Natural Sciences, Philosophy

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5

951203 JIN Journal of Information TechnologySchlagwein

Commentary on Debates and Perspectives Paper


JIT
Journal of Information Technology

Natural sciences, philosophy 2021, Vol. 36(1) 85­–89


© Association for Information
Technology Trust 2020
of science and the orientation Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
of the social sciences https://doi.org/10.1177/0268396220951203
DOI: 10.1177/0268396220951203
Journals.sagepub.com/jinf

Daniel Schlagwein

The debate thesis broadening and extension of IS PhD training is a concrete


measure that I fully support, not the least based on my own
The Debate paper (by Siponen/Klaavuniemi) is part of the experience.
wider discourse whether or not, and with what conse- Third, I am, however, less than convinced by the ‘mis-
quences, Information Systems (IS) and other social sci- characterisations’ or ‘misunderstandings’ attributed to IS
ences could be or should be ‘science’ (most recently researchers. I find the Debate thesis argument and analysis
McBride, 2018; Nelson, 2016). wanting in that IS research quotes have been cherry-picked
The Debate thesis rests on the position that IS research from their textual and historical contexts and crucial distinc-
could be, or should be, based on a model of ‘science’ as tions having been conflated. As a result, the Debate thesis
understood and practised in the natural sciences. The cen- paper contributes less than what I was hoping to clarification
tral Debate thesis, depicted in Figure 1, is the claim that IS of the precise nature of the supposed mis-characterisations.
researchers have mis-characterised the natural sciences. To be clear, in some respects, I agree with some of the ‘mis-
The Debate paper then itemises nine supposed mis-charac- characterisations’, but not with the way in which they are
terisations of the natural sciences by IS researchers, con- framed and analytically supported.2
trasting them to either philosophy of science writings or To contribute, I will seek to add distinctions, history and
examples of research in the applied natural sciences. The context to the Debate. In a sense, the Debate’s analysis is
Debate paper concludes that correctly depicted natural sci- weak precisely on the classical matters of much greater
ences provide an appropriate and applicable model for IS concern to the humanities than to the sciences: the consid-
research, including qualitative IS research, and suggests eration of history, context and Verstehen of meaning and
concrete measures, such as extending the scope of IS PhD intentions.3 The meanings of statements are neither isolated
education. nor timeless; they need to be placed in their textual and
I will comment on the Debate thesis from the perspec- historical contexts.
tive of a qualitative IS researcher (i.e. the target audience)
and from the history of the IS field and that of the philoso-
phy of science. In particular, I am seeking to provide a bal- Adding distinctions, history and
anced presentation of what my IS research colleagues context to the debate
actually meant and of what most scholars in the philosophy
of science and scientists in the natural sciences typically do The Debate thesis oversimplifies the matter in a way that
or argue in their works.1 unfortunately renders invisible the critical nuances. At least
First, I agree with the implication of the Debate thesis two important distinctions need to be added.
that the natural sciences and the philosophy of science dis- First, the Debate thesis conflates the disciplines of the
cipline (my colleague provides an excellent introduction: natural sciences and the philosophy of science in its analysis
Godfrey-Smith, 2003) over past decades have changed and of these mis-characterisations. Physics, chemistry, biology
that they offer important and relevant insights for IS
researchers. I appreciate the thrust of the Debate thesis The University of Sydney, Australia
encouraging my colleagues and me, as IS researchers, to
continue to engage with and read in other disciplines. Corresponding author:
Daniel Schlagwein, Business School, The University of Sydney,
Second, I agree with the actionable conclusions of the Abercrombie Building (H70), Room 4070, Darlington, Sydney, NSW
Debate thesis, and support the suggestions, even if I may 2008, Australia.
approach them from a different analysis. In particular, the Email: schlagwein@sydney.edu.au
86 Journal of Information Technology 36(1)

