Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

The Behavior Analyst 1991, 14, 1-13 No.

1 (Spring)

Humble Behaviorism
Allen Neuringer
Reed College
Key words: behavioral subject-matter, behavioral methods, behavioral theory, personal characteristics
of behavioral scientists, humility, science

If behaviorists were more humble, their lapping categories, both areas where be-
effectiveness as scientists would increase. haviorists' positions are humble and those
An explicitly humble behaviorism could where greater humility might be nur-
reduce the threat of behavioral research tured. The categories are: (1) subject-
perceived by many in our society; melio- matter of contemporary behavioral re-
rate fights among sub-disciplines of psy- search, (2) methods used in such research,
chology, so that adversaries might work (3) theoretical positions held by contem-
together toward common goals, and en- porary behaviorists, and (4) personal
courage researchers to identify and admit characteristics of the behavioral scientist.
their own ignorance and error, thereby My aim is not to exhaust the topic but
motivating research. This hypothesis is to motivate consideration of humility as
not meant as criticism specifically of be- one goal for behavioral researchers. "Hu-
haviorists, for some of my behavioral mility" is used broadly to imply tenta-
colleagues are among the most humble tiveness of theoretical and methodolog-
of people, others not, as is the case in all ical positions, willingness to consider
fields. Nor is behavioral science, or sci- alternative views, support for diversity,
ence generally, unusually arrogant. Sci- openness to criticism-in brief, a scien-
ence depends upon the continual check- tific stance that all knowledge is provi-
ing of one scientist's work by others. Most sional and that one's most deeply held
scientists therefore must be somewhat positions must continually be reconsid-
humble, for often their research is shown ered.
to be insufficient and their conclusions
challenged. At the same time, positions SUBJECT MATTER
can be strongly held, and activities in-
volved in testing and disproving can be Behavioral Classes and Sub-Classes
aggressive and destructive. Arrogance and Behaviorists study behaviors of organ-
humility in science coexist. The present isms. The plural, behaviors, connotes dif-
hypothesis, however, is that humility will ferences among behavioral classes, such
prove to be functional. as unconditioned, respondent, and op-
This paper discusses, under four over- erant (Hearst, 1975; Hineline, 1986).
Generalizations about one class may not
I dedicate this paper to the memory of B. F. hold true for another. Healthy debate
Skinner, my teacher and friend. He may be re- continues as to how best to cut the be-
sponsible for many of my motivations, but not my havioral pie, for example, does respon-
errors. dent behavior differ from operant and, if
A version of the paper was presented to the As- so, how?
sociation for Behavior Analysis, Philadelphia, Pa.,
in May, 1988. The plural also implies that instances
Martha Neuringer, Meg Wilson, Sigrid Glenn and within a given behavioral class may fur-
four anonymous reviewers provided very helpful ther be divided into functional sub-class-
critical comments. Preparation of this manuscript es. For example, Shettleworth (1975)
was partly supported by NSF grant #BNS-8707992. showed that frequencies of some oper-
Reprints may be obtained from the author, Psy-
chology Department, Reed College, Portland, Or- ant-like behaviors, such as grooming, may
egon 97202. be unaffected by food presented contin-
1
2 ALLEN NEURINGER

