Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 15

I

I
I SAMUEL WEBER

I
Theatricality as Medium
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I Fordham University Press New York 2004

I
'il

ADORNO

hig~ time to distinguish the pseudo-simultaneity of repetition, as


10
readmg, theater, and staging, from the monolithic quality of the Im-
mergleiche~ as th.e return of the same. What Adomo saw as the ghostly
spectacle In which the unrepeatable is incessantly repeated might then
Psychoanalysis and Theatricality
I turn out to have been nothing ntore or less than a particularly power-
ful pseudonym for the "nonidentical." Or vice-versa.

I
I T o o 1 s c u s s the significance of theatricality for psycho-
analysis, and in particular for the thought of Freud, it is first necessary
to distinguish what is commonly understood by theatricality from the
quite different conception to which Freud appeals. If a certain notion

I of theater is crucial to Freud in articulating what distinguishes psycho-


analysis from previous modes of thought, then this notion itself will
have to be understood in a way that diverges from the £uuiliar and

I
still dominant use to which it is generally put.
Two citations can illustrate this use. The first is from the introduc-
tion to a book by Joyce McDougall, one of the relatively few analysts
to have placed questions of theatricality at the center of her thinking.

I The passage I want to discuss glosses the title of the book that it
introduces, nmnely, Theaters cif the Ego (Th6a.tres du ]e). McDougall
explains the project of this book in the following tenns:

I The tragedies of Hamlet, Lear, Richard Ill ... entail the history
of men confronted by violent forces of their instinctual nature .
. . . Traversed by stonns of love and of hate, seeking now to

I seduce and cherish, now to punish and destroy, each man was
obliged, fron1 infancy on, to learn how to navigate between the
prohibitions and impossibilities of his life. Obliged to invent a
solution for each of the inevitable conflicts provoked by his

I primitive desires, he had to fmd compromises that satisfied him-


self as much as others. With all these struggles, and as though
with an artistic palette, he sketched the portrait of that person

I he believed himself to be when he says "I." In fact, this I is a


character, an "actor" on the world scene who, in private, in his
internal reality, attends a more intimate theater whose repertory
is secret. Unknown to him, scenarios are organized, farcical

