Motor Awareness in Anosognosia For Hemiplegia - Experiments at Last!

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304

DOI 10.1007/s00221-009-1929-8

R EV IE W

Motor awareness in anosognosia for hemiplegia:


experiments at last!
Paul Mark Jenkinson · Aikaterini Fotopoulou

Received: 23 April 2009 / Accepted: 25 June 2009 / Published online: 11 July 2009
© Springer-Verlag 2009

Abstract Anosognosia for hemiplegia (AHP) is the Introduction


apparent inability to acknowledge contralesional paralysis,
typically following right-hemisphere lesions. Here, we Anosognosia for hemiplegia (AHP) is the apparent inability
review studies that regard AHP as a speciWc deWcit of to acknowledge or recognise contralesional paralysis fol-
motor awareness and explain its symptoms by employing lowing perisylvian lesions, typically to the right hemisphere
an established computational model of motor control. (but see Cocchini et al. 2009). Patients with AHP have a
These accounts propose that AHP arises from a breakdown poorer prognosis than patients with similar motor deWcits
in the monitoring of intended and actual movement. First, but without AHP (Jehkonen et al. 2006; Pedersen et al.
we critically examine physiological and behavioural exper- 1996); unfortunately, there is no known treatment for the
iments, which attempt to provide an account of AHP by condition. The presentation of AHP is not uniform, leading
verifying the presence or absence of motor intentions. We to the suggestion that there may be several sub-types of the
then review more recent experiments that endeavour to disorder (Jehkonen et al. 2000; Marcel et al. 2004). For
empirically address the hitherto unexplored role of motor example, some patients merely fail to appreciate the practi-
intentions and internal representations of movements in cal consequences of a recognised motor impairment, while
AHP patients’ non-veridical (illusory) awareness of move- other AHP patients do not acknowledge their disability
ment. Finally, we consider implications of AHP research despite obvious evidence to the contrary (Bisiach and
for clinical practice and the understanding of motor aware- Geminiani 1991). Unawareness can be speciWc for a given
ness more generally. We conclude that the false experience deWcit, such that patients may fail to acknowledge one
of movement in AHP may provide insight into what occurs problem (e.g. paralysis of the upper limb), but recognise
when the mechanism responsible for monitoring and cor- another (e.g. lower limb paralysis, or some non-motor-
recting signiWcant discrepancies between predicted and related impairment; Berti et al. 1996). Awareness can also
executed actions is impaired. The system seems to continue occur independently at verbal and behavioural levels
to operate by deceiving awareness. (Jehkonen et al. 2006; Marcel et al. 2004; Nimmo-Smith
et al. 2005); for example, AHP patients may admit they
Keywords Anosognosia for hemiplegia · have hemiplegia but attempt to walk, or deny paralysis but
Motor awareness · Motor representations · Intention · remain in bed.
Computational model Another notable feature of AHP is its delusional charac-
ter (Turnbull et al. 2002; Vuilleumier 2004). Some patients
P. M. Jenkinson (&)
with AHP express abnormal beliefs and attitudes towards
Department of Psychology and Mental Health, their paretic limbs, including excessive hatred for the
StaVordshire University, Stoke-on-Trent, UK paretic limb (misoplegia), disownership (asomatognosia),
e-mail: p.m.jenkinson@staVs.ac.uk or attribution of its ownership to someone else (somato-
A. Fotopoulou
paraphrenia). These beliefs are often maintained despite
Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience, repeated questioning, logical arguments, and clear evidence
University College London, London, UK to the contrary, warranting classiWcation as a delusion

123
296 Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304

according to the usual deWnitions (DSM-IV-TR; American Finally, we consider the clinical and theoretical implica-
Psychiatric Association 2000). AHP patients also have tions of these studies, as well as the limitations of this
fewer catastrophic reactions (i.e. episodes of tearfulness approach.
and emotional breakdown), are unduly optimistic, and/or
show emotional indiVerence regarding their condition.
However, AHP patients exhibit an apparently normal range Computational models of the motor system and AHP
of positive and negative emotions (Turnbull et al. 2005,
2002), but tend to direct emotional responses towards Computational models of the motor system propose that the
objects other than their motor deWcit, and respond more central nervous system contains a number of comparators,
slowly to hemiplegia-related words (Nardone et al. 2007). one of which monitors the congruence between intended
These Wndings suggest an implicit awareness of motor deW- and actual movement (Fig. 1). Normally, an internal predic-
cit in AHP. tor, or ‘forward dynamic model’, uses an eVerence copy of
This remarkable condition has been the focus of consid- motor commands to anticipate the expected sensory conse-
erable scientiWc interest over the past few decades; how- quences of an intended movement. Awareness mainly relies
ever, an adequate explanation of AHP has failed to emerge. on these motor predictions, whereas actual sensory feed-
Early studies of AHP were largely descriptive, and used back may not be necessary to construct motor awareness, as
clinical observations to propose that AHP is the result of long as the overall goal of the movement is achieved
inter-hemispheric disconnection (Geschwind 1965), psy- (Fourneret and Jeannerod 1998). Thus, this model implies
chological defence (Weinstein and Kahn 1950, 1955), or a that whenever the motor system makes a sensory prediction
combination of sensory and cognitive deWcits hindering the about an intended movement, awareness that this move-
‘discovery’ of hemiplegia (Levine 1990; Levine et al. ment has been performed may automatically be constructed
1991). However, each of these explanations has failed to (Berti and Pia 2006). When intended movement is per-
withstand subsequent scrutiny when examined directly (see formed as planned, these sensory predictions match actual
Adair et al. 1997; Berti et al. 1996; Marcel et al. 2004; sensory feedback, and this awareness of execution is not
Small and Ellis 1996). AHP also shares a complicated rela- challenged by the system. Errors in the execution of
tionship with unilateral neglect (i.e. a failure to report, intended movements produce a mismatch between the
respond, or orient to novel or meaningful stimuli presented expected and actual sensory feedback, and an error signal at
to the side opposite a brain lesion; Heilman and Valenstein the comparator, which can be used to inform and update
1979). Although the co-occurrence of AHP and neglect is awareness. The results of several studies provide support
common, AHP and neglect double dissociate (Berti et al. for this model: for example, Blakemore and colleagues pro-
2005; Bisiach et al. 1986; Jehkonen et al. 2000, 2006), sug- vide compelling evidence that this model is utilised to dis-
gesting that the two disorders are functionally independent. criminate between self- and externally-produced events in
Typically, accounts of AHP have been limited in healthy individuals (Blakemore et al. 1999, 1998a, b) and
attempting to explain the disorder as the secondary conse- patients with abnormal motor awareness (e.g. delusion of
quence of some concomitant deWcit, without making control; Blakemore et al. 2000; Frith et al. 2000b). Accord-
explicit links to a model of normal motor control, or con- ing to the model, self-produced sensations are normally
ducting experimental investigations (see Berti et al. 2007; attenuated because the forward dynamic model can predict
Vuilleumier 2004 for critical discussions). However, a
promising line of recent research proposes that AHP is a
speciWc disorder of motor control awareness (i.e. awareness
regarding the control of movement) (Berti and Pia 2006;
Berti et al. 2007; Frith et al. 2000a; Pia et al. 2004). In the
remainder of this article, we discuss recent experiments into
AHP, in the context of a well-established framework of
motor control. We begin by summarising a computational
model of motor control (Wolpert 1997), and describing
recent accounts of AHP which utilise this model to provide
a theoretical explanation for the disorder. We then present
existing research that has focused on substantiating these
accounts by verifying whether the intention to move is
present or absent in AHP. Subsequently, we present novel
experimental studies that examine the hitherto unexplored Fig. 1 A simple computational model of the normal motor system
underlying basis of non-veridical awareness in AHP. (from Blakemore et al. 2001)