gent upon the behaviors; whereas, fre- among these phenomena are sufficient
quencies of other operants, such as lever- that they not be lumped together. For
pressing, may readily be increased by example, some behaviorists maintain that
contingent food. As another example, imagining is a covert response to an un-
Garcia, Hankins, and Rusniak (1974) specified stimulus; we imagine the absent
showed that some behaviors are con- box just as we see the present box. Seeing
trolled by events long delayed, up to and imagining are both responses, the dif-
hours, when illness follows the drinking ference being the presence or absence of
of a novel solution; whereas, other be- a specifiable current external stimulus.
haviors are unaffected by events delayed Others who study imagery argue, how-
more than a few seconds (however, see ever, that seeing and imagining may be
Lattal & Gleeson, 1990). Biological pre- sufficiently different to require placement
paredness describes such within-class dif- of the two into different sub-classes.
ferences. Readers probably accept the Necker cubes reverse when looked at but
implied distinctions, whether or not they do not reverse when imagined (see
use that term. Chambers & Reisberg, 1985). Similarly,
thinking, a covert activity, and speaking,
Overt and Covert an overt one, may be sufficiently different
in terms of their dynamics and causes to
Yet behaviorists are criticized for re- require differential treatment and ter-
ducing all meaningful psychological phe- minology. Behaviorists presumably
nomena to a single class, that ofbehavior. would accept important differences in the
Why, we are asked, do we ignore mind, classes of overt and covert, if these were
psyche, and the contents of conscious- demonstrated, just as they presently ac-
ness? In fact, the criticism has two horns. cept different classes within the overt do-
First, we are accused of including too main. Until the evidence is in, humble
much under "behavior." Some behav- agnosticism may be more functional than
iorists view thought, perception, imagi- adherence to any position.
nation, and emotion as behavioral phe- The second horn ofthe criticism is that
nomena. The rationale for so doing is some behaviorists appear to relegate the
that each of these involves an actively causal role of covert behaviors to second-
changing organism under the control of class status. Radical behaviorists (a form
prior and consequent environmental of behaviorism identified with B. F. Skin-
events. An active-responder model gen- ner and colleagues) accept and write about
erates explanations of "mental" phe- such phenomena as feelings and thoughts,
nomena analogous to those for motoric but often imply that they are less impor-
behaviors. Together with most of our tant for understanding overt behaviors
contemporaries in other fields of psy- than are the initiating environmental
chology, we contrast our view of percep- events. What is the empirical evidence,
tion as activity with older views of per- however, for maintaining that feelings,
ception as passive reception. thoughts, and images have little or no
According to critics, however, by clas- independent causal role in the generation
sifying both mental and physical under of overt behaviors, or that they play only
the single rubric of "behavior," we weak- a "collateral" role? These "mental"
en the term. Meaning is based on dis- events are often closer in time to overt
crimination of differences: If everything behavior than the initiating environmen-
is "x," then "x" is meaningless. Our bur- tal events and thus may serve as better
den is to distinguish the class of events predictors. When I attempt to predict my
called "behavior" from other classes, and own overt behaviors, covert states often
to show why it is functional to hypoth- provide helpful information: Do I have
esize similarities between overt (or a bad headache? Have I been ruminating
"physical") and covert (or "mental") about a particular situation? Am I antic-
"behaviors." At the same time, we must ipating a friend's arrival? Am I de-
consider the possibility that differences pressed? Covert and overt behaviors may
HUMBLE BEHAVIORISM 3
be of the same class or they may differ; discriminative responses, in the case of
covert behaviors may play redundant or non-human subjects, concerning subjec-
collateral roles in the generation of overt tive states? An analogous situation might
behaviors, or they may play significant be the following: a scientist and subject
and independent roles. These are hy- both have learned to respond with the
potheses to be tested. word "red" to a red light and "green" to
The distinctions between covert and a green one. One of the two lights is ran-
overt stimuli are also problematic and domly illuminated, the order being con-
must be carefully drawn (Skinner, 1953). trolled by a process not under direct con-
The lever press may be taken as an in- trol of the scientist. The scientist asks the
stance of an overt stimulus; different peo- subject, "What color is that?" and when
ple can observe it and therefore it serves the subject answers, the scientist looks at
as a discriminative stimulus for saying, the color to confirm whether the answer
"That was a lever press." Lever presses was correct or not. Now imagine a screen
are said to be "objective." But the quint- placed between scientist and subject.
essential private phenomenon, pain, may Again, one of the two lights, out of sight
also provide "objective" data. Imagine of the scientist but next to the subject, is
twelve people in a room and one sud- randomly selected for illumination. The
denly says "Ow, I have a tooth ache." subject emits a verbal response, "red" or
Presumably, she is tacting a covert event. "green." The scientist need not devalue
But now image a dentist's drill with twelve such data because she or he cannot also
identical tentacles, each containing a drill. see the color.
A dentist-ex-machina says "pain" and si-
multaneously puts the drill to a tooth in Concurrent Behavior Systems
each of the twelve individuals' mouths.
The drill is removed and the dentist says Also implied by the behaviors of or-
"no more pain." In this situation, pain ganisms is that the behavior of an indi-
is as objective (or, if you prefer, subjec- vidual may be viewed as a combination
tive) as the lever-press. Skinner has not- of many different, concurrently acting be-
ed, correctly I believe, that a more helpful havior sub-systems. I improvise on the
distinction is between events that occur piano, keep the beat with my foot, hum
within the skin of an organism versus an antiphonal melody, read the news-
without. That can be rephrased: one can paper, and make funny faces-all of these
be said to respond to an "objective" occurring concurrently. Other examples
stimulus if the response is consistent with abound: we walk, talk, hear, see, and
those emitted by other observers. One scratch ourselves simultaneously. Each
way to affect such consistency is for a sub-behavior may serve as part of the
number of individuals to receive dis- controlling environment for other sub-
crimination training until all are emitting behaviors-serve as discriminative cues
analogous responses. Such discrimina- and reinforcers, or mediate other func-
tion training may be possible with respect tions. Thoughts may influence actions,
to "having an intention or goal," "being feelings influence thoughts, one type of
worried," and "feeling depressed," as well action influence other concurrently emit-
as other so-called "private states," and ted actions, and so forth. For example,
therefore discriminative responses to concurrent physical movement has been
these "subjective" states would be useful reported to increase the frequency of
in an experimental analysis of behavior. "good ideas" (Neuringer, 1981).
There is another problem, however. Cognitive behavior therapy is another
Often the behavior analyst is not in a example: Thoughts or self-statements in-
position to experience the conditions fluence overt acts. Imagine yourself
leading to the purported emotion, drinking wine and then vomiting; you
thought, rumination, feeling, or the like. may be less likely to actually drink wine
Can behaviorists utilize verbal reports, (Cautela, 1967). Say to yourself, "I can
in the case of human subjects, or other answer these test questions, relax, take
4 ALLEN NEURINGER