'
I
250
251
'0'!1

PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY


PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

scenes and tragic scenes in search of a place of representation the tragic hero does not seem to conform very well to the Shakespear-
and of action. The director, of course, is the I itself, but the face ean figures named by McDougall, it coincides all the more with a
of the characters, the plot as well as its denouement, are veiled certain modem notion of the autonomous, active subject, struggling
to him; he does not even know those who are pushing him to establish control over his destiny.
toward the drama. No warning is given to hin1 that the action Freud's account of the Ego is strikingly different. The conflict situ-
is going to begin and that somewhere, in a place of his psyche, ation in which it is situated is above all neither of its own making nor
a character is moving about-Seagate--and wants to enter the even attributable to it. In Freud's description there is no question of
stage.... And yet it is there, in this interior universe, that the ascribing the forces of conflict to the ego as "his instinctual nature"
greater part of what is to become his life will be decided.• or "his primitive desires"-that is precisely the point, and the joke, if
you will: the clown, "stupid August," is stupid precisely insofar as he
The second passage is from Freud's "On the History of the Psycho-
acts as though he were in control of what is going on. This also deter-
analytic Movement," and is directed against the conception of the ego
mines the kind of theatrical reference that Freud invokes, which is
he associates with the theories of Alfred Adler. At the center of their
very different fron1 McDougall's, as different as a circus farce is from
divergence stands the interpretation of the ego and its relation to
a Shakespearean tragedy. For McDougall, "conflict" and "struggle"
symptom fon11ation. Adlerian theory, Freud argues, overestimates the
importance of the ego in this process: constitute the "dramatic" and hence "theatrical" di1nension of psy-
chic activity, centered on the Ego. For Freud, in this context at least,
Whereby it entirely overlooks the fact that upon countless occa- such tragic pretensions are only part of a ~ore general burlesque role
sions the ego merely makes a virtue out of necessity by accepting that the Ego plays, one that is only indirectly related to its manifest
the most undesirable symptom imposed upon it simply by virtue situation. Freud's theatrical references, then, are not defined primarily
of the utility attached to it, e.g., when it accepts anxiety as a through conflicts that provoke struggle: rather, they are part of a proc-
means of securing something. The ego here plays the ludicrous ess of dissin1ulation, a process that requires others to serve as witnesses.
role of the clown [des d11mmc1r August] in the circus, \vho, by his The position of the spectator, then, in this scenario is never si1nply
gestures, tries to convince the audience that every change in the given or neutral. The function of the spectator, in this passage at leas~,
circus ring happens as a result of his orders. But only the young- is to create and confirm a space of deception, and the content of this
est in the audience are taken in. 2 deception is nothing less than the constitutive aximn or thesis ofWest-
ern modernity: that of the autonomous, active subject qua I, ego, or
Both authors turn to theatrical figures to articulate a situation of self-consciousness. For Freud, this scenario, as espoused by Adler, is
conflict, and both focus upon the effects of this situation on a certain tantamount to confusing a circus with a tragedy, precisely what Mc-
"character." However, the way in which this character then is deter- Dougall then proceeds to do.
mined is significantly different in each. Although Joyce McDougall To be sure, her account of the theatrical situation becomes more
also mentions farce, the model of theater for her remains tragedy, and complicated as the passage proceeds. The cast of characters she assigns
the essence of tragedy is linked to a certain notion of the (Shakespear- to the Ego includes, not just the tragic hero, yet also an "actor" (in
ean) tragic hero: Hamlet, Lear, Richard IlL The dramatic conflict is quotes in the original: "un acteur"), but one who in addition to acting
couched in tenns that make it an attribute of the conflicted subject on the "world stage" is also present at-assiste d:-"a n1ore intimate
itself or, rather, himself. The tragic hero is described as a "man con- theater whose repertory is secret." To complicate matters further, the
fronted by the violent forces of his instinctual nature," who "invent[sJ Ego, which participates as hero, actor, and audience in a secret reper-
solutions to the inevitable conflicts provoked by his primitive desires" tory cmnpany and doesn't even know the company it keeps-is above
(my italics), and who has to "find compromises" that will satisfy hinl- all the company's "director": "le metteur en scene, c'est, bien sUr, le
self as well as others. It should be noted that, ~!though this account of Je lui-meme." This director-ego, who is separated from both charac-

252 253
1
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

ters and plot by a "veil," is obliged to stage the play vvith a cast he explaining his move beyond the pleasure principle, Aristotle points to
does not kno'\v and thus begins to rese1nble Freud's clown, the dummer the fact that repetition, even of manifestly unpleasant objects, can be
August, while the spectacle he is staging begins to look more and more a source of pleasure, and interprets this as evidence of the power and
like a circus than like a tragedy. significance of mimesis in human life. This power is related to the

I Nevertheless, for all of its complexity and subtlety, McDougall's


conception of theater is, as the title of her book indicates, informed
by the point of view of a je, or "I," that ultimately invests the diverse
pleasure afforded all human beings by the act of recognition, even where
the objects thereby recognized are repugnant or troubling in them-
selves:
and conflictual "theater" of the unconscious ';vith an underlying

I structural coherence and unity. One last citation from her book will
indicate how the diversity implied in the notion of theatricality is
There are things that we see with pain so far as they themselves
are concerned but whose images, even when executed in very
great detail, we vie\v with pleasure. Such is the case, for exam-
stn1cturally and methodologically subordinated to the unity of the ple, with renderings of the least favored anim.als, or of cadavers.

