Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

R. Reisenzein & I.

Mchitarjan: Tracing
Social Meinong
Psychology
© 2008 ’s Influence
Hogrefe
2008; Vol.
& Huber on Heider
39(3):141–150
Publishers

“The Teacher Who had the Greatest


Influence on My Thinking”
Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider
Rainer Reisenzein and Irina Mchitarjan
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

University of Greifswald, Germany

Abstract. According to Heider, some of his ideas about common-sense psychology presented in The Psychology of Interpersonal Rela-
tions (Heider, 1958) originally came from his academic teacher, Alexius Meinong. However, Heider makes no reference to Meinong in
his book. To clarify Meinong’s influence on Heider, we compare Heider’s explication of common-sense psychology with Meinong’s
writings, in particular those on ethics. Our results confirm that Heider’s common-sense psychology is informed by Meinong’s psycho-
logical analyses in several respects: Heider adopts aspects of Meinong’s theory of emotion, his theory of value, and his theory of respon-
sibility attribution. In addition, Heider more or less continues Meinong’s method of psychological inquiry. Thus, even without Meinong’s
name attached, many aspects of Meinong’s psychology found their way into today’s social psychology via Heider. Unknowingly, some
of us have been Meinongians all along.

Keywords: attribution, common-sense psychology, Heider, history of psychology, Meinong

Fritz Heider was the last doctoral student of Alexius Mei- ics treated there concerned epistemology, the theory of
nong (1853–1920), who was professor of philosophy at the probability, and the theory of value. Heider also reports that
University of Graz (Austria) from 1882 to 1920. A student he studied Meinong’s epistemological treatise On the Em-
of Franz Brentano, Meinong has come to be regarded as pirical Basis of Our Knowledge (Meinong, 1906a) in depth
one of Austria’s foremost philosophers. He is best known for his dissertation and that the first part of the dissertation
today for his so-called “theory of objects” (Gegenstands- (Heider, 1920), “developed Meinong’s thinking and used
theorie), an early form of logical semantics (Chrudzimski, his vocabulary, which I had really mastered by that time”
2007), though he also made important contributions to oth- (Heider, 1983, p. 37). (An essay based on the dissertation
er areas of philosophical and psychological inquiry. To- was published in 1926 as Ding and Medium [Heider,
gether with his student Christian von Ehrenfels, Meinong 1926]). Although some aspects of Meinong’s philosophy –
founded the so-called “Second Austrian school of value particularly his theory of objects – seemed to Heider “cold
theory” (Eaton, 1930; Fabian & Simons, 1986). With his and lifeless,” Meinong’s thoughts about “the more concrete
students and coworkers (e.g., Benussi, Ehrenfels, Witasek), questions of probability and value, and . . . his more de-
Meinong established the Graz school of Gestalt psycholo- tailed discussions of the common-sense versions of these
gy. He also proposed a sophisticated cognitive theory of ideas” appealed to Heider, who notes: “I must have learned
emotion (see Reisenzein, Meyer, & Schützwohl, 2003). a lot from his [Meinong’s] reflections on these problems”
Last but not least, Meinong founded the first experimental (Heider, 1983, pp. 21–22; italics in the original). In an in-
psychology laboratory of Austria in 1894. terview given several years earlier to the editors of New
Meinong’s influence on Heider has not been investigat- Directions in Attribution Research (Harvey, Ickes, & Kidd,
ed to date. However, such an influence may be expected, 1976), Heider was even more explicit. Referring to Mei-
given their teacher-student relationship. The question that nong as “a great philosopher . . . who was also a psycholo-
occupies us in this article is how strong Meinong’s influ- gist,” Heider stated: “Now I realize that some of the ideas
ence on Heider really was and which topics it concerned. that I developed about common-sense psychology original-
Heider himself gave a partial answer to these questions in ly came from him” (Harvey et al., 1976, pp. 5–6).
his autobiography: “Alexius Meinong was certainly the Given these hints by Heider, we became curious about
teacher who had the greatest influence on my thinking” which “ideas about common-sense psychology” he had in
(Heider, 1983, p. 21). Describing Meinong as a “well-orga- mind and hence, which aspects of Meinong’s psychology
nized person with extraordinary intelligence” who “had a may have found their way into contemporary psychology
commanding presence,” Heider reports that he attended via Heider. Unfortunately, Heider did not elaborate his
Meinong’s lectures and seminars for several years. The top- hints, and The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations (PIR;

© 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150
DOI 10.1027/1864-9335.39.3.141
142 R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider

Heider, 1958) contains no reference to Meinong. We there- his student Ehrenfels (1897) – to desire. Emotions and de-
fore decided to search for an empirical answer by compar- sires, Meinong believes, are the basic value experiences,
ing PIR to Meinong’s writings. The most promising sourc- the original states of consciousness in which we become
es, by Heider’s own account but also in terms of the topics aware, in a prereflective way, of the value of things. To
covered, seemed to be Meinong’s writings on ethics. Ethics understand value, Meinong argues, one therefore needs to
or “practical philosophy” as it is often called, has been tra- turn to psychology, specifically to the study of emotions.
ditionally concerned with interpersonal relations: This is Accordingly, Meinong first presents a fairly detailed theory
the field of philosophical inquiry where philosophers since of emotions and then proceeds to clarify the relation of
Plato and Aristotle discussed topics such as proper conduct, emotions to value judgments and to value in general. Hav-
egoism versus altruism, responsibility, values, obligation ing laid this basis, Meinong then “works out a fascinating
and norms, and the like – topics that also figure prominent- formal theory of moral value, duty, and responsibility, at
ly in common-sense psychology (e.g., Heider,1958; Wei- times working along lines started by Hutcheson and Adam
ner, 1995, 2006). Smith” (Findlay, 1963, p. 275).
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

Meinong’s first and perhaps most influential (Fabian Although Meinong saw himself firmly rooted in the em-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