your time, don't freak out," and you may ever having been previously experienced
then be more likely to complete the exam or reinforced. It is indeed intriguing, as
successfully (Meichenbaum, 1977). psycholinguists point out, that children
"Contingency thinking" may also influ- learn correct usages (or, at some stages,
ence overt behaviors. If I want to de- systematically incorrect usages) if there
crease candy eating, I say to myself at the is no direct reinforcement (see, however,
point oftemptation, "If I eat a candy-bar Moerk, 1983). With psycholinguists, de-
now, that will increase the probability that velopmental psychologists, and cognitive
I eat another one tomorrow. Do I want psychologists, behaviorists are awed by
to do that to myself?" To increase my and applaud the successes of children in
physical activity, I say, "If I don't exer- learning language. But behaviorists note
cise today, that will cause me not to ex- that other common instrumental acts,
ercise tomorrow and the next day-do I such as lever pressing and keypecking,
want that to happen?" Thinking such demonstrate possibly analogous re-
thoughts appears to influence my overt sponse induction and stimulus general-
behaviors. A variant of contingency ization. Rats trained on one type of op-
thinking is simply to ask myself, "If I do erandum will respond appropriately to
such and such behavior, then what might others. Pigeons trained to respond to pro-
the consequences be?" Prior to turning jections ofslides with people in them will
on the television, rising from my desk respond appropriately to pictures of peo-
while writing a paper, or answering a ple they have never before seen (Herm-
question sarcastically, I sometimes in- stein, 1984). In an extension of this work,
quire briefly as to the possible conse- after pigeons were trained to respond on
quences of the act. The covert query, "If one key to music by Bach and another
this behavior-then what consequence?" key to music by Stravinsky, they gener-
again seems to influence my behaviors. alized in ways analogous to people: they
Without controlled study, I do not know responded on the Bach key when probe
whether contingency thinking is, in fact, pieces by Telemann or Buxtehude were
effective or whether its effects are due to introduced, and responded on the Stra-
an interruption of the behavioral stream, vinsky key when music by Eliot Carter
or to some other confounding variable. was played (Porter & Neuringer, 1984).
Contingency thinking is offered as a hy- We applaud these behavioral accom-
pothesis. Note, however, that hypotheses plishments of pigeons as well as the lin-
concerning covert events can readily be guistic accomplishments of children.
stated in a way that may lead to inde- Another aspect of language that, ac-
pendent testing: if the reader engages in cording to non-behaviorists, sets it apart,
contingency thinking, then, according to and therefore sets humans apart from
the present hypothesis, probabilities of other species, is the infinite variability of
overt behaviors will change. That hy- sentences, the fact that novel sentences
pothesis can be tested and the results re- are continually generated and under-
ported to the community (see, for anoth- stood, sentences that may never before
er example, Glenn & Hughes, 1978). have been uttered or heard. How is that
possible, it is asked, of conditioned be-
Verbal Behavior havior? Here, too, the behaviorist at-
tempts to show how. There is variability
The behaviorist acknowledges differ- in all operant behavior. Rats are rein-
ences between verbal and non-verbal be- forced for pressing levers, but no two re-
haviors, but at the same time, hypothe- sponses are identical. We learn to walk
sizes that language has much in common in a particular way, but each of us can
with other instrumental activities (Skin- now walk in unpredictable fashion. An-
ner, 1957). One attribute that sets lan- imals, such as porpoises, have been re-
guage apart, according to many in the inforced explicitly for generating novel
non-behavioral community, is that ap- behaviors (Pryor, Haag, & O'Reilly,
propriate instances are generated without 1969). Thus, a defining attribute of all
HUMBLE BEHAVIORISM 5

instrumental behavior may be its great to think about a "fun" event during the
potential variability and consequent gen- wait period, and a second group to think
erativity. about a "sad" event. The "fun" thinking
children waited significantly longer than
Scientific Language and Translation the "sad" thinkers. Grosch and Neurin-
ger (1981) trained pigeons under analo-
The behaviorists' interest in language gous conditions where pecking a re-
extends to their own scientific language, sponse key caused immediate
and serious attempts are made to emit presentation of less-preferred food,
language that is based on empirical re- whereas waiting caused eventual access
lationships, and to stay close to the ob- to a more-preferred food. An overhead
served data (Hineline, 1980). There has light, the "think fun" stimulus, had pre-
arisen, however, a correlated tendency to viously been correlated with freely pre-
maintain that "our" language is better sented food; a different overhead stim-
than others, for example, the language of ulus, "think sad," had been correlated
philosophers, Freudian psychologists, and with timeout. For pigeons, as well as chil-
cognitive psychologists, to name a few. dren, presenting the "fun" stimulus led
Language as instrumental behavior is ef- to significantly longer self-control than
fective or not, and its effectiveness de- did the "sad" stimulus. The results could
pends on the linguistic community. Are be interpreted in terms either of thinking
the psychodynamic and cognitive lan- processes or conditioned reinforcers and
guages effective? Workers within those punishers.
verbal communities answer yes. We emit Translation brings differing points of
our particular scientific language for a va- view and modes of research to bear upon
riety of reasons, but we must subject these a given phenomenon and helps to broad-
reasons to the same scrutiny that we do en the audience. I ask my students not
other subjects of our science. to talk or write in a particular way, but
Rather than arguing about the best lan- instead to communicate, and that often
guage, all would profit from the more dif- requires that they use a language ground-
ficult but productive activity of transla- ed in observations of behaviors and
tion. Skinner (1974) has, on many events.
occasions, attempted to translate the lan-
guage of mind into behavioral terminol- METHODS
ogy. Many others have also attempted Data and Theory
translations across disciplines (Davey,
1983; Rescorla, 1985; Seligman, 1975). Behaviorists emphasize data because
Grosch and Neuringer (1981) attempted they distrust the selectivity and creativity
to translate between a behavioral anal- of current interpretations and theories,
ysis of self-control in pigeons and psy- including their own. This skepticism re-
chodynamic and cognitive interpreta- sults in publication of precise details of
tions of self-control in children. In the procedures and results, a humble practice
research with children (Mischel & Eb- that hopefully will be appreciated by those
besen, 1970), the experimenter left the who follow. Although data drive much
child alone in a room. If the child rang a behavioral research, behaviorists are
bell, the experimenter returned imme- criticized for being constrained by their
diately and provided the child with a less commitment to theories, for example,
preferred reward (e.g., marshmallows); if concerning reinforcement and environ-
the child did not ring the bell and waited mental contingencies. The objection is
until the experimenter returned on his not to theory, but to premature theoriz-
own, then a more preferred reward was ing, or overgeneralizing. Theories pro-
given (e.g., pretzels). The same procedure vide ideas for research, but it is easy to
was used to explore a number of condi- be seduced by their potential power, as
tions, for example, Mischel, Ebbesen, and have some of our colleagues in other fields
Zeiss (1972) asked one group of children of psychology, as well as some of us. For
6 ALLEN NEURINGER

