Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 48

Left on the Cutting Room Floor:

Two Failed Efforts to Change the American Judiciary’s Constitutional Form and Function

By: Zachary Werrell


23 Dec. 2021
Constitutional Law II: Origins

I. Introduction.
On the journey from the earliest conceptualizations of an American national

government to Ratification of the Constitution and subsequent amendments, the

American Constitution has synthesized a vast array of principles, doctrines, and

structures into one. From the familiar principle of separation of powers, or

structural tripartite framework of the federal government, to more obscure

doctrines better enumerated in countless learned works—our Federal Constitution

embodies a variety of disparate ideas in a unified and coherent manner.

Along this journey of creation, though, an equally vast and disparate array of

ideas were rejected for inclusion into the Constitution—whether due to

compromises, substitutions, or even flat-out losing on a vote at the convention.

These rejected ideas, left flittering to the floor as the final Constitution took shape,

ignite the imagination of any curious modern reader of our Constitution’s history.

Studying these rejected concepts lend itself easily to speculative history, series of

what ifs, and thought experiments—how different our Constitution could have

looked, how dissimilar the United States would function today. Though studying

these rejected proposals will not directly inform the meaning of the constitution,

studying the reasons why these ideas were rejected can shed light on the ideas that

were ultimately included and America’s constitutional order.

1
Specifically, this paper will focus on two concepts that enjoyed significant

traction during the founding era, but ultimately were not included into the

Constitution: the Council of Revision and removal of Federal judges by Congress

and the President. Section II will present the history and theory behind the Council

of Revision proposed by James Madison at the Constitutional Convention with the

Virginia Plan. Section III will chronicle the theories behind, and various attempts to

make Federal judges subject to removal by Congress and or the President. Section

IV will conclude with meditations on the subject.

II. The Counsel of Revision.


Amongst the various items included in the Virginia Plan introduced to the

Constitutional Convention, Proposal Eight called for the creation of Council of

Revision, a body composed of a mix of the national executive and judicial officers,

empowered to negative bills passed by both the National Legislature and the state

legislatures, subject to override by the Congress. This provision of the Virginia plan

ultimately failed by a narrow margin at Convention despite spirited debate.

Section A will introduce Proposal Eight of the Virginia Plan which first

proposed the Counsel of Revision. Section B will trace the historical and theoretical

history behind the Counsel of Revision. Section C will detail the debates over

Proposal Eight at the Constitutional Convention. Second D will detail the demise of

the Proposal and later reflections on the results of its rejection.

A. Proposal Eight of the Virginia Plan.


The uncertainty surrounding the Constitutional Convention was dwarfed

only by the anxieties of the delegates making their way to Philadelphia. The

2
Convention was called under the auspices of amending the Articles of

Confederation—the initial national governmental structure operating during the

Revolution and subsequently thereafter. Though the Convention almost

immediately embraced scrapping the Articles of Confederation and replacing it with

a new national Constitution, the delegates to the convention gathered intending to

fix the Articles. They brought—amongst others—structural, legal, and functional

complaints of deficiencies in the Articles and some notions of how to remedy them.

None of the delegates to the Constitutional Convention came with an articulated,

comprehensive plan for a new constitution to replace—save James Madison.1

Shortly before the commencement of the proceedings, Madison sought to beat the

other delegates to the punch and laid out what would become known as the Virginia

Plan.

The Virginia Plan called for much of what is found in our current

Constitution and laid the necessary foundation for much of the rest. It proposed

many of the innovations found in our current Constitution: a bicameral

legislature—one elected by the people directly, a distinct and separate executive, the

three distinct branches of government; the list goes on. But not everything proposed

in the Virginia Plan was adopted at the Constitutional Convention.

Proposal Eight of James Madison’s Virginia Plan is one such rejected

proposal. It called for the creation of a Counsel of Revision; a quasi-Judicial body

with the power to declare bills in any legislature—State or Federal—null subject to

a Congressional override.
1
Our Unconventional Founding, 62 U. CHI. L. REV. 475, 507.
3
Though seemingly alien to most modern constitutional students, Proposal

Eight of the Virginia Plan was not just something Madison came up with on the fly

that morning before the convention. No—Madison’s Council of Revision was drawn

directly from long and rich traditions in English and American law; and was itself

firmly grounded in constitutional theory. Thus, before detailing Proposal Eight’s

fate at the Constitutional Convention, Section B will detail the historical and

theoretical origins of the Counsel of Revision.

B. Theoretical and Historical Origins of The Council of Revision.


The Counsel of Revision as proposed by Madison in the Virginia Plan was

based firmly in both English jurisprudence and Revolutionary American practice, as

well as being derived from well-founded constitutional theory in its own right.

1. In English Law.
One key inspiration for Madison’s Council of Revision was the English Privy

Council. By the time of the American Revolution, this Council had become an

institution in England and the British Empire. Early English Kings relied on a

council of wise men to assist in the administration of the Kingdom.2 These so-called

witan would help the King declare the law, and after the Norman invasion, would

come to compose the King’s Court.3 The King’s Court performed the executive,

judicial, and legislative functions; and it was from this Court that common law

courts and the Privy Council would emerge.4 Primarily used to implement the

King’s will, the Privy Council was generally a tool of the English Monarchy to

2
COMMENT: The Council of Revision and the Limits of Judicial Power., 56 U. CHI.
L. REV. 235, 237 (“Limits of Judicial Power”).
3
Id.
4
Id.
4
ensure the executive, judicial, and legislative were working in concert. By the

Seventeenth Century, the Privy Council would come to exist as a quasi-judicial body

with a hand in the legislative and executive functions within the Kingdom.5 The

Council had the power to withhold its consent to legislation on the King’s behalf,

and oversaw much of the judiciary.6

Meanwhile, the Parliament in England had begun to grow in both its

legitimacy and influence in English law with respect to the Crown. Much of this

gain by the Parliament would come at the Privy Council’s expense, especially within

England proper. During the English Civil War with the Act of 1640, the Parliament

stripped the Privy Council of its judicial power in England, relegating the Privy

Council to a largely powerless role with respect to Parliamentary legislation.7

Nonetheless, the Privy Council remained influential and consequential

throughout the rest of the Empire’s Territories. The Act of 1640 had only rendered

the Privy Council impotent in England, and thus, as the Empire grew in size,

complexity, and scale, so too did the influence of the Privy Council.8 One need not

scour the far-flung corners of the English Empire to see this increase in eminence of

the Privy Council; simply looking across the Irish Sea would reveal the Privy

Council’s tremendous power. Sir William Blackstone described the power the Privy

Council had in Ireland’s lawmaking:

The method made use of in Ireland, as stated by sir Edward Coke, of


making statutes in their parliaments, according to Poynings' law, of
5
Id.
6
Id.
7
Id., at 238.
8
Id.
5
which hereafter, is this: 1. The lord lieutenant and council of Ireland
must certify to the king under the great seal of Ireland the acts
proposed to be passed. 2. The king and council of England are to
consider, approve, alter, or reject the said acts; and certify them back
again under the great seal of England. And then, 3. They are to be
proposed, received, or rejected in the parliament of Ireland. By this
means nothing was left to the parliament in Ireland, but a bare
negative or power of rejecting, not of proposing, any law. But the usage
now is, that bills are often framed in either house of parliament under
the denomination of heads for a bill or bills; and in that shape they are
offered to the consideration of the lord lieutenant and privy council,
who then reject them at pleasure, without transmitting them to
England.9

Not only did the Privy Council have the power to negative legislation, they

were even empowered to alter it. Moreover, the Privy Council did all this on behalf

of the Crown, but never even had to transmit the considerations to the

Crown—their decision was final and determinative on the issue.

The American Colonies’ experience with the Privy Council was similar to the

Irish; though it followed different contours. In 1696, to manage the increasingly

complex and demanding task of reviewing and adjudicating Empire-wide

legislation, the Privy Council enacted a system of legislative review, delegating the

first inquiry into legislation to the Board of Trade.10 The Board could recommend

legislation it found defective to the Privy Council for disallowance, and, should the

Privy Council agree with the Board, the act would become null and void.11

The Privy Council not only possessed this power to negative colonial

legislatures in theory—it exerted this power with regularity in the American


9
1 William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, at 100. (Emphasis
added.).
10
Irving Kauffman, The Essence of Judicial Independence, 80 COL. L. REV. 671–701,
679.
11
Id.
6
Colonies. In one controversy arising in colonial Georgia, the Georgia Assembly

passed legislation which would quiet title in certain disputed lands in favor of one

group of claimants over another. The Privy Council did not mince words explaining

the reasons for nullifying the act, calling it “arbitrary, irregular and unjust, and

Subversive of those established Principles of the Constitution.”12

Thus, prior to the American Revolution, the American colonists had become

quite familiar with the workings of that quasi-judicial body called the Privy Council,

empowered to revise or annul their colonial legislation. Though easy to imagine that

the colonists would have developed a strong aversion to the Privy Council and its

intermeddling in their affairs, such was not the case.