I ego:
In utilizing this n1etaphor of theater, I hope to shed light on two
The cause of this is that learning is eminently pleasurable not
only to philosophers but to the rest of mankind in the same way,
although their share in the pleasure is restricted, because the
aspects of psychic activity: the framework or place where the

I scene occurs, and the characters that play there. The first aspect reason they take pleasure in seeing the images is that in the
relates to the economy of the psyche, the second to its dvnamic process of viewing they find themselves learning, that is, reck-
significance. It is up to the "I" to compose with these el~ments, oning what kind a given thing belongs to: "This individual is a
to maintaiu mea11it1g and to channel the forces of cathexis. In so-and-so." Because if the viewers happen not to have seen such

I order to achieve this, he must have both invention and imagina-


tion. (p. 11)
a thing before, the reproduction will not produce the pleasure
qua reproduction but through its workmanship or color or
s01nething else of that sort. 3
Whereas the I thus emerges in McDougall's account as star of the

I sho\:v-its hero and director at once-Freud insists on comparing the


Ego to the slapstick clown in the circus, ridiculous but also theatrical
in its attempt to create the appearance of being in control. These two
"Learning," in short, consists in the process of recognition, which
in turn entails "reckoning what kind a given thing belongs to." Which
is to say, being able to put a "given thing" in its proper place by
conceptions of theater have a long history, going back to the earliest subsun1ing it under a familiar, generic category, attaching a predicate
I and nwst influential attempt to articulate a systematic approach to
theater, that of Aristotle in the Poetics. What \Ve have previously (in
to it and thus being able to say, "This individual is a so-and-so." This
explanation of mimesis as recognition through subsumption of the
Chapter 3) referred to as Aristotle's synoptic approach to cheater, privi- individual under the generic will tun1 out to be more important for

I leging tragedy and, within tragedy, the unifying function of the plot-
muthos-has generally been understood as his attempt to rehabilitate
mimesis, and in particular, theatrical m.itnesis, against the Platonic cri-
Aristotelian poetics and its approach to theater than the better-known
reference to catharsis, not merely because reference to catharsis occurs
only once in the Poetics, but also because even that single time makes
tique elaborated in the Republic and the Laws. Plato condetnns theater sense only if one is clear about just what is being "purged." As with

I as a particularly dangerous fon11 of mimesis, which encourages people


to confuse themselves with the parts they play and consequently to
Freud's later use of this term, what is being purged is an impurity, a
tension, a conflict of some sort. But of what sort? Aristotle's examples
forget their proper place in the organization of the polis. Against this in the passage just cited are, as examples almost always are, suggestive

I Platonic verdict, Aristotle defends mimesis and the pleasure it both


procures and exploits as a natural and inevitable learning process. In
a passage that recalls or, rather, anticipate~ Freud's argumentation in
and doubtless significant: "least favored animals and cadavers." These
examples cite borderline cases of living beings: the animals whose life
is n1ost degraded and the physical vestiges of a life that has departed.

I 254 255
!]If?''""!
,,,:_

PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY


PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY I

However, even such unpleasant examples become sources of pleasure locality divided into two interdependent but distinct parts: the space
when they furnish occasions for the recognition just discussed. Aris- of the stage and that of the audience.
totle speaks of mimesis as a learning experience, but the learning in- This tendency to subordinate the scenic-medial dimension of the-
volved in such recognition does not bring anything objectively new. ater to its narrative-representational function poses problems in distin-
Rather, it merely reconfirnJS the identity of the learner, who is able guishing theatrical mimesis from that of other media, for instance epic
to re-identify what he or she has already seen. Learning here is recon-
firmation, repetition of the same, recognition. In identifying the
poetry. This may be one of the reasons why Aristotle tries, as _it were,
to dispose of the question early so that he can get to the pomts that
I

other, even others from whom life has departed, it confirms the living interest him most, concerning above all the structure of the tragic
self-identity of the one \vho identifies. Such confirmation is pleasur- plot. We will come to that in a moment, but first let us take a closer
able, perhaps by suggesting the ability to reckon, not just with the look at the specific problems Aristotle encounters in his attempt to
"given thing" at hand, but more generally, with the future.


