Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

American Economic Association

Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects


Author(s): Charles A. Holt and Susan K. Laury
Source: The American Economic Review, Vol. 92, No. 5 (Dec., 2002), pp. 1644-1655
Published by: American Economic Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3083270
Accessed: 28-10-2015 16:00 UTC

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Economic
Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects

By CHARLESA. HOLT AND SUSAN K. LAURY*

Although risk aversion is a fundamental ele- ever, they also obtain dramatically different
ment in standard theories of lottery choice, asset results depending on whether the choice task
valuation, contracts, and insurance (e.g., Daniel involves buying or selling, since subjects tend
Bernoulli, 1738; John W. Pratt, 1964; Kenneth to put a high selling price on something they
J. Arrow, 1965), experimental research has pro- "own" and a lower buying price on something
vided little guidance as to how risk aversion they do not, which implies risk-seekingbehav-
should be modeled. To date, there have been ior in one case and risk aversion in the other.'
several approaches used to assess the impor- Independentof the method used to elicit a mea-
tance and nature of risk aversion. Using lottery- sure of risk aversion, there is widespreadbelief
choice data from a field experiment, Hans P. (with some theoreticalsupportdiscussed below)
Binswanger (1980) concluded that most farmers that the degree of risk aversion needed to ex-
exhibit a significant amount of risk aversion that plain behaviorin low-payoff settings would im-
tends to increase as payoffs are increased. Al- ply absurdlevels of risk aversionin high-payoff
ternatively, risk aversion can be inferred from settings. The upshot of this is that risk-aversion
bidding and pricing tasks. In auctions, overbid- effects are controversialand often ignoredin the
ding relative to Nash predictions has been at- analysisof laboratorydata.This generalapproach
tributed to risk aversion by some and to noisy has not caused much concern because most
decision-making by others, since the payoff theorists are used to bypassing risk-aversion
consequences of such overbidding tend to be issues by assuming that the payoffs for a game
small (Glenn W. Harrison, 1989). Vernon L. are already measuredas utilities.
Smith and James M. Walker (1993) assess the The natureof risk aversion (to what extent it
effects of noise and decision cost by dramati- exists, and how it depends on the size of the
cally scaling up auction payoffs. They find little stake) is ultimately an empirical issue, and ad-
support for the noise hypothesis, reporting that ditional laboratory experiments can produce
there is an insignificant increase in overbidding useful evidence that complements field obser-
in private-value auctions as payoffs are scaled vations by providing careful controls of proba-
up by factors of 5, 10, and 20. Another way to bilities and payoffs. However, even many of
infer risk aversion is to elicit buying and/or those economists who admit that risk aversion
selling prices for simple lotteries. Steven J. may be importanthave asserted that decision
Kachelmeier and Mohamed Shehata (1992) re- makersshould be approximatelyrisk neutralfor
port a significant increase in risk aversion (or, the low-payoff decisions (involving several dol-
more precisely, a decrease in risk-seeking be- lars) that are typically encounteredin the labo-
havior) as the prize value is increased. How- ratory. The implication, that low laboratory
incentives may be somewhat unrealistic and
* Holt: Department of Economics, University of Vir-
therefore not useful in measuring attitudes to-
ginia, Charlottesville, VA 22903; Laury: Department of
Economics, AndrewYoung School of Policy Studies, Geor-
gia State University, Atlanta,GA 30303. We wish to thank This is analogous to the well-known "willingness-to-
Ron Cummingsfor helpful suggestions and for funding the pay/willingness-to-acceptbias." Asking for a high selling
human subjects' payments. In addition, we are especially price implies a preferencefor the risk inherentin the lottery,
grateful to John List and Brett Katzmanfor setting up the and offering a low purchaseprice implies an aversionto the
sessions at the Universities of CentralFlorida and Miami, risk in the lottery. Thus the way that the pricing task is
respectively. This work was also funded in partby the Na- framed can alter the implied risk attitudes in a dramatic
tional Science Foundation (SBR-9753125, SBR-9818683, manner.The issue is whether seemingly inconsistent esti-
and SBR-0094800). We wish to thank Loren Smith for mates are due to a problem with the way risk aversion is
research assistance, and John Kagel, Dan Levin, Andrew conceptualized,or to a behavioralbias that is activated by
Muller, Tom Palfrey, Peter Wakker,seminarparticipantsat the experimentaldesign. We chose to avoid this possible
the Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta, and an anonymous complication by framing the decisions in terms of choices,
referee for helpful suggestions. not purchasesand sales.
1644

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL.92 NO. 5 HOLTAND LAURY:RISKAVERSIONAND INCENTIVEEFFECTS 1645

TABLE 1-THE TEN PAIREDLOTTERY-CHOICE


DECISIONSWITHLOW PAYOFFS

Expected payoff
Option A Option B difference
1/10 of $2.00, 9/10 of $1.60 1/10 of $3.85, 9/10 of $0.10 $1.17
2/10 of $2.00, 8/10 of $1.60 2/10 of $3.85, 8/10 of $0.10 $0.83
3/10 of $2.00, 7/10 of $1.60 3/10 of $3.85, 7/10 of $0.10 $0.50
4/10 of $2.00, 6/10 of $1.60 4/10 of $3.85, 6/10 of $0.10 $0.16
5/10 of $2.00, 5/10 of $1.60 5/10 of $3.85, 5/10 of $0.10 -$0.18
6/10 of $2.00, 4/10 of $1.60 6/10 of $3.85, 4/10 of $0.10 -$0.51
7/10 of $2.00, 3/10 of $1.60 7/10 of $3.85, 3/10 of $0.10 -$0.85
8/10 of $2.00, 2/10 of $1.60 8/10 of $3.85, 2/10 of $0.10 -$1.18
9/10 of $2.00, 1/10 of $1.60 9/10 of $3.85, 1/10 of $0.10 -$1.52
10/10 of $2.00, 0/10 of $1.60 10/10 of $3.85, 0/10 of $0.10 -$1.85

ward "real-world"risks, is echoed by Daniel In our experiment,we presentsubjectswith a