& Simons, 1986) publication on ethics was the book Psy- pirical tradition of psychology established by his teacher
chologisch-ethische Untersuchungen zur Werth-Theorie Brentano (1874/1955), he did not perform systematic ob-
[Psychological-Ethical Investigations in Value Theory, servations or experiments (in today’s sense) to support his
PIV] (1894). Although little known today, Meinong’s psychological claims in PIV. Rather, Meinong’s “empirical
book, which may well contain the first elaborated general method” was a combination of introspection, thought ex-
theory of value, had a significant influence on the subse- perimentation, logical argumentation, and the analysis of
quent development of value theory, particularly among common-sense notions and ordinary language concepts.
Anglo-American scholars (e.g., Eaton, 1930; Findlay, Regarding the latter method, Eaton (1930) writes: “Mei-
1963; Mackenzie, 1895; Perry, 1926; Urban, 1909; see nong and Ehrenfels had agreed that one of the duties in-
also, Satris, 1982). Some of the ideas in PIV, in particular cumbent on the student of values was to clarify and define
the theory of value and the associated theory of emotion, – not neglect – the ideas and notions involved in the every-
were further developed by Meinong in subsequent publi- day language of the common people” (p. 180). Kindinger
cations (e.g., Meinong, 1906b, 1910, 1912, 1917, 1923). (1968) even suggests that Meinong’s method in PIV is best
However, most of the “ideas about common-sense psy- characterized as a “methodical querying of moral common-
chology” to which Heider (in Harvey et al., 1976) likely sense.”1 Indeed, Meinong (1894) frequently refers to com-
referred as having been informed by Meinong can al- mon-sense as an important source of inspiration or support.
ready be found in PIV. For this reason, we focus on the For example, in his discussion of value, Meinong repeat-
comparison of PIR and PIV. Despite the limitations of edly appeals to the common use of the term “value.” To
our study entailed by this restriction, we believe we were support a proposed division of the moral value scale, he
able to capture main lines of reception of Meinong by argues that it conforms to “the sound intuition of the theo-
Heider (for additional information, see Reisenzein & Ru- retically completely naïve person” (PIV, p. 89). He refers
dolph, this issue; Schönpflug, this issue). We first com- explicitly to the “moral common-sense” (PIV, p. 181) and
pare Meinong’s and Heider’s general aims and methods discusses the “vernacular concept of ought outside of and
in PIV and PIR, respectively, and then turn to three spe- within morality” (PIV, p. 183). Thus, in part at least, Mei-
cific areas: Emotions, the attribution of responsibility, nong’s approach in PIV can indeed be interpreted as the
and the theory of value and ought. attempt to explicate common-sense intuitions in the do-
main of practical philosophy; or as Findlay (1963, p. vii)
put it, to “formalize ordinary morality.” This is also how
Fritz Heider interpreted Meinong’s endeavor in PIV. In a
Meinong’s and Heider’s Aims and note referring to PIV in his Notebooks (edited by M. Be-
nesh-Weiner), Heider (1988, § 105) wrote: “Meinong uses
Methods mainly classification, a few mathematical models, explica-
tion of everyday terms.”
Meinong’s (1894) aim in Psychological-Ethical Investiga- The explication of everyday psychological terms – and
tions in Value Theory was to develop a general theory of thereby of the common-sense psychology contained in ordi-
value (Part I) and, on that basis, a theory of moral value, nary language – is how Heider’s (1958) aim in PIR has come
which Meinong regards as the core part of ethics (Part II). to be described. However, it is important to note that Heider
As reflected in the book’s title, this is as much a psycho- regarded the explication of common-sense psychology only
logical investigation as it is a meta-ethical one. Central to as a means to the larger end of constructing a conceptual
Meinong’s theory of value is the idea that value is intimate- framework for “the scientific study of interpersonal rela-
ly connected to emotion and – as Meinong later granted to tions” (PIR, 1958, p. 3). Influenced by philosophers Cassirer

1 All translations from German are the authors’.

Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150 © 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers
R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider 143

and Carnap and by his friend Kurt Lewin (see Schönpflug, senzein et al., 2003). For example, if one is happy, one is
this issue; and Heider, 1958, pp. 7–9), Heider was convinced happy about something (e.g., that a friend came to visit);
that science requires a precise, preferably formal language if one is afraid, one is afraid of something (e.g., that the
(see also Laucken, 1999).2 Together with his wife, he had friend might have had an accident) and so on. This intro-
translated Lewin’s Grundzüge der topologischen Psycholo- spectively ascertained fact, Meinong argues, has a
gie (Principles of Topological Psychology) into English straightforward but far-reaching implication: It entails
(Lewin, 1936) and was impressed by Lewin’s attempts to that emotions presuppose cognitions. More precisely, any
utilize mathematical language (topology and vector theory) object-directed emotion presupposes, for its existence, a
to represent mental states and their contents (the “psycholog- cognitive representation of its object. Furthermore, Mei-
ical field”). However, Heider could not find a direct way to nong argues, emotions differ from each other primarily –
apply Lewin’s field theory to the representation of interper- that is, beyond the basic distinction between positive and
sonal relations: “It got too complicated” (Heider in Harvey et negative feelings – in terms of the cognitions that form
al., 1976, p. 8). Still, Heider remained convinced that the “for- their “psychological presupposition” (PIV, p. 34).
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

mal approach” to psychology endorsed by Lewin was right. Meinong elaborated this cognitive theory of emotions in
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