2. New York’s Council of Revision.


Shortly after the inauguration of the Revolutionary War, New York adopted a

new state constitution—which included a provision creating what would come to be

known as the Council of Revision.13 Like the King’s Privy Council, New York’s

Council of Revision had the power to interject before bills passed by the New York

legislature became law.14 Unlike the Privy Council, which had developed its role

over a long tumultuous history, the New York Council of Revision was a novel

solution to two familiar problems: checking the legislature and keeping too much

power out of one man’s hand.

As enacted, Section III of the New York Constitution read:

And whereas laws inconsistent with the spirit of this constitution, or


with the public good, may be hastily passed: Be it ordained that the
12
Id.
13
Limits of Judicial Power, at 243.
14
Id.
7
governor for the time being, the chancellor, and the judges of the
supreme court, or any two of them, together with the governor, shall be
and hereby are, constituted as a council to revise all bills to be passed
into laws by the legislature. . . .15

In essence, the New York’s Council of Revision is a novel variation of the

traditional veto power. Instead of simply investing the veto power with the

Governor, the New York Constitution required the Governor be joined by judicial

officers from New York’s highest courts of equity and law in revising—though not

striking down—legislation. In effect, the New York Constitution divested the

Executive of sole authority to veto legislation, and required the power be shared

with the highest judicial officers in the state. Though eventually abolished in 1821,

during its nearly-44-year existence New York’s Council of Revision carried out its

call to great effect and did so without overreaching or causing constitutional crises.

In those 44 years, the Council sent just 169 bills of the legislature back for

reconsideration, with the legislature overriding the council and repassing

51—adopting 26 with various degrees of modification.16

The New York Council of Revision often sent comments back with their

rejected bills, and often, though not always, invoked constitutional reasons for doing

so. Rather straightforwardly, the Council would reject bills using familiar

constitutional reasoning—declaring the bill rejected as “inconsistent with the Spirit

of the Constitution.”17 Other rejections came on procedural grounds, with the


15
Ben Penley Poore, 2 The Federal and State Constitutions, Colonial Charters, and
Other Organic Laws of the United States 1328 (GPO, 2d ed 1878).
16
Frank M. Prescott and Joseph F. Zimmerman, The Council of Revision and the
Veto of Legislation in New York State: 1777-1821 2 (SUNY Albany, Graduate School
of Public Affairs, 1972).
17
Limits of Judicial Power, at 245.
8
Council of Revision rejecting one bill because “the persons affected thereby hav[ing]

an opportunity of being heard.”18 Sometimes, the Council of Revision would offer

simple, vague reasons for rejecting a bill, with one being rejected simply for being

“inconsistent with the public good.”19 Thus, in practice, New York’s Council of

revision had not only served as a constitutional check on the legislature, but had

also exerted its powers to advance procedural and policy goals.

New York’s Council of Revision, despite its peculiarity and novel blend of the

executive and judicial, earned a strong reputation in the Colonies for its

performance. Alexander Hamilton professed his admiration for New York’s Privy

Council and its general reputation in Federalist 73:

This qualified negative, as has been elsewhere remarked, is in this


State vested in a council, consisting of the governor, with the
chancellor and judges of the Supreme Court, or any two of them. It has
been freely employed upon a variety of occasions, and frequently with
success. And its utility has become so apparent, that persons who, in
compiling the Constitution, were violent opposers of it, have from
experience become its declared admirers.20

James Madison was well aware of New York’s Council of Revision21, as well as

the Privy Council, but did not only draw from practical experience and history in

developing Proposal Eight’s Council of Revision. Despite posing a potential

departure from the strictures of separation of powers, the Council of Revision as

proposed by James Madison drew from a deep well of constitutional theory.

18
Id.
19
Id., at 246.
20
The Federalist No. 73, at 446 (Alexander Hamilton) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961).
21
Limits of Judicial Power, at 247.
9
3. Support for the Council of Revision in Constitutional
Theory.
Both the Privy Council and New York’s Council of Revision Councils were

composed of a mixture of the judicial and executive, and were empowered to

intercede in the promulgation of legislation. Additionally, the same judicial officers

making up the Council and having input on the passage of bills would subsequently

have the power of judicial review over legislative acts.22 To some thinkers, bodies

such as the Privy Council or New York’s Council of revision, composed of a blend of

executive and judicial, with the power to interject in legislation, violated

fundamental constitutional theory—the complete and impregnable separation of

powers between political branches.23

Montesquieu’s Spirit of the Laws was not the first articulation of the concept

of separation of powers, but it was the most influential articulation of the principle

in the English speaking world at the time. This was partially an accident of

historical timing—Spirit of the Laws was published in the decades prior to the

American Revolution, and thus was a timely work on an important subject.

Montesquieu studied the various forms of governmental organization, and

specifically focused on what divided despotism, monarchy, and democracy

Despotism, according to Montesquieu, sees that the “immense power of the prince is

devolved intirely upon those whom he is pleased to intrust with the administration.

Persons, capable of setting a value upon themselves, would be likely to create

22
Id., at 249.
23
Limits of Judicial Power, at 241.
10
disturbances. Fear must, therefore, depress their spirits, and extinguish even the

least sense of ambition.”24

But to Montesquieu, despotism and monarchy are not one in the same.

Monarchy merely speaks to the condition of having an embodied sovereign, but

having an embodied sovereign did not necessarily result in despotism. “The whole

difference is, that, in a monarchy, the prince receives instruction, at the same time

that his ministers have greater abilities, and are more versed in public affairs, than

the ministers of a despotic government.”25

Despotic government then, according to Montesquieu, arises when the

sovereign or some voice within the government stands above and outside

constraints of the machinery of government. The despot commands the entire

machinery of the government according to his will, whereas the monarch exists

within and subject to constraints imposed by empowered ministers. When one voice

is capable of commanding the entire machinery of government, despotism arises.

Hence, separating powers between branches was essential to preclude the

development of despotism. By separating powers, the various branches of

government would be capable of resisting such despotism individually, and by

collective action.

Montesquieu did not have a monopoly on theoretical conceptualizations of the

separation of powers however. Blackstone strongly extolled the virtues of a strong

separation of powers—specifically with respect to the judicial department.

24
I Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws, b. III. ch. 9 (1748).
25
I Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws, b. III. ch. 10 (1748).
11
In this distinct and separate existence of the judicial power, in a
peculiar body of men, nominated indeed, but not removable at
pleasure, by the crown, consists one main preservative of the public
liberty; which cannot subsist long in any state, unless the
administration of common justice be in some degree separated both
from the legislative and also from the executive power. Were it joined
with the legislative, the life, liberty, and property, of the subject would
be in the hands of arbitrary judges, whose decisions would be then
regulated only by their own opinions, and not by any fundamental
principles of law; which, though legislators may depart from, yet
judges are bound to observe. Were it joined with the executive, this
union might soon be an overballance for the legislative.26

But Blackstone did not believe that separation of powers necessarily meant

the branches would be hermetically sealed off from one another. Blackstone’s

conception of separation of powers extolled the virtues of a complex, interwoven,

and potentially disruptive system of checks and balances between political

branches.27 In Blackstone’s formulation, these interlocking mechanisms between

the branches were necessary to ensure the disparate branches of government

function coherently and in a mutually beneficial manner. Through strategic political

cross-pollination, the separate branches would not devolve into warring factions but

instead harmonize into effective governance.

Thus every branch of our civil polity supports and is supported,


regulates and is regulated, by the rest; for the two houses naturally
drawing in two directions of opposite interest, and the prerogative in
another still different from them both, they mutually keep each other
from exceeding their proper limits; while the whole is prevented from
separation, and artificially connected together by the mixed nature of
the crown, which is a part of the legislative, and the sole executive
magistrate. Like three distinct powers in mechanics, they jointly impel
the machine of government in a direction different from what either,
26
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 1: Blackstone, William.
Commentaries on the Laws of England: A Facsimile of the First Edition of
1765–1769. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979.
27
Sir William M. Blackstone, 1 Commentaries on the Laws of England, at 48–52.
12
acting by themselves, would have done; but at the same time in a
direction partaking of each, and formed out of all; a direction which
constitutes the true line of the liberty and happiness of the
community.28

This Blackstonian conceptualization of separation of powers—messy and

interwoven—is not inherently mutually exclusive with separation of powers

generally, though many American Founders came to believe that the Blackstonian

articulation was incompatible with Montesque’s call for separation of powers.29

Whether Montesquieu, should he have found himself at the Constitutional

Convention, would have applied his notions of separation of powers as dogmatically

as his American adherents did, or in a more practical, Blackstonian manner is a

discussion outside the scope of this paper. As Section C will develop, however, the

delegates to the Constitutional Convention proceeded to have debates on James

Madison’s Council of Revision along these philosophical lines.