describe just what distinguishes theatrical representation-which he
These considerations inform Aristotle's approach to tragedy in the sees exemplified in tragedy--from its rival, epic poetry. In the latter,
Poetics. Tragedy, he asserts, involves above all the representation upon representation is the result of a narrative discourse, whet?er this ~s­
the stage of an action that is con1plete, unified, and therefore meaning- course is explicitly enunciated by a narrator who, as Anstotle stnk-
ful. Such meaningful representation of action Aristotle designates in ingly puts it, "stays the same [auton]," without changing (kai me
Greek as muthos, or plot. This is the heart and soul, the goal of tragedy metaballonta), or in1plicit in more directly min1etic forms of narrative,
and a fortiori of theater, since tragedy is, for Aristotle, its highest form. in which the narrated characters speak for themselves, as it were. Epic
However, this formulation of the essence of tragedy calls for further poetry consists normally of a mixture of these two modes, both of
elaboration. To designate tragedy as the representation of a unified which, however, are sharply distinguished fron1 the theatrical mode
and complete action in a plot poses a problem for Aristotle. Given the of representation, in which-I translate as literally as possible--"all
narrative structure of the plot, this conception of tragedy tends to those acting and actualizing in a work, produce the mimesis" (e pantas
subordinate tragedy to epic and, indeed, to make it a subspecies of the Jzos praitontas kai energountas taus mimoumenous, 48 a 23). If this transla-
epos. Aristotle, however, insists that tragedy is in its essence both dis- tion sounds odd, you can safely assume that the Greek isn't too much
tinct fron1 and at least as valuable as epic poetry, if not more so. Two clearer:• The French editors of the Poetics note that this "second part of
arguments support his position. First, there is vvhat I have called the the phrase has generally been considered as corrupted and p_racti~y
synoptic argument. Aristotle emphasizes that the didactic value of trag- impossible to translate. " 5 Is this textual difficulty a mere philological
edy is superior to that of the epic by virtue of its compactness and accident or could it be symptomatic of something more significant?
concentration. Tragedy, he insists, should be able to be "taken in at a The designation of those producing the mimetic representation on
single view," if not at a single sitting, in contrast to the epic, which is the stage suggests the latter. The tem1 used, prattontes, is the gerund of
more extended, tnore dispersed, and therefore less unified. Such a the verb prattein, "to act," a word that in its substantive fom1, praxis,
will inform Aristotle's entire attempt to account for theater as tragedy.
synoptic conception of tragedy goes hand in hand with a marginaliza-
As tragedy, he asserts, theater is above all the representation of a single,
tion, if not devaluation, of everything having to do vvith mere opsis,
complete, and meaningful action on the stage. The heart and soul of
that is, with the visual, spectacular nature of theater as a scenic me-
tragedy is not the stage but the action, the praxis thus represented.
dium, rather than with tragedy as its essential manifestation. The opti-
However, in order for that representation to be theatrical, it must be
cal dimension of tragedy, Aristotle argues, is secondary, instrumental,
not just told, but rather acted upon the stage. It therefore requires actors
and does not really pertain to its essence. This is tantamount to assert-
or, rendering Aristotle more literally, actants or actings. 6 The reason the
ing that the essence of tragedy is not theatrical, at least insofar as the- noun acting is so bizarre, particularly when used in the plural, is tha: it
ater remains inseparable from a certain disposition of space, from a suggests a multiplicity of elements that themselves seem more like
256
257
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

