Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

)7-in

51%;

)1.‘-\

GUBA,190 E.
tn HANDBOOK
G.; LINCOLN, OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH
Y. S. Paradigmatic controversies, \

contradictions, Olesen,
and emerging
V. (1994). Feminisms and modelsDENZIN,
confluences. In: N. research.
of qualitative L.; In N. K. Denzin 8:
LINCOLN, Y. S. The Y. S. Sage Handbook
Lincoln (Eds.), Handbookof Qualitative
of qualitative Research.
research (pp. 158-174). 3 ed. Oaks, CA: Sage.
Thousand
\.
i°arl<er,2005.
Sage publications. L., Deyhle.
p.D.,193-215
Villenas, S., 8: Nebeker, K. C. (1998). Guest editor's introduction: Critical race \

theory and qualitative studies in education. Qualitative Studies in Education, 11, 5-6. \\

Shavelson, R., 8: Towne, L. (Eds). (2003). Scientific research in education. Washington, DC: National "’nL‘».
\.
Academies Press. v ~ m..m'étT'Y.’£,’i;~'=.‘?.?~’.-£‘tl*.~‘ \

1'

\
axx

vc
PARADIGMATIC
\
i-X
a\
<
1
T
CONTROVERSIES,
>

s
-T

CONTRADICTIONS, AND
i

-st.
4 EMERGING CONFLUENCES
fa‘ ?.',’a‘~"-.f~"-’“.;>%
cfi)ts-4£‘”"’
we E‘?

<.he
sea:
-é’-1:
Egon G. Guba and Yvonna S. Lincoln ‘
35??‘ .~.

~: ~ ,.

;>.., re-Y1
~
'-:.’\

n our chapter for the first edition of the oriented studies and dissertations. Third, the
Handbook ofQualitative Research, we focused number of qualitative texts, research papers, work-
on the contention among various research shops, and training materials has exploded.
paradigms for legitimacy and intellectual and par- Indeed, it would be difficult to miss the distinct
adigmatic hegemony (Guba & Lincoln, 1994). The turn of the “social sciences toward more interpre-

iii. postmodern paradigms that we discussed (post- tive, postmodern, and criticalist practices and the-
,4 o .. 903
modernist critical theory and constructivism)‘ orizing (Bloland, 1989, 1995). This nonpositivist
1/
.\.~
For 1 were in contention With the received positivist and orientation has created a context (surround) in
F. 5
postpositivist paradigms for legitimacy, and with which virtually no study can go unchallenged by
‘. .\(.<
J/.>.\i§\a one another for intellectual legitimacy. In the more proponents of contending paradigms. Further, it is
r
.\
than 10 years that have elapsed since that chapter obvious that the number of practitioners of new-
» was published, substantial changes have occurred paradigm inquiry is growing daily. There can be no
in the landscape of social scientific inquiry. question that the legitimacy of postmodern para-
o. On» the matter of legitimacy, we observe that digms is Well established and at least equal to the
: 11:3
*" 1
i as‘
readers» familiar with the literature on methods legitimacy of received and conventional paradigms
and paradigms reflect a high interest in ontologies (Denzin &'Linco1n, 1994). i ’ "
and epistemologies that differ sharply from those Onthe matter of hegemony, or supremacy,
undergirding conventional social science. Second, among postmodern paradigms, it is clear» that
even those established professionals trained in Geertz’s (1988, 1993) prophecy about the “blur-
, -/ quantitative social science (including the two of us) ring of genres” is rapidly being fulfilled. Inquiry
i-=1\§:.~ want to learn more about qualitative approaches, methodology can no longer be treated as a set
i
-
...z
.-.\
because new young professionals being mentored of universally applicable rules or abstractions.‘
in graduate schools are asking serious questions Methodology" is inevitably interwoven with and
.-\\-; '
about and looking’ for guidance in qualitatively emerges from the nature of particular disciplines
' n 191
T1
?.‘5:g4:;‘ s?<>.>?-zrfl

192 E1 HANDBOOK OP QUALITATIVE RESEARCI-i—CHAPTER 8 $12

(such as sociology and psychology) and particular examination of these two tabies will reacquaint =3
perspectives (such as Marxism, feminist theory, the reader with our original Handbook treatment; fc
--1
.1-
,1
M
and queer theory). So, for instance, we can read more detailed information is, of course, available
§~>\ €S
feminist critical theorists such as Olesen (2000) in our original chapter.
or queer theorists such as Gamson (2000), or Since publication of that chapter, at least one
we can follow arguments about teachers as set of authors, Iohn Heron and Peter Reason, have tit? .._=
researchers (Kincheioe, 1991) while we under- nal
elaborated on our tables to include the participa- ‘-=t‘IE . -- .

stand the secondary text to be teacher empower- tory/cooperative paradigm (Heron, 1996; Heron 8: -v-<
eneut
?:
3;
ment and democratization of schooling practices. Reason, 1997, pp. 289-290). Thus, in addition to ~.
~
S 'Cosnmstructv Relandspec
visma—ltocal constructedandreal
co-construicted ubjaonseacctt iv findicrenatgsed
/Trsst Hercaldimalectical
Indeed, the various paradigms are beginning to the paradigms of positivism, postpositivism, t
“interbreed” such that two theorists previously critical theory, and constructivism, we add the 3?-
\
thought to be in irreconcilable conflict may now participatory paradigm in the present chapter c
appear, under a different theoretical rubric, to be ral‘, alues
(this is an excellent example, we might add, of R
x
informing one another’s arguments. A personal the hermeneutic elaboration so embedded in our
example is our own work, which has been heavily own view, constructivism). : $5‘ IT
influenced by action research practitioners and Our aim here is to extend the analysis further :1»-3

postmodern critical theorists. Consequently, to by building on Heron and Reasons additions and mviualreality valubjeucte-ivist; gs
argue that it is paradigms that are in contention by rearranging the issues to reflect current ."J§_-1
1'??? alectcal
is probably less useful than to probe where and thought. The issues we have chosen include our
how paradigms exhibit confluence and where and original formulations and the additions, revi- . 'cetal.
alTheory
In!
how they exhibit differences, controversies, and sions, and amplifications made by Heron and .. W'- genderv
onornic,ethnic,and
Crt Hisrealto-ricalis by
soci itical,cuittiuovercmrysetal ized Transactional/s find“medinated
shapedal,pol"39. Dialogic/di
contradictions. Reason (1997), and we have also chosen what we
believe to be the issues most important today. We -“=1 cal
»-1
.1..-
should note that important means several things
as
E Mrnox Issues Conrnonrnvo to us. An important topic may be one that is
9% ult es
ALL PARADIGMS widely debated (or even hotly contested)—valid-
ity is one such issue. An important issue may be tug
In our chapter in the first edition of this one that bespeaks a new awareness (an issue such hr tamettivheods
Handbook, we presented two tables that summa- as recognition of the role of values).An important gp‘~ I,
-1
.-

rized our positions, first, on the axiomatic nature issue may be one that illustrates the influence of '1/ism
.- _ -aw:
of paradigms (the paradigms we considered at one paradigm on another (such as the influence .1. ==-at-,.
'5‘;-1 4"$31 ~A
that time were positivism, postpositivism, critical of feminist, action research, critical theory, and ' Y: i
Posttzpos but
Crreal
rietailcsmal—“rietal”y imperand
onlyfectly probabil sfcal yap rehendible alcrist/obfijeectidvst; finditraditon/cogsm unity; trueprobably Modiexpfieredimentalifpvecr
duModit lmaniism;pulitaictfaallpotsonof
mificathesmay
inclqual
ude
~ _ 1/-.

theory, and constructivism; Guba Br Lincoln, participatory models on researcherconceptions J


. . . stv
1::,~=ss"
1994, p. I09, Table 6.1); and second, on the issues of action .-within and with the community in :‘;:l'?i£"
4 \".1iI~f‘<Y
'

we believed were most fundamental to differenti- which research is carried out). Or issues may be
,:
ating the four paradigms (p. 112, Table 6.2). These important -because new or extended theoretical _t
!:.t\V. . rification hiefly
findi
ist;ngs
tables are reproduced here as a way of remind- and/or field-oriented _t_reatme11ts_ for them are
ing our readers of our previous statements. The newly available—-voice and reflexivity are two tap rehendihle
axioms defined the ontological, epistemological, such issues.
'vism ybu
and methodological bases for both established Table 8.3 reprises the original Table 6.1 but . ,1 -—| ru
and emergent paradigms; fl1ese are shown here adds the axioms of the participatory paradigm Pos
I Nairealisvme—“real” rea1t Duval'st/object tru Experimental! vemanipulative;hypcof
otheses metquanthodsitatve
,_ l
in Table 8.1. The issues most often in contention proposed by Heron and Reason (1997). Table 8.4 AlI(MBasi
nteof
rquitnapthivyescricyParBels) ieafdisgms
that we examined were inquiry aim, nature of deals with seven issues and represents an update .
knowledge, the way knowledge is accumulated, of selected issues first presented in the old Table
goodness (rigor and validity) or quality criteria, 6.2. “Voice” in the 1994 version of Table 6.2
values, ethics, voice, training, accommodation, has been renamed “inquirer posturef’ and we em
8.1.able It Ontology Epistemology Methodology
and hegemony; these are shown in Table 8.2. An have inserted a redefined “voice” in the current T