Kahnemanand Amos Tversky (1979, p. 265), menu of choices that permits measurementof
who suggest an alternative: the degree of risk aversion, and also estimation
of its functional form. We are able to compare
Experimental studies typically involve behaviorunderreal and hypotheticalincentives,
contrived gambles for small stakes, and a for lotteriesthatrangefrom severaldollarsup to
large numberof repetitionsof very simi- several hundreddollars.The wide range of pay-
lar problems.These featuresof laboratory offs allows us to specify and estimate a hybrid
gambling complicate the interpretationof utility function that permits both the type of
the results and restricttheir generality.By
default,the methodof hypotheticalchoices increasing relative risk aversion reported by
emergesas the simplestprocedureby which Binswanger and decreasing absolute risk aver-
a large number of theoretical questions sion neededto avoid "absurd"predictionsfor the
can be investigated.The use of the method high-payoff treatments.The proceduresare ex-
relies on the assumptionthat people often plained in Section I, the effects of incentives on
know how they would behave in actual risk attitudesare describedin Section II, and our
situations of choice, and on the further hybridutility model is presentedin Section III.
assumptionthatthe subjectshave no special
reasonto disguise theirtruepreferences. I. Procedures
In this paper,we directly addressthese issues The low-payoff treatment is based on ten
by presentingsubjects with simple choice tasks choices between the paired lotteries in Table 1.
that may be used to estimate the degree of risk Notice that the payoffs for Option A, $2.00 or
aversion as well as specific functional forms. $1.60, are less variable than the potential pay-
We use lottery choices that involve large cash offs of $3.85 or $0.10 in the "risky"Option B.
prizes that are actually to be paid. To address In the first decision, the probabilityof the high
the validity of using high hypotheticalpayoffs, payoff for both options is 1/10, so only an
we conducted this experiment under both real extreme risk seeker would choose OptionB. As
and hypotheticalconditions. We were intrigued can be seen in the far right column of the table,
by experiments in which increases in payoff the expected payoff incentive to choose Option
levels seem to increase risk aversion, e.g., A is $1.17.2 When the probabilityof the high-
Binswanger's (1980) experiments with low- payoff outcome increases enough (moving
incomefarmersin Bangladesh,andAntoniBosch- down the table), a person should cross over to
Domenech and Joaquim Silvestre (1999), who Option B. For example, a risk-neutralperson
report that willingness to purchase actuarially would choose A four times before switching
fair insuranceagainst losses is increasingin the
scale of the loss. Therefore we elicit choices 2
under both low- and high-money payoffs, in- Expected payoffs were not providedin the instructions
to subjects,which are availableon the Web at (http://www.
creasingthe scale by 20, 50, and finally 90 times gsu.edu/-ecoskl/research.htm).The probabilitieswere ex-
the low-payoff level. plainedin termsof throwsof a ten-sideddie.

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1646 THEAMERICANECONOMICREVIEW DECEMBER2002

to B. Even the most risk-averseperson should selected. The second decision task involved the
switch over by decision 10 in the bottom row, same ten decisions, but with hypotheticalpay-
since Option B yields a sure payoff of $3.85 in offs at 20 times the levels shown in Table 1 ($40
that case. or $32 for Option A, and $77 or $2 for Option
The literature on auctions commonly as- B). The third task was also a high-payoff task,
sumes constant relative risk aversion for its but the payoffs were paid in cash. The final task
computationalconvenience and its implications was a "returnto baseline" treatmentwith the
for bid functionlinearitywith uniformlydistrib- low-money payoffs shown in Table 1. The out-
uted private values. With constant relative risk come of each task was determinedbefore the
aversion for money x, the utility function is next task began. Incentives are likely dilutedby
u(x) = x'-' for x > 0. This specification the random selection of a single decision for
implies risk preferencefor r < 0, risk neutrality each of the treatments,which is one motivation
for r = 0, and risk aversion for r > 0.3 The for runningthe high-payoff condition. Subjects
payoffs for the lotterychoices in the experiment did seem to take the low-payoff condition seri-
were selected so that the crossover point would ously, often beginningwith the easier choices at
provide an interval estimate of a subject's co- the top and bottom of the table, with choices
efficient of relative risk aversion.We chose the neartheir switch point more likely to be crossed
payoff numbers for the lotteries so that the out and changed.
risk-neutral choice pattern (four safe choices To control for wealth effects between the
followed by six risky choices) was optimal for high and low real-payoff treatments, subjects
constant relative risk aversion in the interval were requiredto give up what they had earned
(-0.15, 0.15). The payoff numbers were also in the first low-payoff task in order to partici-
selected to make the choice patternof six safe pate in the high-payoff decision. They were
choices followed by four risky choices optimal asked to initial a statementaccepting this con-
for an interval (0.41, 0.68), which is approxi- dition, with the warning:
mately symmetric around a coefficient of 0.5
(square root utility) that has been reported in Even though the earnings from this next
econometric analysis of auction data cited be- choice may be very large, they may also
low. For our analysis, we do not assume that be small, and differences between people
individuals exhibit constant relative risk aver- may be large, due to choice and chance.
sion; these calculations will provide the basis Thus we realize that some people may
for a null hypothesis to be tested. In particular, prefer not to participate,and if so, just
indicate this at the top of the sheet... . Let
if all payoffs are scaled up by a constant,k, then me reiterate, even though some of the
this constant factors out of the power function
that has constant relative risk aversion. In this payoffs are quite large, there is no catch
or chance that you will lose any money
case, the numberof safe choices would be un- that you happen to earn in this part. We
affected by changes in payoff scale. A change are preparedto pay you what you earn.
in choice patterns as payoffs are scaled up Are there any questions?
would be inconsistentwith constantrelativerisk
aversion.In this case, we can use the numberof Nobody declined to participate,so there is no
safe choices in each payoff condition to obtain selection bias. For comparability,subjectsin the
risk aversion estimates for other functional high-hypothetical treatment were required to
forms. initial a statementacknowledgingthat earnings
In our initial sessions, subjects began by in- for that decision would not be paid. The hypo-
dicating a preference, Option A or Option B, thetical choice does not alter wealth, but the
for each of the ten pairedlottery choices in Ta- high real payoffs alteredthe wealth positions a
ble 1, with the understandingthat one of these lot for most subjects, so the final low-payoff
choices would be selected at randomex post and task was used to determine whether risk atti-
played to determinethe earningsfor the option tudes are affected by large changes in accumu-
lated earnings. Comparingchoices in the final
low-payoff task with the first may also be used
3 When r = 1, the naturallogarithmis used; division by to assess whetherany behavioralchanges in the
(1 - r) is necessary for increasing utility when r > 1. high-payoff condition were due to changes in