ongoing processes than stable entities. The notion of "actor" is still theatrical mode of mimesis tends to undercut. That, I believe, is pri-
m~rphologically indi~idual and hence identifiable with the subject of marily responsible for the incoherence so often noted in Aristotle's
a smgle, self-same act10n or set of actions. Indeed, prattontes can refer account of the prattontes. The unity, completion, and meaningfulness
as e~sily to the characters represented onstage as to the persons repre- of the tragic action, which, as Aristotle never tires of insisting, should
ll se~tm~, the actors. But actants or, even more, actings need not refer
pnmanl~ to. p~rsons or even to things. Persons are doubtless required,
be nude accessible to a single, uninterrupted sitting and viewing,
tends to dissolve in the face of the prattontes acting onstage. First of all,
but qua mdivtduals they need not be the principle of whatever unity as Roselyne Dupont-Roc and Jean Lallot stress in the commentary to
may be involved.
their French edition of the Poetics, the word is used in the plural.
This is a notion that is by no n1eans alien to Aristotle. What dis- They consider this to be the decisive element in the passage: "What
tances his conception of tragedy from that which has become familiar is essential is that, as a group, [the prattontes] divide the I among them-
to us over the past four hundred years is his refusal to place character at selves, assuming the discourse as a whole and putting it to work." The
11 t?e c~nte~ of trJgedy. His most emphatic, if not unequivocal, formula- French editors fommlate this conclusion slightly differently, and that
ti?nm this regard denies that character, ethos, is an indispensable con- difference underscores an in1portant point. They write not of"putting
stituent of tragedy. For, he asserts, "a tragedy cannot exist without a to work" but of a mise ((en acte." The Greek word used by Aristotle,
plot, .but i~ can \Vithout characters" (50 a 23-24). A bit further, he
li. explams th1s provocative assertion: "But a plot is not unified as some
people_ think, simply because it has to do with a single p~rson. A
energow1tas, can of course mean both. It is related to one of the key
"\Yards in his entire ontology, ene1;geia, which is usually translated
"actuality" but which, taken more literally, means the act of "being
~ar~e,_ mdeed an ind_efinite number of things can happen to a given at work," e1z ergon. Associated with the notion of work is the idea of
md1V1dual, some of which go to constitute no unified event· and in completion. But what sort of completed work occurs on the stage? It
the same way there can be many acts of a given individual frod1 which is not just the plurality of actors, of the cast, that is decisive, for that
no single action emerges" (51 a 16-20). This unfounded belief in the could still be fused into the unity of a work, a tragedy, insofar as it

I; unity of an individual's acts or life as a whole is related to a no less


credulou~ overvaluation of "historically given names" in the writing
of tra~edtes, as though such could ground the necessity of the drama.
represents a completed and unified action. Between this goal and the
prattotttes, however, a tension subsists. The latter are not just many;
they are double. It is difficult to tell if the "actings" apply to the
Anstotle thus marks an irreducible distance from the dominant ten- characters represented on the stage through their actions, or to the actors

I dency of "Western" theater in the modern period, a tendency that


Art_aud was to attack bitterly as psychologistic. Yet despite Aris~otle's
annpsychologistic emphasis on action as distinct from character his
representing them. Moreover, there is an essential incompletion associ-
ated with the gerund that Aristotle employs here: coming from the
present participle, its presmce is that of an indefinitely reiterated nwve-
conception of the unity of the representation of action in the t;acic ment bounded only by the quasi-simultaneity of its articulation. And
I muthos s.eems modele~ on the life span of the individual. The tra~c
plot, ~nst?tle emphasizes, should be unified and complete in having
the tnpamte structure of beginning, middle, and end. He associates
yet precisely this precarious presence and sitnultaneity appear to define
the distinctive space-time, the place of theatricality as such. Theatrical
representations cannot be franted by a complete, self-contained,

I this, not just \vith "action," praxis, but also with "life," bios.' Whose
life, however, if not that of the heroes represented? There can be onlv
one answer: the life, or afterlife, of the spectators, the audience fo~
meaningful nmmtive, as seems possible in epic poetry, since the actual-
ization of cheater involves a temporal repetition that is suspended in a
divided space. It is the simultaneity of this division, of actors acting
whom .t~agedy, as mimesis, is to be a learning experience that produces before and to an audience, which both distinguishes theatrical repre-

I recogmtwn and thereby brings the new under the a eo-is of the familiar
the singular under the cover of the generi~. t>

At the same time, it is this cognitive dimension of praxis that the


'
sentation from other kinds and makes it difficult for it to be enclosed
within the stable structure of a work.
This is perhaps ·why Aristotle is so deeply critical of everything