Over time, academia diversified into different fields due to


the increased specialisation of knowledge. The natural sci-
ences were the first to split from philosophy into stand-
alone academic disciplines mostly during the 18th century.
The social sciences split in the late 19th century. Philosophy
Figure 1.  Original thesis: ‘IS researchers mis-characterise the itself remained in the now so-called ‘humanities’ (including
natural sciences’. arts). This led to the development of different ‘intellectual
worlds’ and different cultures: the natural sciences and the
and so on are applied natural science disciplines concerned humanities with the social sciences in between (Kagan,
with explaining the natural world, typically using ‘the scien- 2009; Snow, 1959).
tific method(s)’. In contrast, the philosophy of science is a By the early 20th century, philosophy itself had split into
humanities discipline concerned with understanding the ide- disconnected streams. Analytical philosophy and continen-
alised notion of ‘science’, typically using conceptual and tal philosophy are the two most commonly distinguished
philosophical argumentation. The philosophy of science streams (for brief characterizations: University of Michigan,
discipline is a subfield of philosophy: it is not a natural sci- 2020 or Plato, Stanford).6 Analytical philosophy focuses on
ence nor is it composed of scientists. Most natural scientists realism, logic and science and includes the philosophers
do not read philosophy of science research, form their mentioned in the Debate paper, the logical-positivists such
beliefs and pursue practices largely independent of the phi- as Carnap, Popper and Hempel among others. The philoso-
losophy of science (e.g. Godfrey-Smith, 2003; Okasha, phy of science emerged as a major subdiscipline within
2016). This distinction is important because (a) claims about analytical philosophy, focusing on the study of an idealised
idealtype ‘science’4 cannot be misconstrued as claims about ‘science’. In contrast, continental philosophy (Husserl,
natural science practices and (b) a reader of the Debate Hegel, Heidegger, etc.) focuses on ‘the human condition’
might come away with the mistaken notion that the philoso- and ‘the experience of being’ and, hence, often takes ideal-
phy of science speaks for scientists. ist, subjectivist, constructivist and relativist positions,
Second, the Debate thesis does not distinguish the rele- underpinning many contemporary positions in the humani-
vant groups, presenting IS researchers (or even all social ties (e.g. Melchert, 2014).
scientists) as if they are a homogeneous group. This glosses The long-raging orientation debate in the social sci-
over the key issue that the different groups are leading an ences, at its core, can be seen as being about leaning towards
internal debate about the orientation of IS and social sci- one side or the other. Early social scientists, such as Comte
ence research. We should distinguish ‘scientistic’, ‘positiv- and Durkheim, advocated ‘positivist’, science-oriented
ist’, ‘quantitative’ and ‘science-oriented’ IS researchers social sciences, in which only data through sense experi-
who see themselves as working in a science tradition and ence and logic count as generating valid knowledge. Comte
‘anti-positivist’, ‘interpretivist’, ‘qualitative’ and ‘humani- explicitly called for the formation of an unbiased ‘science
ties-oriented’ IS researchers who see themselves as closer of sociology’ modelled on physical science to discover ‘the
to the humanities. Most quotes in the Debate paper are by laws of human behaviour’. In contrast, building on the
“humanities-oriented” IS researchers (e.g. Myers, Lee, early ideas of Weber and Marx, ‘non/anti-positivist’ social
Orlikowski and Walsham) as part of a discourse that seeks scientists rejected the idea that social and cultural condi-
legitimisation of that form of IS research. These quotes tions could, or should, be studied via a science-oriented
must be interpreted as (a) being about science-ideal-ori- model. Dithney expressed this sentiment as ‘[people] need
ented IS research – which is indeed often quantitative, to be understood in the context of their connections to cul-
cause–effect seeking, and so on – not about physics, biol- tural and social life’ (in Polkinghorne, 1983; see also
ogy and other research works and (b) critiquing this “main- Burrell and Morgan, 1979; Hirschheim, 1985). That is, the
stream” IS research with the intention of legitimisation of views of positivist social scientists often correspond to the
“humanities-oriented” IS research (and not alleging its views of analytical philosophy (e.g. the focus on logic and
superiority or the general impotence of science-based evidence) and the science fields. The ideas of non-positivist
approaches for qualitative or other IS research;5 see also social scientists are closer to those of humanist thinkers and
Cecez-Kecmanovic et al., 2020; Hirschheim and Klein, are rooted in the ideas of continental philosophy (e.g.
2012; Sarker et al., 2018). Husserl’s phenomenology or Hegel’s dialectics).7
Having added these distinctions, let us add historical Most quotes in the Debate thesis are from the IS disci-
context to the Debate. Figure 2, a simplification, aims to pline’s part in this wider ‘social science orientation debate’,
show at least the ‘relevant actors’ and to outline the com- yet little consideration is given to this fact in the analysis.
peting ‘schools of thought’ (and the intellectual heritage via For example, the Debate paper appears to take the 1999
the arrows, unless labelled otherwise). quote ‘while the conventions for evaluating information
Academia was originally composed of just one field, systems case studies conducted according to the natural sci-
philosophy, that included all academic fields and sciences. ence model of social science are now widely accepted, this
Schlagwein 87