123
Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304 297

their sensory consequences, while externally-produced representations of intended movement. In contrast, hemi-
sensations are accentuated because they cannot be accurately plegic patients without anosognosia (i.e. nonAHP) possess
predicted. The existence of the comparator has also been preserved awareness about their motor impairment, because
convincingly demonstrated by PET experiments in which they are able to detect when the predicted and actual sen-
healthy volunteers detect discrepancies between intention sory consequences of their movement do not match. Berti
and sensory feedback (Fink et al. 1999). et al. (2007) support this explanation with evidence that the
Several authors have utilised this computational model brain areas involved in monitoring the correspondence
of the motor system (or a similar variant) to propose that between motor commands and sensory feedback (i.e.
AHP is a disorder of movement monitoring, arising from a Brodmann premotor areas 6 and 44; Berti et al. 2005) are
breakdown at various possible locations in the model. damaged in patients with AHP. Furthermore, this hypothesis
Heilman and colleagues (Heilman 1991; Heilman et al. can account for the transient remission of AHP that has
1998) have proposed that AHP arises from a failure to form been observed following stimulation of the vestibular
an intention to move. According to their interpretation, if system via caloric (i.e. cold water) stimulation of the ear
the patient is unable to generate a motor intention, then the (Cappa et al. 1987; Rode et al. 1992). According to this
normally functioning comparator is not primed by the for- explanation, vestibular stimulation may cause a temporary,
ward model to expect movement. A subsequent lack of maximal activation of brain areas that are both aVerents of
movement does not create a mismatch between intended the vestibular system, and also constitute the neural bases
and actual movement, hence patients never discover that of the comparator (i.e. the insula and premotor cortex). This
they have not moved. Thus, according to Heilman, AHP hyperactivation may temporarily restore the spared compo-
occurs when the motor comparator is intact, but motor nents of the comparator and normal motor awareness.
intentions are impaired. Taken together, the above explanations agree that nor-
Frith et al. (2000a) propose an alternative account of mal motor awareness involves the comparison of intended
AHP, which directly contradicts Heilman’s feed-forward and actual sensory information; however, the accounts
hypothesis by suggesting that representations of intended diVer regarding the pattern of intact and impaired processes
movements are preserved in AHP. According to Frith et al., giving rise to AHP. The ability to formulate an intention to
despite an inability to move, patients with AHP are able to move, and the functionality of the comparator are speciWc
compute motor commands and predict the expected sensory points of disagreement among these accounts. Heilman’s
consequences of intended movements. If, therefore, the rep- feed-forward hypothesis of AHP assumes a failure to form
resentation of intended movements is intact in AHP and an intention to move in the context of a normally function-
awareness of initiating a movement is based on these repre- ing comparator. Frith et al. (2000a), and Berti and col-
sentations (Fourneret and Jeannerod 1998), patients with leagues both emphasise that the ability to form motor
AHP would have the normal experience of having initiated intentions is intact in AHP, and that a failure to register dis-
a movement. Furthermore, the erroneous belief that move- crepancy may be due to a malfunctioning comparator (cf.
ment has been executed successfully is maintained because Berti and colleagues) or an absence of suYcient sensory
of a failure to register the discrepancy between predicted feedback (cf. Frith et al.). The last two accounts, therefore,
and actual sensory feedback. Frith et al., speculate that this aim to explain not only why patients are unaware of their
failure may be related to a lack of contrary sensory infor- motor failures (a negative symptom), but also why they
mation about actual movement, since relevant brain areas have a non-veridical awareness of having moved, when no
are damaged or information is neglected. such movement has been produced (a positive symptom).
Berti and colleagues (Berti and Pia 2006; Berti et al. In Heilman’s account, by contrast, it is diYcult to under-
2007) follow Frith and colleagues in proposing that patients stand how the positive symptom of AHP (i.e. non-veridical
with AHP form appropriate representations of their awareness that movement has occurred) can arise if patients
intended movements, but are unaware of the discrepancy are unable to form intentions to move. Some studies con-
between intended and actual movement. However, Berti ducted around the past decade have attempted to provide
and colleagues take a step further and specify that this fail- clariWcation on these issues, principally by trying to estab-
ure to detect discrepancies is the result of damage directly lish the presence of motor intentions in AHP. We now turn
to the comparator mechanism, and not visuospatial neglect to these studies.
(as originally suggested by Frith et al. 2000a). Indeed, the
position taken by Berti and colleagues excludes a possible
causal role of neglect in the failure to register discrepancies Physiological studies of motor intention in AHP
and pathogenesis of AHP. Instead, damage located in the
comparator itself results in AHP patients constructing (non- Gold et al. (1994) provide support for the feed-forward
veridical) motor awareness based entirely on their intact hypothesis using physiological measures of pectoralis