(text continues, p. 197) E 193


‘ A_’uH
3:5
_§a$Uqofi%E%w
H_ _ :mqOU2 Hamfig
WEUEUE
_bsmU__5€EN Qoiggmngfia
wgwb
vsEa
858HEM _mufi:QMc
OfiA_ o$m@mUaHm@ U6
U5
kaaa
EETE
wE§__§m_ OflHEbmQOUm_ H Egg
HE
agemU555“Q62?
Eamnoafiga
mmofi apcggga
UQwduoamuwg gm
iv
PU$éggfi
>égéwfivEoggggg
fiN225&5
E_Gw:_U ®_‘Egg
E_w%E£ 5ggusgwEgoEggsfig“Saws wE
%§E_m
%gw§_
U>:U EO|U>mSUBDm3U
§_8__UHQEUOU 58"“
®>:eOn_ ®:OU Hmaflgga
EH2”
_g_v6UE_\HeUED_=Ou_ Us
figgj_§§_fi@fi Ea_mgOEm&Egan
o_amw_E55_EHMES
mméué
U>€E§|_§V:_UE MO
%W2OEE&% Mo
anm_fl7H_€gH_
UU__H2_$&$mggugE_~
W QEMGHOEWDH fig
B
g_H_E
wcgmam
ggqwsa
mumfizfiumqcmao
‘_Om3§§m
_v§O_§w_ w5w_5U
EM_
B22UUEHO'%gm q\€_ g_a_H_
tGm JggggaW
Eméwghg mm§U§E%_5 gE:bmgUE Gog bgsfi fi§gH_
QOWUNbx
Emfi
fig
Ecgoéa
wgfifiawm
_mEm§_§M
w§’é_mgUU§gomficWufiamfifla §_§_:§E=8 _§U_‘ _mgoUéU \_NGo€§_£_ _ _ §E25E$m
Iewggé €>Em__E_ a
Msiuo%fi_Eg%me%%>u_
ozfi EOE
Egg
HE
u%q§%>2
>qW_ ‘_ €HW 2n£5
_ 25mPEm__OE&
_ $E CUS UBNQSIOU _8E2£v
E8
E2 wgzgu mwawqm
Eimo
wEgg
gm_fiaU%3m_Bfi Umfiaw
_“_WU=2
>HM_UmDE'=HoU_MHmEH @H_H_s
_wE§w_ 2w“ENcGOQWEOg_E8UHGMEU ?3_ QSfiwafi
EmgM_§Uga Hm”E\WN_5Hu:_H m fig__§E§_a®E,HQ>_5hHEm_
u>u_NaHoM_L_ NUgMua fig
H&>fi__Um
DHNUOBVN
~UU_:
Q“
Nu
bgfi_:_u E
bfiagm
H>
dc bafi\_U_N_~aE€£m§_ _Sg€_
~8_NH_:
HmSg__:E&943 lafig
mfiéafia
lg?E585 gfiofiwfigwofic
geméEgg“ AE5 25208 gm
gg“Egg€_:_ E____%_&
U £53 HOSE’32%
©SE_Sg_U
5%
wmaqé
GEE
b:$__ %=gUNwE£_
2::
“gum W__
_VH0
%wkaaéfluw
gig:H_o_EU%
_%U:&
_m_§U3wU_HB5£n_U_v
$>%Ei
gfiwfiwsv
3:85yfisgpa
§__v
%@E>
EEWEQOZ
E:
8mm_fi
8§_§§_&\EUmfi80$ 283
E_;2
wM8%@_“
_ :UOE_533
D§Mo
_=|H_O€HU<_ Hgggggs
mo
RegsEmHFHBE
$"%_EA£_U_oHwgE_r _
g
_mUEEOEan
mgfi
wflwuasHO
mu HOQEU
*0
EU5hfiésaoa
Egg__m__§_e
QOfl$U=L_ _m _I“|eE2fima_H§ %_M€\£€Uégbfiag
M__SE__U
_k€__§
EQZ
N3kwsgqo M_§§_Bgoa
_H_H_E_w _8QHvmUm%_N%_jn%€m__ na_E_NE
_VY _€§“uG3g_m£bV§H_O2V _%> _
_®aUm73_wE£U‘_U=qm_a%E
__E_w_
as
mggfigfigv
_NUE_ U_§ME_ Um_H_ H m USE35&5_Hvé
wygu>E§_tUg%m%uo£E§Qz%A&gE(%_®§:w$aW _DE oATU_ H5S:Umb_ 8E_6 U8
Mo
§§%g
gfiugfi
MEWSHMEé SE
E8
€é_§Hg$6
__?_®H:
:5
HE
~E_$__ (A_gfifingoa
_%E_U_e 7_€E_ v“NOMfiE_m>_mEggnéfl_U&_fi §_gH2qE&u Dkfi€fl2g%fim$am$g£Ofio7&gFa_
28
H8w'35::
ugQE|M§___m_SV“mU _5m
EUSUQHQ_§8_Um
0_%_H_
5wggmaEmfié
mgfi_N_wI ®fig
§_gag
umEETEgflggg
mbgfim
DUfi‘€m%m__m_w
§mm_n_ vU_£_wE_~%7 wfi_ oVfiflwa
%Oިag%u_ۤU
( __W32Ho
i
EHM_H§\_ ‘E_ _a&$_£WH_ Uq
HE30“
HMHvH
E__UHHMv_wEQ_°mEum_~_vmUugfl
figgfiu
h§_g%MV|EgEm
EN
_g__§
ggmémHgomg axm
UE DWGUE_OU
fig:
fig
flag
5
Gama“
d3“
5
__E___8WE
wumbi
pam m6
mesaQ>E_ w§_%
H_O%_gE 8U<
gggafiug bag
NCBCU
EHbmgvs mBmggow
UmUUT$O:M
BENZ Uw_§>6§
MO @552!
Ngéumum
gag Sim 88>
Eyg
1;

Guba 8t L incoln: (lionuoversies, Contradictions, Confluences in 197

Table 8.5. ln all cases except “inquirer posture,” the absolutist (Bradley 8< Schaefer, 1998); rather, they
entries for the participatory paradigm are those are derived from community consensus regarding
proposed by Heron and Reason; in the one case what is “real,” what is useful, and what has mean-
not covered by them, we have added a notation ing (especially meaning for action and further
r/r that we believe captures their intention. steps). We believe that a goodly portion of social
H
We make no attempt here to reprise the mater- phenomena consists of the ineaning-inaking
Ifi
cilitatoesearcher :._ . -“., _-,. _.,-._ .,_ a
awe-r-97:$a’>‘~rs.P}h,?-‘:§.1_br):v¢'s<|Q-»4,Z2Li'/>._=»
ial well discussed in our earlier Handbook chapter. activities of groups and individuals around those
ECC6 ineactngagievment phenomena. The meaning-making activities
Instead, we focus solely on the issues in Table 8.5:
an
forandot
ms herpresentational axiology; accommodation and commensurability; themselves are of central interest to social con-
CQSS demcocmraptiectence, H
facisss;
letaartocrh] errequires action; control; foundations of truth and knowl- structionists/constructivists, simply because it is
Ofl
edge; validity; and voice, reflexivity, and postmod- the meaning—n'1al<il1g/sense-making/attributional
mm§;fi§
ern textual representation. We believe these seven activities that shape action (or inaction). The
Participatory‘ Exof
tprepnisdatectmdoiclogaly:primacy iIn
in
neof
quicmobmuedrnieyt ds ti
pr
communitesof Coofex
ngruence knowi
lpeerpradspierontapioctnaslg;,itpcorenalsael,natatndional fhum
lourserishivinceof
g y in
Prthawarvoiirmoarughceemani fseslf-treflectiveactilituomohnarmin;eory,
vneratmsaeecondar
tinvtg,e, danceysong,
voices inCthe
oirtareeisaetrechdiers ntobyfa
inpro
quiry letharnand proce emotional personalityandskil s
rough the 9'“)
issues to be the most important at this time. meaning-making activities themselves can be
Ii
is While we believe these issues to be the most changed when they are found to be incomplete,
contentious, we also believe they create the intel- faulty (e.g., discriminatory, oppressive, or non-
lectual, theoretical, and practical space for dia- liberatory), or malformed (created from data that
logue, consensus, and confluence to occur. There can be shown to be false).
in
the
ttot
toworl
aacthectiorndansform emmwé is great potential for interweaving of viewpoints, We have tried, however, to incorporate per-
tiltt
re-vel-proacteoisward spectives from other major nonpositivist para-
for the incorporation of multiple perspectives,
and for borrowing, or bricolage, where borrowing digms. This is not a complete summation; space
‘*3
constructions;vicarious Intrinsic hiandq
story; uanti ative; ._.l,2 constraints prevent that. What we hope to do in
Constructivsm Indandc ectcrrievceonistirnuctg;alionssoubjmknowleetimctcoaleivsietydgee;scingaroundcoinMorsfeonand
ividual olliving
knowi tworthines inclautuhdientngicityforcatalyst
sursmede sophisticated YE experience Trusand “Paspariontaicteipant”faacofmu
isl tator ltivoreicoenstruction seems useful, richness enhancing, or theoretically
heuristic. For instance, even though we are our- this chapter is to acquaint readers with the larger
selves social constructivists/constructionists, our currents, arguments, dialogues, and provocative
F§ call to action embedded in the authenticity crite- writings and theorizing, the better to see perhaps
3S
ria we elaborated in Fourth Generation Evaluation what we ourselves do not even yet see: where and
.3
(Guba 8: Lincoln, 1989) reflects strongly the bent when confluence is possible, where constructive
si g
=$ rapprochement might be negotiated, where voices
to action embodied in critical theorists"perspec-
CriticalTheories hiStsrtuocritcuar l ] insights Hisretovirsicoalnism; by
generalization similarity eroasinceon andmisap reacthensioniso; nstimulus Include —f0rmative
Hisituoartiecalnes ; ignorof Itilt
nct—rimorn al torewarvelatidon “Transformative intel ectual and
advocate activist Resqualocializaitoan;tivelibeand
valratiounesofaltruism,empowerment tives. And although Heron and Reason have elab- are beginning to achieve some harmony
‘valand
ues
orated a model they call the cooperative paradigm,
"--,>;
.575;
careful reading of their proposal reveals a form
S
an
iw
of inquiry that is post—p0stpositive, postmodern, E AXIOLOGY
is
and r
E and criticalist in orientation. As a result, the
all - in
reader familiar with several theoretical and para- Earlier, we placed values on the table as an “issue”
digmatic strands of research will find that echoes on which positivists or phenomenologists might
‘l
Pastposifivism Nonfalsified hythat
pareotheses lfacts
aor
prwsobable cl Techniquantcalita; tive taandqu
tive thseorubstaientsive (I9except
for“
on97),eth'cs” . §.‘_,
of many streams of thought come together in the have a “posture” (Guba 8: Lincoln, 1989, 1994;
Eu
extended table. What this means is that the cate- Lincoln 8: Guba, 1985). Fortunately, we reserved,
gories, as Laurel Richardson (personal communi- for ourselves the right to either get smarter or just
ity
€ cation, September 12, 1998) has pointed out, “are change our minds. We did both. Now, we suspect
ed (although Table 8.5 does not yet reflect it) that
sic fluid, indeed what should be a category keeps
altering, enlarging.” She notes that “even as [we] “axiology” should be grouped with “basic beliefs .”
Posil vism hypotVerihesesfied establish lfaoraswscts blAto
coaddi efinecedge”raliza;tionlinckages
recks”tion—“builndinggknowl“edigof and
ause-ef ect “ribCeonof
cvhemgntaiorkornsal intandext
ernal ernandobj
alvaliditye,rctelivability, Excluenide —influeenced decept
Exttowarr—tiiniodn lt “iDnsfiof
onstecrmiestnteredist”adecsmaker
ision s,polagent
change
icymaker
ss chnical U3qntitatisvue;bstantiv theories
Teand write, the boundaries between the paradigms are In Naturalistic Inquiry (Lincoln 8t Guba, 1985),we
SelIPosis uon
radiese—tctiUopensdgadtmed
Pa shifting.” This is the paradigmatic equivalent of covered some of the ways in which values feed
ll.‘
l the Geertzian “blurring of genres” to which we into the inquiry process: choice of -the problem,
=5 referred earlier. choice of paradigm to guide the problem, choice
Our own position is that of the constructionist of theoretical framework, choice of major data-
Issue Natof
ure knowledge Knowledge ac umulation Goorodnes qualitycriteria Values Ethics Inpostquiruere Training camp, loosely defined. We do not believe that gathering and data-analytic methods, choice of
Tabl
8.4.e based
Herin
Reas
Entr
tand
oncoles
a.his
ounmnare
context, treatment of values already resident
criteria for judging either “reality” or validity are
I96 m
‘ivI_
u_ HUh_mW,Q;
“?\Mk/V2
P_NH_wm\_w\I‘2_m
WUhv“ "%@HA_\umN_W/VI\_“\U‘;_m__$“u\W_MwDH_m‘\_IH\tvhV
HEgg
bGgfi“figsfigs?
aaqvfitma ggséw
Ufi3:8mawzoaEEHU
bgfimg
ED fig
E>EwEa
($mso_5\_§£_ g (
fig
Ea
Hgéma
JU2:m“wasp
>E£_mE:_N0~m_U:“5E6wC_aoUE_EOwUgU
gang nficfi_ka_EOEmofig
iQUEUEQ
céfisesbmfi2
oEg_fl~
2
fimggi
32
migoi Us
ޣ
EH5“
%_2__§
%B
R523_W
gs
£E;_Qa:NUE_mA%C'$NEOEmfiQoEM9_UE5UEN
_GNEW U %o
HE
EE
>Ugags
EMEME
fig
€:E_é
U5
_W3§_§_§
mug“:
EOQEEHQ
§_oHo_gg
?
“Em
bEqhbQ§%%§%
mukmw uiqxkumtwcumtui
ES
rfig
£0“:
EE5
2
5
flgwqgg
ENE6Q_$_§fl_
\ageN
dzflgg
mm
Ha mE§_%£_ B_w&&UE&_w Egg
Qfifiag
EH
EHH83
558
5%Ne&db
MfifigmQ%mé
Mvwag “_E
M5§_§
E05;BBQEGE
afig;
noEEG
5&0raga
\NEH
§_gfiUUmmU
_§E
M
MSEHOQ
figfigEHEWBEB
GBE
_OUME1gag
ow®
waggm UENEUE_W_ :UE_Nm RwfiwméB
m8\FEmagnum=
W
afigs:Jaé_amg|UE~EQEO_a _ouNEm_ m_ Hn_UH_ _ WENU_H
fi2
KEMUMEEE
g:é_£€:_§
Uggw
mégwE8
2
5053
muawgwG%>
_8__EwE
A__§Ufigang
$2“
gm83
g€< H“
mwi_Egg
jgaQg%o_uafiQgfl:Oeo%gm§z_
E\_§D§E=&h:_°U§_§~W
1&3
_gag:
4“"flma_fixH{\\dflM“h"HU_‘~H“_Iu%‘q_1“Y\‘ 34"EWqJ'\wH_"I.d‘1\A:"qHJ“UMIma‘HAJnU“I"_Hq “_
_gmg2M_Um§>_%@M_ HHW
SEB
Hfifigugofim
EV
bfiflgfig
Nndww“Egg EHUEU _|§6M_EaHgofig qgggaENqéfiaafimg
Lsmgfiaugs 3
fiflgmfim Q5"gag
_=_’8w_:U *0
_g%>
Eogfisamw
3
g_§Mm
EODE mH_2_&:_o>A3Asgwd
dfiagé#833; 3__aUE&
U_gamghg
=_ a_E%
g_g§
mEO%g6EV MAESEICB“EEO
E §fl8|€Haga_oU
£13 “QUHMEgs
@UfiE_mUUMO> $sfigga
Us>%E&§:&
mUU_O>GQUEQQ
2§&U£&
352
_v&2_fig_§&§E_w EH8_w_E u_UH_ fiwGgcsees
oU8_E_8$_H _bqH§_w_E_6H%_gU_:
“E38€_N_H_“fi_§H EmUs Ema>5:mwagmfi flu
~3__w_:
Eboat__U
wM_§wg__ 25::av
$E%B__/_V
_qo€EH£wgE Mug
EEWU
PEG m_gwEStBmb=
Swfiufig5&0
E08mgssfi; Egg
8&5“
_‘%Q8
ow
U
$
E
5__€Si_ _5_U3§_§
:MQ_EEH@_M E8
€>€%_O
BEH5
\E_u=§
N2%__2$
E2
§__§8n§fi_
HDOQN
mfl;gt
8?POGM §§_g§__§ Y§>§Eo
fimfl'gm:
1wG_EE
5§mm> ‘ figg
__“E32”: ouflgmw uhmu\kEm
Egg
EqmbEfi£_fi_o 1UmfiE3058
Uumgamhzfiemg
HO
EH
§mE2
2:mQQ%B @932}
egsngga __\Ea
G3
$:_80>g_v
>fi_UU?____m_Ho
_m_:_&§Efi_H£U_agghfiflmmgowB
W0
Ma
86> §~__%%__
8 5%?“_w
5:
mo
_MGgggm
gggagou
_§%mg
éEEM_§_B\__u:_|§a'g€£ ?_fiOdGfiOuUHfi©_5fl_ O5"m_ KEmM_§ _a _Gw§°V%§
_‘Y
EBA;
wuwfié
_$H_U_H“
_ g2
fig
Mo
M6
Maui
magma“ §E_mw_’S€ag©E O4U
N M_E_w_5w_ sE OU E>Ewa:d_s’_H_
U GOMWHfi_uOE OU < _ Egg gmg
_%:>_mu$__t__
_
”ggfiqqégh
8
figmgogmumUs
wggwgg 2 3 3 8 £220_
_ _ m_UoE:&
figfigUWEEOE wgcgm mgéoowv
“ENE_m_w QOMOE EH88
__
Gk
E8 HatWs“
“=3 “E3
Q5
_
__
1 98 E E 1 99
'~r— <1