C. The Council of Revision’s Fate at the Constitutional


Convention.
Though James Madison blindsided the delegates to the Constitutional

Convention with the Virginia Plan, Proposal Eight of the Virginia Plan was firmly

rooted in theory and practice familiar to all in attendance. The full text of Proposal

Eight of the Virginia plan read:

Resolved that the Executive and a convenient number of the National


Judiciary, ought to compose a Council of revision with authority to
examine every act of the National Legislature before it shall operate, &
every act of a particular Legislature before a Negative thereon shall be
final; and that the dissent of the said Council shall amount to a
28
Id., at 151.
29
Limits of Judicial Power, at 241.
13
rejection, unless the Act of the National Legislature be again passed,
or that of a particular Legislature be again negatived by ______ of the
members of each branch.30

The proposal contains these main components: a body composed of a

combination of the judicial and the executive; empowered to negative all Federal

and state laws prior to enactment; subject to an override by the National

Legislature.

The delegate’s reception of Madison’s Council of Revision would largely come

down to whether they were dogmatic supporters of their conceptualization of

Montesquieu’s absolute separation of powers, or whether they held a more practical,

Blackstonian conceptualization of separation of powers.

1. Arguments Against the Council at Convention.


Opponents to the Council of Revision argued that the Council of Revision

represented an intolerable violation of their interpretation of Montesquieu’s

separation of powers.31 John Dickinson of Pennsylvania forcefully articulated this

position. To Dickinson, the Council of Revision was an “improper mixture of powers”

which would derail the overall constitutional design separating powers between the

branches.32 Similarly, Elbridge Gerry of Connecticut called the Council of Revision

“an improper coalition between the Executive & Judiciary departments.”33 Such

objections are rooted in theories derived from a dogmatic interpretation of

30
Butler, Max Farrand, ed, 1 The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, 21 note
54 (Yale, 1911).
31
Limits of Judicial Power, at 253.
32
Id., at 253–54.
33
Id., at 254.
14
Montesquieu’s separation of powers. Under this conceptualization, any mixture of

any of the branches would be considered “improper.”

Arguments against the Council of Revision did not always arise from

reasoning from first principles. Others made practical arguments against the

Council of Revisions, informed by their understanding of separation of powers.

Gerry further argued that with a veto lodged in the executive, judicial review would

provide “a sufficient check agst. [legislative] encroachments,” making the Council of

Revision’s existence duplicative and unnecessary.34 Similarly, Luther Martin argued

that to give the Council input into legislation while the judiciary empowered with

judicial review would give the judicial system a “double negative” over the

operations of the legislature.35 Moreover, it was argued that having the judicial

branch involved in the passage and interpretation of legislation would

inappropriately prejudice justices reviewing the legislation after just having been

involved in its passage. Nathaniel Gorham of Massachusetts extolled this notion,

"[j]udges ought to carry into the exposition of the laws no prepossessions with

regard to them."36

Others argued that the Council of Revision would give the judicial branch an

inappropriate amount of influence over decisions of national policy, representing

both a theoretical conflict as well as inappropriately exposing the judicial branch to

the whims and dangers of national politics. For many Framers, the judicial branch’s

proper function was deciding disputes between parties—emphatically excluding the


34
Id., at 255.
35
Id.
36
Id., at 254.
15
potential for judicial involvement in questions of national policy.37 According to this

line of thought, only the branches with direct electoral ties to the People were the

proper branches in which to decide national policy disputes. After implementing

national policy, the political officers could be reelected or defeated depending on

their constituent’s impressions of their decisions. The wholly-unelected judicial

branch, however, would be completely precluded from such popular input. Moreover,

because these judges are unelected and thus a step removed from the people, Luther

Martin argued the public confidence in the Judiciary would quickly erode "if

[judges] are employed in the task of remonstrating agst. popular measures of the

Legislature."38

2. Arguments In Favor of the Council at Convention.


Proponents of the Council of Revision, led by James Madison, articulated

their support for the proposal in Blackstonian theoretical terms informed by a

more-nuanced understanding of Montesquieu, as well as voicing support based on

practical considerations in favor of the creation of the Council of Revision.

James Madison believed it was impossible to construct a government in a

dogmatic, theoretical manner—the practical realities involved require creative

solutions and compromises in order to effectuate the whole experiment.39 This view

largely won out at the Constitutional Convention, as theoretical conflicts were

largely subordinated in pragmatic compromises. But for a majority of the delegates

at the Constitutional Convention, the Council of Revision’s theoretical conflicts with

37
Id., at 255.
38
Id.
39
Id., at 242.
16
their interpretation of Montiesquieu’s separation of powers were too much to

overcome.

But James Madison strongly rejected the idea that Montiesquieu stood for

complete and total separation of powers. To Madison, Montiesquieu’s call for

complete separation of powers was not aimed at ensuring that the three branches of

government should have absolutely no influence over the functioning of the other.

Rather, Madison argued, Montesquieu was making a top-down argument—it was

not the involvement of other branches in any other branch’s functions that was

inapposite to good government per se. Rather, the fundamental impetus of

Montesquieu’s separation of powers is preventing one branch from exercising the

powers or discharging the duties of another branch. According to Madison,

Montesquieu’s concern was not the joint action of two branches, or even the

intermingling of functions between the two; but rather the legislative acting as the

judicial or executive, the judicial acting as the legislative or executive, etc.

From these facts by which Montesquieu was guided it may clearly be


inferred, that in saying “there can be no liberty where the legislative
and executive powers are united in the same person, or body of
magistrates,” or “if the power of judging be not separated from the
legislative and executive powers,” he did not mean that these
departments ought to have no partial agency in, or no controul over the
acts of each other. His meaning, as his own words import, and still
more conclusively as illustrated by the example in his eye, can amount
to no more than this, that where the whole power of one department is
exercised by the same hands which possess the whole power of another
department, the fundamental principles of a free constitution, are
subverted.40

40
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 1, Chap. 10 (Separation of Powers), Doc. 14:
Hamilton, Alexander; Madison, James; and Jay, John. The Federalist, 323–31.
Edited by Jacob E. Cooke. Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1961.
17
Such an understanding, according to Madison, was the only way to properly

interpret Montesquieu, especially considering how the model for Montesquieu’s

work—England—functioned in reality.

This would have been the case in the constitution examined by him, if
the King who is the sole executive magistrate, had possessed also the
compleat legislative power, or the supreme administration of justice; or
if the entire legislative body, had possessed the supreme judiciary, or
the supreme executive authority. This however is not among the vices
of that constitution. The magistrate in whom the whole executive
power resides cannot of himself make a law, though he can put a
negative on every law, nor administer justice in person, though he has
the appointment of those who do administer it. The judges can exercise
no executive prerogative, though they are shoots from the executive
stock, nor any legislative function, though they may be advised with by
the legislative councils. The entire legislature, can perform no judiciary
act, though by the joint act of two of its branches, the judges may be
removed from their offices; and though one of its branches is possessed
of the judicial power in the last resort. The entire legislature again can
exercise no executive prerogative, though one of its branches
constitutes the supreme executive magistracy; and another, on the
empeachment of a third, can try and condemn all the subordinate
officers in the executive department.41

Proponents of the Council of Revision also argued that a purely executive

veto would be an insufficient check against the legislature, and that the combined

weight of the judicial and executive branches exercising a check on the legislature

would be both more effective and better promote balance between the branches. At

the Convention, James Wilson argued that a joint executive and judicial veto was

necessary to marshall the full strength of both in battling back an overreaching

legislature.42 Similarly, Madison argued that adding judicial involvement in

exercising the veto would “render [the] Check or negative more respectable.”43 Thus,
41
Id.
42
Limits of Judicial Power, at 249.
43
Id.
18
Wilson and Madison argued that including the judicial in the exercise of the veto

power would not only render the check more complete, but that it would also

increase the validity of that check with the People and their elected officials.