example, if"undermatching" and "over- tantly for the present point, human ob-
matching" are as common as "match- servers collect the data by judging wheth-
ing" under concurrent schedules of re- er the infant looked at the left or right
inforcement, does the theory ofmatching card. It would be possible to collect "ob-
have explanatory power, or does it con- jective" data concerning the motion of
strain how we think about the phenom- the infant's eyes and head, but a global
enon of "choice"? Similarly, what is the estimation by a human observer appears
predictive power of a mathematical de- to be the better means of gathering the
scription that contains many "free" pa- data: the noise of the infant's move-
rameters? In the long run, the humble ments, and the lack of explicit definition
approach ofgathering data may best lead of when a "look" occurred, makes it dif-
to attainable goals, at least at the early ficult to define the exact stimulus-but
stages of a given science. In place of ver- there is high reliability between observers
bal or mathematical theory, one could judging the direction of the look.
indicate circumscribed hypotheses-if Other examples abound ofinstances in
food is presented within t seconds of a which reliable human discriminations can
keypeck in pigeons, then .. ., or, as Char- be made although the exact bases of the
lie Perkins (personal communication, discriminations are not known. Absence
January, 1990) has suggested, instruc- of knowledge concerning effective stim-
tional rules: do this in order to get such ulus control does not preclude intersub-
and such an effect in a given situation. jective agreement. If such agreement ex-
ists, then phenomena such as awareness,
Measurement Operations attention, desire, interest, contentment,
or striving may readily be accessible to
The scientists' own discriminations behavioral analysis: An observer's re-
define what they study. Sometimes we sponse, human or non-human, serves to
can specify with precision the physical operationally define the dependent vari-
characteristics of what is to us a discrim- able.
inative stimulus, such as a lever press,
and therefore automate its measurement. Methodological Consistency and
Other times, however, there may be in- Basic Questions
tersubjective agreement without our be-
ing able to specify the precise stimulus. What basic behavioral researchers
The preferential looking method pro- study is guided by available behavioral
vides one example from the research lab- methodology, and as a result, they tend
oratory. Human (Teller, Morse, Borton, to choose questions which can be studied
& Regal, 1974) and monkey (Lee & in the operant chamber. One reason for
Boothe, 1981) infant sensory capacities so circumscribing the field is that we are
are evaluated by showing the infants two unable to read all of the psychological
cards on a grey background, one card be- literature, be conversant with all meth-
ing an identical grey color as the back- ods, or teach all of psychology in our
ground, the other consisting of black and courses. But selection based on meth-
white stripes. Infants have a tendency to odological consistency-look only at
look toward novel and patterned stimuli, journals which emphasize N-of- 1 re-
and thus look at the striped, rather than search, or in which rates of responding
the solid gray, card. Stripe frequency (or in operant chambers are the dependent
stripe width) is varied systematically, variable-may be less effective than se-
thereby enabling specification of visual lection based upon the questions. If your
acuity. When the stripe widths are suf- goal is to create a pure behavior analytic
ficiently small, the striped card is per- science, then possibly ignore work on hu-
ceived (by you or me, and therefore pre- man preference judgments. On the other
sumably by the infants) as a grey, identical hand, if your goal is to explain choice
to the background, and consequently behavior, then attempt to relate Kahne-
there is no preferential looking. Impor- man and Tversky's findings (e.g., Kahne-
HUMBLE BEHAVIORISM 7

man, Slovic, & Tversky, 1982) to those averages may not predict an individual's
from concurrent schedules of reinforce- behavior, and partly because each step in
ment, as is being attempted by Rachlin the research evolves from the individual
(1989). Method-oriented research may subject's performance under preceding
have the inadvertent consequence of in- conditions. Experimental manipulations
verting the processes of science: Ques- are often motivated by the research pro-
tions are asked because they can be stud-cess itself This feedback-loop, as docu-
ied, rather than methods chosen to answermented in Ferster & Skinner (1957)
questions. among others, can be characterized as
Where important questions come from scientific play-and the term is used in
is not dictated by scientific method or its best sense. No more important advice
any other formal means. The questions can be given to a young scientist than to
have a variety of sources (see Beveridge,learn to play with his or her subject-mat-
1950). As suggested above, a major source
ter. Play around and, depending upon
has been laboratory research. Another is what you learn, play some more.
society, that is, the perception of societalOne result of scientific play is to in-
problems. Development of behavioral crease the probability of serendipitous
techniques to deal with such issues has findings. Skinner discovered control by
been one result (Greene, Winett, Van reinforcement schedules, James Olds dis-
Houten, Geller, & Iwata, 1987). A third covered reinforcing intracranial brain
source is our own behaviors and prob- stimulation, Flemming discovered pen-
lems, a source that has led me to self- icillin, Roentgen discovered x-rays, Gal-
experimentation, a field with a long his-vani discovered reflex action due to elec-
tory both in medicine and in psychology trical stimulation -the list of"accidental"
(Altman, 1987; Franklin & Sutherland, discoveries is long. While the discoverer
1984; Neuringer, 1981, 1984). My stu- must prepare him or herself for such
dents have self-experimented on ques- chance findings, often the discovery pro-
tions concerning sleep, fear of speaking,cess is neither pre-planned nor rational
sex, self-control, addiction, study perfor-
(see Root-Bernstein, 1988).
mance, memory, social interactions, cir- Scientific play also helps to generate
cadian rhythms and the like. intuitions, that is, a sense of subject that
As with all research, a self experiment
is neither rational nor verbal. Einstein
may lead to questions appropriate for described the discovery process as in-
study using different methods, for ex- volving kinaesthetic body feels; he first
ample, "other" experimentation, using felt the solution to a difficult problem and
other people or non-human animals. only then worked at translating those
Skinner's description of stimulus controlfeelings into equations or words (Ghise-
over his professional work (Skinner, lin, 1952, pp. 43-44). Poincare hypoth-
1987) led to similar attempts by others. esized that his discoveries involved an
Farley Mowat's (1963) description of initial period of hard work followed by a
multiple short sleep periods led studentsnon-conscious, intuitive process of selec-
to try the same. And studies of my own tion based on the relative aesthetics of
ability to generate random numbers has the ideas (Ghiselin, 1952, pp. 33-42).
led to the experimental analyses of op- Science may be the art of generating ver-
erant variability in rats, pigeons, and oth-
ifiable intuitions.
er people (Cohen, Neuringer, & Rhodes, Whether scientific play should be care-
1990; Neuringer, 1986; Page & Neurin- fully documented is a question of heu-
ger, 1985). ristics-is it helpful to fill journal pages
with descriptions of play? Do the end re-
Individual Designs and sults benefit from descriptions of initial
Scientific Play processes? Documentation (and formal
analyses of obtained results) at early stages
Behaviorists emphasize data from in- of play-research may be inhibiting and
dividual organisms, partly because group non-functional. For one reason, it slows
8 ALLEN NEURINGER