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL.92 NO. 5 HOLTAND LAURY:RISKAVERSIONAND INCENTIVEEFFECTS 1647

TABLE2-SUMMARYOFLOTTERY-CHOICE
TREATMENTS

Number of Average Minimum Maximum


Treatment subjects earnings earnings earnings
20x HypotheticalOnly 25 $ 25.74 $ 19.40 $ 40.04
20x Real Only 57 $ 67.99 $ 20.30 $116.48
20x Hypotheticaland Real 93 $ 68.32 $ 11.50 $105.70
50x Hypotheticaland Real 19 $131.39 $111.30 $240.59
90x Hypotheticaland Real 18 $226.34 $ 45.06 $391.65

risk attitudeor from more careful consideration tively. All of these sessions were conducted at
of the choice problem. Georgia State University. The number of sub-
All together,we conductedthe initial sessions jects in these treatmentswas necessarily much
(with low and 20x payoffs) using 175 subjects, smaller due to the large increase in payments
in groups of 9-16 participantsper session, at required to conduct them. All subjects were
three universities (two at Georgia State Univer- presented with both real and hypothetical
sity, four at the University of Miami, and six at choices in these two treatments,allowing for a
the Universityof CentralFlorida).About half of within-subjects comparison. Average earnings
the students were undergraduates,one-third were about $70 in the 20x sessions using real
were MBA students,and 17 percent were busi- payments,$130 in the 50x sessions, and $225 in
ness school faculty. Table 2 presentsa summary the 90x sessions.5 All individual lottery-choice
of our experimental treatments. In these ses- decisions, earnings, and responses to 15 demo-
sions, the low-payoff tasks were always done, graphicquestions (given to subjects at the con-
but the high-payoff condition was for hypothet- clusion of the experiment)can be found on the
ical payoffs in some sessions, for real money in Web at (http://www.gsu.edu/-ecoskl/research.
others, and in about half of the sessions we did htm).
both in order to obtain a within-subjectscom-
parison. Doing the high-hypothetical choice II. Incentive Effects
task before high real allows us to hold wealth
constant and to evaluate the effect of using real In all of our treatments,the majorityof sub-
incentives. For our purposes, it would not have jects chose the safe option when the probability
made sense to do the high real treatmentfirst, of the higherpayoff was small, and then crossed
since the careful thinking would bias the high- over to Option B without ever going back to
hypothetical decisions. We can compare Option A. In all sessions, only 28 of 212 sub-
choices in the high real-payoff treatmentwith jects ever switched back from B to A in the first
either the first or last low-payoff task to allevi- low-payoff decision, and only 14 switched back
ate concerns that learning occurred as subjects in the final low-payoff choice. Fewer than one-
worked throughthese decisions. fourthof these subjectsswitchedback from B to
In order to explore the effect of even larger A more thanonce. The numberof such switches
increases in payoffs we next ran some very was even lower for the high-payoff choices,
expensive sessions in which the 20x payoffs
were replaced with 50x payoffs and 90x pay-
5 All of the
offs. In the two 50x sessions (19 subjects), the lottery-choice tasks reportedin this paper
were preceded by an unrelatedexperiment.Those sessions
"safe" payoffs were $100 and $80, while the conductedat the Universities of Miami and CentralFlorida
"risky"payoffs were $192.50 and $5. In the 90x followed a repeated individual-decision (tax compliance)
sessions (18 subjects)the safe and risky payoffs task conductedby a colleague, for which earningsaveraged
were ($180, $144) and ($346.50, $9), respec- about$18. The lottery-choicesessions conductedat Georgia
State University followed a different set of (individual-
choice) tasks for which average earnings were somewhat
higher (about $27). We conclude that these differences are
4 Of course, the orderthat we did use could bias the
high probablynot relevant;in the 20x payoff sessions, including
real decision toward what is chosen under hypothetical Georgia State data does not alter the means, medians, or
conditions, but a comparisonwith sessions using one high- modes of the number of safe choices in any of the treat-
payoff treatmentor the other indicates no such bias. ments by more than 0.05.

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1648 THEAMERICANECONOMICREVIEW DECEMBER2002