Madison offered a second pragmatic argument for the inclusion of the

judiciary in the exercise of the veto—judicial officers are significantly better-versed

in the nuance and intricacy of law and constitutional questions than are legislators.

Instead of merely getting input from the executive by way of the veto, giving the

legislature access to the wisdom of the judicial branch "would be useful to the

Legislature by the valuable assistance it would give in preserving a consistency,

conciseness, perspicuity & technical propriety in the laws."44 Oliver Ellsworth of

Connecticut recognized that the legislative process often involves legal or

constitutional questions, and that “[of] this the Judges alone will have competent

information."45

Finally, Madison argued that having the judiciary have a role in the creation

of bills would be far more convenient and protective of individual rights than

relegating the judiciary to only striking down laws after they had been passed and

brought into operation.

It may be said that the Judicial authority under our new system will
keep the States within their proper limits, and supply the place of a
negative on their laws. The answer is, that it is more convenient to
prevent the passage of a law, than to declare it void after it is passed;
that this will be particularly the case, where the law aggrieves
individuals, who may be unable to support an appeal agst. a State to
the supreme Judiciary; that a State which would violate the
Legislative rights of the Union, would not be very ready to obey a
44
Id., at 250.
45
Id.
19
Judicial decree in support of them, and that a recurrence to force,
which in the event of disobedience would be necessary, is an evil which
the new Constitution meant to exclude as far as possible.46

James Wilson similarly argued the utility of having a Council with

revisionary powers was superior to one only having the power to retroactively annul

legislation. Wilson believed that judges would be less inclined to strike down

legislation after it had passed than to intercede prospectively in ameliorating

constitutional conflicts.

Laws may be unjust, may be unwise, may be dangerous, may be


destructive; and yet not be so unconstitutional as to justify the Judges
in refusing to give them effect. Let them have a share in the
Revisionary power, and they will have an opportunity of taking notice
of these character[istics] of a law, and of counteracting, by the weight
of their opinions the improper views of the Legislature.47

D. Convention Results And Aftermath.


Ultimately, the Council of Revision was rejected multiple times at the

Constitutional Convention. On June 6th 1787, the Convention voted down Proposal

Eight by a eight to three margin.48 Upon reconsideration on July 21st, the

Convention rejected the Proposal again, this time by a four to three vote (with two

delegations divided and thus abstaining).49 Finally, on August 15th, Madison

proposed a final compromise to save the theories embodied in the Council of

Revision, giving both the executive and judicial their own, separate chance to

46
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 1, Chap. 17 (Constitutional Government),
Doc. 22: The Papers of James Madison, 10:207–15. Edited by William T. Hutchinson
et al. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1962–77 (vols. 1–10);
Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1977–(vols. 11–).
47
Limits of Judicial Power, at 250.
48
Id., at 257.
49
Id.
20
review legislation, rather than combining the powers in the Council of Review. This

last-ditch effort by Madison failed eight to three.50

And with that final vote, the Council of Revision and its pragmatic

descendents finally died—and the instantiation of judicial review was complete.

Madison continued to lament this failure for decades.

These considerations remind me of the attempts in the Convention to


vest in the Judiciary Dept. a qualified negative on Legislative bills.
Such a Controul, restricted to Constitutional points, besides giving
greater stability & system to the rules of expounding the Instrument,
would have precluded the question of a Judiciary annulment of
Legislative Acts. 51

III. Removal of Federal Judges.


While revolutionary both in structure and precedent, the American

Constitution drew heavily on known lessons learned from the English legal

experience. One such lesson was the need for an independent judiciary—one where

judicial officers did not rely on the will of the King alone for their positions and

authority. Despite totally overthrowing the monarchical legal authority during the

American Revolution, the Framers extended the English legal innovations

providing judicial independence to our Federal judges, and pushed these notions to

their logical extreme: life tenure, removal only for bad behavior, and non-reducable

salaries—all commanded by the Constitution. But this outcome was not assured, as

the debate over adding a constitutional provision allowing the removing of Federal

50
Id.
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 2, Cl. 1, Doc. 70: The Writings of
51

James Madison, 8:406–07. Edited by Gaillard Hunt. 9 vols. New York: G. P.


Putnam’s Sons, 1900–10.
21
judges continued from the opening of the Constitutional Convention for nearly 30

years, finally concluding with a failed Constitutional Amendment in 1811.

Section III will begin in Part 1 by introducing the development of judicial

independence under pre-revolutionary English Law. Part 2 will trace the

implementation of America’s expansive version of judicial

independence—structurally and constitutionally. Part 3 will explore the concerns

voiced about America’s implementation of English judicial independence, with Part

4 chronicling the failed attempts to constitutionally permit the recall of Federal

judges.

A. Development of Judicial Independence in England.


As Mel Brooks once infamously quipped, “it’s good to be the King.” Though

playing the soon-to-be-beheaded King Louis XVI of France and speaking of his

unchecked sexual improprieties with unwilling female subjects, this line brilliantly

understates the absolute and terrifying power European Monarchs wielded

throughout much of history. In such systems, the Monarch is sovereign—all power

flows from and through the crown. The judicial system is no exception.

But as English law developed out of its primordial, Medieval substrate, it

became apparent that the impartial administration of justice was impeded by the

fear of a crown (or potentially a guillotine) floating over the judge’s heads when

rendering decisions—most especially decisions against the King. This reality stood

in direct conflict with the development of English common law’s developing

protection of individual rights, impartiality and consistency of legal decisions, and

22
burgeoning theories of separation of powers. Thus, the English law developed a

number of innovations intended to mute or eliminate these conflicts.

1. Life Tenure, Good Behavior, and Fixed Salaries.


Personal independence for judges in England developed over many centuries

leading into America’s Revolution. Initially coming in the form of small concessions

from the King, English judges would slowly be secured in their independence with

life tenure, during good behavior, and a salary immune from reduction. Though

these protections never became ubiquitous and uniform for all judicial positions in

England, they represented tremendous innovations advancing the impartiality of

justice. As Alexander Hamilton proclaimed, “[t]he standard of good behaviour for

the continuance in office of the judicial magistracy is certainly one of the most

valuable of the modern improvements in the practice of government.”52

To understand why Alexander Hamilton (and many other Framers) believed

these innovations promoting judicial independence in such high regard, one must

understand the development of this standard in England: the conflicts which

created the need, the gravity of the need itself, and how well judicial independence

ameliorated that need.

Joseph Story brilliantly expounded the initial conditions giving rise to the

need to create judicial independence in England. There, “the king is considered, as

the fountain of justice; not indeed as the author, but as the distributer of it; and he

possesses the exclusive prerogative of erecting courts of judicature, and appointing

52
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 11: Hamilton,
Alexander; Madison, James; and Jay, John. The Federalist, 521–30. Edited by Jacob
E. Cooke. Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1961.
23
the judges.”53 Headed by a hereditary monarch, English government and legal

systems were designed and developed around the Monarch’s authority. The judicial

system is no exception.

In antiquity, the King was the judicial system. But as history progressed, it

became increasingly difficult and eventually impossible for the King to hear cases.54

To effectuate the administration of justice, the King needed to at least empower

subordinates to hear and try cases, eventually leading to the devolution of the

judicial power from the King to the courts.

Indeed, in early times, the kings of England often in person heard and
decided causes between party and party. But as the constitution of
government became more settled, the whole judicial power was
delegated to the judges of the several courts of justice; and any
attempt, on the part of the king, now to exercise it in person, would be
deemed an usurpation.55

Simply establishing a court system, however, does nothing to actually ensure

that justice is impartially administered throughout a Kingdom. Courts require

judges, and so naturally enough the King would appoint officers to serve in that

role. But, at this stage of England’s historical development, a King with the power

to appoint was a King with the power to remove. This reality created untoward

pressures on judicial officers.