Figure 2.  Broader debate: the orientation of the social sciences.

is not the case for interpretive field studies’ (Klein and science’s contemporary understandings of ‘science’.8 For
Myers, 1999: 67) to mean that science could not be a foun- example, the preference for ‘systematic literature
dation for qualitative IS research. This is not at all in line reviews’ (over narrative reviews in IS research; analysed
with my reading of the quote. The full textual and historical in Boell and Cecez-Kecmanovic, 2015) or the claim that
context makes it clear that the authors were calling for ‘experimental research, often considered to be the “gold
humanities-oriented (interpretivist) qualitative research to standard” in research designs, is one of the most rigorous
be (a) generally accepted in IS and (b) evaluated on its own of all research designs’ (relative to other social science
quality criteria, not those of positivist-scientistic IS methods; Bhattacherjee, 2012: 62) may then probably be
research. This is neither a statement about the natural sci- an indication of the misunderstanding at which the Debate
ences nor does it mean that a science-oriented approach is is pointing. In any case, I agree with the authors – and
not also conducive to qualitative research, an idea that had earlier arguments (Dube and Pare, 2003; Lee and Hubona,
already been introduced years earlier (Benbasat et al., 2009) – that science can equally support (some forms of)
1987). That is, the supposed misunderstanding does not qualitative research.
exist if the quote is properly placed in its context. The one mis-understanding where I disagree is the belief
Figure 2 is hopefully useful to place into context the that Klein and Myers would mis-characterise science by
alleged ‘mis-characterisations’ of the natural sciences by IS attributing hermeneutics to the humanist Gadamer and not to
researchers. Let us analyse two of these mis-characterisations, science (Klein and Myers, 1999; mis-characterisation [6]).
one where I agree with the Debate’s analysis and one where I The first problem is that it seems quite undisputed that her-
disagree. meneutics historically, and as an applied method, must be
I agree that at least some IS researchers may wrongly attributed to humanities, not the natural sciences. As the
believe that ‘science’ implies a quantitative or mathemat- Debate paper states, hermeneutics originated in theology and
ical approach must be taken or that it is preferable (mis- then moved to fields such as history. But theology and his-
characterisation [2]). As per Figure 1 (the Debate thesis), tory are not natural sciences! Therefore, Klein and Myers
this may be a misunderstanding of the natural sciences by (1999) placed hermeneutics rather appropriately. The second
IS researchers. Through Figure 2, it is now possible to see problem is that, while the authors and some individual phi-
that the misunderstanding, if there is one, is by some sci- losophers (e.g. Heelan and Bernstein) may believe that the
ence-oriented IS researchers relative to the philosophy of sciences are hermeneutic at their core, this is not shown to be
88 Journal of Information Technology 36(1)