200 in HANDBOOK OP QUALITATIVE RESEARCHACHAPTER 8 Guba Sr Lincoln: Controversies, Contradictions, Confluences in 201

within the context, and choice of format(s) for each other in ways that make the simultaneous come more easily to the human-as-instrument. The action, from the overturning of specific unjust
presenting findings. We believed those were practice of both possible. We have argued that reader should particularly note the absence of an practices to radical transformation of entire
antiquantitative stance, precisely because the natu- societies. The call for action-—whether in terms of
strong enough reasons to argue for the inclusion at the paradigmatic, or philosophical, level, com-
ralistic and conventional paradigms are so often- internal transformation, such as ridding oneself
of values as a major point of departure between mensurability between positivist and postposi-
mistakenly—equated with the qualitative and of false consciousness, or of external social trans-
positivist, conventional modes of inquiry and tivist worldviews is not possible, but that within i I
quantitative paradigms, respectively. Indeed, there formationa-differentiates between positivist
interpretive forms of inquiry. each paradigm, mixed methodologies (strategies)
are many opportunitiesfor the naturalistic investiga-
A second “reading” of the burgeoning literature may make perfectly good sense (Guba 8: Lincoln, and postmodern criticalist theorists (including
tor to utilize quantitative a'ata—probably more than
and subsequent rethinking of our own rationale 1981,1982, 1989, 1994; Lincoin 8: Guba, 1985). So, feminist and queer theorists). The sharpest shift,
ti are appreciated. (pp. 198-199; emphasis added)
have led us to conclude that the issue is much for instance, in Eflective Evaluation we argued: however, has been in the constructivist and par-
larger than we first conceived. If we had it to do all Having demonstrated that we were not then ticipatory phenomenological models, where a
over again, we would make values or, more cor- The guiding inquiry paradigm most appropriate (and are not now) talking about an antiquantita— step beyond interpretation and Verstehen, or
rectly, axiology (the branch of philosophy dealing to responsive evaluation is . . . the naturalistic, phe-
tive posture or the exclusivity of methods, but understanding, toward social action is probably
with ethics, aesthetics, and religion) a part of the nomenological, or ethnographic paradigm. It will be
rather about the philosophies of which paradigms one of the most conceptually interesting of the
seen that qualitative techniques are typically most shifts (Lincoln, 1997, 1998a, 1998b). For some
basic foundational philosophical dimensions of are constructed, we can ask the question again
appropriate to support this approach. There are theorists, the shift toward action came in
paradigm proposal. Doing so would, in our opin- regarding commensurability: Are paradigms com-
times, however, when the issues and concerns voiced response to widespread nonutilization of evalua-
ion, begin to help us see the embeddedness of by audiences require information that is best gener- mensurable? Is it possible to blend elements of one
ethics within,'not external to, paradigms (see, for tion findings and the desire to create forms of
ated by more conventional methods, especially quan- is paradigm into another, so that one is engaging in
instance, Christians, 2000) and would contribute to
11?-'
1,»
research that represents the best of both world- evaluation that wouid attract champions who
titative methods. . . . In such cases, the responsive 4?‘
ts:
the consideration of and dialogue about the role of conventional evaluator will not shrink from the
It
views? The answer, from our perspective, has to be might follow through on recommendations with
spirituality in human inquiry. Arguably, axiology appropriate application. (Guba 8: Lincoln, I981, p. 36) \. a cautious yes. This is especially so if the models meaningful action plans (Guba 8: Lincoln, 1981,
- - .,\.
wti.
has been “defined out of” scientific inquiry for no
.,,,
=<-~‘
1
gag (paradigms) share axiomatic elements that are 1989). For others, embracing action came as both
larger a reason than that it also concerns “religion.” As we tried to make clear, the “argument” aris- :li%.
similar, or that resonate strongly between them. a political and an ethical commitment (see, for
.-: i--
But defining “religion” broadly to encompass spiri- ing in the social sciences was not about method, So, for instance, positivism and postpositivism instance, Carr 8: Kemmis, 1986; Christians, 2000;
tuality would move constructivists closer to partic- although many critics of the new naturalistic, E
are clearly commensurable. In the same vein, ele- Greenwood 8: Levin, 2000; Schratz 8< Walker,
ipative inquirers and would move critical theorists ethnographic, phenomenological, and/or case 1995; Tierney, 2000).
ments of interpretivist/postmodern critical theory,
closer to both (owing to their concern with libera- study approaches assumed itwas? As late as 1998, .-, constructivist and participative inquiry, fit com- Whateverf the source of the problem to which
tion from oppression and freeing of the human Weiss could be found to claim that “some evalua- fortably together. Commensurability is an issue inquirers were responding, the shift toward
spirit, both profoundly spiritual concerns). The tion theorists, notably Guba and Lincoln (1989), only when researchers want to “pick and choose” connecting research, policy analysis, evaluation,
expansion of basic issues to include axiology, then, hold that it is impossible to combine qualitative among the axioms of positivist and interpretivist and/or social deconstruction (e.g., deconstruction
is one way of achieving greater confluence among and quantitative approaches responsibly within an models‘, because the axioms are contradictory and of the patriarchal forms of oppression in social
the various interpretivist inquiry models. This is evaluation” (p. 268), even though we stated early mutually exclusive. V structures, which is the project informing much
the place, for example, where Peter Reason’s pro- on in Fourth Generation Evaluation (1989) that feminist theorizing, or deconstruction of the
found concerns with “sacred science” and human 53;.»
homophobia embedded in public policies) with
functioning find legitimacy; it is a place where those claims, concerns, and issues that have not '1 :.‘>§._
E THE CALL TO ACTION action has come to characterize much new-para
Laurel Richardson’s “sacred spaces” become been resolved become the advance organizers for digm inquiry work, both at the theoretical and at
authoritative sites for human inquiry; it is a information collection by the evaluator. . . . The One of the clearest ways in which the paradig- the practice and praxis-oriented levels. Actionhas
information may be quantitative or qualitative. matic controversies can be demonstrated is to become ‘a major controversy that limns the ongo-
place-—-or the place—where the spiritual meets
Responsiveevaluation does not rule out quantita~ compare the positivist and postpositivist adher- ing debates among practitioners of the various
social inquiry, as Reason (1993), and later Lincoln
tive modes, as is mistakenly believed by many, but paradigms. The mandate for social action, espe-
and Dentin (1994), proposed some years earlier. ents, who view action as a form of contamination
deals with whatever information is responsive to cially action designed and created by and for
of research results and processes, and the inter-
the unresolved claim, concern, or issue. (p. 43)
_ pretivists, who see action on research results as a research participants with the aid and coop~
Ifl ACCOMMODATION AND meaningful and important outcome of inquiry eration of-researchers, can be most sharply
We had also strongly asserted earlier, in Natur-
COMMENSURABILITY processes. Positivist adherents believe action to delineated between positivist/postpositivist and
alistic Inquiry (1985), that
be either a form of advocacy or a form of subjec- new-paradigm inquirers. Many positivist and
Positivists and postpositivists alike still occasion- qualitative methods are stressed within the tivity, either or both of which undermine the aim postpositivist inquirers still consider “action”
ally argue that paradigms are, in some ways, naturalistic paradigm not because the paradigm is \ of objectivity. Critical theorists, on the other hand, the domain-of communities other than resear-
commensurable; that is, they can be retrofitted to antiquautitative but because qualitative methods
-4».
have always advocated varying degrees of social chers and research participants: those of policy