It is certain, that this power of the crown must have produced an


influence upon the administration, dangerous to private rights, and
subversive of the public liberties of the subjects. In political
accusations, in an especial manner, it must often have produced the
53
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 38: Story, Joseph.
Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States. 3 vols. Boston, 1833. (“Story,
Commentaries on the Constitution”).
54
Id.
55
Id.
24
most disgraceful compliances with the wishes of the crown; and the
most humiliating surrenders of the rights of the accused.56

Historically, all judicial officers served at the pleasure of the crown, during a

tenure of the crown’s choosing. “Anciently, the English judges held their offices

according to the tenure of their commissions, as prescribed by the crown, which was

generally during the pleasure of the crown, as is the tenure of office of the Lord

Chancellor, the judges of the courts of admiralty, and others, down to the present

day.”57

As Joseph Story chronicles, however, by the late 1500’s, England began to

shield some judicial officers from the pernicious influence of the Crown by

implementing an objective standard for continuation in judicial office. This

standard is tenure in office during good behavior. As opposed to the first standard,

service at the pleasure of the crown, permitting some judges to serve during good

behavior prevented those judges from being coerced or threatened by the Crown

arbitrarily. This standard was expanded over time. “In the time of Lord Coke, the

Barons of the Exchequer held their offices during good behaviour, while the judges

of the other courts of common law held them only during pleasure. And . . . [during]

restoration of Charles the Second, the commissions of the judges were during good

behaviour.”58

This innovation in English law—the standard of good behavior—began to

take hold during a tumultuous and consequential period in English History. As the

56
Id.
57
Id.
58
Id.
25
Sixteenth Century ended and the Seventeenth Century began, England found itself

in political turmoil—civil war, religious struggles, succession crises, and

revolution.59 Underlying most of the instability was the struggle between the

Monarchy and an increasingly-powerful Parliament for primacy in the English legal

order.60 Ultimately, with the Glorious Revolution of 1688 and the Bill of Rights 1689,

Parliament secured its dominance over the Monarchy in the English System.61

Newly emboldened and empowered, the Parliament began to assert its dominance

and circumscribe or limit the Monarch’s power in a variety of spheres.

One major Parliamentary advance was The Act of Settlement of 1701, passed

to ameliorate a succession crisis and install Sophia of Hanover as Monarch (to

dethrone Charles I’s line).62 Importantly, too, the Act included a significant change

to the Monarch’s power over the removal of judges sitting in common law courts.

The Settlement officially eliminated the previous standard, durante bene placito

(pleasure of the crown) and replaced it with quam diu bene se gesserint (good

behavior).63 The Parliament did not completely divest the Monarch of all power to

remove all judges, however, as they could still be removed, “by the king, upon the

address of both houses of parliament; and their offices expired by the demise of the

king.”64
59
Martha Andes Ziskind, Judicial Tenure in the American Constitution: English and
American Precedents, The Supreme Court Review, Vol. 1969 135-154, 137. The
University of Chicago Press, 1969 (“Judicial Tenure”).
60
Id.
61
Oxford J Legal Studies (1999) 19 (3): 365.
62
Id.
63
Joseph H. Smith, An Independent Judiciary: The Colonial Background, 124 U. PA.
L. REV. 1104 (1976). (“Colonial Background”).
64
Story, Commentaries on the Constitution, at §1602.
26
The English legal experiment with judicial independence was thus underway,

despite only protecting a fraction of judges with tenure during good behavior.

Systemic improvements resulting from this experiment impelled the English to

push forward with other variations on judicial independence. Undoubtedly, job

security certainly helps ensure the impartial administration of justice, but as

Alexander Hamilton said, “a power over a man’s subsistence amounts to a power

over his will.”65 Reforms allowing judges continue to hold their positions would do

little to insulate the judge if the judge is no longer being paid to hold that office.

This reality was not lost on the English.

Eventually, King George III—the King of England during America’s

Revolution—recommended Parliament pass a law requiring that every judge hold

their office during good behavior, including after the death of a Monarch, and to

secure their salaries during their commission. The Parliament obliged. Both the

King of England and Joseph Story extolled the virtue and importance of this act:

Upon that occasion, the monarch made a declaration, worthy of


perpetual remembrance, that “he looked upon the independence and
uprightness of the judges, as essential to the impartial administration
of justice; as one of the best securities of the rights and liberties of his
subjects; and as most conducive to the honour of the crown.” Indeed,
since the independence of the judges has been secured by this
permanent duration of office, the administration of justice has, with a
single exception, flowed on in England, with an uninterrupted, and
pure, and unstained current. It is due to the enlightened tribunals of
that nation to declare, that their learning, integrity, and impartiality,
have commanded the reverence and respect, as well of America, as
Europe.66
65
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 12: Hamilton, Alexander;
Madison, James; and Jay, John. The Federalist, 531–34. Edited by Jacob E. Cooke.
Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1961.
66
Story, Commentaries on the Constitution, at §1602.
27
B. Constitutional Independence of Judges in America.
Unfortunately for the American Colonists, despite major concessions to the

Parliament in England, the Monarchy would retain enormous power over the

administration of justice in its possessions overseas. As with the Privy Council,

legal reforms promoting the independence of judges did not spread beyond the

shores of England. In fact, throughout the Colonial Era, England continued with the

practice of keeping judges only at the pleasure of the crown in the

Colonies67—denying Americans the relief resulting from these innovations becoming

increasingly-entrenched in English law.

The American Colonists, who believed themselves to be every bit as English

and imbued with all the same rights as Englishmen, had witnessed these

advancements in judicial independence taking place in England and incredible legal

improvements resulting therefrom. But they were denied the benefits of these

advancements. This disappointment contributed significantly to the Revolutionary

attitudes expressed in the American Colonies, ultimately culminating in the

Declaration of Independence. Thomas Jefferson specifically articulated this

grievance in the document: “He has obstructed the Administration of Justice, by

refusing his Assent to Laws for establishing Judiciary powers.—He has made

Judges dependent on his Will alone, for the tenure of their offices, and the amount

and payment of their salaries.”68

67
The Colonial Background, 124 U. Pa. L. Rev., at 1104 (1976).
68
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 2.
28
This complaint did not only manifest in the Declaration of Independence

itself. As the American Revolution took course, numerous states adopted

constitutional provisions or made declarations intending to forever instantiate

judicial independence in their jurisdictions. The Maryland Constitution of 1776, for

example, created a constitutional protection for the tenure of judicial officers while

exhibiting good behavior. “That the Chancellor, all Judges, the Attorney- General,

Clerks of the General Court, the Clerks of the County Courts, the Registers of the

Land Office, and the Registers of Wills, shall hold their commissions during good

behaviour, removable only for misbehaviour, on conviction in a Court of law.”69

Delaware similarly pronounced the importance of judicial independence in its 1776

Declaration of Rights, stating, “[t]hat the Independency and Uprightness of Judges

are essential to the impartial Administration of Justice, and a great Security to the

Rights and Liberties of the People.70

Thus, prior to the adoption of the Constitution, States and the Citizens

thereof proclaimed their strong support for an independent judiciary—though such

efforts only constituted internal, intra-state judicial independence. In adopting the

Constitution, however, the Framers would institute a national federal judiciary that

had not only secured the complete personal independence of judges—through life

69
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 5: Thorpe, Francis
Newton, ed. The Federal and State Constitutions, Colonial Charters, and Other
Organic Laws of the States, Territories, and Colonies Now or Heretofore Forming the
United States of America, 3:1697. 7 vols. Washington, D.C.: Government Printing
Office, 1909.
70
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 3: Sources of Our
Liberties, 340. Edited by Richard L. Perry under the general supervision of John C.
Cooper. [Chicago:] American Bar Foundation, 1952.
29
tenure, good behavior, and fixed salaries—but also the judiciary’s Constitutional

Independence as a whole.

1. Personal Independence: Tenure, Behavior, Salary.


Article III Section 1 of the Constitution commands that Federal judges will

have tenure so long as they maintain good behavior, and shall not have their

salaries diminished.

The Judges, both of the supreme and inferior Courts, shall hold their
Offices during good Behaviour, and shall, at stated Times, receive for
their Services, a Compensation, which shall not be diminished during
their Continuance in Office.71
In so doing, the Framers of the Constitution expanded the English

experiment in personally-secured judicial independence into a judiciary-wide,

constitutional command. The reasons were simple: English history proved that

insulating judges from personal coercion by other elements of the government

radically improves the chances that judges will feel pressure to save their own neck

and will feel secure in handing down just results, regardless of whether others in

power are offended. Article III, Section 1 of the Constitution took this lesson to its

logical extreme, which was not seen in England, as Joseph Story explained:

It is observable, that the constitution has declared, that the judges of


the inferior courts, as well as of the Supreme Court, of the United
States, shall hold their offices during good behaviour. In this respect
there is a marked contrast between the English government and our
own. In England the tenure is exclusively confined to the judges of the
superior courts, and does not (as we have already seen) even embrace all
of these.72

James Wilson flatly articulated the reasoning behind expanding these

protections to all Federal judges. “In their salaries, and in their offices, they ought
71
United States Constitution, Art. III, sec. 1.
72
Story, Commentaries on the Constitution, at §1621.
30
to be completely independent: in other words, they should be removed from the most

distant apprehension of being affected, in their judicial character and capacity, by

any thing, except their own behaviour and its consequences.”73

But should Federal judges display such ‘bad’ behavior, they could be removed

according to the impeachment provisions of Article II, Section 4. “The President,