Lewin only had made an unfortunate choice when opting for greatest detail for the so-called judgment-based emotions
field theory as the formal language of psychology, because it (Urteilsgefühle). These include most emotions distinguished
was unsuited for social psychology (as was also argued by a in ordinary language, such as joy, sorrow, pity and joy for
reviewer of Lewin’s book [Garrett, 1939]). Heider’s ultimate another person, hope and fear, anger, guilt, and shame. Ac-
aim in PIR is to do better than Lewin: To provide a “scientific cording to Meinong, the judgment-based emotions are char-
language that . . . is broader and more flexible than these other acterized and distinguished from other emotions by two main
psychological languages [e.g., topology], and at the same features: (1) They have propositions, or states of affairs, as
time . . . sufficiently exact to permit analysis of a wide variety objects, and (2) they presuppose beliefs or judgments about
of commonly experienced human interactions” (PIR, 1958, their objects. For example, joy about a state of affairs (e.g.,
p. 10). Believing that a great deal of relevant knowledge con- Schmidt is elected for president) presupposes the belief that
cerning such a scientific language is already available in our this state of affairs obtains (e.g., that Schmidt was, indeed,
implicit common-sense psychology, Heider proposes to ex- elected).
plicate “the implicit theoretical models of perception, action, Everyday experience indicates, however, that not every
motivation, sentiments, and norms” (Heider, 1958, p. 298), as belief engenders an emotion and that the same belief – that a
one method to arrive at the desired scientific language for particular state of affairs obtains – can cause joy in some
psychology. Although Heider never formalized his explica- people and sorrow in others. Meinong recognized that, to
tion, he saw this as a desirable goal and took first steps in this explain these facts, another mental precondition of emotions
direction (see the appendix to PIR). needs to be postulated. Although he did not discuss this ques-
When comparing Heider’s (1958) and Meinong’s (1894) tion in depth, it appears that he thought that in many (though
aims and methods, it appears that they are not far apart: not all) cases, this additional precondition of emotions is a
Both theorists wanted to establish the foundations of a sci- motivational state, a desire for (wanting) or an aversion
entific psychology, either as an end in itself (Heider), or against (“diswanting”) the state of affairs in question (Mei-
with the additional aim of providing a basis for ethics (Mei- nong 1906b, 1917; see also, Höfler, 1897). Thus, joy about a
nong). And, as one method to construct a scientific lan- state of affairs x is experienced if one believes x and desires
guage for psychology, Heider returned to Meinong’s meth- x; sorrow about x is experienced if one believes x and is aver-
od of psychological inquiry. As will be seen, he also adopt- sive against or “diswants” x. In the typical case, one first
ed some of the results that Meinong had obtained with this comes to desire or to diswant a state of affairs x. Subsequent-
method. ly, on the basis of perception or inference, one acquires the
belief that x obtains. Together, the desire or diswant and the
belief then cause a feeling of pleasure or displeasure directed
at the same object, x. This object-directed feeling of pleasure
Meinong and Heider on Emotions or displeasure is the emotion of joy or sorrow, respectively,
or at least constitutes the core of these emotional experiences
Meinong’s Theory of the Judgment Emotions (Meinong, 1906b).

General Emotion Theory


Distinctions Between Emotions
Following his teacher Brentano, Meinong (1894) begins
his analysis of the emotions with the assumption that emo- In Meinong’s view, pleasure and displeasure about a state
tions are object-directed (see also Meinong, 1906b; Rei- of affairs are the two basic forms of the judgment-based

2 Heider’s desire for precision was apparently kindled by Meinong. “The lectures seemed to come out of his mouth ready to be published.
After getting used to Meinong’s talks everybody else seemed sloppy, messy and diffuse” (Heider, 1970, p. 132).

© 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150
144 R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider

emotions. That is, all other judgment-based emotions are Heider’s Explication of the Common-sense
subtypes or variants of these basic emotions. Their differ- Psychology of Emotions
ences are mainly due to differences in their cognitive pre-
conditions. Pleasure and Displeasure
Specifically, Meinong (1894) proposed that belief
strength (degree of certainty) distinguishes hope and fear Heider deals with emotions in several chapters of PIR. In
from joy and sorrow: If one is uncertain whether a desired Chapter 5, entitled “Desire and Pleasure,” Heider proposes:
state of affairs obtains, one feels hope rather than joy; if “In naive psychology, the concept desire . . . is linked to plea-
one is uncertain whether an undesired state of affairs ob- sure upon the fulfillment of the desire, thus: Desire for [an
tains, one feels fear rather than sorrow. According to object] x plus obtaining x leads to pleasure . . . when a desire
Meinong, the certain-uncertain distinction reflects a dif- exists, its fulfillment will be satisfying” (PIR, pp. 129–130).
ference in the mode of the mental state, a difference in As Heider makes clear a few pages later, this postulate applies
the manner of believing (believing firmly vs. less than to psychological reality, not to objective reality: “It is not the
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

firmly). However, most of the differences between judg- actual occurrence of the [desired] event but rather the belief
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

ment-based emotions are due to differences in the prop- that the event has occurred that is the necessary and sufficient
ositional contents of the beliefs and desires underlying cause for . . . enjoyment” (p. 145). Hence, enjoyment is
the emotions. For example, if a cognized state of affairs “based on a . . . judgment” (PIR, p. 146), that can be acquired
concerns one’s own wellbeing, one feels joy or sorrow. in various ways: “He may see it happen; he may infer its
In contrast, if this state of affairs concerns another per- occurrence from other events; he may be told about it” (PIR,
son’s emotional experiences, one experiences “emotions p. 144). As soon as we become convinced that a desired event
of sympathy or antipathy” (PIV, p. 47) – so-called by has happened, “this wish will cease and enjoyment take its
Meinong because the hedonic tone or valence of the ex- place” (p. 144).3
periencer’s emotion agrees (emotions of sympathy) or Although the desire for x and the belief that x obtains
disagrees (emotions of antipathy) with that of the per- are sufficient conditions for pleasure about x (PIR, p. 144),
ceived emotion of the other person. desire is not a necessary condition for pleasure (PIR,
The emotions of sympathy are joy for another person p. 132). This, Heider proposes, is suggested by the fact that
and pity. Joy for another person is felt if one believes that emotions can be caused by entirely unexpected events, like
the other experiences a positive feeling and desires this pleasure about a happy surprise beyond our fondest wishes
perceived fact; pity for another if one believes that the or displeasure about disasters we had never thought of as
other experiences a negative feeling and diswants this possible (PIR, p. 132). An analogous argument for the non-
state of affairs. The emotions of antipathy are envy/re- necessity of desire for judgment-based emotions was made
sentment and Schadenfreude (joy at another’s misfor- by Meinong’s student Höfler in a textbook where he de-
tune). Envy or resentment is felt if one believes that an- scribed Meinong’s emotion theory (Höfler, 1897, p. 404).
other person experiences a positive feeling and diswants
this perceived fact; Schadenfreude is felt if one believes
that another person experiences a negative feeling and if Other Emotions
one desires this state of affairs. Of particular importance
to ethics, the judgment-based emotions also comprise the Like Meinong, Heider assumes that the differences between
traditional “moral emotions” (e.g., guilt, indignation, and emotions (beyond positive and negative) are mainly due to
moral elevation), which Meinong (1894) defines in gen- differences in their cognitive preconditions. Specifically, in
eral terms as feelings of moral approval and moral disap- general agreement with Meinong, though less general in his
proval of an action or actor. formulation, Heider (PIR, p. 141) proposes that according to
common-sense psychology, “hope arises when the person,
separated from x and desiring x, believes that x will come
within his reach” (PIR, p. 141), whereas “fear arises when the
Functions of Emotions person, in contact with and enjoying x, recognizes the possi-
bility of losing x” (PIR, p. 141). Furthermore, in Chapter 11
Meinong proposes that the main function of emotions is of PIR, entitled “Reaction to the Lot of the Other Person,”
informational, or epistemic: Emotions provide the expe- Heider proposes that “four types of [emotional] reaction to
riencer with information about the value of objects. More the lot of the other person may be schematically distin-
than that: According to Meinong, emotions (and desires) guished” (p. 277): Sympathetic enjoyment, sympathy or
constitute the primary value experiences; they are the ba- compassion, envy, and malicious joy or Schadenfreude.
sic, original forms of becoming aware of the value of ob- Sympathetic enjoyment is pleasure about the perceived fact
jects and states of affairs. that another person has a positive experience; or as Heider