its I
its
‘ii. 55
NE: ta :5:
~ ———— 7- - _

202 Ill HANDBOOK OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH-CHAPTER 3 Guba 8: Lincoln: Controversies, Contradictions, Confluences E 203

personnel, legislators, and civic and political context members to be the aim of inquiry within a scientific method, conventional, positivist) research- for testing them as truthful (although we may
officials. Hard-line foundationalists presume that community. For none of these paradigmatic adher- ers, most assuredly there is a “real” reality “out have great difficulty in determining what those
the taint of action will interfere with, or even ents is control an issue of advocacy, a somewhat 1
l
t there,” apart from the flawed human apprehen- criteria are); nonfoundationalists tend to argue
negate, the objectivity that is a (presumed) char- deceptive term usually used as a code within a sion of it. Further, that reality can be approached that there are no such ultimate criteria, only those
acteristic of rigorous scientific method inquiry. larger metanarrative to attack an inquiry’s rigor, (approximated) only through the utilization of that we can agree upon at a certain time and
objectivity, or fairness. Rather, for new-paradigm methods that prevent human contamination of its under certain conditions. lioundational criteria
researchers control is a means of fostering emanci- apprehension or comprehension. For foundation- are discovered; nonfoundational criteria are
E Conrnot pation, democracy, and community empower- alists in the empiricist tradition, the foundations negotiated. It is the case, however, that most real-
ment, and of redressing power imbalances such of scientific truth and knowledge about reality ists are also foundationalists, and many nonfoun-
Another controversy that has tended to become that those who were previously marginalized now 3 reside in rigorous application of testing phenom- dationalists or antifoundationalists are relativists.
problematic centers on control of the study: Who achieve voice (Mertens, 1998) or “human flourish- ena against a template as much devoid of human An ontological formulation that connects
initiates? Who determines salient questions? Who ing” (Heron 8: Reason, 1997). Control as a con- bias, misperception, and other “idols” (Francis realism and foundationalism within the same
determines what constitutes findings? Who deter- troversy is an excellent place to observe the Bacon, cited in Polkinghorne, 1989) as instru- “collapse” of categories that characterizes the
mines how data will be collected? Who determines phenomenon that we have always termed “Catholic mentally possible.As Polkinghorne (1989) makes ontological-epistemological collapse is one that
in what forms the findings will be made public, if questions directed to a Methodist audience.” We clear: exhibits good fit with the other assumptions of
at all? Who determines What representations will use this description—given to us by a workshop jl constructivism. That state of affairs suits new-
be made of participants in the research? Let us be participant in the early 1980s--to refer to the The idea that the objective realm ‘is independent of paradigm inquirers well. Critical theorists,
ri
very clear: The issue of control is deeply embedded ongoing problem of illegitimate questions: ques- the knower’s subjective experiences of it can be constructivists, and participatory/cooperative
ll
in the questions of voice, reflexivity, and issues of tions that have no meaning because the frames of found in Descartes’s dual substance theory, with its inquirers take their primary field of interest to be
t
postmodern textual representation, which we shall reference are those for which they were never i <i. distinction between the objective and subjective precisely that subjective and intersubjective social
intended. (We could as well call these “Hindu ques- realms. . . . In the splitting of reality into subject
take up later, but onlyfor new-paradigm inquirers. knowledge and the active construction and cocre-
’ and object realms, what can be known “objectively”
For more conventional inquirers, the issue of con- tions to a Muslimf’ to give another sense of how iii-=1-ts ation of such knowledge by human agents that is
is only the objective realm. True knowledge is lim-
trol is effectively walled off from voice, reflexivity, paradigms, or overarching philosophies-or produced by human consciousness. Further, new-
itedto the objects and the relationships between
and issues of textual representation, because each theologies—are incommensurable, and how ques- them that exist in the realm of time and space. paradigm inquirers take to the social knowledge
of those issues in some way threatens claims to tions in one framework make little, if any, sense in Human consciousness, which is subjective, is not field with zest, informed by a variety of social,
rigor (particularly objectivity and validity). For another.) Paradigmatic formulations interact such a
accessible to science, and thus not truly knowable. intellectual, and theoretical explorations. These
new-paradigm inquirers who have seen the preem- that control becomes inextricably intertwined with .
(p. 23) theoretical excursions include Saussurian linguis-
<15: .=<~:-
inent paradigm issues of ontology and epistemol- mandates for objectivity. Objectivity derives from l%€!J-=.. it-..
_ ,5“ '-<‘»I .
tic theory, which views all relationships between
ogy effectively folded into one another, and who the Enlightenment prescription for knowledge of -= Now, templates of truth and knowledge can be words and what those words signify as the func-
have watched as methodology and axiology logi- the physical world, which is postulated to be sepa-
;.=
defined in a variety of ways—as the end product tion of an internal relationship within some lin-
cally folded into one another (Lincoln, 1995, 1997), rate and distinct from those who would know of rational processes, as the result of experiential guistic system; literary theorfs deconstructive
control of an inquiry seems far less problematic, (Polkinghorne, 1989). But if knowledge of the sensing, as the result of empirical observation, contributions, which seek to disconnect texts from
except insofar as inquirers seek to obtain partici- social (as opposed to the physical) world resides in 2 and others. In all cases, however, the referent is the any essentialist or transcendental meaning and
pants’ genuine participation (see, for instance, meaning-making mechanisms of the social, men- 111 . .5.
1».-4",.
physical or empirical world: rational engagement resituate them within both author and reader his-
Guba 8: Lincoln, 1981, on contracting and attempts tal, and linguistic worlds that individuals inhabit, with it, experience of it, empirical observation of torical and social contexts (Hutcheon, 1989;
to get some stakeholding groups to do more than then knowledgecannot be separate from the 11’1
it. Realists, who work on the assumption that Leitch, 1996); feminist (Addelson, 1993; Alpern,
stand by while an evaluation is in progress). knowenbutrather is rooted in his or her mental or there is a “real” world “out theref’ may in individ- Antler, Perry, 8: Scobie, 1992; Babbitt, 1993;
Griticaltheorists, especially those who work in linguistic designations ofthat world (Polkinghorne, ual cases also be foundationalists, taking the view Harding, 1993), race and ethnic (Kondo, 1990,
community organizing programs, are painfully 1989; Salner, 1989). -- - . that all of these ways of defining are rooted in 1997; Trinh, 1991), and queer theorizing (Gamson,
aware of the necessity for members of the commu- 1 phenomena existing outside the human mind. 2000), which seeks to uncover and explore varieties
1
nity, or research participants, to take control of 1. Although we can think about them, experience of oppression and historical colonizing between
their futures. Constructivists desire participants to E Fouuoxrrous or Tuurn AND them, or observe them, they are nevertheless dominant and subaltern genders, identities, races,
take an increasingly active role in nominating Kuowuaoos IN PARADIGMS transcendent, referred to but beyond direct appre- and social worlds; the postmodern historical
1
questions of interest for anyrinquiry and in design- $13..
q.
hension. Realism is an ontological question, moment (Michael, 1996), which problematizes
ing outlets for findings to be shared more widely Whether or not the world has a “real” existence whereas foundationalism is a criterial question. truth as partial, identity as fluid, language as an
within and outside the community. Participatory outside of human experience of that world is an Some foundationalists argue that real phenomena unclear referent system, and method and criteria
inquirers understand action controlled by the local open question. For modernist (i.e., Enlightenment, necessarily imply certain final, ultimate criteria as potentially coercive (Ellis 8: Bochner, 1996); and
iii?
vi: ' I
~:
204 in HANDBOOK OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH»-CHAPTER 8 Guba 8< Lincoln: Controversies, Contradictions, Confluences m 205