I 258
259
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

pertaining to the stage, to the theatrical medium as such, which he Without such a telos, all that might be left would be the ongoing
seeks to portray as the n1erely technical and empirical instrument of a iterations and gesticulations of the "actants" or "actings" on the stage.
more ideal form of representation, that of tragedy. This is why he There would then be smnething like pure repetition, not simply of
spends most of his energy attempting to describe the most effective the san1e, but of the eternally different, one shock following another,
structure of the tragic plot: the muthos through which praxis is repre- surprise piling up on surprise. Something else is dead~ require~, both
sented onstage. It is muthos that distinguishes tragedy fi:om mere the- to call a halt to this indefinite series of shocks and, m so domg, to
ater and endows it vv:ith the completeness of a work. What, then, is endov..- its repetitiveness with the significance of a genuine work.
characteristic of the tragic muthos? Here three elements emerge. This third quality Aristotle calls anagnorisis, usually translated as
First, there is the general trait that characterizes all tragic plots, ''recognition," signifying, however, not just the repetition or return
insofar as they hope to be theatrical. They all involve some sort of of cocrnition after the shock of the unexpected turn, but also the pas-
change, in Greek, a metabasis. We have already encountered this word, sage from a state of wonder and even ignorance to a. state of insight.
which Aristotle employs to distinguish the two fonns of narrative dis- The best tragic plots, Aristotle insists, are marked not JUSt by the pres-
course, one in which the narrator stays the same, without changing, ence of both of these features, pe1ipeteia and anagn.orisis, but even more
and the other in which he n1etamorphoses into his characters. Plato by their quasi-simultaneity: "The finest recognition is. one that ha~­
cited the latter use as evidence of the unreliability and corrupting pens at the same time as a peripeteia, as is the case w1t~1 the one .1n
effects of poetic mitnesis.:. For Aristotle, however, change as such is Oedipus." The mention of Oedipus, here and elsew?ere ~n the PoetiCS,
neither problematic nor interesting, or in any event, not interesting reminds us that, despite the length of this apparent digressiOn, we have
enough to define the essence of effective tragic plots. He is after some- not wandered very far from Freud and psychoanalysis, to which, in a
thing else, as his distinction of plots into two general types, "simple" n1oment, vve will return.
and "complex," suggests. Both types recount situations that change, But not before indicating that what infon11s Aristotle's discussion
but in different ways. In simple plots, the changes are predictable, of complex tragic plots is the way they challenge the conscious, pre-
create no surprise, and hence are not very interesting to an audience. conscious, and perhaps unconscious expectations of the audience. The
This shows us something about mimesis itself, which leads us to audience that attended perfonnances of Oedipus Tyrannos already
the second element of the tragic muthos. To the extent that Aristotle "knev,•" the story, at least in its outlines. They therefore could not
defends m.in1esis as a learning experience, the recognition to which have been very surprised by the shocks and surprises that ineluctably
the tragic muthos leads cannot be entirely predictable. Something un- drive Oedipus to acknowledge what Tiresias tells him, namely, that
"you are the slayer of the nun whose slayer you seek. " In this res~ect,
9
expected must intervene, something whose essential affmity to theater
informs the French expression that arose in the eighteenth century to Sophocles' audience was not unlike Dora, from who~1 Freud recerved
describe an unexpected turn of events, whether onstage or off, which one of his earliest lessons in the unconscious, espectally when, after
is to say, on other stages. This was, and is, the coup de thecltre, which repeatedly resistincr
0
one of his interpretations, she admitted that she
10
signifies a spectacular turn of events that need not take place in a had "known it all the time," just never "thought of it. " Oedipus
consecrated theater, since it is the "coup" that makes the theater. Aris- could have said the same, for he too "knew it all the time," he just
totle is perhaps the first to introduce this concept systematically, as never "thought of it" that way. Most of the facts of his ~ife. w~re
one of the traits that distinguish complex tragic plots. He calls it peripe- familiar to him, but precisely this familiarity concealed theu sigmft-
teia, and it involves the advent of the unexpected, interrupting inten- cance from him. The messenger who brings the news of the death of
tion and expectation and creating the kind of excitement that is King Polybus and then seeks to assuage Oed~pus' ~ears by revealin~
characteristic of effective theater. Such instances of peripeteia alone, that the king and queen of Corinth, who ra1sed hm1, were not lus
however, even if they are an essential part of effective theater, are not true parents, only conftrms them. What Oedipus is thereby c~~ed
in themselves sufficient to endow it with the status of a valuable work. upon to "recognize" is the complexly relational structure of cogmtiOn