?
I1 .----------- lies to the right of the risk-neutralprediction,
0.99
showing a tendency toward risk-averse behav-
0.8 ior among these subjects. The thin lines in the
0.7 i
0.6,
figure show the observedchoice frequenciesfor
the hypothetical(20x, 50x, and 90x) treatments;
0.5
these are quite similar to one another and are
; 0.4
also very close to the line for the low real-
0.3
, 0.2
payoff condition. Actual choice frequenciesfor
the initial (20x payoff) sessions, along with the
0.1!
0---- implied risk-aversionintervals,are shown in the
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 "low real" and "20x hypothetical"columns of
Decision Table 3. Even for low-payoff levels, there is
FIGURE 1. PROPORTION OF SAFE CHOICES IN EACH
considerable risk aversion, with about two-
DECISION: DATA AVERAGES AND PREDICTIONS thirds of subjects choosing more than the four
safe choices that would be predicted by risk
Note: Data averages for low real payoffs [solid line with
dots], 20x, 50x, and 90x hypotheticalpayoffs [thin lines], neutrality.However, there is no significantdif-
and risk-neutralprediction [dashed line]. ference between behavior in the low real- and
high- (20x, 50x, or 90x) hypothetical-payoff
treatments.
althoughthis difference is small (6.6 percentof Figure 2 shows the results of the 20x real-
choices in the last low-payoff task, compared payoff treatments(the solid line with squares).
with about 5.5 percent in the 50x and 90x real- The increase in payoffs by a factor of 20 shifts
payoff treatments). More subjects switched the locus of choice frequencies to the right in
back in the hypotheticaltreatments:between 8 the figure,with more than 80 percentof choices
and 10 percent. in the risk-aversecategory (see Table 3). Of the
Even for those who switched back and forth, 150 subjects who faced the 20x real-payoff
there is typically a clear division point between choice, 84 showed an increase in risk aversion
clusters of A and B choices, with few "errors" over the low-payoff treatment.Only 20 subjects
on each side. Therefore, the total number of showed a decrease (the others showed no
"safe"A choices will be used as an indicatorof change). This difference is significant at any
risk aversion.6Figure 1 displays the proportion standardlevel of confidence using a Wilcoxon
of A choices for each of the ten decisions (as test of the null hypothesis that there is no
listed in Table 1). The horizontal axis is the change.8 The risk-aversioncategories in Table
decision number,and the dashed line shows the 3 were used to design the menu of lottery
predictionsunderan assumptionof risk neutral- choices, but the clear increase in risk aversion
ity, i.e., the probabilitythatthe safe OptionA is as all payoffs are scaled up is inconsistent with
chosen is 1 for the first four decisions, and then constantrelative risk aversion.One notable fea-
this probability drops to 0 for all remaining ture of the frequenciesin Table 3 is that nearly
decisions. The thick line with dots shows the 40 percent of the choice patterns in the 20x
observedfrequencyof OptionA choices in each
of the ten decisions in the low-real-payoff (lx)
treatment.7This series of choice frequencies to the 93 subjects who made choices under real and hypo-
thetical conditions. A Kolmogorov-Smirov test fails to
rejectthe null hypothesisof no differencein the distribution
6 The
analysis reportedin this paperchanges very little if of the numberof safe choices between the full sample and
we instead drop those subjects who switch from B back to the relevant restrictedsample for any of our comparisons.
A. The average numberof safe choices increases slightly in Moreover,the actualdifferencein distributionsis very small
some treatmentswhen we restrictour attentionto those who in all cases.
never switch back, but typically by less than 0.2 choices. 8
Following Sydney Siegel (1956), observations with
7 For this no change were not used. In addition, a one-tailed Kol-
figure, and other frequencies reportedbelow,
the full sample of available observations was used. For mogorov-Smirnovtest applied to the aggregate cumulative
example, in Figure 1, the choices of all 212 subjects are frequencies, based on all observations, allows rejection of
reportedin the low-payoff series. This includes those in the the null hypothesisthatthe choice distributionsare the same
20x, 50x, and 90x sessions. Similarly,when choices involv- between the low (either first or last) and 20x real-payoff
ing 20x payoffs are reported,we do not limit our attention treatments(p < 0.01).

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL.92 NO. 5 HOLTAND LAURY:RISKAVERSIONAND INCENTIVEEFFECTS 1649

BASED ON LOTTERYCHOICES
TABLE3-RISK-AVERSION CLASSIFICATIONS

relativerisk
of relative Proportionof choices
Number ~Range
Number
Range
of safe aversion for Risk preference Low 20x 20x
choices U(x) = xl-r/(1 - r) classification reala hypothetical real
0-1 r < -0.95 highly risk loving 0.01 0.03 0.01
2 -0.95 < r < -0.49 very risk loving 0.01 0.04 0.01
3 -0.49 < r < -0.15 risk loving 0.06 0.08 0.04
4 -0.15 < r < 0.15 risk neutral 0.26 0.29 0.13
5 0.15 < r < 0.41 slightly risk averse 0.26 0.16 0.19
6 0.41 < r < 0.68 risk averse 0.23 0.25 0.23
7 0.68 < r < 0.97 very risk averse 0.13 0.09 0.22
8 0.97 < r < 1.37 highly risk averse 0.03 0.03 0.11
9-10 1.37 < r stay in bed 0.01 0.03 0.06
a
Average over first and second decisions.

displayed in Table 4 show how risk aversion


0.9 increases as real payoffs are scaled up.
0.8 Given the increase in risk aversion observed
0.7 when payoffs are scaled up by a factorof 20, we
0.6
0 were curious as to how a further increase in
^ 0.5
0.4
payoffs would affect choices. The increase in
?
payoffs from their original levels (shown in
i 0.3 Table 1) by factorsof 50 and 90, producedeven
a 0.2
more dramaticshifts toward the safe option. In
0.1
the latter treatment, the safe option provides
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 either $144 or $180, whereas the risky option
Decision provides $346.50 or $9. One-thirdof subjects
who faced this choice (6 out of 18) avoided any
FIGURE2. PROPORTIONOF SAFE CHI
DECISION:DATA AVERAGESAND IORED
Echance
ICTION of the $9 payoff, only switching to the
Note: Data averages for low real payof fs
risky option in decision 10 where the high-
monds, 990x wrlth
dots], 20x real [squares], 50x real [disamonds], real payoff outcome was certain. There is an in-
payoffs [triangles], and risk-neutral p)rediction [dashed crease in the average number of safe choices
line]. (shown in Table 4) and a correspondingright-
ward shift in the distribution of safe choices
real-payoff condition involve s;even or more (shown by the diamondsand trianglesin Figure
safe choices, which indicates a' very high level 2). The increasein the numberof safe choices is
of risk aversion for those individluals.The over- also reflectedby the median and modal choices.
all message is thatthere is a lot o)f risk aversion,
centered around the 0.3-0.5 rsange, which is
roughly consistent with estimaltes implied by 0.45 for 27 one-shot matrixgames (Goeree and Holt, 2000).
behaviorin games, auctions, andI other decision SandraCampoet al. (2000) estimate r = 0.56 for field data
tasks.9Both Table 3 and the treattmentaverages from timber'auctions.One thing to note is thatrisk-aversion
estimatescan be quiteunstablewhen inferredfromwillingness-
to-pay prices as compared with much higher willingness-
to-accept prices that subjects place on the same lottery
9 In a classic study, Binswanger(1980)) finds moderateto (Kachelmeier and Shehata, 1992; R. Mark Isaac and
high levels of constant relative risk aveirsion (above 0.32), Duncan James, 2000). The low willingness-to-pay prices
especially for high-stakes gambles (increasing relative risk imply risk aversion, whereas the high willingness-to-accept
aversion). Some recent estimates for rellative risk aversion prices imply risk neutralityor risk seeking. One important
are: r = 0.67, 0.52, and 0.48 for privvate-valueauctions implication of this measurement effect is that the same
(James C. Cox and Ronald L. Oaxacia, 1996; Jacob K. instrumentshould be used in makinga comparison,as is the
Goeree et al., 1999; Kay-Yut Chen ancd Charles R. Plott, case for the comparisonof risk attitudesof individualsand
1998, respectively), r = 0.44 for sieveral asymmetric groups conducted by Robert S. Shupp and Arlington W.
matching pennies games (Goeree et al., 2000), and r = Williams (2000).