criticalist theories of social change (Carspecken, change. Social critique may exist apart from done in the physical sciences. We might predict inquiry, however, it is not merely method that
1996; Schratz 8r Walker, 1995). The realization of social change, but both are necessary for critical- that, if not in our lifetimes, at some later time the promises to deliver on some set of local or context-
the richness of the mental, social, psychological, ist perspectives. dualist idea of an objective reality suborned by grounded truths, it is also the processes of
and linguistic worlds-that individuals and social Constructivists, on the other hand, tend limited human subjective realities will seem as interpretation. Thus we have two arguments pro-
groups create and constantly re-create and cocre— toward the antifoundational (Lincoln, 1995, quaint as flat-earth theories do to us today. ceeding simultaneously. The first, borrowed from
ate gives rise, in the minds of new-paradigm 1998b; Schwandt, 1996). Antijbandational is the positivism, argues for a kind of rigor in the appli-
postmodern and poststructural inquirers, to end- term used to denote a refusal to adopt any per- cation of method, whereas the second argues for
lessly fertile fields of inquiry rigidly walled off manent, unvarying (or “foundational”) standards E VALIDITY2 AN EXTENDED AGENDA both a community consent and a form of rigor——
from conventional inquirers. Unfettered from the by which truth can be universally known. As one defensible reasoning, plausible alongside some
pursuit of transcendental scientific truth, inquir- of us has argued, truth—and any agreement Nowhere can the conversation about paradigm other reality that is known to author and reader-
ers are now free to resituate themselves within regarding what is valid knoWledge—arises from differences be more fertile than in the extended in ascribing salience to one interpretation over
texts, to reconstruct their relationships with the relationship between members of some stake- controversy about validity (Howe 8: Eisenhart, another and for framing and botmding an inter-
research participants in less constricted fashions, holding community (Lincoln, 1995). Agreements 1990; Kvaie, 1989, 1994; Ryan, Greene, Lincoln, pretive study itself. Prior to our understanding
and to create re-presentations (Tierney 8: Lincoln, about truth may be the subject of community Mathison, 8: Mertens, 1998; Scheurich, 1994, that there were, indeed, two forms of rigor, we
1997) that grapple openly with problems of negotiations regarding what will be accepted as 1996). Validity is not like objectivity. There are assembled a set of methodological criteria, largely
inscription, reinscription, metanarratives, and truth (although there are difficulties with that fairly strong theoretical, philosophical, and prag- borrowed from an earlier generation of thoughtful
other rhetorical devices that obscure the extent formulation as well; Guba 8: Lincoln, 1989). Or matic rationales for examining the concept of anthropological and sociological methodological
to which human action is locally and temporally agreements may eventuate as the result of a dia- objectivity and finding it wanting. Even within theorists. Those methodological criteria are still
shaped. The processes of uncovering forms of logue that moves arguments about truth claims positivist frameworks it is viewed as conceptually useful for a variety of reasons, not the least of
inscription and the rhetoric of metanarratives or validity past the warring camps of objectivity flawed. But validity is a more irritating construct, which is that they ensure that such issues as pro-
are genealogical——~“expos[ing] the origins of the and relativity toward “a communal test of validity one neither easily dismissed nor readily config- longed engagement and persistent observation are
view that have become sedimemfed and accepted through the argumentation of the participants in 3 ured by new-paradigm practitioners (Enerstvedt, attended to with some seriousness.
as truths” (Polkinghorne, 1989, p. 42; emphasis a discourse” (Bernstein, 1983; Polkinghorne, .1989; Tschudi, 1989). Validity cannot be dis- It is the second kind of rigor, however, that has
added)—or archaeological (Foucault, 1971; 1989; Schwandt, 1996). This “communicative and missed simply because it points to a question that received the most attention in recent writings: Are
Scheurich, 1997). " pragmatic concept” of validity (Rorty, 1979) is has to be answered in one way or another: Are we inteipretii/eh: rigorous? Can our cocreated con-
New-paradigm inquirers engage the founda- never fixed or unvarying. Rather, it is created by these" findings sufficiently authentic (isomorphic structions be trusted to provide some purchase
tional controversy in quite different ways. Critical means of a community narrative, itself subject to to some reality, trustworthy, related to the way on some important human phenomenon? 1
theorists, particularly critical theorists more the temporal and historical conditions that gave others construct their social worlds) that l‘may Human phenomena are themselves the subject
positivist in orientation, who lean toward Marxian rise to the community. Schwandt (1989) has also trust myself in acting on their implications? More of controversy. Classical social scientists would
interpretations, tend toward foundational per- argued that these discourses, or community to the point, would I feel sufficiently secure about like to see “human phenomena” limited to those
spectives, with an important difference. Rather narratives, can and should be bounded by moral these findings to construct social policy or legis- social experiences from which (scientific) gener-
than locating foundational truth and knowledge considerations, a premise grounded in the eman- lation based on them? At the same time, radical alizations may be drawn. New-paradigm inquir-
in some external reality “out there,” such critical cipatory» narratives of the critical theorists, the reconfigurations of validity leave researchers with ers, however, are increasingly concerned with the
theorists tend to locate the foundations oftruth in philosophical pragmatism of Rortjc the demo- multiple, sometimes conflicting, mandates for what single experience, the individual crisis, the
specific historical, economic, racial, and social cratic focus of constructivist inquiry, and the constitutes rigorous research. epiphany or moment of discovery, with that most
infrastructures of oppression, injustice, and mar- “humanflourishing” goals of participatory and One of the issues around validity is the confla- powerful of all threats to conventional objectivity,
ginalization. Knowers are not portrayed as sepa- co operative inquiry. A tion: between method’ and interpretation. The feeling and emotion. Social scientists concerned
rate from some objective reality, but may be cast The controversies around foundationalism postmodern turn suggests that no method can with the expansion of what count as social data
as unaware .actors in such.historical realities (and, to a lesser extent, essentialism) are not likely deliver on ultimate truth, and in fact “suspects all rely increasingly on the experiential, the embod-
(“false'-consciousness”) or as aware of historical to be resolved through dialogue between para- methodsj’ the more so the larger their claims to ied, the emotive qualities of human experience
forms -of-oppression, but unable or unwilling, digm adherents. The likelier event is that the delivering on truth (Richardson, 1994). Thus, that contribute the narrative quality to a life.
because of conflicts, to act on those historical “postmodern turn” (Best 8: Kellner, 1997), with its although one might argue that some methods are Sociologists such as Ellis and Bochner (2000) and
forms to alter specific conditions in this historical emphasis on the social construction of social more suited than others for conducting research Richardson (2000) and psychologists such as
moment (“divided consciousness”). Thus the reality, fluid as opposed to fixed identities of the on human construction of social realities (Lincoln Michelle Fine (see Fine,Weis,Weseen, 8rWong, 2000)
“foundation” for critical theorists is a duality: self, and the partiality of all truths, will simply 8: Guba, 1985), no one would argue that a single concern themselves with various forms of auto-
social critique tied in turn to raised consciousness overtake modernist assumptions of an objective method—or collection of methods—is the royal ethnography and personal experience methods,
of the possibility of positive and liberating social reality, as indeed, to some extent, it has already road to ultimate knowledge. In new-paradigm both to overcome the abstractions of a social

_____i_____ ,__,__ ,_,,____ ,___ __ _ i 1,


F —

206 a HANDBOOK or QUALITATIVE RESEARCI-I—-CHAPTER s Guba 8: Lincoln: Controversies,Contradictions,Confluences E 207