the process. For another, it inhibits un- However, we are tentative about induc-
planned, "non-rational" changes in pro- ing from the animal laboratory to the hu-
cedure. Notes to oneself might suffice. man sphere, tentative because we are as
ready to document differences among an-
Group Designs imals-including human-as homolo-
gies
The demonstrated worth of single-sub- tinually and analogies. Thus, we need con-
ject research (Barlow & Hersen, 1984) animal model to go back and forth between
does not imply, however, that group de- order to validate and human application in
signs are unhelpful. Group designs are of the behavioral the model. The study
effects of drugs (Carl-
necessary to study gender differences, ef- ton, 1983) and of uncontrollable
fects of prenatal malnutrition, irreversi- events (Seligman, 1975) provideaversive impor-
ble diseases, or other developmental or tant examples of interactions between
inherited characteristics. The point here
is a general one: Because X is valid or animal and human levels.
functional does not imply that Y or Z are
invalid or non-functional. J. S. Mill cap- Empathy
tured this point when he wrote, "[The] "Objectivity" is associated with be-
... danger is not so much of embracing havioral But objectification of
falsehood for truth, as of mistaking part behavior studies.
should be the standard only so
of the truth for the whole" (cited in far as it is functional. If attempting to
Boakes, 1984, p. 174). Single-subject and "put yourself in the place of a rat" helps
group designs complement one another, us to understand, predict, and control the
each leading to predictions to be tested rat's behavior, then we should do so.
within the other's domain. One problem Practitioners in biology, chemistry, and
with single subject research is the un- physics do that sort of thing: They imag-
known representativeness of the partic- ine themselves as bacteria, organic mol-
ular subject. The only way to find out is ecules, or atomic particles (Judson, 1980).
by testing other subjects, leading to a Empathy may turn out to be as functional
group design. A related problem is the in the experimental analysis of behavior
unknown contribution of the history of as it is in human social interactions.
a given subject prior to the experiment. Empathy may play another functional
The ABA design permits assessment of role. Occam's razor and Lloyd-Morgan's
the effectiveness of a particular experi- canon have served psychologists well: Do
mental manipulation, but its effective- not assert of another organism some ca-
ness may vary with prior history. Fur- pacity more intricate or complex than is
thermore, although feedback-loop necessitated the immediate data. This
research has, indeed, been correlated with point of viewbymay referred to as the
Skinner's single-subject studies, group simplicity hypothesis,bethat is, assume that
researchers can engage in analogous forms an organism's capacities and
of scientific play. It may be more difficult are as "simple" as required bybehaviors
to treat a group as an individual, and to dence at hand. There is, however,theanevi- al-
manipulate procedures based on, say, the ternative point of view which may also
average performance of the group, but it functional: Within the limits of the
is possible and might help the process of be evidence available, hypothesize that an-
group study. other organism can do what you, your-
Induction from Animals to People self, can do. This can be referred to as
the similarity hypothesis. Both simplicity
Behaviorists hypothesize that human and similarity hypotheses must lead to
actions may be modeled by animals in experimental tests, but they work in op-
operant chambers. The emphasis here is posite directions. Simplicity works from
on the last word in the phrase, "behaviors the bottom up through a series of proofs
of organisms." People are animals who or demonstrations of function; similarity
share much with our animal cousins. leads to a series of attempts at disproof,
HUMBLE BEHAVIORISM 9