123
298 Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304

majores (pectorale) muscle activity (electromyography, These results suggest that the patient was able to formulate
EMG) in a patient with AHP. When healthy individuals the intention to move and control her forearm muscle
move either their left or right arm, electrical activity and activity, despite an inability to execute overt movement
muscle contraction is registered in the pectorales on both and persistent AHP.
body sides; i.e. muscle activity on one side of the body is A similar EMG study by Berti et al. (2007) conWrms the
accompanied by a simultaneous activation of the same presence of intention for action in AHP. They instructed
muscle on the opposite side. This situation arises due to participants to perform a reaching action with the left or
bilateral corticospinal innervation of the pectorale muscles. right hand, and compared muscle activity in the back of the
On this basis, patients with unilateral stroke and hemiple- neck (i.e. upper trapetius bilaterally) in a patient with AHP,
gia, but without anosognosia, should show bilateral muscle left-hemiplegic control patient without AHP (nonAHP),
activation when asked to move their impaired (paralysed) and neurologically healthy control. An intention to reach
limb if intention is intact. In contrast, according to the feed- with the left or right arm should be accompanied by muscle
forward hypothesis AHP patients asked to perform the activity in the ipsilateral trapetius muscle; therefore, an
same movement should not show bilateral activation, since absence of intention to move the hemiplegic limb in AHP
the intention to move their impaired limb is defective. Con- would predict no activation of the muscle on the hemiplegic
sistent with this, Gold et al. recorded muscle activity in side when asked to reach, whereas a request to reach with
both the left and right pectorales of all controls asked to the right arm should result in muscle activity on the
squeeze a dynamometer with their intact and impaired unaVected side. In contrast, if intention to move were pre-
hand. The patient with AHP did not contract either pecto- served, the AHP patient should show muscle activation on
rales muscle when asked to squeeze the dynamometer with the side that movement is requested, regardless of actual
his paretic hand, while both pectorales muscles contracted ability to move (Berti et al. 2007). Findings supported this
when asked to squeeze with the intact hand. latter prediction; in all participants, including the AHP
Gold et al. (1994) interpret their Wndings as supporting patient, muscle activity was elicited when asked to reach
the feed-forward hypothesis of AHP. However, while a loss with the left arm. Behavioural observations also conWrmed
of intention is a plausible explanation in this case, Berti that the AHP patient was attempting movement of the left
et al. (2007) suggest that the diagnosis of AHP is debatable arm requested by the experimenter, demonstrating intact
in this case. The clinical description of the patient indicated intention to move.
that he was able to squeeze the dynamometer with the
paretic hand, indicating that contralesional hemiplegia was
not complete. Berti et al. (1996) have suggested that study- Behavioural studies of motor intention in AHP
ing unawareness in cases of complete hemiplegia, where
the impossibility of moving the aVected limb can be inde- Whilst physiological investigation of motor intentions are
pendently corroborated, generates more reliable Wndings useful, behavioural observation of intention to move might
than milder cases where some degree of movement remains provide a more direct examination of this ability in AHP.
possible. The extent to which Gold et al.’s Wndings contrib- Adair et al. (1997) induced AHP using intracarotid barbitu-
ute to our understanding of AHP, therefore, depends on the rate injection in patients undergoing preoperative evalua-
diagnostic criteria used to deWne the disorder. Unfortu- tions for intractable epilepsy surgery. After inducing AHP,
nately, it is diYcult to compare across studies, identiWed the formation of an intention to move was manipulated by
commonalities in Wndings, and develop a cohesive under- asking patients to move their paralysed arm, after which
standing of AHP if diagnosis is uncertain. changes in awareness were measured. In three out of the
Further physiological investigations of the feed-forward four cases, attempted movement was associated with an
hypothesis have suggested that patients with AHP might improvement in awareness of hemiplegia. Awareness of
possess intact motor intentions. Hildebrandt and Zieger hemiplegia returned in the Wnal patient after attempted
(1995) report a 59-year-old woman who developed AHP movement was combined with visual feedback regarding
for left-sided hemiplegia after a unilateral right-hemisphere performance. These Wndings support the idea that intentions
haemorrhagic stroke involving the frontal, temporal and are important for motor awareness, and Adair et al. suggest
parietal lobes. Electrodermal activity (i.e. skin conductance that AHP may be related to a motor-intention deWcit. How-
response, SCR) and muscle responses (EMG) were ever, the failure of one of the four patients to regain aware-
recorded while the patient was asked to perform mental ness following an intention to move is not in keeping with
imagery of movement and speciWc tasks involving use of the feed-forward hypothesis. In addition, reversal of AHP
the impaired hand. Changes in SCR and EMG response in one patient only took place when the patient was oVered
were observed from the hemiplegic limb during these pro- visual feedback, thus highlighting the incongruence
cedures, although the left arm always remained hemiplegic. between intention and feedback. This Wnding suggests that