Vice President and all civil Officers of the United States, shall be removed from

Office on Impeachment for, and Conviction of, Treason, Bribery, or other high

Crimes and Misdemeanors.”74 Though not explicitly including Federal judges by

name, the prevailing understanding of the Convention was that they too would be

subject to this impeachment protocol.75

2. Constitutional, Legal Independence.


Aside from completing the English project by Constitutionally ensuring

personal independence for all Federal judges, the Constitution of the United States

also radically redefined foundational structural precepts of English law by making

the Federal Judiciary its own, independent, coequal branch of government. The

earliest English judiciary initially developed within the King’s executive powe, and

it was not until the creation of the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom in 2009

that the English judiciary would finally become a fully-independent branch of

73
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 15: The Works of James
Wilson, 1:296–97. Edited by Robert Green McCloskey. 2 vols. Cambridge: Belknap
Press of Harvard University Press, 1967.
74
United States Constitution, Article II, Sec. 4.
75
The Revival of Impeachment as a Partisan Political Weapon, 34 Hastings Const.
L.Q. 161, 172.
31
English government.76 At the time of the Founding, though, the judicial system in

England was largely nested within the Parliament. Outside of England proper,

specifically the American Colonies, the judiciary existed largely within or

subordinate to the King’s Privy Council—a quasi-judicial body with the power to

nullify laws passed by Colonial legislatures—and the local judicial system being

housed within the Colonial Governor’s power.77

But after the American Colonies severed political ties with the crown, the

Framers had a unique opportunity to create a constitutional structure anew—free

from the historical scars, vested interest s, and political realities that gave rise

to the then-existing English legal order. One of the most transformative—and, for

lack of a better word—revolutionary aspects of the American Constitution was the

quite intentional decision to establish a wholly co-equal third branch—the

American Judiciary.

Aside from actualizing Montesquieu's envisioned tripartite

government—judicial, legislative, and executive power divided into branches

accordingly—for successful operation, the Constitution required the Federal

Judiciary be capable of holding its own against the other two branches of

government, and not wither on the vine into constitutional irrelevancy.

Many Framers assumed the Judicial branch to be the weakest of the three

branches by its very nature—and thus had to be fortified and empowered to

76
Constitutional Reform Act 2005 (c. 4), Part 3, Section 23. The National Archives,
United Kingdom (2005).
77
Judicial Tenure, at 138.
32
withstand encroachments from the two more imposing political branches. Alexander

Hamilton’s Federalist 78 is the most famous pronouncements to this effect:

The executive not only dispenses the honors, but holds the sword of the
community. The legislature not only commands the purse, but
prescribes the rules by which the duties and rights of every citizen are
to be regulated. The judiciary on the contrary has no influence over
either the sword or the purse, no direction either of the strength or of the
wealth of the society, and can take no active resolution whatever. It may
truly be said to have neither Force nor Will, but merely judgment; and
must ultimately depend upon the aid of the executive arm even for the
efficacy of its judgments.78

C. Contrary Voices and Rejoinders.


The opponents of complete, constitutional judicial independence made two

general sorts of arguments: first, that the fundamental differences between the

English Monarchy and the American Republic lessened the need for English-style

judicial independence, and second, that practical reasons abound for allowing the

removal of Federal judges outside of the impeachment context.

1. Fundamental Distinctions Between England and


America.
Some felt overthrowing the king and creating a republic in the place of a

monarchy fundamentally transformed the relationship between the branches of

government, and thus the English legal innovations might not be calibrated

appropriately for the newly-founded, kingless Republic. As Brutus began no. 15,

“Though in my opinion the judges ought to hold their offices during good behaviour,

yet I think it is clear, that the reasons in favour of this establishment of the judges

in England, do by no means apply to this country.”79


78
Hamilton 78. (Emphasis added).
79
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 10; Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 2,
Cl. 1, Doc. 22: Storing, Herbert J., ed. The Complete Anti-Federalist, 2.9.186–93. 7
vols. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981 (“Brutus 15”).
33
Brutus spent considerable time articulating the some familiar pressures on

English judges stemming from their relationship with the Crown:

While the judges held their places at the will and pleasure of the king,
on whom they depended not only for their offices, but also for their
salaries, they were subject to every undue influence. If the crown
wished to carry a favorite point, to accomplish which the aid of the
courts of law was necessary, the pleasure of the king would be signified
to the judges. And it required the spirit of a martyr, for the judges to
determine contrary to the king’s will.—They were absolutely
dependent upon him both for their offices and livings.80

A King rules for life, with title bequeathed hereditarily—thus, judges

appointed by the king were given office for life as a balance to these interests of the

King. In America, judges are appointed by the legislature and executive, both

serving in office for a term of years. This fundamental distinction, according to

Brutus, poses fundamental problems for the blanket extension of English

protections in America:

The king, holding his office during life, and transmitting it to his
posterity as an inheritance, has much stronger inducements to
increase the prerogatives of his office than those who hold their offices
for stated periods, or even for life. Hence the English nation gained a
great point, in favour of liberty. When they obtained the appointment
of the judges, during good behaviour, they got from the crown a
concession, which deprived it of one of the most powerful engines with
which it might enlarge the boundaries of the royal prerogative and
encroach on the liberties of the people. But these reasons do not apply
to this country, we have no hereditary monarch; those who appoint the
judges do not hold their offices for life, nor do they descend to their
children. The same arguments, therefore, which will conclude in favor
of the tenor of the judge’s offices for good behaviour, lose a considerable
part of their weight when applied to the state and condition of
America.81

80
Id.
81
Id.
34
But not all observers agreed with the notion that America’s status as a

Republic lessened the need for the English-style guarantees of personal

independence for judges. St. George Tucker argued that in fact, the protections

offered by personal independence for judges were just as necessary in a Republic as

they were in a Monarchy.

This absolute independence of the judiciary, both of the executive and


the legislative departments, which I contend is to be found, both in the
letter, and spirit of our constitutions, is not less necessary to the liberty
and security of the citizen, and his property, in a republican
government, than in a monarchy: if in the latter, the will of the prince
may be considered as likely to influence the conduct of judges created
occasionally, and holding their offices only during his pleasure, more
especially in cases where a criminal prosecution may be carried on by
his orders, and supported by his influence; in a republic, on the other
hand, the violence and malignity of party spirit, as well in the
legislature, as in the executive, requires not less the intervention of a
calm, temperate, upright, and independent judiciary, to prevent that
violence and malignity from exerting itself “to crush in dust and ashes”
all opponents to it’s tyrannical administration, or ambitious projects.
Such an independence can never be perfectly attained, but by a
constitutional tenure of office, equally independent of the frowns and
smiles of the other branches of the government.82

Stated differently, removing the King did not not ameliorate the need for

complete personal independence for judges, as removing the King from the equation

only made room for the pernicious threats of factionalism, sectionalism, and politics

generally to fill his place. Thus, according to such arguments, insulating the

judiciary from the whims of the political branches in America was just as necessary

as insulating the judiciary from any undue influence of the King.


82
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 26: Tucker, St. George.
Blackstone’s Commentaries: With Notes of Reference to the Constitution and Laws of
the Federal Government of the United States and of the Commonwealth of Virginia.
5 vols. Philadelphia, 1803. Reprint. South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1969.
35
Alexander Hamilton articulated a similar argument.

In a monarchy it is an excellent barrier to the despotism of the prince:


In a republic it is a no less excellent barrier to the encroachments and
oppressions of the representative body. And it is the best expedient
which can be devised in any government, to secure a steady, upright
and impartial administration of the laws.83

2. Peculiar Dangers of Life Tenure in America’s


Constitutional Order.
In addition to guaranteeing personal independence of judges, the

Constitution also created a wholly-independent Judicial Branch. Unlike in England,

where the courts were largely nested within other departments, the Federal judicial

branch was instantiated to stand on its own. In England, the House of Lords sat

above the courts, empowering the Legislative to oversee the decisions of the courts.

The Framers rejected such a framework. No such structure of oversight of the

courts exist in the Constitution and thus the Federal Courts—specifically the

Supreme Court—have no authority above them to control their decisions.

For thinkers like Brutus, this lack of control or influence over the Federal

Judiciary, when combined with their constitutionally-guaranteed personal judicial

independence created a tremendous threat to the long-term viability of the

Constitutional American order.