the majority view nor the typical view of either natural scien- 4. The philosophy of science itself debates the precise bound-
tists or philosophers in the philosophy of science. The infa- ary of ‘science’ across the spectrum of academic fields. The
mous ‘Sokal Hoax’ during the ‘Science Wars’ precisely natural sciences are ‘in’ while the arts and humanities are
ridiculed this idea of hermeneutics in science (Godfrey- ‘out’. It is unclear if the philosophy of science would aspire
to include all social sciences in its explanations (let alone
Smith, 2003; Sokal, 1996). Unless an unreported general
normatively guide those fields; for example, Godfrey-Smith,
mind-shift has occurred, the characterisation of the natural
2003; Okasha, 2016).
sciences as fundamentally being, methodologically using or 5. To drive the point home with an analogy, the 2020 politi-
understanding themselves as hermeneutic would be inaccu- cal slogan ‘Black Lives Matter’ could only be legitimately
rate (again, a characterisation should refer to the ‘typical’ understood as ‘only Black lives matter’ without a contextual
case or view; more on hermeneutics: Zimmermann, 2015). understanding. In the actual historical context, the meaning is
This space does not allow discussion of all the supposed clearly ‘Black lives should matter equally’. Context matters.
‘mis-characterisations’ of the natural sciences by IS 6. I acknowledge but set aside pragmatism and Eastern
researchers. However, I believe that considering context, philosophies.
history and the above distinctions help to better clarify 7. This is to say that the humanities have their distinct
whether they are, in fact, mis-characterisations at all (or approaches and intellectual foundations, not that they never
use science-type research methods or analytical ideas.
simply value differences) and, if so, precisely of what and
8. For one example, the philosophy of science’s increased
by whom.9 The Debate thesis authors need to be careful
acknowledgement of fundamental disciplinary differences
here not to add their own set of mis-characterisations between fields led to the emergence of the philosophy of the
through simplistic analysis. I thank the authors of the special sciences. For instance, it was recognised that even the
Debate thesis and those of another debate (McBride, 2018 other natural sciences, such as biology, should not be treated
and responses) for reigniting the fundamental question like physics, thus leading to the philosophy of biology (see
about IS research: What kind of field of inquiry is it or for more Mayr, 1961; Okasha, 2019).
what kind should it be? 9. Two brief notes: By ‘theory-ladenness of data’, the philoso-
phy of science refers to scientists in different paradigms or
Declaration of conflicting interests networks of auxiliary assumptions, the example referring to
‘a layperson versus a scientist’ is rather off the point (in mis-
The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with characterisation [8]). The quote by Mannheim (1936) now
respect to the research, authorship and/or publication of this might be considered wrong but, to me, it seemed to be rather
article. correct at the time. Kuhn’s (1962) Structure of Scientific
Revolution had not yet been published and, in 1936, the views
Funding in the natural sciences and the philosophy of science aligned
The author(s) received no financial support for the research, with those of Mannheim (in mis-characterisation [9]).
authorship and/or publication of this article.
References
ORCID iD Benbasat I, Goldstein DK and Mead M (1987) The case research
Daniel Schlagwein https://orcid.org/0000-0002-1591-4660 strategy in studies of information systems. MIS Quarterly
11(3): 369–386.
Bhattacherjee A (2012) Social Science Research. Tampa, FL:
Notes
University of South Florida.
1. The quotes selected in the Debate thesis are in relation Boell SK and Cecez-Kecmanovic D (2015) On being ‘system-
to idealtype ‘science’ – the idealised typical case (Weber, atic’ in literature reviews: Prescriptions, presumptions, pre-
1904). These characterisations can only be fairly labelled tense and perils. Journal of Information Technology 30(2):
‘mis-characterisations’ if the typical case is different at 161–173.
the relevant time. Arguing a mis-characterisation based on Burrell G and Morgan G (1979) Sociological Paradigms and
expectational cases, minority opinions or later changes cer- Organisational Analysis. London: Heinemann.
tainly sets the bar too low. Categories are useful for argu- Cecez-Kecmanovic D, Davison RM, Fernandez W, et al. (2020)
ments even if they do not capture all borderline cases (van Advancing qualitative IS research methodologies: Expanding
Fraassen, 1980). (The same holds for ‘qualitative vs quanti- horizons and seeking new paths. Journal of the Association
tative’ IS research: it is certainly not a perfect, but is a prag- for Information Systems 21(1): 1.
matically useful, distinction.) Dube L and Pare G (2003) Rigor in information systems positivist
2. I also note the focus on methodological/epistemologi- case research: Current practices, trends, and recommenda-
cal issues at the expense of ontological and value/ethical tions. MIS Quarterly 27(4): 597–635.
considerations. Godfrey-Smith P (2003) Theory and Reality: An Introduction
3. Critical reflection would also be expected in interpretivist to the Philosophy of Science. Chicago, IL: University of
research (Klein and Myers, 1999) such as a discussion how Chicago Press.
the fact that there is a Debate co-author with a science back- Hirschheim R (1985) Information systems epistemology: An his-
ground but no co-author with a humanities background may torical perspective. In: Mumford E (ed.) Research Methods
have predisposed the analysis. I will set this aside. in Information Systems. Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 13–35.
Schlagwein 89