3 Compare Meinong (1917, p. 96): “The desire is annihilated as soon as the judgment [that the desired state of affairs obtains] replaces the
assumption; this is the subjective aspect of what is called . . . the fulfillment of the desire.”

Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150 © 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers
R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider 145

puts it: “that o has a positive experience is positive for p” putation” is a traditional term for the attribution of retro-
(PIR, p. 277). Compassion is displeasure about the fact that o spective responsibility (Werner, 2002; see also Heider,
has a negative experience; envy is displeasure about o’s hav- 1944). Meinong proposes that the process of responsibility
ing a positive experience; and Schadenfreude is pleasure attribution comprises a cognitive and an emotional compo-
about o’s displeasure. Echoing Meinong’s (1894) distinction nent.4
between “emotions of sympathy” and “emotions of antipa-
thy,” Heider suggests that in sympathetic enjoyment and
compassion “the relation between p and o is syntonic or con- The Cognitive Component of Moral Imputation
cordant” (PIR, p. 277), whereas the emotions of envy and
Schadenfreude “show a discordance or antagonism between The cognitive component of moral imputation (responsi-
p and o” (PIR, pp. 277–278). bility attribution) comprises the “cognitive operations that
are necessary to clarify the relation between the given ac-
tion and the personality that stands behind it” (PIV, p. 206).
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

The Function of Emotions At issue is the question to which degree the action emerged
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

from the actor’s attitude and what the nature of this attitude
Like Meinong, Heider claims that “neither desire nor plea- is – more precisely, to which degree the action was moti-
sure are merely states with a peculiar quality; both have cog- vated by the good-will or ill-will of the actor, his altruistic
nitive aspects,” with “one kind of cognitive meaning [be- or antialtruistic motives. To clarify the conditions under
ing]. . . the value relation between p and x” (PIR, pp. 137– which a person is held responsible for an action, Meinong
138). Heider explains: lists the most important cases in which an action cannot be
“Desire and pleasure imply the apprehension of a quality of x,
imputed to a person, as well as the most important factors
the quality of being satisfying to the person.” (PIR, p. 138) “It that reduce responsibility.
is as if the positive quality of the object is discerned through Meinong proposes that a person cannot be held respon-
such different avenues as remembering with pleasure, enjoy- sible (1) when no intention was present at all, such as omis-
ing, desiring, hoping for, etc. We see, so to speak, the same sions due to paralysis or unconsciousness, and (2) when an
hedonic property of the object from different points of view” intention and hence an action was present, but the conse-
(PIR, p. 141). quences of the action were “different from what was willed,
To summarize, many aspects of Heider’s “explication of or at least foreseen (this pertains specifically to harm
common-sense psychology” in the field of emotions corre- caused)” (PIV, p. 197). In contrast, when the consequences
spond to Meinong’s theory of the judgment-based emo- of an action were foreseen or even intended, responsibility
tions. Heider’s proposals concerning the link between be- is in principle always present. Still, the degree of responsi-
lief and desire on the one hand, and pleasure/displeasure bility may be reduced even in these cases if (3) “the willing
on the other hand; his distinction between joy and hope and cannot be regarded as an expression of the impersonal [i.e.,
between sorrow and fear; his analysis of the emotional re- the morally relevant] concerns of the actor, either because
actions to the lot of others; and his assumption that emo- the willing is not of a moral nature at all, or because it must
tions serve cognitive functions by providing information be attributed to different causes, that is, to external (phys-
about value–all these assumptions correspond fairly well ical or mental) duress in the widest sense” (PIV, p. 197)
to Meinong’s views in PIV. The main difference is that, in such as temptation or social pressure. Meinong then dis-
the process of reception, some of the precision and detail cusses in some detail the various factors that reduce respon-
of the Meinongian original got lost. sibility.

The Emotional Component of Moral Imputation


Meinong and Heider on the
Meinong proposes that the cognitive operation of respon-
Attribution of Responsibility sibility ascription is followed and “completed” by an emo-
and on Moral Emotions tional reaction. This emotion is a “moral worth feeling,” a
feeling of moral approval or disapproval of the action or
Meinong’s Theory of Moral Imputation actor. As already mentioned, feelings of moral approval
and disapproval belong to the class of judgment-based
In Chapter IV of the second part of PIV, Meinong (1894) emotions. Specifically, they are caused by the judgment
examines the mental processes involved in the moral im- that the other person is responsible. According to Meinong,
putation [moralische Zurechnung] of actions. “Moral im- these emotions are more intense (a) the higher the positive

4 Meinong’s analysis of the attribution of responsibility may have been influenced by his knowledge of law, as he began his University studies
as a law student. Interestingly, the main translation of “Zurechnung” and the verb “zurechnen” into English is “attribution” and “to attribute,”
respectively.