123
Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304 299

the inability to become aware of this incongruence, rather investigated the role of motor intention in the generation of
than the lack of motor intention per se is the critical deWcit illusory movements in AHP (i.e. instances of non-veridical
in AHP. awareness of movement). This was the aim of a recent
Evidence concerning the feed-forward hypothesis is fur- study involving patients with lesions to the territory of the
ther complicated by a single case study on AHP reported by right middle cerebral artery (Fotopoulou et al. 2008); four
Cocchini et al. (2002). They examined patient NS, a 27- hemiplegic patients with (AHP) and four without anosog-
year-old, right handed man with chronic (i.e. >1 year) AHP nosia (nonAHP) were provided with false visual feedback
following severe closed head injury, which resulted in cor- of movement in their left paralysed arm using a prosthetic
tical and subcortical lesions within the frontal lobes bilater- rubber hand. This allowed for realistic, three-dimensional
ally. When asked to lift his hemiplegic arm and leg, NS visual feedback of movement, and deceived patients in to
“tried very hard to comply with the examiner’s request, res- believing the rubber-hand was their own. Crucially, in
olutely contracting the muscles of his left limbs with no some conditions, visual feedback that was incompatible
success” (p. 2032). These muscle contractions provide evi- with the patient’s intentions was given. For instance, in a
dence of the intention to move in a patient with AHP, critical condition, patients were instructed to move their left
which is inconsistent with the proposal of a motor-intention hand, but the prosthetic hand remained still. This condition
deWcit. However, attempted movements temporarily altered essentially mirrored the classic anosognosic scenario within
awareness of hemiplegia in NS. He was apparently sur- an experimentally controlled procedure (cf. Ramachandran
prised by his movement failures, making statements such as 1995). In this way the study was able to examine whether
“oh, dear me, it’s not moving”. As Heilman predicted, this the ability to detect the presence or absence of movement,
Wnding suggests that the formation of an intention to per- based on visual evidence, varied according to whether the
form a speciWc movement can temporarily increase aware- patient had planned to move their limb or not. The key
ness of hemiplegia. Nevertheless, the exact role of motor measure of interest was the patient’s response to a move-
intention and its interaction with sensory and visual feed- ment detection question (i.e. ‘Did your left hand move?’),
back in these temporary increases of awareness is unclear. which required a simple yes/no response. The results
Moreover, it remains unknown why these changes in revealed a selective eVect of motor intention in patients
awareness are not permanent in AHP patients, as well as with AHP; they were more likely than nonAHP controls to
why some patients experience illusory (non-veridical) ignore the visual feedback of a motionless hand and claim
movements when attempting to move (Feinberg et al. 2000; that they moved it when they had the intention to do so
Fotopoulou et al. 2008). A far more controlled and system- (self-generated movement) than when they expected an
atic experimental procedure than that used by Cocchini experimenter to move their own hand (externally-generated
et al. is necessary to reliably address such questions. We movement), or there was no expectation of movement. In
present a Wrst step towards addressing these outstanding other terms, patients with AHP only believed that they had
issues in the next section. moved their hand when they had intended to move it them-
In sum, existing evidence regarding the role of motor selves, while they were not impaired in admitting that the
intentions in AHP does not allow Wrm conclusions. Physio- hand did not move when they had expected someone else to
logical studies of AHP rely on indirect inference about the move it. By contrast, the performance of nonAHP patients
formation of motor intentions via the presence or absence was not inXuenced by these manipulations of intention, and
of an autonomic/muscle response, and have produced they did not claim they moved their hand when the hand
equivocal results. Likewise, studies examining motor inten- remained still.
tions in AHP via patients’ behaviour are inconclusive, as To our knowledge, this is the Wrst direct demonstration
sample sizes are typically very small, procedures are that illusory awareness of action in AHP reXects a domi-
uncontrolled, and the Wndings do not provide clear support nance of motor intention prior to action over visual sensory
for either position. Moreover, veriWcation of the presence information about the actual eVects of movement. Finally,
or absence of the intention to move is not suYcient to this experiment had the advantage of being able to simulta-
explain the non-veridical awareness of action in some AHP neously examine two alternative interpretations of AHP.
patients (see also Berti et al. 2007 for discussion). First, by manipulating visual feedback of movement at a
given spatial location the study has ruled out the eVects of
visuospatial neglect (AHP patients did perceive unexpected
The role of motor intention in AHP: a new study motor ‘failures’ in conditions of externally-generated
of patients’ non-veridical awareness of action movements). Second, because patients were able to detect
such discrepancies, it is unlikely that the Wndings reXect a
Although motor intentions have been the focus of the AHP general deWcit in detecting abnormalities and contradictions
studies reviewed in the above sections, none have directly as Ramachandran (1995) has suggested. These Wndings

123
300 Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304

provide further support to the view that AHP is a speciWc Using this technique, we measured the accuracy of
sensorimotor disorder and not the secondary result of some motor representations in eight patients with AHP, 10
concomitant neurocognitive deWcits. nonAHP hemiplegic control patients, and 22 age-matched
healthy controls. Motor representations for the left (i.e.
paralysed) arm were found to be less accurate in patients
The role of motor representations (motor imagery) than healthy controls; however, accuracy remained high in
in AHP both AHP and nonAHP patients (i.e. there was around 80%
correspondence between prospective and actual move-
The experiment described above supports the idea that ment). Moreover, there was no diVerence in the accuracy of
motor intentions are intact in AHP and are crucial in these motor representations between the two patient groups.
patients’ non-veridical motor awareness. According to In other words, AHP patients are able to represent move-
computational models of the motor system, these motor ments involving their hemiplegic limb to a degree compara-
intentions reXect the planning of ‘to-be-executed’ move- ble with that of patients without anosognosia, thus negating
ments, which are mistaken for actual movement in AHP. It the possibility that impaired motor representations alone
has also been suggested that motor imagery is a form of can account for AHP. This crucial Wnding is consistent with
movement planning, which involves mental representation the suggestion that patients with AHP can form representa-
of movements and an internal simulation of motor activity, tions of intended movements due to spared activity in pre-
but not motor execution (Blakemore and Sirigu 2003; Bux- motor areas (Berti et al. 2005), which are known to be
baum et al. 2005; Jeannerod 2001; Sabaté et al. 2004). As involved in planning movements and motor representations
such, motor imagery provides an ideal means of evaluating (Beltramello et al. 1998; Grèzes and Decety 2001; Roland
the ability to plan movements in AHP. The computational 1993).
account implies that patients with AHP are able to mentally To summarise, the results of the two experiments
represent intended movements involving their hemiplegic described in this section provide support for the idea that
limb. However, until recently, the ability to mentally repre- mental representations of intended movements are present
sent intended movements had not been directly examined in in AHP. These Wndings are consistent with the accounts of
patients with AHP. This ability to generate motor represen- Frith et al. (2000a) and Berti and colleagues (Berti and Pia
tations in AHP was investigated in a recent study by 2006; Berti et al. 2007), rather than the earlier proposal of
Jenkinson et al. (2009b). The experiment utilised an impaired motor intention made by the feed-forward hypoth-
established motor imagery task (Johnson 2000a, b; Johnson esis (Heilman 1991; Heilman et al. 1998). Moreover, the
et al. 2002), which compares how participants prospec- two experiments described above provide the Wrst experi-
tively say they would grasp an object and how they actually mental evidence in support of the claim that these represen-
grasp the same object. SpeciWcally, participants were Wrst tations of intended movements may actually form the basis
presented with the image of a wooden handle painted half- of illusory movements experienced by some AHP patients.
pink half-yellow, and prospectively asked to state where
their hand would be (i.e. which half their thumb would
mostly touch) if they were to reach and grasp the handle. Implications and limitations of motor control
This procedure was repeated with handles at various orien- explanations
tations in random order. Following this, participants actu-
ally grasped the real wooden handle at the same set of The aforementioned Wndings (Fotopoulou et al. 2008;
orientations. The degree of correspondence between the Jenkinson et al. 2009b) in AHP have important implications
prospective and actual grips provides a direct measure of for the model of normal motor control. The model proposes
internal motor representation accuracy. An especially use- that normal motor awareness is dominated by representa-
ful feature of this task is that it can be used to assess motor tions of intended movements, while actual sensory informa-
representations in situations where actual movement is tion is not necessary, nor suYcient for awareness. Indeed,
impossible (e.g. because of hemiplegia). Because the two evidence from neurologically healthy people suggests that
hands are mirror images of each other, the way an individ- when the discrepancy between what one intended to do and
ual chooses to grasp an object with their intact (non-paraly- what one actually did is relatively small (in both temporal
sed) hand provides a near perfect indication of how the and spatial terms), sensory feedback regarding one’s actual
same movement is performed with their paralysed hand (cf. body state has a remarkably limited role in awareness (e.g.
Johnson 2000a, b; Johnson et al. 2002). By applying this Fourneret and Jeannerod 1998). In fact, it is only when the
method to AHP patients, we were able to provide a unique, discrepancy between predicted and actual consequences
behavioural assessment of motor representations for the exceeds a certain threshold that we become aware of errors
hemiplegic arm in AHP. in motor execution (Slachevsky et al. 2003). Given that in