Hirschheim R and Klein HK (2012) A glorious and not-so-short Sokal AD (1996) Transgressing the boundaries: Towards a trans-
history of the information systems field. Journal of the formative hermeneutics of quantum gravity. Social Text 46–
Association for Information Systems 13(4): 188–235. 47(1): 217–252.
Kagan J (2009) The Three Cultures: Natural Sciences, Social University of Michigan (2020) Styles of Philosophy [2020-05-
Sciences, and the Humanities in the 21st Century. Cambridge: 16]. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan.
Cambridge University Press. van Fraassen BC (1980) The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford
Klein HK and Myers MD (1999) A set of principles for conduct- University Press.
ing and evaluating interpretive field studies in information Weber M (1904) Die ‘Objektivität’ Sozialwissenschaftlicher
systems. MIS Quarterly 23(1): 67–93. Und Sozialpolitischer Erkenntnis [‘Objectivity’ in Social
Kuhn TS (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (2nd edn). Science and Social Policy]. Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft
Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press. und Sozialpolitik 19(1): 22–87.
Lee AS and Hubona GS (2009) A scientific basis for rigor in infor- Zimmermann J (2015) Hermeneutics. Oxford: Oxford University
mation systems research. MIS Quarterly 33(2): 237–262. Press.
McBride N (2018) Is information systems a science?
Communications of the Association of Information Systems Author biography
43(1): 163–174. Daniel Schlagwein is associate professor of Business Information
Mannheim K (1936) Ideology and Utopia. London: Routledge. Systems at The University of Sydney. He is co-editor-in-chief of
Mayr E (1961) Cause and effect in biology. Science 134(3489):
the leading Journal of Information Technology (JIT). At The
1501–1506.
University of Sydney, he co-directs the Digital Disruption Research
Melchert N (2014) The Great Conversation: A Historical
Introduction to Philosophy (7th edn). Oxford: Oxford Group (DDRG). He is the leading chief investigator on the
University Press. Australian Research Council’s (ARC) Discovery Project on
Nelson RR (2016) The sciences are different and the differences Digital Nomadism (2019–2022). His research interests are new
matter. Research Policy 45(9): 1692–1701. forms of digital working and organising (e.g. crowdsourcing, digi-
Okasha S (2016) Philosophy of Science (2nd edn). Oxford: Oxford tal nomadism and IT-enabled openness) as well as the epistemo-
University Press. logical and philosophical foundations of Information Systems (IS)
Okasha S (2019) Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Oxford research. Daniel’s research is published in leading journals such as
University Press. the Information Systems Journal, the Journal of Information
Polkinghorne D (1983) Methodology for the Human Sciences: Technology, the Journal of the Association for Information
Systems of Inquiry. Albany, NY: State University of New
Systems (AIS) and The Journal of Strategic Information Systems.
York Press.
The AIS Research Ranking 2018 puts him in the top 100 of IS
Sarker S, Xiao X, Beaulieu T, et al. (2018) Learning from first-
generation qualitative approaches in the IS discipline. researchers worldwide, while the Financial Times Ranking 2019
Journal of the Association for Information Systems 19(1): puts him in the top 100 of German business researchers. Daniel’s
752–774. research is featured in, for example, Sky News, The Sydney
Snow CP (1959) The Rede Lecture. Cambridge: Cambridge Morning Herald and the McKinsey Quarterly. He frequently
University Press. speaks at both industry and academic conferences.

You might also like