'sentiment.' beauty, to restore to beauty some of
Hegel writes that "the beauty of art what gave it the moral weight it had in
presents itself to sense, feeling, intuition, Edwardian aesthetics.
imagination ; it has a different sphere The first, somewhat overdetermined
than thought, and the apprehension of example comes from Proust. In a section
its activity and its products demands an called "The Intermitancies of the
organ other than scientific thinking." Heart," in the fourth volume of In Search
That is why art has come to an end, to of Lost Time, the Narrator has returned
invoke his celebrated thesis. We have to the seaside resort of Balbec. On his
risen above the sphere of sense in the first stay, he was accompanied by his be
respect that philosophy, or Wissenschajft, loved grandmother, who has since died.
is an exercise of pure understanding and The section of the book in which he de
analysis. So "the conditions of our pres scribes his grandmother's death is curi
ent time are not favorable to art." The ously clinical and detached, which is
end of art thus has nothing to do with somewhat inconsistent with what we
the decline of art but rather with the as would expect, given their earlier bond.
cent of reason. We feel we have learned something
through this about the character of Mar
A here remains the question of whether cel, who seems a much colder person
there is an important difference between than we would have believed him to be.
natural and artistic beauty, just so far as This impression proves to be false ; the
perceiving the object itself is concerned. moment he returns to his room at the
Let's allow that in the appreciation of Grand Hotel, he is overwhelmed with a
natural beauty, the object which is the sense of loss and bereavement, and de
vehicle of beauty - which has beauty scends into an acute depression as his
among it properties - is not connected grandmother's irrevocable absence
with a thought that explains its exis floods his consciousness completely.
tence, whereas with a work of art the Marcel now sits gazing at his grand
beautiful is explained by the thought mother's photograph, which tortures
that it is necessary to grasp in order to him. He realizes how self-centered he
appreciate the beauty. Is the apprecia had been when he had been the object of
tion of beauty different between the two his grandmother's totally dedicated
cases ? love - how he had failed, for example, to
I want to present a pair of examples - notice how ill she had been on that first
one of natural, one of artistic beauty - in sojourn to Balbec. This mood lasts until
which we can see Hume's way of dealing he goes for a walk one day in the direc
with the distinction at work. I have se tion of a high road, along which he and
lected the examples because they raise his grandmother used to be driven in the
some striking psychological issues that carriage of Mme. de Villeparisis. The
bear on the moral grounds evoked in road was muddy, which made him think
treating beauty as shallow and false to of his grandmother and how she used to
the reality of the world. They bear on return covered with mud when she went
what I take the prophet Isaiah to have walking whatever the weather. The sun
meant in envisioning a world in which is out, and he sees a "dazzling specta
those who suffer are given beauty in cle" - a stand of apple trees in blossom :

D dalus Fall 2002 53

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur C. The disposition of the apple trees, as far as two hands exist, to invoke one of
Danto
on J tjie could reach, were in full bloom, Moore's most famous arguments. You
beauty unbelievably luxuriant, their feet in the cannot argue anyone into accepting that
mire beneath their ball-dresses, heedless if they are uncertain of it - for what
of spoiling the most marvelous pink satin could be more certain than that? If they
that was ever seen, which glittered in the doubt that, their doubt is irremediable.
sunlight; the distant horizon of the sea This I think is Hume's point about nat
gave the trees the background of a Japan ural beauty. You can't argue anyone into
ese print ; if I raised my head to gaze at the feeling it. Natural beauty was at the core
sky through the flowers, which made its of Marcel's experience - even if there
serene blue appear almost violent, they was an aura of metaphors drawn from
seemed to draw apart to reveal the im his experience of art, which enters into
mensity of their paradise. Beneath that his descriptions.
azure a faint but cold breeze set the blush My second example is of a relatively
ing bouquets. [It was] as though it had contemporary work, Maya Lin's Viet
been an amateur of exotic art and colors nam Veterans Memorial of 1982, which I
that had artificially created this living select because it is widely regarded as
beauty. But it moved one to tears because, possessing great beauty, both by those in
to whatever lengths it went in its effects of the art world and by quite ordinary per
refined artifice, one felt that it was natural, sons for whom it has become one of the
that these apple trees were there in the most widely admired sights in Washing
heart of the country. ton, D.C.
The Memorial is simplicity itself. It
The example is overdetermined because
consists of two symmetrical triangular
only someone like Marcel would have
wings that bend away from one another
seen this glorious sight as he did. He is
at a mild angle -125 degrees - from a
like his counterpart, Swann, in seeing
shared vertical base to gently enfold
everything through the metaphors of
art. Someone who had never seen Hiro those who approach it. It is a very re
duced form of the Bernini colonnades
shige or an Ascension of the Virgin, or in
enclosing St. Peter's Square in Rome,
whose life there were no ballgowns or
buts performs a similar role. Maya Lin
pink satin, could hardly have experi
was an undergraduate at Yale when she
enced the apple trees quite as he did.
presented the idea, and was told by her
Still, it was a piece of natural beauty,
instructor that the angle between the
which might have taken the breath away
two wings "Had to mean something."
from anyone fortunate enough to have
seen it. Marcel tells us that from this The two walls are of polished black gran
ite, and inscribed with the names of ev
moment, his grief for his grandmother
ery American soldier killed in the Viet
began to diminish ; metaphorically, one nam War - about 58,000 in all - listed
might say, she had entered paradise. He
chronologically by date of death.
was given beauty for ashes. The beauty, The commission of Lin's scheme for
one might truly say, helped heal him.
the memorial almost had the quality of a
The apple trees at Balbec might be on
fairy tale : it took the twenty-one-year
anyone's short list for Moore's world of
old all of six weeks to complete the win
beauty. A world with such sights in it
would be better, Moore is confident in ning model, selected unanimously from
1,421 entries in blind review. This, after
arguing, than a world of ashes. That
would be as obvious as the fact that his Lin's peers had criticized the work as