science far gone with quantitative descriptions of as practical philosophy” that has as its aim social inquiries that are faithful enough to some affirmatively with respect to inclusion, and to act
human life and to capture those elements that i
“enhancing or cultivating critical intelligence in human construction that we may feel safe in with energy to ensure that all voices in the inquiry
make life conflictual, moving, problematic. parties to the research encounter,” critical intel- acting on them, or, more important, that members effort had a chance to be represented in any texts
For purposes of this discussion, we believe the ligence being defined as “the capacity to engage S
of the community in which the research is con- and to have their stories treated fairly and with
adoption of the most radical definitions of social in moral critique.” And finally, he proposes a third ducted may act on them? To that question, there balance.
science is appropriate, because the paradigmatic way in which we might judge social inquiry is no final answer. There are, however, several Ontological and educative nutlzenticity were
controversies are often taking place at the edges as practical philosophy: We might make judgments discussions of what we might use to make both designated as criteria for determining a raised
of those conversations. Those edges are where the about the social inquirer-as-practicabphilosopher. 4 professional and lay judgments regarding any level of awareness, in the first instance, by indi-
border work is occurring, and, accordingly, they He or she might be “evaluated on the success to piece of work. It is to those versions of validity vidual research participants and, in the second, by
are the places that show the most promise for pro- which his or her reports of the inquiry enable the that we now turn. individuals about those who surround them or
jectingwhere qualitative methods will be in the training or calibration of human judgment” (p. 69) with whom they come into contact for some social
near and far future. or “the capacity for practical wisdom” (p. 70). or organizational purpose. Although we failed to
i Validity as Authenticity see it at that particular historical moment (1989),
Schwandt is not alone, however, in wishing to
say “farewell to criteriology,” at least as it has been Perhaps the first nonfoundational criteria were there is no reason these criteria cannot be—at
Whither and Whether Criteria
previously conceived. Scheurich (1997) makes a I those we developed in response to a challenge by this point in time, with many miles under our
1
At those edges, several conversations are similar plea, and in the same vein, Smith (I993) Iohn K. Smith (see Smith 8: Deemer, 2000). In theoretic and practice feet—reflective also of
occurring around validity. The first—-and most also argues that validity, if it is to survive at all, those criteria, we attempted» to locate criteria for Schwandt’s (1996) “critical intelligence,” or capac-
radical—is a conversation opened by Schwandt must be radically reformulated if it is ever to serve judging the processes and outcomes of naturalistic ity to engage in moral critique. in fact, the authen-
(1996), who suggests that we say “farewell to cri- phenomenological research well (see also Smith or constructivist inquiries (rather than the appli- ticity criteria we originally proposed had strong
teriologyf’ or the “regulative norms for removing 8: Deemer, 2000). cation of methods; see Guba 8: Lincoln, 1989). moral and ethical overtones, a point to which we
doubt and settling disputes about what is correct At issue here is not whetherwe shall have cri- We described five potential outcomes of a social later returned (see, for instance, Lincoln, 1995,
or incorrect, true or false” (p. 59), which have cre- teria, or whose criteria we as a scientific commu- constructionist inquiry (evaluation is one form of 1998a, 1998b). It was a point to which our critics
ated a virtual cult around criteria. Schwandt does nity might adopt, but rather what the nature of disciplined inquiry; see Guba 8: Lincoln, 1981), strongly objected before we were sufficiently self-
not, however, himself say farewell to criteria social inquiry ought to be, whether it ought to each grounded in concerns specific to the para- aware to realize the implications of what we had
\Y
forever; rather, he resituates social inquiry, with undergo a transformation, and what might be the I digm we had tried to describe and construct, and proposed (see, for instance, Sechrest, 1993).
other contemporary philosophical pragmatists, basis for criteria within a projected transforma- apart from any concerns carried over from the Catalytic and tactical authenticities refer to the
1
within a framework that transforms professional tion. Schwandt (1989; also personal communi- positivist legacy. The criteria were instead rooted ability of a given inquiry to prompt, first, action
social inquiry into a form of practical philosophy, cation, August 2l, 1998) is quite clear that both ii in the axioms and assumptions of the construc- on the part of research participants and, second,
lg1.
characterized by “aesthetic, prudential and moral the transformation and the criteria are rooted in it tivist paradigm, insofar as we could extrapolate the involvement of the researcherievaluator in
E;
considerations as well as more conventionally sci- dialogic efforts. These dialogic efforts are quite tii:; and infer them. r training participants in specific forms of social
entific ones” (p. 68).When social inquiry becomes clearly themselves forms of “moral discourse.” it Those authenticity criteria~—so called because and political action if participants desire such
the practice of a form of practical philosophy—a Through the specific connections of the dialogic, we believed them to be hallmarks of authentic, training. It is here that constructivist inquiry
deep questioning about how we shall get on in the the idea of practical wisdom, and moral dis- trustworthy,‘ rigorous, or “valid” constructivist or practice begins to resemble forms of critical the-
world and what we conceive to be the potentials courses, much of Schwandfs work can be seen phenomenologicalinquiry-—were fairness, onto- orist action, action research, or participative or
and limits of human knowledge and function- to be related to, and reflective of, critical theorist logical authenticity, educative authenticity, cooperative inquiry, each of which is predicated
ing—then we have some preliminary under- and participatory paradigms, as well as construc- catalytic authenticity, and tactical authenticity on creating the capacity in research participants
standing of what entirely different criteria might tivism, although Schwandt specifically. denies (Guba 8: Lincoln, 1989, pp. 245-251). Fairness was for positive social change and forms of emancipa-
be for:judging social inquiry I _ the relativity of truth. (For a more sophisticated thought to be a quality ofbalance; that is, all stake- tory community action. It is also at this specific
Schwandt (1996) proposes threeisuch criteria.
First, he argues, we should search -for a social
explication and critique of forms of construc-
tivism, hermeneutics, and interpretivism, see
i holder views, perspectives, claims, concerns, and point that practitioners of positivist and postpos-
itivist social inquiry are the most critical, because
voices should be apparent in the text. Omission
inquiry that “generate[s] knowledge that comple- Schwandt, 2000. In that chapter, Schwandt spells ii.1, any action on the part of the inquirer is thought to
of stakeholder or participant voices reflects, we
ments or supplements rather than displac[ing] lay out distinctions between realists and nonrealists, i.€-z. believe, a form of bias. This bias, however, was and destabilize objectivity and introduce subjectivity,
probing of social problems? a form of knowledge and between foundationalists and nonfounda- is not related directly to the concerns of objectivity resulting in bias. The problemof subjectivity and
for which we do not yet have the content, but from tionalists, far more clearly than it is possible for us that flow from positivist inquiry and that are bias has a long theoretical history, and this chapter
which we might seek to understand the aims of to do in this chapter.) 1 - ' " . .11- reflective of inquirer blindness or subjectivity. - is simply too brief for us to enter into the various
practice from a variety of perspectives, or with dif- To return to the central question embedded in formulations that either take accotmt of subjec-
ferent lenses. Second, he proposes a “social inquiry validity: How do we know when we have specific i
is,.a-.;=,-.¢~L_-4. Rather, this fairness was defined by deliberate
attempts to prevent marginalization, to act tivity or posit it as a positive learning experience,
i
ti3&1
war;-.
. l. .r . . y
Z‘
20s n nrmnsoox or ouxrmrrrvs Resaxacnficnarrnn s S‘
Guba 8rLincoln: Controversies, Contradictions, Confluences in 209
r
practical, embodied, gendered, and emotive. For mixed-genre texts, we have moved from plane problematic presence—a poststructural and poststructuralists and postmodernists to reflect
l
purposes of this discussion, it is enough to say geometry to light theory, where light can be both decidedly postmodern form of discourse theory, upon their representational practices, representa-
that we are persuaded that objectivity is a waves and particles. Crystallization, without losing hence textual revelation. tional practices themselves become more prob-
chimera: a mythological creature that never structure, deconstructs the traditional idea of lematic. Three of the most engaging, but painful,
existed, save in the imaginations of those who “validity” (we feel how there is no single truth, we i
r issues are the problem of voice, the status of
see how texts validate themselves); and crystal- 3 Validity as an Ethical Relationship
believe that knowing can be separated from the reflexivity, and the problematics of postmod-
knower. lization provides us with a deepened, complex,
As Lather (1993) points out, poststructural ern/poststructural textual representation, espe-
thoroughly partial understanding of the topic.
Paradoxically, we know more and doubt what we forms for validities “bring ethics and epistemology cially as those problematics are displayed in the
Validity as Resistance, Validity as know. (Richardson, 1997, p. 92) together” (p. 686); indeed, as Parker Palmer (1987) shift toward narrative and literary forms that
Poststructural Transgression i also notes, “every way of knowing contains its directly and openly deal with human emotion.
The metaphoric “solid object” (crystal/text), own moral trajectory” (p. 24). Peshkin reflects on
Laurel Richardson (1994, 1997) has proposed Noddings’s (1984) observation that “the search for
which can be turned many ways, which reflects l Voice
another form of validity, a deliberately “transgres- justification often carries us farther and farther
and refracts light (light/multiple layers of mean-
sive” form, the crystalline. In writing experimental from the heart of morality” (p. 105; quoted in Voice is a multilayered problem, simply
ing), through which we can see both “wave” (light
(i.e., nonauthoritative, nonpositivist) texts, particu- Peshkin, 1993, p. 24). The way in which we know is because it has come to mean many things to dif-
wave/human currents) and “particle” (light as
larly poems and plays, Richardson (1997) has most assuredly tied up with both whatwe know and ferent researchers. In former eras, the only appro-
“chunks” of energy/elements of truth, feeling,
sought to “problematize reliability, validity and connection, processes of the research that “flow” our relationships with our research participants. priate “voice” was the “voice from nowhere”-the
truth” (p. 165) in an effort to create new relation- Accordingly, one of us worked on trying to under- “pure presence” of representation, as Lather terms
together) is an attractive metaphor for validity.
ships: to her research participants, to her work, to standthe ways in which the ethical intersects both it. As researchers became more conscious of
The properties of the crystal-as-metaphor help
other women, to herself. She says that transgressive il the interpersonal and the epistemological.(as a form the abstracted realities their texts created, they _
writers and readers alike see the interweaving
forms permit a social scientist to “conjure a diflerent of authentic or valid knowing; Lincoln, 1995). The became simultaneously more conscious of having
of processes in the research: discovery, seeing,
kind of social science ; . . [whichl means changing ll
result was the first set of imderstandings about readers “hear” their informants—permitting
telling, storying, re-presentation.
one’s relationship to one’s work, how one knows and emerging criteria for quality that were also rooted readers to hear the exact words (and, occasionally,
tells about the sociological” (p. 166). In order to see in the epistemology/ethics nexus. Seven new stan- the paralinguistic cues, the lapses, pauses, stops,
“how transgression looks and how it feels,” it is nec- Other “Transgressive” Validities '11
ti-‘(flu dards were derived from that search: positionality or starts, reformulations) of the informants. Today
essary to “find and deploy methods that allow us to Laurel Richardson is not alone in calling for standpoint, judgments; specific discourse commu- voice can mean, especially in more participa-.
uncover the hidden assumptions and life-denying forms of validity that are “transgressive” and |a,.- a.i ->,~:. - nities and research sites as arbiters of quality; voice, tory forms of research, not only having a real
repressions of sociology; resee/refeel sociology. disruptive of the status quo. Patti Lather (1993) or the extent to which a text has the quality of researcher—and a researcher’s voice—in the
r._,_:
Reseeing and retelling are inseparable” (p. 167). seeks “an incitement to discourse,” the purpose of fil polyvocality; critical subjectivity (or what might be text, but also letting research participants speak
ll
. The way to achieve such validity is by examin- which is “to rupture validity as a regime of truth, i termed intense self-reflexivity); reciprocity, or the for themselves, either in text form or through
ing the properties of a crystal in a metaphoric to displace its historical inscription . . . via a dis- ls extent to which the research relationship becomes plays, forums, “town meetings,” or other oral and
sense. Here we present an extended quotation to persion; circulation and proliferation of counter- £1 reciprocal ratherthan hierarchical; sacredness, or performance-oriented media or communication
E
give some flavor of how such validity might be practices of authority that. take the crisis of =>
1
the profound regard for how science can (and does) forms designed by research participants them-
ill
described and deployed: representation into account” (p. 674). In addition
fl 1
.3 contribute to human flourishing; and sharing the selves. Performance texts, in particular, give an
to catalytic validity (Lather, 1986), Lather (1993) perquisites of privilege that accrue to our positions emotional immediacy to the voices of researchers
. . I propose that the central imaginary for “validity” poses validity as simulacra/ironic validity; as academics with university positions. Each of and research participants far beyond theirown
m>»e¢»>§a;,<.zea :;.»‘>
~..;for postmodernist texts is not the triangle—a Lyotardiari paralogy/neopragmatic validity, a form =1 these standards was extracted from a body of sites and locales (see McCall, 2000).. Rosanna
' ,rigid,.g fixed, two-dimensional object. Rather the of validity that “foster[s] heterogeneity, refusing
-1
Ls‘.
research, often from disciplines as disparate as Hertz (1997) describes voice as , ~.
Cengtral imaginary is the crystal, which combines sa,,.
management, philosophy, and women’s studies
disclosure” (p. 679);.,Derridean rigor/rhizomatic §1
symmetry and substance with an infinite variety a struggle to figure out how to present the author’s
of shapes, substances, transmutations, multidi-
validity, a form ofbehaving “via relay, circuit, mul- (Lincoln, 1995). .
self while simultaneously writing the respondents’
mensionalities, and angles of approach. Crystals tiple openings” (p. 680); and voluptuous/situated accounts and representing their selves. Voice has
- grow, change, alter, but are not amorphous. validity which “embodies a situated,partial tenta- multiple dimensions: First, there is the voice of the
Crystals are prisms that reflect externalities and tiveness” and “brings ethics: and epistemology E Voice, REFLEXIVITY, AND Posrnooanu author. Second, there is the presentation of the
refract within themselves, creating different colors, together . . . via practices of engagement and self- 2!)?/J;¢§v.$'¥r.‘n'.c¢
-‘.5 - - - TEXTUAL REPRESENTATION voices of one’s respondents“ within the text.A third
iii
~ patterns, arrays, casting off in different directions. reflexivity” (p. 686). Together, these form a way of " dimension appears when the-self is the subject of
What we see depends upon our angle of repose. interrupting, disrupting, and transforming “pure” the inquiry. . . . Voice is how authors express them-
Not triangulation, crystallization. In postmodernist presence into a disturbing, fluid, partial, and
- Texts have to do la lot more work these days
selves within an ethnography. (pp. xi—xii) A . 's
;E
M than they used to. Even as they are charged by
r
., .

.32.
§l _7_-;-_;_a»_-;-%m-- I-— _ -=1-;¢_»£~:~—-M»Me-—'=~*!v'=\*\‘Q':"e:'::~€<?é&‘%:~*;»%;“"'“’?E'fi1".13':‘:'
. . -. . ,_.T
i
210 til HANDBOOK OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH~CHAPTER 8 Guba 8: Lincoln: Controversies, Contradictions, Confluences in 211
But knowing how to express ourselves goes far (p. 5). Each of those selves comes into play in the of historical oppression. Put another way, we are personal narratives, first-person accounts, reflexive
beyond the commonsense understanding of research setting and consequently has a distinc- confronted with a crisis of authority (which tells interrogations, and deconstruction of the forms of
“expressing ourselves.” Generations of ethnogra- tive voice. Reflexivity—as well as the poststruc- us the world is “this way” when perhaps it is some tyranny embedded in representational practices
phers trained in the “cooled-out, stripped-down tural and postmodern sensibilities concerning other way, or many other ways) and a crisis of rep- (see Richardson, 2000; Tierney 8: Lincoln, 1997).
rhetoric” of positivist inquiry (Firestone, 1987) quality in qualitative research—~demands that we resentation (which serves to silence those whose Representation may be arguably the most
find it difficult, if not nearly impossible, to interrogate each of our selves regarding the ways lives we appropriate for our social sciences, and open—ended of the controversies surrounding
“locate” themselves deliberately and squarely in which research efforts are shaped and staged which may also serve subtly to re-create this phenomenological research today, for no other
within theirtexts (even though, as Geertz [I988] around the binaries, contradictions, and para- world, rather than some other, perhaps more reasons than that the ideas of what constitutes
has demonstrated finally and without doubt, the doxes that form our own lives. We must question
l
l
complex, but just one). Catherine Stimpson legitimate inquiry are expanding and, at the same
authorial voice is rarely genuinely absent, or even our selves, too, regarding how those binaries and 1
l
(1988) has observed: time,the forms of narrative, dramatic, and rhetor-
hidden)? Specific textual experimentation can paradoxes shape not only the identities called l
ical structure are far from being either explored
help; that is, composing ethnographic work into forth in the field and later in the discovery Like every great word, “representation/s” is a stew. or exploited frilly. Because, too, each inquiry, each
i
various literary forms—the poetry and plays of processes of writing, but also our interactions A scrambled menu, it serves up several meanings inquirer, brings a unique perspective to our
Laurel Richardson are good exan1ples—can help with respondents, in who we become to them in at once. For a representation can be an image—
understanding, the possibilities for variation and
a researcher to overcome the tendency to write in visual, verbal, or aural. . . .A representation can
the process of becoming to ourselves. Someone exploration are limited only by the number of
the distanced and abstracted voice of the disem- also be a narrative, a sequence of images and
once characterized qualitative research as the those engaged in inquiry and the realms of social
bodied “I.” But such writing exercises are hard ideas. . . . Or, a representation can be the product of
twin processes of “writing up” (field notes) and _!E