© 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150
146 R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider

or negative value of the action (or outcome), and (b) “the Even in these cases, responsibility is reduced (though not
more this action can be taken to be an emanation of the abolished) when the intention was not produced by the per-
actor’s personality” (PIV, p. 206), that is, the higher the per- son’s morally relevant attitudes, but by “physical or mental
ceived degree of responsibility. of the actor. duress in the widest sense” (PIV, p. 197). Thus, Meinong’s
case 3 comprises Heider’s level 4 (intention) and level 5
(justification). As to Heider’s remaining levels, Meinong
classifies these as cases in which responsibility is absent,
Heider’s Theory of Responsibility Attribution whereas Heider speaks of responsibility “at a lower level.”
and its Emotional Consequences However, this difference is not a true disagreement about
Responsibility Attribution the meaning of “responsibility,” because Heider links the
lower levels of responsibility to earlier levels of cognitive
development that presumably reflect an imperfect mastery
One of the first ideas from PIR subjected to empirical test
of the adult responsibility concept. Meinong’s case 1 cor-
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

was Heider’s theory of responsibility attribution (Shaw &


responds to Heider’s level 1 (association); Meinongs case
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

Sulzer, 1964). This theory subsequently became perhaps


2 subsumes Heider’s level 2 (causality) and 3 (foreseeabil-
the most influential theory of the attribution of responsibil-
ity). In contrast to Heider, Meinong makes no assumptions
ity in social and developmental psychology (McGraw,
about the developmental course of the responsibility con-
1987) and stimulated numerous empirical studies (e.g., Fin-
cept. In fact, Heider adopted this aspect of his theory from
cham & Jaspars, 1980; Weiner, 1995, 2006).
Piaget (1932; see Heider, 1958, p. 113). Thus, Heider’s
Heider proposes that the process of responsibility ascrip- “common-sense theory of responsibility attribution” can be
tion encompasses the causal attribution of the action to per- regarded as a combination of Meinong’s and Piaget’s views
sonal versus environmental factors, and that attributed re- on the subject.5
sponsibility depends on the relative importance of the en-
vironmental factors: “In general, the more [situational
factors] are felt to influence the action, the less the person
is held responsible” (PIR, p. 113). Heider then proposes Emotional Reactions to Benefit and Harm
five successive stages of responsibility attribution that rep-
resent increasingly sophisticated, cognitively demanding Like Meinong, Heider assumes that ascriptions of respon-
levels of attribution. These levels are as follows (with la- sibility for an action often cause emotional reactions in
bels taken from Fincham & Jaspars, 1980): At the most those affected by the action or in onlookers. Heider makes
primitive level 1 (association), a person p is held responsi- these proposals in Chapter 10 of PIR, where he analyzes
ble for any outcome x with which p is connected in any reactions to benefit and harm received from others. Heider
way. At level 2 (causality), p is held responsible for x when- specifically mentions two emotions that would be classi-
ever p physically caused x, even if x was not p’s aim, and fied by Meinong as emotions of (possibly moral) approval
even if p did not and could not have foreseen x. At level 3 and disapproval: Gratitude (as a reaction to benefit) and
(foreseeability), p is held responsible for x whenever p feelings of revenge (as a reaction to harm). Heider proposes
physically caused and could have foreseen x, even if x was that for both emotions, “attribution to source and intention”
not his goal. At level 4 (intention), p is held responsible for (PIR, p. 265) is of utmost importance. He explains:
x whenever p intended to produce x. Finally, at level 5 (jus- “An everyday fact is that the feelings of both revenge and grat-
tification), p is held (fully) responsible for x only if p in- itude become markedly attenuated, if not completely dissipat-
tended to produce x and p’s intention was not, in turn, ed, upon the discovery that the harm or the benefit was not the
forced upon p by the environment, as is the case for exam- true goal of the agent. We do not feel grateful to a person who
ple in “traitorous acts committed under duress” (PIR, helps us fortuitously, or because he was forced to do so, or
p. 114). In the latter cases, responsibility is “at least shared because he was obliged to do so. Gratitude is determined by
by the environment” (PIR, p. 114). the will, the intention, of the benefactor. Attribution to source
and intention has similar significance in the case of revenge”
If one compares Heider’s theory of responsibility ascrip- (PIR, p. 265).
tion to Meinong’s assumptions about the cognitive compo-
nent of moral imputation, it becomes evident that Heider Although Heider does not explicitly refer to responsibility
and Meinong discuss the same topic and arrive at highly in this context, his discussion implies that, at least in adults,
similar conclusions. The main difference is that Heider feelings of gratitude and revenge arise only to the extent
concentrates on the conditions that allow the ascription of that one holds the other person responsible for a received
responsibility, whereas Meinong focuses on the conditions benefit or harm at Heider’s level 4 (intention). If responsi-
that eliminate or reduce responsibility. According to Mei- bility is ascribed at a lower level (unintended benefit or
nong, responsibility can be ascribed only when the out- harm), gratitude and revenge are reduced or abolished. The
come of an action was intended and foreseen by the person. same happens when intentionality is present but mitigating

5 Later, however, Heider distanced himself from the developmental interpretation of his theory (Fincham & Jaspars, 1980).

Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150 © 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers
R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider 147

circumstances prevail (level 5, justification). Hence, like case of moral ought is distinguished from the nonmoral
Meinong, Heider assumes that feelings of moral approval case primarily in terms of the object of the “ought to”: One
and disapproval, such as gratitude and revenge, presuppose morally ought to do what is morally good and to refrain
the ascription of responsibility and increase in intensity from doing what is morally bad – that is, what elicits the
with the degree of responsibility ascribed. approval or disapproval of the impartial observer.