54 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Visual poetry' - it is, after all, a kind of The abuse
nam Veterans Memorial, the thought
of beauty
book - and had expressed their uncer belongs to the work and explains the
tainty of its architectural merit. Mean beauty. In natural beauty, the beauty is
while, Lin was young, female, of Asian external to the thought; in art the beauty
descent, and had lost no loved ones in is internal to the work.
the conflict : she failed all the tacit tests
the designer of such a memorial was A he idea of internal beauty, of beauty
supposed to meet. as integral to the meaning of a work, ori
When the organizer of the competi ginally came to me in thinking of Robert
tion, Jan Scruggs, first saw the work he Motherwell's Elegy for the Spanish Repub
was profoundly disillusioned. "A big lic. People have sometimes read its black
bat. A weird-looking thing that could forms as icons for the penis and testicles
have been from Mars. Maybe a third of a bull, and, thus, the work as elegizing
grader had entered the competition. All the loss of virility. But I see them as hu
the fund's work had gone into making a man and architectural elements in a
huge bat for veterans. Maybe it symbol landscape of devastation : shawled wom
ized a boomerang," Scruggs thought. en and broken pillars, against early day
"It's weird and I wish I knew what the
light, as with the Christ figure in Piero's
hell it is." It is amazing that it was not Resurrection. Motherwell achieved a rep
voted down. Everyone wondered how resentation that transcends the history it
the general public would react, but one interprets, personal experience, and
person told Scruggs that "You would be memory, as will Lin's work in a relative
surprised how sophisticated the general ly short period of time.
public really is." That of course turned What impressed me was the way the
out to be true.
very idea of elegy is connected with the
The beauty of the work is almost in idea of beauty - that its being an elegy
stantly felt, and then perhaps best ex meant it was intended to be beautiful,
plained in terms of the emotional re and that the beauty was intended to be
sponse of visitors, many of whom come healing, the way the music at a funeral
to see the name of someone they loved is, or the flowers, or - this is not to my
and to do a rubbing of it to carry home. taste - even the beautification of the de
They see themselves reflected in the parted for the occasion of a 'viewing.' I
same wall that carries the name of the mean in any case that Motherwell's Ele
dead, as if there were a community of gies do not just happen to be beautiful.
the living and the dead, though death it Their being beautiful is part of their
self is forever. Possibly there is an analo meaning, and integral to their impact.
gy to a natural phenomenon - such as
the surface of a very still body of water IVAy heart leaps up when I behold a
in which the sky is reflected, as in Mo rainbow in the sky" - Wordsworth's
net's immense paintings of water lilies sentiment expresses a species of beauty
that make visible the way clouds and and aesthetic surprise we have all experi
flowers seem to occupy the same space. enced. But my concern in the preceding
Whatever the proper explanation of the paragraphs has been mainly to make
felt beauty of the wall, it is understood plain the relationship between beauty
with reference to the 'thought.' It is part and thought, and between the kinds of
of the meaning of the work. In Proust's thoughts that go into the experience of
orchard, the thought is his. In the Viet external as against internal beauty - how

D dalus Fall 2002 55

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Arthur C. in the first instance the thoughts are per connected and in different ways with
anto sonal and in the second objectively resi "the deepest interests of mankind and
beauty dent in the work. the most comprehensive truths of the
My concern in this essay as a whole, spirit." Because these interests are con
on the other hand, has been to show the nected with the way we are made, they
connection between beauty and art : might help us begin the detoxification of
beauty is connected with art when its beauty in contemporary art and philoso
presence is part of the meaning of the phy, always recognizing that both have
work. shown that it is not part of the definition
The Taj Mahal is beautiful, but I am of art.
not certain I want to say that about the Beauty is one mode among many
Cathedral of Cologne, or about The Last through which thoughts are presented in
Judgment of Michelangelo or the Demoi art to human sensibility - disgust, hor
selles d Avignon - and certainly not of the ror, sublimity, and sexuality are still oth
Simone Madonna, Woman with a Hat, ers. These modes explain the relevance
Raphael's Transfiguration. The cases of of art to human existence, and room for
beauty I have considered go some dis them all must be found in an adequate
tance toward supporting Hegel's view definition of art.
that art and philosophy are differently

56 D dalus Fall 2002

This content downloaded from


85.73.131.5 on Sat, 26 Dec 2020 16:54:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like