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1650 THEAMERICANECONOMICREVIEW DECEMBER2002

TABLE 4--AVERAGE NUMBER OF SAFE CHOICES BY TREATMENT

Number of First High High Second


Treatment subjects low real hypothetical real low real
20x All 175 5.2 4.9a 6.0b 5.3
20x Hypotheticaland Real 93 5.0 4.8 5.8 5.2
50x Hypotheticaland Real 19 5.3 5.1 6.8 5.5
90x Hypotheticaland Real 18 5.3 5.3 7.2 5.5

aN = 118.
bN = 150.

For payoff scales of 20x, 50x, and 90x the percent) in the 20x hypothetical-payoffcondi-
mediansare, respectively, (6.0, 7.0, 7.5) and the tion thanis the case in the othertreatments(6-8
modes are (6.0, 7.0, and 9.0). This increased percent). A Kolmogorov-Smirnovtest on the
tendency to choose the safe option when pay- change in hypothetical distributionsshows no
offs are scaled up is inconsistentwith the notion change as payoffs are scaled up from 20x to 50x
of constantrelativerisk aversion(when utility is to 90x. Behavior is a little more erratic with
written as a function of income, not wealth). hypothetical payoffs; for example, one person
This increase in risk aversion is qualitatively chose Option A in all ten decisions, including
similar to Smith and Walker's (1993) results. the sure hypothetical$40 over the hypothetical
However, unlike the subjects in their auction $77 in decision 10. The only other case of
experiments, our subjects exhibit much larger Option A being selected in decision 10 also
(and significant)changes in behavioras payoffs occurredin the 20x hypotheticaltreatment.
are scaled up. Kachelmeierand Shehata(1992) This result raises questions about the validity
also observed a significant change in behavior of Kahneman and Tversky's suggested tech-
when the payoff scale was increased, although nique of using hypothetical questionnaires to
their subjects (who demandeda relatively high addressissues that involve very high stakes. In
price in orderto sell the lottery) appearedto be particular,it casts doubt on their assumption
risk preferringin their baseline treatment.As that"peopleoften know how they would behave
noted earlier, our design avoids any potential in actual situations of choice" (Kahnemanand
willingness-to-acceptbias by framingthe ques- Tversky, 1979, p. 265).
tion in a neutralchoice setting. To summarize: We can also addresswhetherfacing the high-
increases in all prize amountsby factors of 20, payoff treatment affected subsequent choices
50, and 90 cause sharpincreasesin the frequen- under low payoffs. Looking at Table 4, the
cies of safe choices, and hence, in the implied roughly comparablechoice frequencies for the
levels of risk aversion. "before"and "after"low-payoff conditions (an
In contrast,successive increases in the stakes average of 5.2 versus 5.3 safe choices for 20x
do not alter behavior very much in the hypo- payoffs, and 5.3 versus 5.5 for the 50x and 90x
thetical payoff treatments. Subjects are much treatments)suggests that the level of risk aver-
more risk averse with high real-payoff levels sion is not affected by high earnings in the
(20x, 50x, and 90x) than with comparablehy- intermediate high-payoff condition that most
pothetical payoffs. The clear treatmenteffect subjects experienced. This invariance is sup-
suggestedby Figure2 is supportedby the within- ported by a simple regression in which the
subjects analysis. Of the 93 people who made change in the number of safe choices between
both real and hypotheticaldecisions at the 20x the first and last low-payoff decisions is re-
level, 44 showed more risk aversionin the real- gressed on earningsin the high real-payoffcon-
payoff condition, 42 showed no change, and 7 dition that were obtained in between. The
showed less risk aversion.The positive effect of coefficient on earnings is near zero and insig-
real payoffs on the number of safe choices is nificant.If we only considerthe subset who won
significant using either a Wilcoxon test or a the $77 prize, 21 people did not change their
Kolmogorov-Smirov test (p < 0.01). How- number of safe choices, 11 increased, and 14
ever, there is more risk-seeking behavior (15 decreased. We observe similar patterns in the