Heider on Ought and Value


Meinong and Heider on Value and
Ought As mentioned, in Chapter 3 of PIR Heider proposes, like
Meinong, that values are properties of objects that are ap-
Meinong on Value and Ought prehended through emotions (and desires). In Chapter 8 of
PIR, entitled “Ought and Value,” Heider further explicates
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

As mentioned, Meinong (1894) proposed that values are this concept. As the title suggests, Heider’s focus in this
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

psychologically grounded in emotions. Specifically, emo- chapter is on moral value and its relation to normative ob-
tions are the means by which the value of objects is appre- ligations (“oughts”). Heider’s resulting “explication of the
hended. But what are the values themselves? Are they ob- naive value concept” seems to incorporate aspects of both
jectively existing properties of objects, or just projections Meinong’s early value theory (in PIV) and of his later, more
of our emotions onto objects? In the words of Plato, do we strongly “objectivist” view (e.g., Meinong, 1917; 1923).
like something because it is good, or is it good because we Thus, Heider agrees with Meinong’s (1894) proposal that
like it? Meinong (1894) takes an intermediate position values are dispositions of objects to elicit particular reac-
here, by proposing a dispositional theory of value (see tions in us: “Both value and like belong to the dimension
Smith, 1989): According to Meinong, the value of an object of potentiality . . . under proper conditions, they may evoke
is the object’s capacity to elicit emotional experiences oughts or wishes” (PIR, p. 224). But at the same time, Hei-
(feelings of worth) under normal circumstances: “An ob- der emphasizes the objectivity of value. For example, he
ject has value if it has the capacity to serve as the actual writes that the term “value” means “the property of an en-
basis of a feeling of worth for the sufficiently oriented, nor- tity . . . with the connotation of being objectively positive
mally constituted person” (PIV, p. 25; “feelings of worth” in some way . . . any strictly impartial observer, particularly
are judgment-based emotions). Hence, already in this early one who is well informed and wise, would recognize it as
phase of his thinking about value, Meinong was not entirely being positive” (PIR, pp. 223–224).
subjectivist about value (Reicher, 2005). In later years, in With respect to the concept of ought, Heider proposes,
connection with the development of his theory of objects, also similar to Meinong, that “the content of ‘I (or o) ought
Meinong’s (1912, 1917, 1923) value theory became decid- to do x’ may be said to be fashioned after the idea ‘some-
edly “objectivist.” According to the revised version of the body wants or commands that I (or o) do x.’ In the case of
theory, values, although apprehended through personal ought, however, it is not a particular somebody that is felt
emotional experiences, are neither personal nor relative, to want or command people to do x, but some suprapersonal
but fully objective properties of objects. Furthermore, Mei- objective order . . . oughts are impersonal. They refer to
nong now granted to Ehrenfels (1897) that not only emo- standards . . . independent of the individual’s wishes.”
tions but also desires belong to the primary experiences of (PIR, p. 219).
value. In sum, Heider’s “explication of the common-sense con-
Based on his general theory of value, Meinong (1894) cepts of ought and value” agrees in its major outlines with
in the second part of PIV sets out to clarify the notion of Meinong’s theory of moral value and moral obligation.
moral value. According to Meinong, the moral goodness
or badness of an action is its capacity to elicit feelings of
approval or disapproval in an impartial observer. These
feelings are based on the impartial observer’s judgment of Discussion
responsibility, which (as noted) reflects the degree to which
the action is seen as resulting from the good-will versus Our comparative historical investigation both confirmed
ill-will of the actor. and clarified Heider’s hint that “some of the ideas that I
In Chapter III of the second part of PIV, Meinong exam- developed about common-sense psychology originally
ines the “vernacular concept of ought outside of and within came from [Meinong]” (Heider in Harvey et al., 1976,
morality” (p. 183): “Generally speaking . . . the term ‘ought p. 6). Of course, PIR also takes up and integrates ideas from
to’ means the complex fact that there is a willing or a desire other philosophers and psychologists, and in nearly every
directed at the action or intention of the person who ‘ought case, Heider elaborates these ideas and combines them with
to’. The person who ought to and the person who wills can his own in creative ways. Still, the Meinongian memes in-
be the same subject, although it is more natural if they are herent in PIR – Meinong’s theory of emotions, his theory
not” (PIV, p. 184). Furthermore, Meinong proposes that the of value, and his theory of responsibility attribution – play

© 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150
148 R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider

an important role in Heider’s “scientific language for social 1995), but back in 1958, the situation was certainly differ-
psychology.” Nor are these all correspondences between ent. Heider may have feared that the chances of getting his
PIR and PIV. For example, both Heider’s proposal that peo- book published in the behavioristic climate of the 1950s
ple strive to attribute effects to stable dispositional causes would be further reduced if Meinong were prominently
because such causes are best suited for predictions (e.g., featured there. Finally, Heider may have consciously or un-
PIR, p. 30), and the related concept of increasingly “deep- consciously suppressed Meinong’s name in PIR to assert
er” levels of attribution (e.g., PIR, p. 81) can be traced back his intellectual independence from Meinong’s “command-
to Meinong’s analysis of responsibility attribution. In this ing presence.” Fabian and Simons (1986) propose a parallel
context, interested readers may also wish to consult Mei- explanation for Meinong’s sparse reference to his teacher
nong’s (1919) elaborated theory of dispositions (see also Brentano.
Mulligan, 2003). In addition, as mentioned, Heider more Ultimately, however, this issue is of secondary impor-
or less continued Meinong’s method of psychological in- tance. The main result of our study is that even without
quiry. Meinong’s name attached to them, Heider helped to trans-
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

Given these results, the complete lack of a reference to port some of Meinong’s ideas into today’s social psychol-
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