ideology, that vast scheme for showing forth the and intrapersonal life that become interesting
work. This is also work that is embedded in the “writing down” (the narrative). But Clandinin and to researchers. The only thing that can be said for
world and justifying its dealings. (p.223)
practices of reflexivity and narrativity, without Connelly (I994) have made clear that this bitex- certain about postmodern representational prac-
which achieving a voice of (partial) truth is tual reading of the processes of qualitative 1
‘i One way to confront the dangerous illusions tices is that they will proliferate as. forms and they
impossible. research is far too simplistic. In fact, many texts '5 (and their underlying ideologies) that texts may will seek, and demand much of, audiences, many
are created in the process of engaging in field- foster is through the creation of new texts that of whom may be outside the scholarly and aca-
Reflexivity work. As Richardson (1994, 1997, 2000; see also I/2'1J.~‘>M4-'§‘\|Aac.; break boundaries; that move from the center to demic world. In fact, some forms of inquiry may
-3
Richardson 8: St. Pierre, Chapter 38, this volume) it the margins to comment on and decenter the cen- never show up in the academic world, because
Reflexivity is the process of reflecting critically makes clear, writing is not merely the transcrib- :3;l
ter; that forgo closed, bounded worlds for those their purpose will be use in the immediate con-
on the self as researcher, the “human as instru- ing of some reality. Rather, writing»-of all the 3
Qé more open-ended and less conveniently encom- text, for the consumption, reflection, and use of
ment” (Guba 8r Lincoln, 1981). It is, we would texts, notes, presentations, and possibilities—is :<
passed; that transgress the boundaries of conven- indigenous audiences. Those that are produced
assert, the critical subjectivity discussed early on also a process of discovery: discovery of the tional social science; and that seek to create a for scholarly audiences will, however, continue to
in Reason and Rowan's edited volume Human subject (and sometimes‘ of the problem itself) social science about human life rather than on be untidy, experimental, and driven by the need t0
Inquiry (1981). It is a conscious experiencing of and discovery of the self. * subjects, ~ communicate social worlds that have remained
the self as both inquirer and respondent, as There is good news and bad news with the Experiments with how to do this have pro- private and“nonscientif1c” until now. .v
teacher and learner, as the one coming to know most contemporary of formulations. The good ml
/4
duced “messy texts” (Marcus 8: Fischer, 1986).
the self within the processes of research itself. news is that the multiple selves—ourselves and Messy textsare not typographic nightmares
Reflexivity forces us to come to terms not only our respondents-—of postmodern inquiries ,3 E A GLIMPSE or THE Futons
(although they may be typographically nonlin~
with our choice of research problem and with may give rise to more dynamic, problematic, ear); rather, they are texts that seek to break the
those with whom we engage in the research open-ended, and complex forms of writing and binary between science and literature, to portray The issues raised in this chapter are by no means
/1M}"‘<s$':Ie£tl1azt=~>5/»‘
process,~but with our selves and with the multiple gl
representation. The bad news is that the multiple tiit .
‘>= the contradiction and truth of human experience, the only ones under discussion for the near and
.-£9
identities that represent the fluid self in the selves we create and encounter give rise to more to break the rules in the service of showing, even far future. But they are some of the critical ones,
research setting (Alcoff 8: Potter, 1993). Shulamit dynamic, problematic, open-ended, and complex partially, how real human beings cope with both and discussion, dialogue, and even controversies
Reinhari (1997), for example, argues that we not forms of writing and representation. - the eternal verities of human existence and the are bound to continue as practitioners of the
only “bring the self to the field . . . [we also] create daily irritations and tragedies of living that exis- various new and emergent paradigms continue
the,self in_t_he field” (p. 3). She suggests that ‘gar
tence. Postmodern representations search out and either to look for common ground or to find ways
although we all have many selves we bring with Postmodern Textual Representations _ .
experiment with narratives that expand the range in- which to distinguish their forms of inquiry
us, those selves fall into three categories: research- There are twodangers inherent in the conven-
1%:
of understanding, voice, and storied variations from others.
based selves, brought selves (the selves that tional texts of scientific method: that they may in human experience. As much as they are social ' Some time ago, we expressed our hope that
historically, socially, and personally create our lead us to believe the world is rather simpler than scientists, inquirers also become storytellers, practitioners of both positivist and new-paradigm
st
standpoints), and situationally created selves it is, and that they may reinscribe enduring forms poets, and playwrights, experimenting with forms of inquiry might fmd some way of resolving
212 131 HANDBOOK OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH-CHAPTER 8 Guba8:l.incoln: Controversies, Contradictions, Confluences in 213
their differences, such that all social scientists inquiries are both tied and untied, as a means of .»_. L.- . L,§ Alpern, S., Antler, ]., Perry, E. 1., 8: Scobie, I. W. (Eds.). Fine, M., Weis, L., Wescen, S., 8: Wong, L. (2000). For
could work within a common discourse—and finding where our interests cross and where we (1992). The challenge of feminist biography: whom? Qualitative research, representations,
perhaps even several traditions--once again. can both be and promote others’ being, as whole i1 Writing the lives of modern American women. and social responsibilities. l.n N. K. Denzin 8:
In retrospect, such a resolution appears highly Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative
human beings.
unlikely and would probably even be less than Babbitt, S. (1993). Feminism and objective interests: research (2nd ccl., pp. 107- 1 3l ). Thousand Oaks,
The role of transformation experiences in ratio- CA: Sage.
useful. This is not, however, because neither posi-
nal deliberation. In L. Alcoff 8: E. Potter (Eds.), Firestone, W. (1987). Meaning in method: The rhetoric
tivists nor phenomenologists will budge an inch E Notes Feminist epistemologies (pp. 245-264). New York: of quantitative and qualitative research. Educa-
(although that, too, is unlikely). Rather, it is tional Researcher; 16(7), 16—2l.
Routledge.
because, in the postmodern moment, and in the 1. There are several versions of critical theory, Foucault, M. (1971). The order of things: /in archaeol-
t Bernstein, R. I. (1983). Beyond objectivism and rela-
wake of poststructuralism, the assumption that including classical critical theory, which is most closely
tivism: Science, hermeneutics, and praxis. Oxford: ogy of the human sciences. New York: Pantheon.
there is no single “truth”-that all truths are but related to neo-Marxist theory; postpositivist formula- l
Blackwell. Gamson, I. (2000). Sexualities, queer theory, and qual-
partial truths; that the slippage between signifier tions, which divorce themselves from Marxist theory l itative research. In N. K. Denzin 8: Y. S. Lincoln
Best, S., 8: Kellner, D. (1997). The postmodern turn.
and signified in linguistic and textual terms but are positivist in their insistence on conventional l (Eds.), Handbook ofqualitative research (2nd ed.,
New York: Guilford.
creates re-presentations that are only and always rigor criteria; and postmodernist, poststructuralist, or pp. 347-365). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
_l
l
Bloland, H. (1989). Higher education and high anxiety:
constructivist-oriented varieties. See, for instance, Fay Geertz, C. (1988). Works and lives: The anthropologist as
shadows of the actual people, events, and places; Objectivism, relativism, and irony. Journal of
(1987), Carr and Kemmis (1986), and Lather (1991). author. Cambridge: Polity.
that identities are fluid rather than fixed—leads Higher Education, 60, 519-543;
See also Kemmis and McTaggart (2000) and Kincheloe Geertz, C. (1993). Local knowledge: Further essays in.
us ineluctably toward the insight that there will Bloland, H. (1995). Postmodernism and higher educa-
and McLaren (2000). interpretive anthropology. London: Fontana.
be no single “conventional” paradigm to which all tion. lournal ofHigher Education, 66, 521-559.
2. For a clearer understanding of how methods Greenwood, D. ]., 8: Levin, M. (2000). Reconstructing
social scientists might ascribe in some common Bradley, ]., 8: Schaefer, K. (1998). The uses and misuses
came to stand in for paradigms, or how our initial (and, A the relationships between universities and society
ofdata and models. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
terms and with mutual understanding. Rather, we thought, quite clear) positions came to be miscon- " through action research. In N. K. Denzin 8:
.,_, . Carr, W. L., 8: Kemmis, S. (1986). Becoming critical:
we stand at the threshold of a history marked by Sifllfid, S86 Lancy (I993) or, even more currently, Weiss Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative
Education, knowledge and action research. London:
multivocality, contested meanings, paradigmatic (1998, esp. p. 26s). Fahner. research (2nd ed., pp. 85-106). Thousand Oaks,
controversies, and new textual forms.At some dis- 3. For example, compare this chapter with, say, the CA: Sage.
Carspecken, P. E (1996). Critical ethnography in educa-
tance down this conjectural path, when its history work of Richardson (2000) and Ellis and Bochner Guba, E. G., 8: Lincoln,Y. S. (1981).Effectivc evaluation:
tional research: A theoretical and practical guide.
is written,we will find that this has been the era of (2000), where the authorial voices are clear, personal, Improving the usefulness of evaluation results
New York: Routledge.
emancipation: emancipation from what Hannah vocal, and interior, interacting subjectivities. Although i
through responsive and naturalistic approaches.
Christians, C. G. (2000). Ethics and politics in qualita-
some colleagues have surprised us by correctly identi- E San Francisco: jossey-Bass. _
Arendt calls “the coerciveness of Truthf’ emanci- tive research. In N. K. Denzin 8: Y. S. Lincoln
fying which chapters each of us has written in given ‘t
Guba, E. G., 8: Lincoln,Y. S. (1982). Epistemological and
pation from hearing only the voices of Western (Eds.), Handbook ofqualitative research (2nd ed.,
books, nevertheless, the style of this chapter more methodological bases for naturalistic inquiry.
Europe, emancipation from generations of silence, pp. 133-155). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. ~
closely approximates the more distanced forms of“real- r Educational Communications and Technology
and emancipation from seeing the world in one l Clandinin, D. ]., 8: Connelly, F. M. (1994). Personal
ist” writing than it does the intimate, personal “feeling t journal, 31, 233-252. '
color. 8‘ .
experience methods. In N. K. Denzin 8:
tone” (to borrow a phrase from Studs Terkel) of other Guba, E. G., 8: Lincoln, Y. S. (1989). Fourth generation
{
E‘. Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative
We may also be entering an age of greater spir- chapters. Voices also arise as a function of the material evaluation. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
‘Til research (pp. 413-427). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
ituality within research efforts. The emphasis on being covered. The material we chose as most impor- £11‘
Guba, E. G., 8: Lincoln, Y. S. (1994). Competing
Denzin, N. K., 8: Lincoln,Y. S. (Eds.). (1994). Handbook
inquiry that reflects ecological values, on inquiry tantifor this chapter seemed to demand a less personal
ofqualitative research. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. paradigms in qualitative research. In N. K. Denzin
that respects communal forms of living that are tone, probably because there appears to be much more 8: Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative
Ellis, C., 8: Bochner, A. P. (Eds.). ("1996). Composing
not Western, on inquiry involving intense reflex- “contention” than calm dialogue concerning these A research (pp. 105-117). Thousand Oaks,’ CA:
a£i§.1>/,=?wuri»;/ <',sgv ethnography: Alternative forms of qualitative
ivity regarding how our inquiries are shaped issues. The “cool” tone likely stems from our psycholog- Sage.
writing. Walnut Creek, CA: AltaMira.
by our own historical and gendered locations, and ical response to trying to create a quieter space for dis- Harding, S. (1993). Rethinking standpoint epistemol-
Ellis, G., 8: Bochner, A. P. (2000). Autoethnography,
cussion around controversial issues.What can we say? ogy: What is “strong objectivity”? In L. Alcoff 8:
on inquiry. into “human flourishing,” as Heron 1..- _ . . personal narrative, reflexivity: Researcher as
and Reason (I997) call it, may yet reintegrate the ' subject. In N. K. Denzin 8: Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), E. Potter (Eds.), Feminist epistemologies (pp. 49-
1*”, -'
sacred with the secular in ways that promote»free- Handbook of qualitative research (2nd ed., 82).NewYork: Routledge. -
dom -and self-determination. Egon Brunswik, E Rsrnnnucrs get
pp. 733-768). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Heron, I. (1996). Cooperative inquiry: Research into the
-Er!
Enerstvedt, R. (1989). The problem of validity in social human condition. London: Sage. A
the organizational theorist, wrotei of “tied” and
Addelson, K. P. ( 1993). Knowersldoers and their moral . science. In S. Kvale (Ed.), Issues ofvalidity in qual- Heron, ]., 8: Reason, P. (1997). A participatory inquiry
“untied” variables—variab1es that are linked, or problems. In L. Alcoff 8: E. Potter (Eds.), Feminist
Ft-'
paradigm. Qualitative Inquiry, 3, 274-294. ' . '
. itative research (pp. 135-173). Lund,‘ Sweden:
clearly -not linked, with other variables—when H epistemologies (pp. 265-294). New York: Routledge. .-. \ Hertz, R. (1997). Introduction: Reflexivity and voice. In
Studentlitteratur.
studying human forms of organization. We may Alcoff, L., 8: Potter, E. (Eds.). (1993). Feminist episte- Fay, B. (1987). Critical social science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell R. Hertz (Ed.), Reflexivity and voice. Thousand
be in a period of exploring the ways in which our mologies. New York: Routledge. * ii _
fifé
Oaks, CA: Sage. '
.
M. . University Press.