123
Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304 301

many tasks we are able to correct and adjust our move- and bizarre beliefs (e.g. asomatognosia, somatoparaphre-
ments towards achieving a certain goal without awareness nia) that are often a feature of AHP. The observation that
of the need for these adjustments, it has been argued that awareness in AHP may be modiWed when questions are
this deception of awareness (i.e. unawareness of small dis- phrased in an emotionally neutral (i.e. “Are either of your
crepancies) serves the important purpose of allowing Xexi- arms weak?”) versus emotionally ladened way (i.e. “Is it
bility (e.g. fast and eYcient adjustment of movements) in ever naughty? Does it ever not do what you want?”; Marcel
the system (Knoblich and Kircher 2004). On that view, a et al. 2004) is also diYcult to reconcile by purely motor
small degree of unawareness of motor failures is built in to accounts of AHP. Marcel et al. (2004) also note that the
the motor system, possibly as a result of the inherent noise consequences of paralysis in AHP (e.g. falls occurring
(e.g. feedback delay) that is present in most sensorimotor because of attempts to get out of bed), extend beyond sim-
loops (see Wolpert 1997), or because the comparator mech- ple awareness of the immediate movement failure. The
anism may be insensitive to such minor discrepancies for model of motor control might account for abnormal aware-
the reasons outlined above. AHP can therefore be regarded ness about movement failures during their execution; how-
as an exaggerated form of the normally functioning motor ever, additional impairments must be present in AHP for
system. SpeciWcally, AHP seems to represent an instance of patients to be unaware of such adverse incidents, and to
pathological (i.e. lesion-induced) unawareness of large dis- maintain their belief of unimpaired movement.
crepancies between predicted and actual consequences. The In a recent single case study, visual feedback from a
counterintuitive experience of movement in anosognosic video replay resulted in a sudden and permanent reinstate-
patients may provide insight into what occurs when the ment of awareness in a severely anosognosic patient
threshold of signiWcant discrepancy between predicted and (Fotopoulou et al. 2009; see below). Anosognosia was
executed actions is reached, but the mechanism that triggers formally assessed before and after the video using measures of
the conscious processes capable of monitoring and correct- verbal awareness (Berti et al. 1996; Feinberg et al. 2000),
ing such discrepancies is impaired. The system seems to and ratings of the patient’s ability to perform bi-manual/
continue to operate by deceiving awareness. petal tasks (Marcel et al. 2004). The video was Wlmed with
AHP may also provide insight into the neurocognitive the patient’s upper body clearly in view [including her
correlates of our sense of agency (i.e. the sense that ‘I am hemiplegic (left) and intact (right) limbs], and showed the
the one causing an action’), of which there are two domi- patient answering the awareness questions, including gen-
nant views. One approach suggests that agency arises as a eral questions (e.g. “Why are you here?”), speciWc ques-
retrospective means of explaining behaviour (see Wegner tions about the patient’s limbs (“Can you move your left
2003), whilst an alternative proposes that agency could arm?”), and direct confrontation [“Please try reaching my
arise as a consequence of the processes associated with pre- hand (extended in front of the patient) with your left hand?
paring a movement (see Haggard 2005, 2009). Our Wndings Have you done it?”]. During the clip, the patient admitted
are consistent with the latter stance, and the suggestion that to having a stroke, but claimed she had improved since.
the experience of executing a movement arises from activ- When asked the confrontation question, she incorrectly
ity in brain areas responsible for conscious intention and reached with her right arm then remained silent. When
predicted consequences (Desmurget et al. 2009). prompted further, the patient acknowledged she had used
It should be noted, however, that several other observa- her right hand, but did nothing when asked if she could do
tions in AHP cannot be accounted for by referring only to the task with her left hand. Interestingly, the only observ-
the computational model of motor control. The breakdown able change in the patient’s cognitive and emotional proWle
of a single motor comparator cannot adequately explain the after the reinstatement of awareness was the substantial
reported speciWcity of AHP; for example, patients who are increase in self-reported negative mood. This observation
aware of one motor impairment (e.g. lower limb paralysis) also tallied with the patient’s own subjective awareness into
but not another (e.g. upper limb paralysis) (Berti et al the reasons for her anosognosia (after recovery). She stated
1998; Marcel et al. 2004). However, one possible way to that during the period of her unawareness she kept hoping
account for these dissociations is the existence of multiple she could move. This suggests that emotional factors may
comparators, each responsible for selective monitoring of a have a role in AHP. However, it remains to be empirically
given function. A growing body of work suggests that this tested whether such emotional factors play a secondary role
monitoring might even be implemented by the same neural in maintaining the unawareness beliefs (a form of psycho-
networks responsible for controlling the function that has to genic denial superimposed on sensorimotor deWcits), or
be monitored (Berti et al. 2005; Spinazzola et al. 2008). whether they interact at some neurological level with the
Much more problematic for explanations that refer only deWcits that cause motor failures and motor unawareness
to the motor system are the abnormal emotional attitudes (see Fotopoulou 2009; Vuilleumier 2004 for discussion on
(e.g. emotional indiVerence, or hatred of the paretic limb) this point).