Meinong in PIR certainly is surprising. Attribution theo- ogy. Unknowingly, some of us have been Meinongians all
rists have pointed out that surprising events instigate spon- along.
taneous causal search (Meyer, Reisenzein, & Schützwohl,
1997; Weiner, 1985): We want to know why the surprising
event – in our case, the lack of reference to a scientific Acknowledgments
mentor – occurred. Although we do not have enough data
to provide a definitive answer to this question, we can offer We thank Uwe Laucken, Wulf-Uwe Meyer, Udo Rudolph,
a number of (not necessarily exclusive) causal hypotheses. and Wolfgang Schönpflug for their helpful comments on
First, it is possible that when Heider wrote PIR in the an earlier version of the manuscript.
1950s, he had forgotten the source of the Meinongian ideas
contained in his book; he recalled or rediscovered their
source only after PIR had been published (e.g., when doing
research for his 1970 article on the early history of Gestalt
psychology). This hypothesis receives support from Hei-
References
der’s statement in the interview with Harvey et al. (1976,
Brentano, F. (1874/1955). Psychologie vom empirischen Stand-
p. 6) that he “now realized” that some of the ideas in PIR
punkt [Psychology from the empirical point of view] (Vol. 1,
originally came from Meinong. It is even possible that Hei- edited by O. Kraus). Hamburg: Meiner.
der had never read PIV before that time and only came into Chrudzimski, A. (2007). Gegenstandstheorie und Theorie der In-
contact with the material contained in it in Meinong’s lec- tentionalität bei Alexius Meinong [Alexius Meinong’s theory
tures6. Second, as proposed by Schönpflug (2008, this is- of objects and theory of intentionality]. Berlin: Springer-Ver-
sue), Heider may not have felt obliged to cite Meinong be- lag.
cause, in the generation of scholars to which he belonged, Eaton, H.O. (1930). The Austrian philosophy of values. Norman:
meticulous citation of the works of others, particularly University of Oklahoma Press.
members of the own “school,” was deemed unnecessary. Ehrenfels, C. (1897). System der Werttheorie [System of value
As Schönpflug and Heidelberger (2007) have documented, theory]. Leipzig: Reisland.
Heider’s friend and colleague Lewin was equally mute Fabian, R. & Simons, P.M. (1986). The second Austrian school of
about his early academic influences. And sure enough, value theory. In B. Smith & W. Grassl (Eds.), Austrian econom-
Meinong also borrowed from those before him, like Bren- ics: Historical and philosophical background (pp. 37–101). New
York: New York University Press.
tano, Lotze, Adam Smith, Hume, Hutcheson, and Spinoza
Fincham, F.D., & Jaspars, J.M. (1980). Attribution of responsi-
(see Fabian & Simons, 1986; Findlay, 1963; Satris, 1982)
bility: From man the scientist to man as lawyer. In L. Berko-
without always crediting them. Indeed, PIV contains hardly witz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology
any references at all (in the preface, Meinong attributes (Vol. 13, pp. 81–138). New York: Academic Press.
their lack to time pressure). Third, Heider (1958) may have Findlay, J.N. (1963). Meinong’s theory of objects and values (2nd
been reluctant to cite Meinong because the latter had at the ed.). Oxford: Clarendon.
time fallen into disrepute among analytical philosophers, Garrett, H.E. (1939). Lewin’s topological psychology: An evalu-
mainly due to criticisms of his theory of objects (e.g., Rus- ation. Psychological Review, 46, 517–524.
sell, 1904; Ryle, 1933, cited in Findlay, 1963) that Heider Harvey, J.H., Ickes, W.J., & Kidd, R.F. (Eds.). (1976). New direc-
may in fact have shared (Heider, 1983, p. 22). Meinong has tions in attribution research (Vol. 1). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
since been rehabilitated (e.g., Chrudzimski, 2007; Lambert, Heider, F. (1920). Zur Subjektivität der Sinnesqualitäten [On the

6 Heider’s (1920) dissertation contains no reference to PIV (Meinong, 1894). However, it contains references to Meinong (1906a, 1917, 1919)
and to a psychology textbook written by Meinong’s student Witasek (1908). As mentioned, Heider later referred to PIV in his Notebooks
(Heider, 1988).

Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150 © 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers
R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider 149

subjectivity of sense qualities]. Unpublished dissertation, Uni- (Eds.). (1977). Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe [Alexius Me-
versity of Graz. inong’s complete works] (Vol. IV). Graz, Austria: Akademi-
Heider, F. (1926). Ding und Medium [Thing and medium]. Sym- sche Druck- und Verlagsanstalt.
posion, 1, 109–157. Reprint 2005, Berlin: Kadmos Verlag. Meinong, A. (1912). Für die Psychologie und gegen den Psycho-
Heider, F. (1944). Social perception and phenomenal causality. logismus in der allgemeinen Werttheorie [For psychology and
Psychological Review, 51, 358–374. against psychologism in the general theory of value]. Logos,
Heider, F. (1946). Attitudes and cognitive organization. The Jour- 3, 1–14.
nal of Psychology, 21, 107–112. Meinong, A. (1917). Über emotionale Präsentation [On emotional
Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations. New presentation]. Sitzungsberichte der Kaiserlichen Akademie der
York: Wiley. Wissenschaften in Wien, Philosophisch-Historische Klasse,
Heider, F. (1970). Gestalt theory: Early history and reminiscences. 183, 2–181. [Reprinted in R. Haller & R. Kindinger (Eds.).
Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 6, 131–139. (1968). Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe [Alexius Meinong’s
Heider, F. (1983). The life of a psychologist: An autobiography. complete works] (Vol. III, pp. 285–465). Graz, Austria: Aka-
Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas. demische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt]
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