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL.92 NO. 5 HOLTAND LAURY:RISKAVERSIONAND INCENTIVEEFFECTS 1651

higher-payoff treatments.In the 50x treatment, 1 -U - - - -U- -I

only one subjectwon the $192.50 prize, and this 0.9


0.8
person increased the number of safe choices
<0.7
(from three to four). In the 90x payoff treat-
0 0.6
ment, four subjects won the $346.50 prize.
0.5
Three of these subjects did not change their I
, 0.4 I
decision in the last choice from the first, and the
v, 0.3
remainingsubject decreasedthe numberof safe 0.2
choices from five to four. Thus high unantici- ', I I
0.1
pated earnings appearto have little or no effect 0
on risk preferencesin this context. This obser- 7 8 9 10
vation would be consistent with constant abso-
lute risk aversion, but we argue in Section III
FIGURE 3. PROPORTION OF SAFE CHOICES IN EACH
below that constant absolute risk aversion can-
DECISION: DATA AVERAGES AND PREDICTIONS
not come close to explaining the effects of
Note: Data averages for low real payoffs [solid line with
increasingthe stakes on observedchoice behav-
ior. Alternatively, the lack of a strong correla- dots] and 20x real payoffs [squares], with corresponding
predictionsfor constantabsoluterisk aversion with a = 0.2
tion between earningsin the high-payoff lottery [thick dashed lines] and risk neutrality[thin dashed line].
and subsequentlottery choices could be due to
an "isolationeffect" or tendency to focus on the
statusquo and considerrisks of payoff changes, Catherine Eckel et al. (1998). The surprising
i.e., changes in income instead of final wealth. result for our data is that this gender effect
In fact, there is no experimentalevidence that disappearsin the three high-payoff treatments.
we know of which supportsthe "asset integra- Finally, althoughthe white/nonwhitevariableis
tion" hypothesis that wealth affects risk atti- not significant, in our 20x payoff sessions the
tudes (see Cox and Vjollca Sadiraj,2001). Hispanic variableis; this effect is even stronger
It also appearsunlikely that exposure to the at the 20x level than at the low-payoff level.
high-payoff choice task affected choices in the There were almost no Hispanic subjects in our
subsequentlow-payoff decision. Almost half of 50x and 90x sessions, and so we cannot esti-
all subjectswho face one of our high real-payoff mate a model including this variable for these
treatments choose the same number of safe sessions.10
choices in the first and last low-payoff task.
About the same numberof subjects change the III. Payoff Scale Effectsand Risk Aversion
numberof safe choices by one (these are almost
equally divided between increasing and de- The increased tendency to choose the safe
creasing by one choice). Very few individuals option as the stakes are raised is a clear indica-
change the numberof safe choices by more than tion of increasing relative risk aversion, which
one between the first and last decision tasks. could be consistent with a wide range of utility
We distributed a postexperiment question- functions, including those with constant abso-
naire to collect informationaboutdemographics lute risk aversion, i.e., u(x) = -exp(-ax).
and academicbackground.While the study was The problem with constant absolute risk aver-
not designed to addressdemographiceffects on sion is indicatedby Figure 3, where an absolute
risk aversion, the subject pool shows a wide risk-aversioncoefficient of a = 0.2 predictsfive
variation in income and education, and some safe (Option A) choices under low-payoff con-
interestingpatternsdo appearin our data.Using ditions, as shown by the thick dashed line with
any of the real-payoffdecisions to measurerisk dots just to the right of the thin dashed line for
aversion,income has a mildly negative effect on risk neutrality.This predictionis approximately
risk aversion (p < 0.06). Othervariables(ma-
jor, MBA, faculty, age, etc.) were not signifi- 10This
cant. Using the low-payoff decisions only, we Hispanic effect may be due to the narrow geo-
find that men are slightly less risk averse (p < graphic basis of the sample. Most of the Hispanic subjects
were studentsat the University of Miami; however, we did
0.05), making about 0.5 fewer safe choices. not obtain informationabout their ancestry or where they
This is consistent with findings reported by were raised.

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1652 THEAMERICANECONOMICREVIEW DECEMBER
2002

correctfor the low real-payofftreatment,which


produces a treatmentaverage of about 5.2 safe
choices. But notice the dashedline with squares
on the far right side of Figure 3; this is the -O
o
c

correspondingprediction of nine safe choices 4._

for a = 0.2 in the 20x payoff treatment.This is 0


4

L.
(9

q
far more than the treatmentaverage of 6.0 safe
&l
choices. The intuitionfor this "absurd"amount
of predictedrisk aversioncan be seen by recon-
sidering the utility when payoffs, x, are scaled -- -- r
up by 20 underconstantabsolute risk aversion: 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10
u(x) = -exp(-a20x). Since the baseline Decision

payoff, x, and the risk-aversionparameterenter FIGURE 4. PROPORTION OF SAFE CHOICES IN EACH


multiplicatively, scaling up payoffs by 20 is DECISION: DATA AVERAGES AND PREDICTIONS
equivalent to having 20 times as much risk Note: Data averages for low real payoffs [solid line with
aversion for the original payoffs. This is our
dots] and 20x real payoffs [squares], with predictions for
interpretationof the "Rabin critique" that the risk neutrality[thin dashed line] and noise parameterof 0.1
risk aversionneeded to explain behaviorin low- [thick dashed line].
stakes situations implies an absurd amount of
risk aversion in high-stakes lotteries (Matthew
Rabin, 2000). This observationraises the issue
of whether any utility function will be consis- where the denominatorsimply ensures that the
tent with observed behavior over a wide range probabilities of each choice sum to 1. Notice
of payoff stakes.11Obviously, such a function that the choice probabilities converge to one-
will have to exhibit decreasing absolute risk half as tL becomes large, and it is straightfor-
aversion, although constant absolute risk aver- ward to show that the probabilityof choosing
sion (with the right constant) may yield good the option with the higher expected payoff goes
predictionsfor some particularlevel of stakes. to 1 as ,Lgoes to 0. Figure 4 shows how adding
First, notice that the locus of actual frequen- some error in this manner (,u = 0.1, as an
cies is not as "abrupt"as the dashed line pre- example) causes the dashed line predictionsun-
dictions in Figure 3, which indicatesthe need to der risk neutralityto exhibit a smoothertransi-
add some "noise"to the model. This noise may tion, i.e., there is some curvatureat the corers.
reflect actualdecision-makingerrorsor unmod- Obviously, we must add some risk aversion
eled heterogeneity, among other factors. This to explain the observed preferencefor the safe
additionis also essential if we want to be able to option in decisions 5 and 6. As a first step, we
determinewhetherthe apparentincrease in risk keep the noise parameterfixed at 0.1 and add an
aversion with high stakes is merely due to di- amountof constantrelative risk aversionof r =
minished noise. We do so by introducing a 0.3, which yields predictions shown by the
probabilisticchoice function. The simplest rule dashedlines in Figure5. The dashedlines for the
specifies the probabilityof choosing Option A threetreatmentscannotbe distinguished,which is
as the associated expected payoff, UA, divided not surprisinggiven the fact that payoff-scale
by the sum of the expected payoffs, UA and UB, changes do not affect the predictionsundercon-
for the two options. Following Duncan Luce stantrelativerisk aversion.However, underone
(1959), we introducea noise parameter,,L,that specific payoff scale, constantrelativerisk aver-
capturesthe insensitivityof choice probabilities sion can provide an excellent fit for the data
to payoffs via the probabilisticchoice rule: patterns.Given this, we see why this model has
been useful in explaining laboratory data for
"normal"payoff levels (see Goeree et al., 1999,
(1) Pr (choose OptionA) = At ul/
+ 2000).
u1 t u
The next step is to introduce a functional
form thatpermitsthe type of increasingrelative
Fora criticaldiscussion of the Rabincritique,see Cox risk aversion seen in our data, but avoids the
and Sadiraj(2001). absurdpredictionsof the constantabsoluterisk-