123
302 Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304

It has been suggested that the heterogeneous presenta- between the eVects of Wrst and third person perspective as
tion of AHP reXects the existence of various subtypes of the viewed ‘online’ could not be determined, since awareness
disorder (Jehkonen et al. 2000; Marcel et al. 2004). More- recovered completely and permanently following observa-
over, the diVerent presentations of AHP might reXect the tion of the video. Thus, further studies are needed to
distinct contribution of various deWcits. Therefore, a com- explore the role of Wrst and third person viewpoints, both
prehensive understanding of AHP may rest in the combina- online and oZine, in AHP.
tion of several, existing theories. For example, the
delusional aspects of AHP might reXect the breakdown of
more general mechanisms involved in other delusional Implications for rehabilitation
beliefs. For instance, delusions of control in schizophrenia
have been linked to deWcits in source and reality monitoring The above Wndings might be used to inform clinical prac-
(i.e. processes that enable one to discriminate between fan- tice in a number of ways. A growing body of research sug-
tasy and reality) (Anselmetti et al. 2007; Brébion et al. gests that visual feedback (mirror therapy) and mental
2002; Johnson 1991; Johnson et al. 1993; Keefe 1998). rehearsal of movement (i.e. repetition and practice of
Consistent with this, Venneri and Shanks (2004) have spec- movements with the impaired limb(s) using imagination),
ulated a link between reality monitoring and AHP, and a are eVective means of motor rehabilitation after stroke (de
recent study of reality monitoring in AHP suggests a Vries and Mulder 2007; Dunsky et al. 2008; Stevens and
tendency to attribute information to an external source in Phillips Stoykov 2003; Yue and Cole 1992). Likewise,
anosognosic patients (Jenkinson et al. 2009a). Further these strategies might be a useful means of rehabilitating
research is required to elucidate the exact nature and contri- motor function in AHP. Third-person perspective on one’s
bution of reality monitoring impairments in the pathogenesis deWcits (feedback from mirrors and video replays) may turn
of AHP. out to be important in facilitating motor awareness, as the
Marcel et al. (2004) also make the interesting observa- previously described single case study suggests (Fotopoulou
tion that AHP patients who fail to recognise paralysis when et al. 2009). In addition, the study of motor representations
questioned about their own abilities (e.g. “in your present in AHP (Jenkinson et al. 2009b), demonstrated that
state how well, compared with your normal ability, can you despite an inability to execute movements with the hemi-
walk?”), are able to recognise the same paralysis attributed plegic limb, the ability to generate an internal representa-
to another person (e.g. asked “if I was in your present state tion of a speciWc action is relatively preserved. Therefore, it
how well would I be able to walk compared with my usual may be possible for patients with AHP to use mental
ability”). Notably, both questions require explicit knowl- rehearsal as a rehabilitation strategy, since the underlying
edge of the patient’s own motor ability; therefore, in terms functional mechanisms are relatively preserved. This sug-
of the computational model of motor control, the same gestion is tentative, and future research might proWtably
comparison processes should be engaged to give both assess the eVectiveness of mental rehearsal in the rehabili-
answers. However, the greater awareness of paralysis dem- tation of motor function in AHP. Applying mental rehearsal
onstrated when AHP patients respond to questions attribut- to patients with AHP would have several advantages:
ing impairment to another person, suggests a dissociation awareness of actual ability to perform the imagined move-
within awareness according to the manner or viewpoint of ment is not necessary; therefore, the technique can be
the question (i.e. Wrst vs. third person perspective). This implemented acutely post-stroke, when awareness is
dissociation has been examined more recently by the afore- impaired and physical practice is hindered by weakness and
mentioned study, in which an AHP patient regained normal fatigability. Additionally, mental rehearsal training is
awareness of hemiplegia following observation of her low-cost, low-risk, and less labour-intensive than physical
paralysis in a video replay (Fotopoulou et al. 2009). The practice.
video allowed the patient to observe her motor impairment
‘from the outside’ (i.e. from a third person perspective) and
‘oZine’ (i.e. at a time later than the actual attempt to exe- Conclusions
cute movement). The authors suggest that these conditions
may have allowed the patient to update her body represen- In this paper we reviewed experiments that examine AHP
tation when the ability to do so in the Wrst-person is in the context of an established computation model of the
impaired by brain damage. In terms of the computational motor system. We argued that previous research, which
model of motor control, judgements of ability made oZine aimed to establish the presence or absence of an intention to
might facilitate awareness because the intention to move, move in AHP, does not account for the positive symptom
which usually produces non-veridical awareness (as of non-veridical awareness of movement. We therefore
described above), is no longer present. A direct comparison reviewed novel experiments, which suggest that AHP patients