a series of demonstrations that the or- den variables account for the apparent
ganism fails to perform under a set of randomness of quantum phenomena,
tasks and demands. Eventually, both others hypothesize a completely random
similarity and simplicity strategies should or unpredictable underlying nature. A
lead to the same identification of func- scientist can posit causal relationships
tion, one getting there from top down, while entertaining the possibility of en-
the other from bottom up (see Porter & dogenous control, random influences, or
Neuringer, 1984). Which hypothesis to both.
use is not a question of right and wrong, This last assertion is not as far from
but of scientific heuristics. the radical behaviorist's position as might
appear. Behaviorists describe relation-
THEORETICAL ISSUES ships between environment and re-
External Versus Endogenous sponses in terms of response probabili-
Determinants ties. Especially with respect to operant
behaviors, where we talk of response
Behaviorism is associated with the emission -as opposed to elicitation -we
philosophical position of determinism: acknowledge an underlying uncertainty
Behaviors are hypothesized to be func- or variability of response. One can rea-
tionally related to events, with those sonably hypothesize that the source of
events external to the behaving organism such random variation lies within the or-
most helpful in predicting and control- ganism. As indicated above, pigeons and
ling behavior. Of course, genetic deter- rats respond quite adequately when vari-
minants are important, on the one hand, able sequences of responses are rein-
and external events may initiate a long forced (Page & Neuringer, 1985) and hu-
sequence of neural responses or covert mans learn to generate number sequences
occurrences, on the other, but to gain which are indistinguishable, according to
control over behavior, behaviorists em- a subset of statistical tests, from that of
phasize control by external stimuli. a computer-based random generator
Determinism is thought to be a func- (Neuringer, 1986).
tional position. If scientists assume that There are two major classes of expla-
all behaviors are controlled by external nation for such random-like behavior,
variables, then current ignorance will spur chaotic and stochastic. A chaotic basis of
them to try to identify those variables. random behavior (see Gleick, 1987) is
The opposite point of view, we are told, consistent with philosophical determin-
leads to giving up the search. But enter- ism, but, at the same time, provides trou-
tain for a moment two alternatives: first, ble for those whose goal is to relate all
that endogenous mechanisms-those behavior to environmental causes. Many
which may function relatively indepen- readers are familiar with computer-based
dently of external environmental stim- random numbers generated from simple,
uli -exert important behavioral control, deterministic equations, whose outputs
for example, timing oscillators respon- meet many of the statistical requirements
sible for circadian rhythms and other of randomness. There are two aspects of
timing functions (e.g., Meck, Church, & such random outputs: First, the output
Gibbon, 1985; Roberts, 1981). Here, indeed appears to be random according
knowledge of environmental events to statistical evaluations. Second, if you
would not suffice to predict or control know the generating equation and the po-
behavior. Second, and more problemat- sition in the sequence, you can predict
ic, is the possibility of endogenous ran- with certainty the next instance. Assum-
dom generators, that is, influences inter- ing that animals and people do, in fact,
nal to the organism which contribute contain an internal mechanism for gen-
randomly to behavioral output. In phys- erating highly variable outputs, the
ics, chemistry, and biology, the possibil- mechanism employed may be a chaotic
ity of truly random events is accepted. one, that is, based on an underlying de-
Although some physicists argue that hid- terministic process. The output would be
10 ALLEN NEURINGER
random-like, but, with complete knowl- tion, but if it is intended to imply in-
edge, every instance could be predicted. stances, then many behavioral events may
There remains, however, a problem for be unpredictable. That conclusion need
the determinist-behaviorist whose goal is not inhibit a humble science ofbehavior.
to predict and control. It may be impos-
sible to learn the underlying generating Reinforcement
mechanism from the output of a chaotic
generator. That is, if you already know Operants are reinforced; they are se-
the chaotic mechanism, you may be able lected by their consequences. However,
to predict instances, but it may be im- in any particular instance, reinforcers
possible to discover what that mecha- must be identified, not assumed. As has
nism is. There simply are too many (pos- been pointed out by many researchers,
sibly infinite) alternative ways to generate the intermittent presentation of food or
chaotic outputs. Thus, we could be secure water to a food- or water-deprived ani-
in the belief that every instance of be- mal may elicit patterns ofbehavior which
havior is determined, in part by the appear to be operant (Neuringer, 1970;
workings of a chaotic generator, but un- Skinner, 1948; Staddon & Simmelhag,
able to discover its characteristics and 1971). Instrumental acts may evolve be-
therefore unable to predict instances. haviorally in ways analogous to the se-
The second class of possible explana- lection of neutral phenotypes (Kimura,
tions involves a stochastic, or "truly ran- 1983). Such behaviors are not reinforced;
dom" generator. As an analogy, imagine they occur for other reasons. There is an-
the atomic emissions of radioactive par- other way in which we could be more
ticles. According to physicists, there is no tentative with respect to the role of re-
way- empirically or theoretically- to inforcement. By speaking of the rein-
predict the exact time of emission of the forcement of operant responses, we im-
next particle. One can readily describe ply a uniformity which may or may not
the general function, but not the instance. exist. Until the data compel generaliza-
If we have such an internal random gen- tions, it is safer to speak descriptively:
erating mechanism, and it somehow in- The animal's lever press was followed by
fluences which among a set of responses food pellets, rather than the animal's op-
is to be emitted, then, empirically and erant behavior was reinforced.
theoretically, it will be impossible to pre-
dict instances (see Peirce, 1923). PERSONAL CHARACTERISTICS
That aspects of behavior are stochas- Relations with Other
tic, or probabilistic, is consistent with Psychological Disciplines
much of radical behavioral writings. That
the stochasticity may imply an inability Important research is performed in
to predict and control goes, however, other areas of psychology: physiological,
against a major goal of the science-as cognitive, perceptual, developmental, and
indicated by Zuriff(l 985), among others. social, to name a few. We hinder our con-
Control and prediction may be possible tributions to a science ofbehavior by not
in some cases, but understanding may be taking that research seriously. For ex-
the realistic goal in others (see Boakes, ample, research on event-related evoked
1984, for analogous positions held by brain potentials, reaction time, psycho-
early functionalists). By understanding is logical changes occurring in infants when
meant the ability to specify the relative they begin to explore their environments,
contributions of endogenous versus ex- and the consequences of being in a group
ternal influences or predict the circum- versus being alone are a few of the areas
stances in which unpredictable behaviors that may assist us. Our attention to other
are likely to occur-for instance, when a research areas increases the probability
prey is chased by a predator. If prediction that others will attend to our work: In-
is used in its broadest sense, then science terest is presently being shown by ecol-
always involves some aspect of predic- ogists and economists to ecologically-rel-
HUMBLE BEHAVIORISM 11