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL.92 NO. 5 HOLTAND LAURY:RISKAVERSIONAND INCENTIVEEFFECTS 1653

likelihood of -315.68.12 These parameterval-


ues were used to plot the theoreticalpredictions
for the four treatmentsshown in Figure 6. This
model fits most of the aggregate data averages
0.6-
0.5-
quite closely. The amount of risk aversion
needed to explain behavior in the low-stakes
0.4-
treatmentdoes not imply absurdpredictions in
0.3-
I the extremelyhigh-stakestreatment.The largest
0.2-
0.1- prediction errors are for the 50x treatment,
0
which is more erraticgiven the low numberof
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 observations used to generate each of the ten
Decision choice frequenciesfor that treatment.Note that
FIGURE 5. PROPORTION OF SAFE CHOICES IN EACH
the model slightly underpredictsthe extreme
DECISION: DATA AVERAGES AND PREDICTIONS degree of risk aversionfor decision 9 in the 90x
treatment.Still, this three-parameter
model does
Note: Data averages for low real payoffs [solid line with
dots] and 20x real payoffs [squares], with predictions for
a remarkablejob of predictingbehavior over a
risk neutrality [thin dashed line] and a noise parameterof payoff range from several dollars to several
0.1 with constantrelative risk aversion of 0.3 [thick dashed hundreddollars.
line].
IV. Conclusion

aversion model. This can be done with a hybrid This paper presents the results of a simple
"power-expo" function (Atanu Saha, 1993) lottery-choiceexperimentthatallows us to mea-
that includes constant relative risk aversion sure the degree of risk aversion over a wide
and constant absolute risk aversion as special rangeof payoffs, rangingfrom severaldollarsto
cases: several hundreddollars. In addition, we com-
pare behavior under hypothetical and real
1 - exp(- ax -r)
incentives.
(2) U(x) = Although behavior is slightly more erratic
under the high-hypotheticaltreatments,the pri-
mary incentive effect is in levels (measuredas
which has been normalizedto ensurethatutility the numberof safe lottery choices in each treat-
becomes linear in x in the limit as a goes to 0. ment). Even at the low-payoff level, when all
It is straightforwardto show that the Arrow- prizes are below $4.00, about two-thirdsof the
Prattindex of relative risk aversion is: subjects exhibit risk aversion. With real pay-
offs, risk aversion increases sharplywhen pay-
offs are scaled up by factors of 20, 50, and 90.
-u"(x)x This result is qualitatively similar to that re-
(3) =r+ a( - r)xr,
u'(x) portedby Kachelmeierand Shehata(1992) and
Smith and Walker (1993) in different choice
which reduces to constantrelative risk aversion environments. In contrast, behavior is largely
of r when a = 0, and to constant absolute risk unaffectedwhen hypotheticalpayoffs are scaled
aversion of a when r = 0. For intermediate up. This paper presents estimates of a hybrid
cases (both parameters positive), the utility "power-expo"utility function that exhibits: (1)
function exhibits increasing relative risk aver- increasingrelativerisk aversion,which captures
sion and decreasingabsoluterisk aversion (Mo- the effects of payoff scale on the frequency of
hammed Abdellaoui et al., 2000).
Using the proportionof safe choices in each 12
of the ten decisions in the four real-payofftreat- If we restrictour attentionto those subjectswho never
ments, we obtained maximum-likelihood pa- switch back to Option A after choosing Option B, the noise
rameterestimates for this "power-expo"utility parameteris smaller, and both risk-aversionparametersare
larger.The estimates (and standarderrors)from this sample
function: /u = 0.134 (0.0046), r = 0.269 are I. = 0.110 (0.0041), r = 0.293 (0.017), and a = 0.032
(0.017), and a = 0.029 (0.0025), with a log- (0.003), with a log-likelihood of -247.8.

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
)

1654 THEAMERICANECONOMICREVIEW DECEMBER 2002

1 i--t--- xv.
0.9 - 0 .9 -
0.8 -Low 0 .8 - 20x Real Payoffs
Payoffs
0.7 - 0.7 - ',
', \\
o 0.6 - S 0..6-
? 0.5 - .5 - ',
= 0.4- '
0.4-
0.3 - . 0 .3-
v 0.2-, o .2 -

0.1 0).1- I U.' .