123
Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304 303

are still able to mentally represent movements of their Blakemore SJ, Rees G, Frith CD (1998a) How do we predict the
plegic arm, and that their non-veridical awareness of consequences of our actions? A functional imaging study. Neuro-
psychologia 36:521–529
movement seems to stem from the dominance of such rep- Blakemore SJ, Wolpert DM, Frith CD (1998b) Central cancellation of
resentations about the intention to move over sensory infor- self-produced tickle sensation. Nat Neurosci 1:635–640
mation about the actual eVects of movement. Findings of Blakemore SJ, Frith CD, Wolpert DM (1999) Spatio-temporal predic-
these experiments are consistent with an established com- tion modulates the perception of self-produced stimuli. J Cogn
Neurosci 11:551–559
putational model of motor control. However, sensorimotor Blakemore SJ, Smith J, Steel R, Johnstone EC, Frith CD (2000) The
accounts of AHP cannot fully account for all aspects of the perception of self-produced sensory stimuli in patients with audi-
disorder, such as the observed speciWcity, emotional and tory hallucinations and passivity experiences: evidence for a
delusional features. Future studies in AHP patients are breakdown in self-monitoring. Psychol Med 30:1131–1139
Blakemore SJ, Frith CD, Wolpert DM (2001) The cerebellum is in-
needed to specify how motor awareness (as described by volved in predicting the sensory consequences of action. Neuro-
the model of motor control) interfaces with other cognitive report 12:1879–1884
processes, such as source/reality monitoring, emotional Brébion G, Gorman JM, Amador X, Malaspina D, Sharif Z (2002)
processing and body representations. These ongoing studies Source monitoring impairments in schizophrenia: characterisa-
tion and associations with positive and negative symptomatology.
into AHP are crucial, as they can inform our knowledge of Psychiatry Res 112:27–39
normal self-awareness, and may generate new rehabilita- Buxbaum LJ, Johnson-Frey SH, Bartlett-Williams M (2005) DeWcient
tion strategies for AHP patients. internal models for planning hand-object interactions in apraxia.
Neuropsychologia 43:917–929
Cappa S, Sterzi R, Vallar G, Bisiach E (1987) Remission of hemine-
glect and anosognosia during vestibular stimulation. Neuropsych-
References ologia 25(5):775–782
Cocchini G, Beschin N, Della Sala S (2002) Chronic anosognosia:
Adair JC, Schwartz RL, Na DL, Fennell E, Gilmore RL, Heilman KM a case report and theoretical account. Neuropsychologia
(1997) Anosognosia: examining the disconnection hypothesis. 40(12):2030–2038
J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry 63:798–800 Cocchini G, Beschin N, Cameron A, Fotopoulou A, Della Sala S
American Psychiatric Association (2000) Diagnostic and statistical (2009) Anosognosia for motor impairment following left brain
manual of mental disorders, 4th edn, text revision (DSM-IV-TR). damage. Neuropsychology 23(2):223–230
American Psychiatric Association, Washington, DC de Vries S, Mulder T (2007) Motor imagery and stroke rehabilitation:
Anselmetti S, Cavallaro R, Sechi M, Angelone SM, Ermoli E, Cocchi a critical discussion. J Rehabil Med 39:5–13
F et al (2007) Psychopathological and neuropsychological corre- Desmurget M, Reilly KT, Richard N, Szathmari A, Mottolese C, Sirigu
lates of source monitoring impairment in schizophrenia. Psychia- A (2009) Movement intention after parietal cortex stimulation in
try Res 150:51–59 humans. Science 324:811–813
Beltramello A, Cerini R, Puppini G, El-Dalati G, Viola S, Martone E Dunsky A, Dickstein R, Marcovitz E, Levy S, Deutsch J (2008) Home-
et al (1998) Motor representation of the hand in the human cortex: based motor imagery training for gait rehabilitation of people
an f-MRI study with a conventional 1.5 T clinical unit. Ital J Neu- with chronic poststroke hemiparesis. Arch Phys Med Rehabil
rol Sci 19:277–284 89:1580–1588
Berti A, Pia L (2006) Understanding motor awareness through normal Feinberg TE, Roane DM, Ali J (2000) Illusory limb movements in ano-
and pathological behavior. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 15(5):245–250 sognosia for hemiplegia. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry 68:511–
Berti A, Làdavas E, Della Corte M (1996) Anosognosia for hemiple- 513
gia, neglect dyslexia, and drawing neglect: clinical Wndings and Fink GR, Marshall JC, Halligan PW, Frith CD, Driver J, Frackowiak
theoretical considerations. J Int Neuropsychol Soc 2:426–440 RSJ et al (1999) The neural consequences of conXict between
Berti A, Làdavas E, Stracciari A, Giannarelli C, Ossola A (1998) Ano- intention and the senses. Brain 122:497–512
sognosia for motor impairment and dissociations with patients’ Fotopoulou A (2009) The aVective neuropsychology of confabulation
evaluation of the disorder: theoretical considerations. Cogn Neu- and delusion. Cogn Neuropsychiatry (in press)
ropsychiatry 3(1):21–44 Fotopoulou A, Tsakiris M, Haggard P, Vagopoulou A, Rudd A,
Berti A, Bottini G, Gandola M, Pia L, Smania N, Stracciari A et al Kopelman M (2008) The role of motor intention in motor aware-
(2005) Shared cortical anatomy for motor awareness and motor ness: an experimental study on anosognosia for hemiplegia. Brain
control. Science 309:488–491 131:3432–3442
Berti A, Spinazzola L, Pia L, RabuVetti M, Haggard P, Rossetti Y et al Fotopoulou A, Rudd A, Holmes P, Kopelman M (2009) Self-observa-
(2007) Motor awareness and motor intention in anosognosia for tion reinstated motor awareness in anosognosia for hemiplegia.
hemiplegia. In: Sensorimotor foundations of higher cognition. Neuropsychologia 47:1256–1260
Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 163–181 Fourneret P, Jeannerod M (1998) Limited conscious monitoring of
Bisiach E, Geminiani G (1991) Anosognosia related to hemiplegia and motor performance in normal subjects. Neuropsychologia
hemianopia. In: Prigatano GP, Schacter DL (eds) Awareness of 36:1133–1140
deWcit after brain injury: clinical and theoretical issues. Oxford Frith CD, Blakemore SJ, Wolpert DM (2000a) Abnormalities in the
University Press, New York, pp 17–39 awareness and control of action. Philos Trans R Soc Lond Biol
Bisiach E, Vallar G, Perani D, Papagno C, Berti A (1986) Unawareness Sci 355:1771–1788
of disease following lesions of the right hemisphere: anosognosia Frith CD, Blakemore SJ, Wolpert DM (2000b) Explaining the symp-
for hemiplegia and anosognosia for hemianopia. Neuropsycholo- toms of schizophrenia: abnormalities in the awareness of action.
gia 24:471–482 Brain Res Rev 31:357–363
Blakemore SJ, Sirigu A (2003) Action prediction in the cerebellum and Geschwind N (1965) Disconnexion syndromes in animals and man.
in the parietal lobe. Exp Brain Res 153:239–245 Brain 88:237–294