I do not object to the judges holding their commissions during good


behaviour. I suppose it a proper provision provided they were made
properly responsible. But I say, this system has followed the English
government in this, while it has departed from almost every other
principle of their jurisprudence, under the idea, of rendering the judges
independent; which, in the British constitution, means no more than
83
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 11: Hamilton,
Alexander; Madison, James; and Jay, John. The Federalist, 521–30. Edited by Jacob
E. Cooke. Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1961 (“Hamilton 78”).
36
that they hold their places during good behavior, and have fixed
salaries, they have made the judges independent, in the fullest sense of
the word. There is no power above them, to controul any of their
decisions. There is no authority that can remove them, and they cannot
be controuled by the laws of the legislature. In short, they are
independent of the people, of the legislature, and of every power under
heaven.84

Despite the Anti-Federalists losing the battle over the constitution—Brutus’s

arguments would continue to live on. As will be seen in Section D, Thomas Jefferson

continued making similar arguments almost until his death.

3. Practical Arguments against Life Tenure during Good


Behavior.
Not all opponents of American-style judicial independence couched

their opposition to the concept in terms of deeply-considered constitutional theory.

Many simply made the practical argument that removing inane or insane judges

makes perfectly good sense; and the argument for complete,

constitutionally-required judicial independence systemically fails when considering

individual judges. Being insane or inane is not a crime—much less a high crime or

misdemeanor—and therefore bad judges will be allowed to be bad judges until they

die, retire, or commit an actual high crime or misdemeanor.

Brutus explains the difficulties posed by this constitutional requirement

when it comes to individually-incompetent judges.

Errors in judgement, or want of capacity to discharge the duties of the


office, can never be supposed to be included in these words, high crimes
and misdemeanors. A man may mistake a case in giving judgment, or
manifest that he is incompetent to the discharge of the duties of a
judge, and yet give no evidence of corruption or want of integrity. To
support the charge, it will be necessary to give in evidence some facts

84
Brutus 15.
37
that will shew, that the judges commited the error from wicked and
corrupt motives.85

Whether wicked or merely wanting of capacity, the effects of either are the

same: a miscarraige of justice. Whenever a judge rules incorrectly, whether due to

corruption or due to insanity—the fact remains, the judge has ruled incorrectly.

Others argued that the constitutional provisions requiring a two-thirds vote

of the legislature for the removal of Federal judges posed a severe limitation on the

practical possibility of removal, essentially ensuring no judges would ever be

removed—even for bad behavior. As Thomas Jefferson explained:

Before the revolution we were all good English Whigs, cordial in their
free principles, and in their jealousies of their executive Magistrate.
These jealousies are very apparent in all our state constitutions; and,
in the general government in this instance, we have gone even beyond
the English caution, by requiring a vote of two thirds in one of the
Houses for removing a judge; a vote so impossible where any defence is
made, before men of ordinary prejudices & passions, that our judges
are effectually independent of the nation.86

Jefferson also argued that giving judges life tenure, during good behavior,

with fixed salaries itself was not properly counterweighted—as mere promises to

appoint ‘good men’ to the bench does nothing in reality to combat the threat posed

by life appointments.

It is not enough that honest men are appointed judges. All know the
influence of interest on the mind of man, and how unconsciously his
judgment is warped by that influence. To this bias add that of the
esprit de corps, of their peculiar maxim and creed that “it is the office
of a good judge to enlarge his jurisdiction,” and the absence of
85
Brutus 15.
86
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 1, Chap. 8 (Federal v. Consolidated
Government), Doc. 44: The Works of Thomas Jefferson, 1:120–23. Collected and
edited by Paul Leicester Ford. Federal Edition. 12 vols. New York and London: G. P.
Putnam’s Sons, 1904–05.
38
responsibility, and how can we expect impartial decision between the
General government, of which they are themselves so eminent a part,
and an individual state from which they have nothing to hope or fear.87

To Jefferson, it was quite simple. America institutionalizes maniacs, and

therefore America ought to be able to remove bad judges from the bench; whether

the judges erred intentionally or not.

I repeat that I do not charge the judges with wilful and ill- intentioned
error; but honest error must be arrested where it’s toleration leads to
public ruin. As, for the safety of society, we commit honest maniacs to
Bedlam, so judges should be withdrawn from their bench, whose
erroneous biases are leading us to dissolution. It may indeed injure
them in fame or in fortune; but it saves the republic, which is the first
and supreme law.88

In response to those wishing to remove justices from the bench due to a want

of capacity, supporters of the good behavior standard argued it was impossible to

determine with any certainty where to draw the line with respect to diminished

capacity. Allowing the removal of judges due to their cognitive decline or

insufficiency would open pandora’s box—for making an objective determination on

the status of a person’s mental facilities was simply impossible. Thus, the standard

for removal would become subjective, which then puts judges right back into the

compromised position that life tenure, good behavior, and irreducible salaries were

intended to preclude. As Joseph story explains:

A proposition of a more imposing nature was to authorize a removal of


judges for inability to discharge the duties of their offices. But all
considerate persons will readily perceive, that such a provision would
either not be practised upon, or would be more liable to abuse, than
calculated to answer any good purpose. The mensuration of the

87
Id.
88
Id.
39
faculties of the mind has no place in the catalogue of any known art or
science. An attempt to fix the boundary between the region of ability
and inability would much oftener give rise to personal, or party
attachments and hostilities, than advance the interests of justice, or
the public good. And instances of absolute imbecility would be too rare
to justify the introduction of so dangerous a provision.89

Alexander Hamilton made a similar argument, that including the power to

remove senile or incompetent justices would essentially result in arbitrary removal

of judges and undo all concepts of judicial independence.

The mensuration of the faculties of the mind has, I believe, no place in


the catalogue of known arts. An attempt to fix the boundary between
the regions of ability and inability, would much oftener give scope to
personal and party attachments and enmities, than advance the
interests of justice, or the public good. The result, except in the case of
insanity, must for the most part be arbitrary; and insanity without any
formal or express provision, may be safely pronounced to be a virtual
disqualification.90

Thus constituted the main debate over removing federal judges. This debate

would continue from the calling of the Constitutional Convention through to the

War of 1812.

D. Failed Efforts to Add Removal of Justices to the Constitution.


The forces calling for a constitutional mechanism to remove federal judges

would make multiple efforts to add this concept into the constitution during the

first decades of the American Republic. The delegates to the Constitutional

Convention were the first to take up the issue, as they repeatedly considered

whether to add provisions to the Constitution making members of the Federal

Judiciary removable beyond impeachment, either by the executive, legislature, or

89
Story, Commentaries on the Constitution, at §1619.
90
Hamilton 78.
40
some combination thereof. The creation of the Federal Judiciary did not progress

linearly at the Convention. Multiple drafts of provisions detailing the appointment

process were presented and considered throughout the Convention—and the earlier

drafts did not mention nor consider any provisions for the removal of justices.91

By mid-August 1787, however, the delegates to the Constitutional Convention

began to seriously consider provisions allowing for the removal of Federal judges

outside of the impeachment context. On August 27, John Dickinson of Pennsylvania

moved for the addition of a provision which would make members of the Federal

Judiciary removable by the President on application to the House and Senate.92

Elbridge Gerry of Massachusetts seconded the motion93, with Roger Sherman of

Connecticut arguing in its favor by pointing out England had a very similar

procedure for the removal of judges.94

Among the opponents of this provision were Gouvernor Morris of New York,

Edward Rutledge of South Carolina, and James Wilson of Pennsylvania. Gouvernor

Morris found that such a removal provision would be incompatible with the good

behavior standard—because then in theory, the good behavior clause was rendered

a nullity if the political branches could remove judges for reasons other than bad

behavior.95 Edward Rutledge argued because the Supreme Court would be the

arbiter between the United States government and the several states, making

Supreme Court justices removable by the Federal government potentiated the


91
Judicial Tenure, at 149.
92
Id., at 150.
93
Id.
94
Id.
95
Id.
41
Federal government unduly swaying the court against the States.96 James Wilson

was convinced that the House and Senate would collude to remove

politically-problematic judges.97

Ultimately, Dickinson’s motion failed at the Convention, with only one state

supporting the motion, seven voting against it, and with three state abstentions.98, 99

But this vote at the convention did not end the debate, and by the

revolution of 1800, Thomas Jefferson and his Democratic allies sought to remove

the so-called Midnight Judges. After Thomas Jefferson defeated John Adams in the

1800 presidential election, Adams and his Federalist Allies used the lame-duck

period of his presidency to appoint as many new justices of the peace as possible

before Jefferson became President to frustrate his term in office.100 The last-minute

nature of these appointments, however, lead to some of the commissions never

making their way physically to those selected for the role—and when Thomas

Jefferson became president, he ordered his new administration to bury these

commissions.101

One of the appointees who subsequently barred from receiving their

commission, William Marbury, sued for his commission—and the Supreme Court

handed down one of the Court’s landmark cases. Chief Justice John Marshall’s

opinion in Marbury v. Madison is a complex, intricate case which among other


96
Id.
97
Id.
98
Id.
99
Story, Commentaries on the Constitution, §1616.
100
See After Midnight: The Circuit Judges and the Repeal of the Judiciary Act of
1801, 24 Y ALE J.L. & HUMAN. 253.
101
Id.
42
things, instantiated the Constitution’s superiority over mere acts of the legislature

in addition to cementing the concept of Judicial review into the American

constitutional order.