evant (Fantino & Abarca, 1985) and CONCLUSION


economically-relevant (Rachlin, Batta-
lio, Kagel, & Green, 1981) operant stud- In conclusion, behaviorists are asked
ies. A humble stance with regard to other to cultivate a humble science of behavior.
disciplines -asking for help in solving our Self-assuredness, aggressiveness, guerril-
problems -may, in the long run, serve la warfare, methodological consistency,
all better than a continuation of the and philosophical purity may be effective
"you're wrong/I'm right" battles. in the short run. Humility is difficult when
fighting for grant funds, laboratory space,
Constructive Criticism research support, faculty positions, and
As suggested at the outset, science de- students. Nevertheless, over the long run,
pends upon continual checking and crit- humble behaviorism may be most likely
icizing. However, criticism can be more to effect our scientific and social goals.
or less aversive. Yerkes and Dodson Four objections are anticipated: (a)
(1908) suggested that the more complex "Humble" behaviorism blurs the dis-
the behavior, the less aversive a punish- tinction between behavioral research and
ing stimulus need be to effect desired other fields. (b) The author defines "hum-
changes (see, also, Balaban, Rhodes, & ble" behaviorism in terms ofhis own re-
Neuringer, in press). Doing science is search. (c) He writes about constructive
complex behavior par excellence, and criticism but attacks behavioral practic-
therefore mutual support, especially when es. (d) Anyone who admonishes humility
we are being critical, is helpful in chang- cannot be very humble. Each of these
ing behaviors. Criticize the research or criticisms will be considered briefly.
theory, don't punish the individual, and (a) There is much overlap between the
criticize constructively (Lyons, 1976). "field" of behavioral research and other
One form of constructive criticism is: areas. The humble behaviorist's goal is
When you do or say "A," that results in to discover laws and solve problems (to-
"B," the consequence of which is "C"; gether, whenever possible, with col-
rather than "You're wrong," or "That leagues from different "fields") rather
position is harmful." Along with con- than to prove the correctness of his or
structive criticism, the humble behav- her own field or philosophical commit-
iorist accepts and reinforces small ac- ment. If humble behavioral practices
complishments. yield scientific and social progress, they
will survive the test of time.
Behavioral Ethics (b) I chose examples from areas I know
Humble behaviorists attempt to sub- best. Readers might try to strengthen the
stitute if-then contingency statements for argument that contemporary behavior-
the more easily uttered "rights" and ism is, in fact, a humble science, and de-
"wrongs," and "oughts" and "shoulds." scribe other ways and reasons to increase
In place of "You ought not use intro- our humility as researchers and practi-
spective reports," we try to substitute, "If tioners.
you use introspective reports then...." (c) It is difficult to criticize those closest
This is a scientific ethic-one suggested to you. If any of these ideas is worthy, I
by Reichenbach (1 95 1) and others. State- ask the reader's help to transmit them in
ments of the prescriptive form-Do not a way that does not alienate.
speed -contain either implicit or explicit (d) Finally, Golda Meir told an asso-
contingencies. The behaviorist's goal is ciate (cited in Safire & Safir, 1982, p. 162):
to specify the contingencies, through re- "Don't be so humble. You're not that
search. Given insufficient knowledge great." The humble behaviorist accepts
concerning the contingency, a humble Golda Meir's challenge by attempting to
behavioral scientist is silent, admits ig- complete the contingency statement, "If
norance, or specifies what he, she, or oth- behaviorists were more humble, then
ers do in the situation. ,,
12 ALLEN NEURINGER