123
304 Exp Brain Res (2010) 204:295–304

Gold M, Adair JC, Jacobs DH, Heilman KM (1994) Anosognosia for Levine DN, Calvanio R, Rinn WE (1991) The pathogenesis of anosog-
hemiplegia: an electrophysiologic investigation of the feed-for- nosia for hemiplegia. Neurology 41:1770–1781
ward hypothesis. Neurology 44:1804–1808 Marcel AJ, Tegnér R, Nimmo-Smith I (2004) Anosognosia for plegia:
Grèzes J, Decety J (2001) Functional anatomy of execution, mental speciWcity, extension, partiality and disunity of bodily awareness.
simulation, observation and verb generation of actions: a meta- Cortex 40:19–40
analysis. Hum Brain Map 12:1–19 Nardone IB, Ward R, Fotopoulou A, Turnbull OH (2007) Attention
Haggard P (2005) Conscious intention and motor cognition. Trends and emotion in anosognosia: evidence of implicit awareness and
Cogn Sci 9:290–295 repression? Neurocase 13(5):438–445
Haggard P (2009) The sources of human volition. Science 324:731– Nimmo-Smith I, Marcel AJ, Tegnér R (2005) A diagnostic test of
733 unawareness of bilateral motor task abilities in anosognosia for
Heilman KM (1991) Anosognosia: possible neuropsychological mech- hemiplegia. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry 76:1167–1169
anisms. In: Prigatano GP, Schacter DL (eds) Awareness of deWcit Pedersen PM, Jørgensen HS, Nakayama H, Raaschou HO, Olsen TS
after brain injury: clinical and theoretical issues. Oxford Univer- (1996) Frequency, determinants, and consequences of anosogno-
sity Press, New York, pp 53–62 sia in acute stroke. J Neurol Rehabil 10:243–250
Heilman KM, Valenstein E (1979) Mechanisms underlying hemispa- Pia L, Neppi-Modona M, Ricci R, Berti A (2004) The anatomy of ano-
tial neglect. Ann Neurol 5:166–170 sognosia for hemiplegia: a meta-analysis. Cortex 40:367–377
Heilman KM, Barrett AM, Adair JC (1998) Possible mechanisms of Ramachandran VS (1995) Anosognosia in parietal lobe syndrome.
anosognosia: a defect in self-awareness. Philos Trans R Soc Lond Conscious Cogn 4:22–51
Biol Sci 353:1903–1909 Rode G, Charles N, Perenin MT, Vighetto A, Trillet M, Aimard G
Hildebrandt H, Zieger A (1995) Unconscious activation of motor re- (1992) Partial remission of hemiplegia and somatoparaphrenia
sponses in a hemiplegic patient with anosognosia and neglect. Eur through vestibular stimulation in a case of unilateral neglect.
Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci 246:53–59 Cortex 28:203–208
Jeannerod M (2001) Neural simulation of action: a unifying mecha- Roland PE (1993) Brain activation. Wiley-Liss, New York
nism for motor cognition. Neuroimage 14:S103–S109 Sabaté M, González B, Rodríguez M (2004) Brain lateralization of mo-
Jehkonen M, Ahonen JP, Dastidar P, Laippala P, Vilkki J (2000) tor imagery: motor planning asymmetry as a cause of movement
Unawareness of deWcits after right hemisphere stroke: double-dis- lateralization. Neuropsychologia 42:1041–1049
sociations of anosognosias. Acta Neurol Scand 102:378–384 Slachevsky A, Pillon B, Fourneret P, Reni L, Levy R, Jeannerod M
Jehkonen M, Laihosalo M, Kettunen J (2006) Anosognosia after et al (2003) The prefrontal cortex and conscious monitoring of
stroke: assessment, occurrence, subtypes and impact on func- action: an experimental study. Neuropsychologia 41:655–665
tional outcome reviewed. Acta Neurol Scand 114:293–306 Small M, Ellis S (1996) Denial of hemiplegia: an investigation into the
Jenkinson PM, Edelstyn NMJ, Drakeford JL, Ellis SJ (2009a) Reality theories of causation. Eur Neurol 36:353–363
monitoring in anosognosia for hemiplegia. Conscious Cogn Spinazzola L, Pia L, Folegatti A, Marchetti, Berti A (2008) Modular
18:458–470 structure of awareness for sensorimotor disorders: evidence from
Jenkinson PM, Edelstyn NMJ, Ellis SJ (2009b) Imagining the impos- anosognosia for hemiplegia and anosognosia for hemianaesthe-
sible: motor representations in anosognosia for hemiplegia. Neu- sia. Neuropsychologia 46:915–926
ropsychologia 47:481–488 Stevens JA, Phillips Stoykov ME (2003) Using motor imagery in the
Johnson MK (1991) Reality monitoring: evidence from confabulation rehabilitation of hemiparesis. Arch Phys Med Rehabil 84:1090–
in organic brain disease patients. In: Prigatano GP, Schacter DL 1092
(eds) Awareness of deWcit after brain injury: clinical and theoret- Turnbull OH, Jones K, Reed-Screen J (2002) Implicit awareness of
ical issues. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 176–197 deWcit in anosognosia? An emotion-based account of denial of
Johnson SH (2000a) Imagining the impossible: Intact motor represen- deWcit. Neuropsychoanalysis 4:69–86
tations in hemiplegics. Neuroreport 11(4):729–732 Turnbull OH, Evans CEY, Owen V (2005) Negative emotions and
Johnson SH (2000b) Thinking ahead: the case for motor imagery in anosognosia. Cortex 41:67–75
prospective judgements of prehension. Cognition 74:33–70 Venneri A, Shanks MF (2004) Belief and awareness: reXections on a
Johnson MK, Hashtroudi S, Lindsay DS (1993) Source monitoring. case of persistent anosognosia. Neuropsychologia 42:230–238
Psychol Bull 114:3–28 Vuilleumier P (2004) Anosognosia: the neurology of beliefs and
Johnson SH, Sprehn G, Saykin AJ (2002) Intact motor imagery in uncertainties. Cortex 40:9–17
chronic upper limb hemiplegics: evidence for activity-indepen- Wegner DM (2003) The mind’s best trick: how we experience con-
dent action representations. J Cogn Neurosci 14:841–852 scious will. Trends Cogn Sci 7:65–69
Keefe RSE (1998) The neurobiology of disturbances of the self: auton- Weinstein EA, Kahn RL (1950) The syndrome of anosognosia. Arch
oetic agnosia in schizophrenia. In: Amador XF, David AS (eds) Neurol Psychiatry 64:772–779
Insight and psychosis. Oxford University Press, New York, pp Weinstein EA, Kahn RL (1955) Denial of illness: symbolic and phys-
142–173 iological aspects. Charles C. Thomas, SpringWeld, IL
Knoblich G, Kircher TTJ (2004) Deceiving oneself about being in con- Wolpert DM (1997) Computational models of motor control. Trends
trol: conscious detection of changes in visuomotor coupling. Cogn Sci 1(6):209–216
J Exp Psychol Hum Percept Perform 30(657):666 Yue G, Cole KJ (1992) Strength increases from the motor program:
Levine DN (1990) Unawareness of visual and sensorimotor defects: comparison of training with maximal voluntary and imagined
a hypothesis. Brain Cogn 13:233–281 muscle contractions. J Neurophysiol 67(5):1114–1122

123

You might also like