Specifically, Marbury considered whether the Executive Branch could deny

judicial appointees their commissions—commissions created by duly-enacted

legislation and signed by a former President—by executive action. Chief Justice

Marshall wasted no time in declaring such actions by the President to be void.

Where an officer is removable at the will of the executive, the


circumstance which completes his appointment is of no concern;
because the act is at any time revocable; and the commission may be
arrested, if still in the office. But when the officer is not removable at
the will of the executive, the appointment is not revocable, and cannot
be annulled: it has conferred legal rights which cannot be resumed.
The discretion of the executive is to be exercised, until the appointment
has been made. But having once made the appointment, his power over
the office is terminated, in all cases where, by law, the officer is not
removable by him. The right to the office is then in the person
appointed, and he has the absolute unconditional power of accepting or
rejecting it.

Mr. Marbury, then, since his commission was signed by the president,
and sealed by the secretary of state, was appointed; and as the law
creating the office, gave the officer a right to hold for five years,
independent of the executive, the appointment was not revocable, but
vested in the officer legal rights, which are protected by the laws of his
country. To withhold his commission, therefore, is an act deemed by the
court not warranted by law, but violative of a vested legal right.102

Because the Congress created five-year tenure for these judicial offices (and

in the absence of statutory authorization for removal by the executive) the executive

was powerless to divest those officeholders of their commissions.

102
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 2, Cl. 1, Doc. 47.
43
Thus in so doing, Chief Justice Marshall slammed the door shut on a

potential extra-constitutional avenue for the other branches of the Federal

Government to interfere with the tenures of judicial appointees. Unless authorized

to remove such judicial appointees at will, the President is powerless to terminate

their vested legal right to hold office prior to the expiration of the office. With the

constitutional command that members of the Federal Judiciary hold their offices

during good behavior, then, under Marbury, it should be clear that no Executive

could effectively remove a duly-appointed justice by withholding the delivery of

their commission—or by means of any other procedural gadgets which might be

subsequently invented to effectuate the same.

After Marbury, one final attempt to amend the constitution to allow the

removal of Federal judges was made. In 1811, Maryland Congressman Robert

Wright proposed a constitutional amendment in the Congress allowing for the

removal of Federal Justices by joint address of the House and Senate. Like other

such efforts, Congressman Wright’s amendment died with a whimper.

Mr. Wright called for the consideration of the resolution submitted by


him on Wednesday last, in the following words:

Resolved, by the Senate and House of Representatives of the United


States of America, in Congress assembled, two-thirds of both Houses
concurring, That the following section be submitted to the Legislatures
of the several States; which, when ratified by the Legislatures of three-
fourths of the States, shall be valid and binding as a part of the
Constitution of the United States:

“The Judges of the Supreme Court and inferior courts, may be removed
from office by the joint address of the Senate and House of
Representatives of the United States.”

44
Mr. W. wished it considered barely with a view to a reference to a
Committee of the Whole, and to make it the order of the day for some
distant day.

The House refused to consider the resolution; 53 to 38.103

Though the failure of Mr. Wright’s Amendment marked the last serious

attempt to constitutionally allow for the removal of Federal judges, dissenters

remained. In his 1821 autobiography, Thomas Jefferson lamented the failure to

include a constitutional means to remove Federal judges.

But there was another amendment of which none of us thought at the


time and in the omission of which lurks the germ that is to destroy this
happy combination of National powers in the General government for
matters of National concern, and independent powers in the states for
what concerns the states severally.104

Jefferson was certainly aware of the theoretical support for the independence

of the judiciary, but argued that additional modest controls over Federal judges

were necessary.

I would not indeed make them dependant on the Executive authority,


as they formerly were in England; but I deem it indispensable to the
continuance of this government that they should be submitted to some
practical & impartial controul: and that this, to be imparted, must be
compounded of a mixture of state and federal authorities.105

Thomas Jefferson was gravely concerned that with the failure to implement

controls over the Federal Judiciary, the judiciary would do what all powerful bodies

tend to do—accumulate more power. Such accumulations of power are dangerous in

and of themselves, but under the Federal Constitution, these accumulations would

103
The Founders’ Constitution, Vol. 4, Art. 3, Sec. 1, Doc. 31: Annals of Congress.
The Debates and Proceedings in the Congress of the United States, 22:857. “History
of Congress.” 42 vols. Washington, D.C.: Gales & Seaton, 1834–56.
104
Jefferson Biography.
105
Id.
45
directly threaten the States. And without the ability to remove justices guilty of

such behavior, there would be no constitutional mechanism to avert this disaster.

Jefferson’s lament, therefore, is a strong echo of Brutus—good behavior, life tenure,

and fixed salaries are fantastic, but with America’s complete constitutional judicial

independence, the judges could not be stopped should they begin to undermine the

American Constitutional order.

To this bias add that of the esprit de corps, of their peculiar maxim and
creed that “it is the office of a good judge to enlarge his jurisdiction,”
and the absence of responsibility, and how can we expect impartial
decision between the General government, of which they are
themselves so eminent a part, and an individual state from which they
have nothing to hope or fear. We have seen too that, contrary to all
correct example, they are in the habit of going out of the question
before them, to throw an anchor ahead and grapple further hold for
future advances of power. They are then in fact the corps of sappers &
miners, steadily working to undermine the independant rights of the
States, & to consolidate all power in the hands of that government in
which they have so important a freehold estate.106

Thomas Jefferson would die five years after the publication of his

Autobiography, and so he did not live long enough to see how closely his predictions

presaged the contours of American Legal History.

IV. Conclusion.
Had these two ill-fated efforts to fundamentally alter America’s constitutional

order been successful it is clear the development of American law and government

would have taken a radically different trajectory. Had the Constitutional

Convention supported the Council of Revision, the entire history of judicial review

and the relationship between the three branches of American government would

have necessarily diverged from the record. No longer would the Supreme Court be
106
Id.
46
relegated to a ‘wait and see’ position when it comes to adjudicating constitutional

issues related to legislation, and instead the Council of Revision would have allowed

an active, preemptive strike against unconstitutional legislation. How this

difference would play out in more legally fraught modern times is impossible to

know.

What we do know, however, is that the winning argument at the

Constitutional Convention cemented the importance of the Presidential veto and

judicial review. The Convention Delegates were of the opinion that those two checks

on the legislature originating separately in the executive and judicial branches were

sufficient checks against legislative overreach. Perhaps it is the case that these two

checks are in fact the best two, and that the Council of Revision would have only

increased the tension within the system or been relegated to irrelevance.

With respect to efforts to allow the constitutional removal of Federal judges,

it is clear the prevailing view of the Founders has played a significant role in the

development of America’s Constitutional Order. Would Thomas Jefferson and the

Democratic-Republicans have sought to remove John Marshall from the Federal

Bench after Marbury? Would Andrew Jackson have done the same in a later

decade? Is it possible that in the wake of Dred Scott the national mood would have

soured against Rodger Tawney and caused him to be removed, potentially avoiding

the Civil War? Would the ‘Switch in Time’ have simply been effectuated by FDR by

removing Federal judges problematic for the implementation of the New Deal?

47
As with the Council of Revision, it is impossible to know how the inclusion of

a constitutional mechanism to remove Federal judges would have played out. These

thought experiments are interesting to undertake, but one thing remains clear—by

leaving the appointees to the Federal Courts beyond recall of the political branches,

significant constitutional crises between branches did not result in Legislative and

Executive domination of the Judicial. Perhaps such domination would have been

inevitable, and the current system of Judicial Review and Supremacy was the only

path available to prevent the same.

Despite these (and many other) unanswered questions of alternative history

raised by the Council of Revision and removal of Federal judges, it is clear that

these two rejected Constitutional revisions were not anti-constitutional theoretical

heresies. No, both proposals derived from substantial English and American

traditions and were borne out of the very same set of thinkers, principles, and

compromises that gave us our current Constitution and should be remembered as

such.

48

You might also like