20 47
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 89 10 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 I(1
-
Decision Decision

.9 6-
0.9 0.9 - I
,I\
' \ 50x Real Payoffs 11 Ox Real Payoffs
0.8 0.8 - I
II
0.7 0.7 - II
' 0.6
II .<
i \\ io 0.6 - II
. 0.5
I'
II ~~ ~ II
^ :_
0.5 - II
II
D 0.4 0.4 - II
II~ ~ \ _, II
I
i 0.3 , I \ 0.3- I
v 0.2 ,II,
9L( 0.2 - 1
"A

II
0.1 0.1- II
I
0 0v
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10
Decision Decision

FIGURE 6. PROPORTION OF SAFE CHOICES IN EACH DECISION: DATA AVERAGES AND PREDICTIONS

Note: Data [thick lines], risk neutrality [thin dashed lines], and predictions [thick dashed lines] with noise, for the hybrid
"power-expo"utility function with r = 0.269, a = 0.029, and noise = 0.134).

safe choices, and (2) decreasing absolute risk tive Utility with Revealed Preference: Ex-
aversion, which avoids absurdamounts of risk perimental Arguments Based on Prospect
aversion for high-stakes gambles. Behavior Theory." Working paper, CREED, Univer-
across all treatmentsconforms closely to the sity of Amsterdam, 2000.
predictionsof this model. Arrow, Kenneth J. Aspects of the theory of risk
One implicationof these results is that, con- bearing. Helsinki: Academic Bookstores,
trary to Kahnemanand Tversky's supposition, 1965.
subjects facing hypothetical choices cannot Bernoulli, Daniel. "Specimen Theoriae Novae de
imagine how they would actually behave under Mensura Sortis." Comentarii Academiae Sci-
high-incentive conditions. Moreover, these dif- entiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae, 1738, 5,
ferences are not symmetric: subjects typically pp. 175-92 [translated by L. Sommer in
underestimate the extent to which they will Econometrica, January 1954, 22(1), pp. 23-
avoid risk. Second, the clear evidence for risk 36].
aversion, even with low stakes, suggests the Binswanger,HansP. "AttitudeTowardRisk: Ex-
potential danger of analyzing behavior under perimental Measurement in Rural India."
the simplifying assumptionof risk neutrality. American Journal of Agricultural Econom-
ics, August 1980, 62, pp. 395-407.
REFERENCES Bosch-Domenech, Antoni and Silvestre, Joaquim.
"Does Risk Aversion or Attraction Depend
Abdellaoui, Mohammed; Barrios, Carolina and on Income?" Economics Letters, December
Wakker, Peter P. "Reconciling Introspec- 1999, 65(3), pp. 265-73.

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL.92 NO. 5 HOLTAND LAURY:RISKAVERSIONAND INCENTIVEEFFECTS 1655

Campo, Sandra; Perrigne, Isabelle and Vuong, Isaac, R. Mark and James, Duncan. "Just Who
Quang."Semi-ParametricEstimationof First- Are You Calling Risk Averse?" Journal of
Price Auctions with Risk Aversion." Work- Risk and Uncertainty,March2000, 20(2), pp.
ing paper,University of SouthernCalifornia, 177-87.
2000. Kachelmeier, Steven J. and Shehata, Mohamed.
Chen, Kay-Yut and Plott, Charles R. "Nonlinear "Examining Risk Preferences Under High
Behaviorin Sealed Bid First-PriceAuctions." MonetaryIncentives:ExperimentalEvidence
Games and Economic Behavior, October from the People's Republic of China."Amer-
1998, 25(1), pp. 34-78. ican Economic Review, December 1992,
Cox, James C. and Oaxaca, Ronald L. "Is Bid- 82(5), pp. 1120-41.
ding Behavior Consistent with Bidding The- Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos. "Prospect
ory for Private Value Auctions?" in R. M. Theory:An Analysis of Choice Under Risk."
Isaac, ed., Research in experimentaleconom- Econometrica, March 1979, 47(2), pp. 263-
ics, Vol. 6. Greenwich,CT: JAI Press, 1996, 91.
pp. 131-48. Luce, Duncan.Individualchoice behavior. New
Cox, James C. and Sadiraj, Vjollca. "Risk Aver- York: John Wiley & Sons, 1959.
sion and Expected-UtilityTheory:Coherence Pratt,John W. "Risk Aversion in the Small and
for Small- and Large-Stakes Gambles." in the Large." Econometrica, January-April
Workingpaper,University of Arizona, 2001. 1964, 32(1-2), pp. 122-36.
Eckel, Catherine;Grossman,Philip;Lutz, Nancy Rabin, Matthew."Risk Aversion and Expected
and Padmanabhan, V. "Playing it Safe: Gen- Utility Theory: A Calibration Theorem."
der Differences in Risk Aversion." Working Econometrica, January 2000, 68(5), pp.
paper, Virginia Tech, 1998. 1281-92.
Goeree,JacobK. and Holt, CharlesA. "A Model Saha, Atanu. "Expo-PowerUtility: A Flexible
of Noisy Introspection."Workingpaper,Uni- Form for Absolute and Relative Risk Aver-
versity of Virginia, 2000. sion."AmericanJournal of AgriculturalEco-
Goeree,Jacob K.; Holt, CharlesA. and Palfrey, nomics, November 1993, 75(4), pp. 905-13.
Thomas."QuantalResponse Equilibriumand Shupp, Robert S. and Williams, Arlington W.
Overbidding in Private-Value Auctions." "Risk Preference Differentials of Small
Working paper, CaliforniaInstituteof Tech- Groupsand Individuals."Workingpaper,In-
nology, 1999. diana University, 2001.
. "Risk Aversion in Games with Mixed Siegel, Sydney. Nonparametric statistics. New
Strategies." Working paper, University of York: McGraw-HillBook Company, 1956.
Virginia, 2000. Smith, Vernon L. and Walker, James M. "Re-
Harrison,GlennW. "Theoryand Misbehaviorin wards, Experience, and Decision Costs in
First-Price Auctions." American Economic First Price Auctions." Economic Inquiry,
Review, September1989, 79(4), pp. 749-62. April 1993, 31(2), pp. 237-44.

This content downloaded from 132.210.236.20 on Wed, 28 Oct 2015 16:00:48 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like