REFERENCES Bever, & H. S. Terrace (Eds.), Animal cognition


(pp. 233-261). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Altman, L. K. (1987). Who goes first? The story Hineline, P. N. (1980). The language of behavior
of self-experimentation in medicine, New York: analysis: Its community, its functions, and its
Random House. limitations. Behaviorism, 8, 67-86.
Balaban, M. T., Rhodes, D. L., & Neuringer, A. Hineline, P. N. (1986). Retuning the operant-
(in press). Orienting and defense responses to respondent distinction. In T. Thompson & M.
punishment: Effects on learning. Biological Psy- D. Zeiler (Eds.), Analysis and integration of be-
chology. havioral units (pp. 55-79). Hillsdale, NJ: Erl-
Barlow, D. H., & Hersen, M. (1984). Single case baum.
experimental designs. New York: Pergamon. Judson, H. F. (1980). The search for solutions.
Beveridge, W. I. B. (1950). The art of scientific New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
investigation. New York: Vintage. Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.).
Boakes, R. (1984). From Darwin to behaviourism. (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Carlton, P. L. (1983). A primerofbehavioralphar- Press.
macology. New York: Freeman. Kimura, M. (1983). The neutral theory of molec-
Cautela, J. R. (1967). Covert sensitization. Psy- ular evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
chological Reports, 20, 459-468. sity Press.
Chambers, D., & Reisberg, D. (1985). Can mental Lattal, K. A., & Gleeson, S. (1990). Response
images be ambiguous? Journal of Experimental acquisition with delayed reinforcement. Journal
Psychology: Human Perception and Perfor- of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior
mance, 11, 317-328. Processes, 16, 27-39.
Cohen, L., Neuringer, A., & Rhodes, D. (1990). Lee, C., & Boothe, R. G. (1981). Visual acuity
Effects of ethanol on reinforced variations and development in infant monkeys (Macacca ne-
repetitions by rats under a multiple schedule. mestrina) having known gestational ages. Vision
Journal ofthe ExperimentalAnalysis ofBehavior, Research, 21, 805-809.
54, 1-12. Lyons, G. (1976). Constructive criticism. Berke-
Davey, G. C. L. (Ed.). (1983). Animal models of ley, CA: Issues in Radical Therapy.
human behavior. New York: John Wiley. Meck, W. H., Church, R. M., & Gibbon, J. (1985).
Fantino, E., & Abarca, N. (1985). Choice, optimal Temporal integration in duration and number
foraging, and the delay-reduction hypothesis. Be- discrimination. Journal of Experimental Psy-
havioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 315-330. chology: Animal Behavior Processes, 11, 591-597.
Ferster, C., & Skinner, B. F. (1957). Schedules of Meichenbaum, D. (1977). Cognitive-behavior
reinforcement. New York: Appleton-Century- modification. New York: Plenum Press.
Crofts. Mischel, W., & Ebbesen, E. B. (1970). Attention
Franklin, J., & Sutherland, J. (1984). Guinea pig in delay of gratification. Journal of Personality
doctors: The drama of medical research through and Social Psychology, 16, 329-337.
self-experimentation. New York: William Mor- Mischel, W., Ebbesen, E. B., & Zeiss, A. (1972).
row. Cognitive and attentional mechanisms in delay
Garcia, J., Hankins, W. G., & Rusniak, K. W. of gratification. Journal ofPersonality and Social
(1974). Behavioral regulation of the milieu in- Psychology, 21, 204-218.
terne in man and rat. Science, 185, 824-831. Moerk, E. L. (1983). The mother of Eve-As a
Ghiselin, B. (Ed.). (1952). The creative process. first language teacher. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
New York: New American Library. Mowat, F. (1963). Never cry wolf. New York: At-
Gleick, J. (1987). Chaos. New York: Viking. lantic Monthly Press.
Glenn, S. S., & Hughes, H. H. (1978). Imaginal Neuringer, A. J. (1970). Superstitious key pecking
response events in systematic desensitization: A after three peck-produced reinforcements. Jour-
pilot study. Biological Psychology, 7, 303-309. nal of the Experimental Analysis ofBehavior, 13,
Greene, B. F., Winett, R. A., Van Houten, R., Gell- 127-134.
er, E. S., & Iwata, B. A. (Eds.). (1987). Behavior Neuringer, A. (1981). Self-experimentation: Acall
analysis in the community. Lawrence, KA: Jour- for change. Behaviorism, 9, 79-94.
nal of Applied Behavior Analysis. Neuringer, A. (1984). Melioration and self-ex-
Grosch, J., & Neuringer, A. (1981). Self-control perimentation. Journal of the Experimental
in pigeons under the Mischel paradigm. Journal Analysis ofBehavior, 42, 397-406.
of the Experimental Analysis ofBehavior, 35, 3- Neuringer, A. (1986). Can people behave "ran-
21. domly?": The role of feedback. Journal of Ex-
Hearst, E. (1975). The classical-instrumental dis- perimental Psychology: General, 115, 62-75.
tinction: Reflexes, voluntary behavior, and cat- Page, S., & Neuringer, A. (1985). Variability is an
egories of associative learning. In W. K. Estes operant. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
(Ed.), Handbook of learning, and cognitive pro- Animal Behavior Processes, 11, 429-452.
cesses: VoL 2. Conditioning and behavior theory Peirce, C. S. (1923). Chance, love and logic. New
(pp. 181-223). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. York: Barnes & Noble.
Herrnstein, R. J. (1984). Objects, categories, and Porter, D., & Neuringer, A. (1984). Music dis-
discriminative stimuli. In H. L. Roitblat, T. G. criminations by pigeons. Journal of Experimen-
HUMBLE BEHAVIORISM 13
tal Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 10, Hunger, environment, and food reinforcement.
138-148. Journal ofExperimental Psychology: Animal Be-
Pryor, K. W., Haag, R., & O'Reilly, J. (1969). The havior Processes, 1, 56-87.
creative porpoise: Training for novel behavior. Skinner, B. F. (1948). "Superstition" in the pi-
Journal ofthe ExperimentalAnalysis ofBehavior, geon. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 38,
12, 653-661. 168-172.
Rachlin,H. (1989). Judgment,decision,andchoice. Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behav-
New York: W. H. Freeman. ior. New York: The Free Press.
Rachlin, H., Battalio, R., Kagel, J., & Green, L. Skinner,B.F. (1957). Verbalbehavior. NewYork:
(1981). Maximization theory in behavioral psy- Appleton-Century-Crofts.
chology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 371- Skinner, B. F. (1974). About behaviorism. New
417. York: Knopf.
Reichenbach,H. (1951). Theriseofscientificphi- Skinner, B. F. (1987). How to discover what you
losophy. Berkeley: University of California Press. have to say: A talk to students. In B. F. Skinner,
Rescorla, R. A. (1985). Pavlovian conditioning Uponfurther reflection (pp. 131-143). Englewood
analogues to Gestalt perceptual principles. In F. Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
R. Brush & J. B. Overmier (Eds.), Affect, condi- Staddon, J. E. R., & Simme1hag, V. L. (1971). The
tioning, and cognition (pp. 113-130). Hillsdale, "superstition" experiment: A reexamination of
NJ: Erlbaum. its implications for the principles of adaptive be-
Roberts, S. (1981). Isolation of an internal clock. havior. Psychological Review, 78, 3-43.
Teller, D. Y., Morse, R., Borton, R., & Regal, D.
Journal ofExperimental Psychology: Animal Be- (1974). Visual acuity for vertical and diagonal
havior Processes, 7, 242-268. gratings in human infants. Vision Research, 14,
Root-Bernstein, R. S. (1988). Setting the stage for 1433-1439.
discovery. The Sciences, 28(3), 26-34. Yerkes, R. M., & Dodson, J. D. (1908). The re-
Safire, W., & Safir, L. (1982). Good advice. New lation of strength of stimulus to rapidity ofhabit-
York: Times Books. formation. Journal of Comparative Neurological
Seligman, M. E. P. (1975). Helplessness. San Fran- Psychology, 18, 459-482.
cisco: W. H. Freeman. Zuriff, G. E. (1985). Behaviorism: A conceptual
Shettleworth, S. J. (1975). Reinforcement and the reconstruction. New York: Columbia University
organization of behavior in golden hamsters: Press.

You might also like