Meinong, A. (1919). Allgemeines zur Lehre von den Dispositio-


This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

Heider, F. (Ed. Marijana Benesh-Weiner). (1987–1989). “The


notebooks,” Vols. 1–6. München: PVU. nen [On the general theory of dispositions]. In A. Martinak
Heider, F. (Ed. Marijana Benesh-Weiner). (1988). “The note- (Ed.), Beiträge zur Pädagogik und Dispositionstheorie.
books,” Vol. 5: Attributional and interpersonal evaluation. Eduard Martinak zur Feier seines 60. Geburtstages [Contri-
München: PVU. butions to the theory of dispositions] (pp. 33–54). Prag: Haase.
Heider, F., & Simmel, M. (1944). An experimental study of apparent Meinong, A. (1923). Zur Grundlegung der allgemeinen Werttheorie
behavior. American Journal of Psychology, 57, 234–259. [On the foundations of general value theory]. Graz, Austria:
Höfler, A. (1897). Psychologie [Psychology]. Wien: Tempsky. Leuschner and Lubensky. [Reprinted in R. Haller & R. Kindinger
Kindinger, R. (1968). Vorwort [Preface]. In R. Haller & R. Kin- (Hg.) (1968), Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe Band III [Al-
dinger (Eds.), Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe [Alexius Me- exius Meinong’s complete works] (Vol. III, pp. 471–656). Graz,
inong’s complete works] (Vol. III, pp. VII–XIII). Graz, Aus- Austria: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt]
tria: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt. Meyer, W.-U., Reisenzein, R., & Schützwohl, A. (1997). Toward
Lambert, K. (1995). Substitution and the expansion of the world. a process analysis of emotions: The case of surprise. Motiva-
Grazer Philosophische Studien, 49, 129–143. tion and Emotion, 21, 251–274.
Laucken, U. (1999). “An exceptionally important publication”: Mulligan, K. (2003). Dispositions, their bases and correlates: Mei-
Fritz Heider (1896–1988). Berichte aus dem Institut zur Erfor- nong’s analysis. In K. Kijania-Placek (Ed.), Philosophy and log-
schung von Mensch-Umwelt-Beziehungen, 31, Universität ic: In search of the Polish tradition. Essays in honour of Jan
Oldenburg. [A shortened version of this essay is published as: Wolenski on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 193–211).
Laucken, U. (2000). Fritz Heider: The psychology of interper- Dordrecht: Kluwer.
sonal relations (1958). In H.E. Lück, R. Miller & G. Sewz- Perry, W. (1926). General theory of value. New York: Longmans,
Vosshenrich (Hrsg.) Klassiker der Psychologie [Classics of Green.
psychology] (pp. 203–208). Stuttgart/Berlin/Köln: Kohlham- Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgment of the child. New York:
mer] Harcourt Brace.
Lewin, K. (1936). Principles of topological psychology. New Reicher, M.E. (2005). Wertgefühle [Value feelings]. In A. Früh-
York: McGraw-Hill. wirth, M.E. Reicher, & P. Wilhelmer (Eds.), Markt-Wert-Ge-
Mackenzie, J.S. (1895). Notes on the theory of value. Mind, 4, fühle: Positionen und Perspektiven einer multidisziplinären
425–449. Wertdebatte [Market-value emotions: Positions and perspec-
McGraw, K.M. (1987). Guilt following transgression: An attribu- tives of a multidisciplinary value debate]. Vienna: Passagen.
tion of responsibility approach. Journal of Personality and So- Reisenzein, R., Meyer, W.-U., & Schützwohl, A. (2003). Einfüh-
cial Psychology, 53, 247–256. rung in die Emotionspsychologie, Band III: Kognitive Emo-
Meinong, A. (1894). Psychologisch-ethische Untersuchungen zur tionstheorien [Introduction to the psychology of emotion,
Werth-Theorie [Psychological-ethical investigations in value the- Vol. 3: Cognitive theories of emotion]. Bern: Huber.
ory]. Graz, Austria: Leuschner & Lubensky. Reprinted in R. Hal- Reisenzein, R., & Rudolph, U. (2008). The discovery of common-
ler & R. Kindinger (Eds.). (1968). Alexius Meinong Gesamtaus- sense psychology. Social Psychology, 39, 125–133.
gabe[Alexius Meinong’s complete works] (Vol. III, pp. 3–244). Russell, B. (1904). Meinong’s theory of complexes and assump-
Graz, Austria: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt. tions. Mind, 13, 204–219 (Part 1); 336–354 (Part 2); 509–524
Meinong, A. (1906a). Über die Erfahrungsgrundlagen unseres (Part 3).
Wissens [On the empirical basis of our knowledge]. Berlin: Satris, S. (1982). The theory of value and the rise of ethical emo-
Springer-Verlag. [Reprinted in R. Haller & R. Kindinger tivism. Journal of the History of Ideas, 43, 109–128.
(Eds.). (1973). Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe [Alexius Me- Schönpflug, W. (2008). Fritz Heider – My academic teacher and
inong’s complete works] (Vol. V, pp. 369–481). Graz, Austria: his academic teachers: Heider’s “Seminar in Interpersonal Re-
Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt.] lations” and comments on his European background. Social
Meinong, A. (1906b). Über Urteilsgefühle: Was sie sind und was sie Psychology, 39, 134–140.
nicht sind [On judgment-based feelings: What they are and what Schönpflug, W., & Heidelberger, M. (2007). Kurt Lewin und
they are not]. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 6, 22–58. seine Lehrer Alois Riehl und Ernst Cassirer: Wissenschaft-
Meinong, A. (1910). Über Annahmen [On assumptions] (2nd ed.). liche Philosophie, Erkenntnistheorie und Feldtheorie [Kurt
Leipzig, Austria: Barth. Reprinted in R. Haller & R. Kindinger Lewin and his teachers Alois Riehl and Ernst Cassirer]. In

© 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150
150 R. Reisenzein & I. Mchitarjan: Tracing Meinong’s Influence on Heider

W. Schönpflug (Ed.), Kurt Lewin – Person und Werk, Um- Düwell, C. Hübenthal, & M.H. Werner (Eds.), Handbuch Ethik
feld und Rezeption [Kurt Lewin – Person and work, context, [Handbook of ethics] (pp. 521–527). Stuttgart: Metzler.
and reception]. Frankfurt am Main: Lang. Witasek, S. (1908). Grundlinien der Psychologie [Outline of psy-
Shaw, M.E., & Sulzer, J.L. (1964). An empirical test of Heider’s chology]. Leipzig: Felix Meiner.
levels in attribution of responsibility. Journal of Abnormal and
Social Psychology, 69, 39–46.
Smith, M. (1989). Dispositional theories of value. Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society, 63, 89–111. Rainer Reisenzein
Urban, W.M. (1909). Valuation: Its nature and laws. London: Al-
len & Unwin. University of Greifswald
Weiner, B. (1985). “Spontaneous” causal thinking. Psychological Institute of Psychology
Bulletin, 97, 74–84. Franz-Mehring-Straße 47
Weiner, B. (1995). Judgments of responsibility: A foundation for D-17489 Greifswald
a theory of social conduct. New York: Guilford. Germany
This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

Weiner, B. (2006). Social motivation, justice, and the moral emo- Tel. +49 3834 863770
This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.

tions: An attributional approach. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Fax +49 3834 863763
Werner, M.H. (2002). Verantwortung [Responsibility]. In M. E-mail rainer.reisenzein@uni-greifswald.de

Social Psychology 2008; Vol. 39(3):141–150 © 2008 Hogrefe & Huber Publishers

You might also like