an

.___ -Lm,,m-_m..,.._-_»%\_-_- ..... 1 -- - :-L2:;?¢1 ;;ZJfI1i';;,,E;:Tmmuma1|Q


T1

214 m HANDBOOK OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH—CHAPTER 8 1, Guba 8: Lincoln: Controversies, Contradictions, Confluences E 215

Howe, K., 8: Eisenhart, M. (1990). Standards for interpretive researchers. Theory and Research in Richardson, L. (1997). Fields of play: Constructing and social constructionism. In N. K. Denzin 8: Y. S.
qualitative (and quantitative) research: A prolego- Social Education, 26(1), 12-29. an academic lrfia. New Brunswick, NI: Rutgers Lincoln (Eds.), I-Iundboolc of qualitative research
menon. Educational Researchen 19(4), 2-9. Lincoln,Y. S., 8: Denzin, N. K.(1994). The fifth moment. (2nd ed., pp. 189-213). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
University Press.
Hutcheon, L. (I989). The politics of postmodernism. In N. K. Denzin 8: Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook l Richardson, L. (2000). Writing: A method of inquiry. Sechrest, L. (1993). l’rogram evaluution.' A pluralistic
l
New York: Routledge. of qualitative research (pp. 575-586). Thousand In N. K. Denzin 8: Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook enterprise. San Francisco: Iossey-Bass.
Kemmis, S., 8: McTaggart, R. (2000). Participatory Oaks, CA: Sage. Smith, I. K. (1993). Afler the dernise ofempiricisrn: The
i of qualitative research (2nd ed., pp. 923-948}.
action research. In N. K. Denzin 8: Y. S. Lincoln Lincoln,Y. S., 8: Guba, E. G. (1985). Naturalistic inquiry. I Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. problem ofjudging social and educational inquiry.
(Eds.), Handbook ofqualitative research (2nd ed., Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Norwood, N): Abiex.
pp. 567-605). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Marcus, G. E., 8: Fischer, M. M. I. (1986). Anthropology Princeton, NI: Princeton University Press. Smith, I. 1(., 8: Deemer, D. K. (2000). The-2 problem of
Kincheloe, I. L. (1991). Teachers as researchers: as cultural critique: An experimental moment criteria in the age of relativism. in N. K. Denzin
Ryan, K. E., Greene, I. C., Lincoln, Y. S., Mathison, S., 8:
Qualitative inquiry as a path to empowerment. in the human sciences. Chicago: University of Mertens, D. (1998). Advantages and challenges of 8: Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative
London: Palmer. Chicago Press. _ research (2nd ed., pp. 877-896). Thousand Oaks,
using inclusive evaluation approaches in evalua-
Kincheloe, I. L., 8: McLaren, P. (2000). Rethinking critical McCall, M. M. (2000). Performance ethnography: CA: Sage.
tion practice. American Iournal ofEvaluation, 19,
theory and qualitative research. In N. K. Denzin 8: A brief history and some advice. In N. K. Denzin 101-122. Stimpson, C. R. (1988). Nancy Reagan wears a hat:
Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.),Handbook ofqualitative research 8: Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative Salner, M. (1989). Validity in human $Ci€nC@ Feminism and its cultural consensus. Critical
(2nd ed., pp. 279-313). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. research (2nd ed., pp. 421-433). Thousand Oaks, research. In S. Kvale (Ed.), Issues of validity in Inquiry, I4, 223-243.
Kondo, D. K. (1990). Crafting selves: Power; gender; _ CA: Sage. ' Tierney, W. G. (2000). Undaunted courage: Life history
qualitative research (pp. 47-72). Lund, Sweden:
and discourses ofidentity in a lapanese workplace. Mertens,D. (1998). Research methods in education and Studentlitteratur. and the postmodern challenge. In N. K. Denzin 8:.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. psychology: Integrating diversity with quantitative Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative
Scheurich, I. I. (1994). Policy archaeology. Iournal of
Kondo, D. K. (1997). About face: Performing race in and qualitative methods. Thousand Oaks, CA: ~. Educational Policy, 9, 297-316. research (2nd ed., pp. 537-553). Thousand Oaks,
fashion and theater New York: Routledge. Sage. Scheurich, I. I. (1996). Validity. International journal of CA: Sage.
Kvale, S. (Ed.). (1989). Issues of validity in qualitative Michael, M. C. (1996). Feminism and the postmodern Tierney,W. G., 8: Lincoln,Y. S. (Eds.). (1997). Represen-
Qualitative Studies in Education, 9, 49-60.
research. Lund, Sweden: Studentlitteratur. impulse: Post— World War IIfiction. Albany: State Scheurich, I. I. (1997). Research method in thepostmod- tation and the text: Re—frarning the narrative voice.
Kvale, S. (1994, April). Wilidation as communication University of New York Press. u Albany: State University of New York Press.
w/->1-r<v‘r¢s‘45>~"'r ern. London: Palmer.
and action. Paper presented at the annual meet- Noddings, N. (1984). Caring: A feminine approach to Schratz, M., 8: Walker, R. (1995). Research as social Trinh, T. M. (1991). When the moon waxes red:

ing of the American Educational Research ethics and moral education. Berkeley: University 3‘
Egg
change: New opportunitiesfor qualitative research. Representation, gender and cultural politics.
Association, New Orleans. - H . of California Press. New York: Routledge. New York: Routledge.
Lancy,D. E (1993). Qualitative research in education:An Olesen,V. L. (2000). Peminisms and qualitative research l::I:.:.‘- --
Tschudi, F. (1989). Do qualitative and quantitative
I Schwandt, T. A. (1989). Recapturing moral discourse
introduction to the major traditions. New York: . , at and into the millennium. In N. K. Denzin 8: if .
Q .II methods require different approaches to valid-
1-<1
in evaluation. Educational Researcher, 18(8),
Longman. V ' .Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative at '1'.-1" 1:‘
-N 11-16, 34. ity? In S. Kvale (Ed.),Issues ofvalidigl in qualita-
Lather, P. (1986). Issues of validity in openly ideologi- research (2nd ed., pp. 215-255). Thousand Oaks, ':..i?ii!»'
tive research (pp. 109-134). Lund, Sweden:
"S
.:-E. . Schwandt, T. A. (1996). Farewell to criteriology.
cal research: Between a rock and a soft place. CA: Sage. ' Qualitative Inquiry, 2, 58-72. Studentlitteratur.
Interchange, 17(4), 63-84. Palmer, P. I. (1987, September-October). Community, ,.\-. Schwandt, T. A. (2000). Three epistemological stances for Weiss, C. H. (1998). Evaluation (2nd ed.). Upper Saddle
Lather, P. (1991). Getting smart: Feminist research and conflict, and ways of knowing. Change, 19, 20-25. River, NI: Prentice Hall. I I a i
qualitative inquiry: Interpretivism, hermeneutics,
pedagogy with/in the postmodern. New York: Peshkin, A. ( 1993). The goodness of qualitative
Routledge. - " i research. Educational Researcher, 22(2), 24-30.
Lather, R (1993). Fertile obsession: Validity after post- Polkinghorne, D. E. (1989). Changing conversations
. structuralism. Sociological Quarterly, 34, 673-693. about human science. In S. Kvale (Ed.), Issues of
Leitch, V B. (1996). Postmodern: Local efizcts, global c validity in qualitative research (pp. 13-46). Lund,
~ flows. Albany: State University of New York Press. Sweden:Studentlitteratur. ~ ~ :.

Lincoln, Y. S. (1995). Emerging criteria for quality in Reason,- P. (1993).. Sacred experience and sacred .i\<-
- ' qualitative and interpretive research. Qualitative science. Iournal ofI_‘/Ianagementlnquiry, 2, 10-27.
Inquiry, 1, 275-289. - - Reason, P., 8: Rowan, I. (Eds). (1981). Human inquiry.
Lincoln,Y. S. ( 1997).What constitutes quality in interpre- London: Iohn Wiley. r
' tive research? In C. K. Kinzer, K. A. Hinchman, 8: D. I. Reinharz, S. (1997). Who am I? The need for a variety
Leu (Eds.),Inquiries in literacy: Theory andpractice of selves in the field. In R. Hertz (Ed.), Reflexiviiy
- ' (pp. 54-68).-Chicago: National Reading Conference. and voice (pp. 3-20). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Lincoln,Y. S. (1'998a). The ethics of teaching qualitative Richardson," L. (1994). Writing: A method of inquiry. In
research. Qualitative Inquiry 4, 305-317.. " N. K. Denzin 8: Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of
Lincoln, Y. S. (1998b). From understanding to action: qualitative research (pp. 516-529). Thousand
} 7

-re
:21‘ 1-
New imperatives, new criteria, new methods for Oaks, CA: Sage. " ~

$
We
.{'il‘»<

You might also like