261
260
I PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

I a~ such-something that the conqueror of the Sphinx is not in a posi-


tJ.on to understand at the outset of the play.I' Cognition is elusive
b~cause it is irreducibly relational, involving not something self-con-
objective action in this play, its plot nevertheless fulfills Aristotle's for-
mal requirements: peripeteia and anagnorisis. These are, of course, closer
to parapraxes than to praxis, since they are precisely not the result of

I tamed or substantial but rather, in Freudian terms, an overdetermined


12
network of relations (Lacan's "signifYing chain"). These relations are
intrinsically open-ended, but for the singular human being they are
conscious intention, will, or expectation. They generally consist in
statements that reinscribe events in ways that radically alter their in-
tended, anticipated significance. The possibility of such alteration
also_ f~te. This ten~ion, bet\veen a signification that is potentially leads to a double conclusion: first, that the significance of events, per-

I u~1hrmted and an eXIstence that is finite, informs the Theban trage-


dies-and perhaps tragedy itself "Pity and fear," anxiety and desire,
are its m.ost obv-ious affective consequences. This is why a notion such
sons, and things depends not just on their intrinsic qualities but on
their situation, which is to say, on their relation to what is external to
rhein; and, second, that such sintatedness can never be internally de-

I as ''catharsis'' can never be sufficient to circumscribe the effects of


trage~y. any more than it can circumscribe the workings of the un-
co~scious. _It als~ indicates why this notion should recur again and
fined, never finished in the sense of being completed, but only inter-
rupted.
What is interrupted is the expectation of a self-contained story-
agam. Oedipus himself uses the word to describe his initial strateQ'V in and a life-that would add up to a meaningful whole. Such a narrative

I dealing with the plague. The pollution, the miasma presumed ;;; be
the cause of the pes_tilence, can in his eyes be "purified" only by being
expelled from the City, as though the opposition of inside versus out-
stntcture is presupposed by Aristotle's demand for a unifying percep-
tion capable of synthesizing the diverse elements of the opsis into a
synopsis. This in turn depends on the ability of anagnC:il'isis to reassemble
side, self versus other, had any relevance to the problems ofThebes. what peripcteia has overturned. Only thus can tragic mimesis yield the
I It is this illusion that the fateful words ofTiresias dispel: "You are the
slayer of the n1an whose slayer you seek." This, ho"\vever, is the one
kind oflearning experience upon which Aristotle insists. Learning, for
Aristotle, at least in the Poetics, is the equivalent of knowing, in the
message Oedipus cannot accept. The problem is intra muros, not sense of predication: "This individual is a so-and-so." 13 There is,

I merely as a Trojan horse brought in from the outside, but because the
~n~erior is already the outside, just as the ostensible foreigner, Oedipus,
IS 111 fact native-born if not bred.
ho...,vever, a conception of learning that separates it radically from
predicative knowledge and it is precisely such a conception that we
encounter in the fmal Chorus of Oedipus Tyrannos:
What is at stake, then, in this exemplary tragedy has ultimately
I ~no re to ~o wi~ a realigm~en~ of topographical notions of place than
It does With actton. Indeed, 111 VIew of Aristotle's conception oftraCTedy
Sons and daughters of Thebes, behold: this was Oedipus,
Greatest of men; he held the key to the deepest mysteries;
Was envied by all his fellowmen for his great prosperity;
as the representation of action through plot, what is striking is tha~ the
Behold, what a full tide of m.isfortt.me swept over his head
I plot of Oedipus Tyrmmos, as of its sequel, Oedipus at Colonus, entails
v~rtually no action at all, nothing except a series of speeches, messages,
dialo~es-nothing, in short, but language. As for the action, what-
Then leant that mortal man must always look to [episkopounta]
the final day,
And call no one happy before he has crossed life's border [tenna
ever IS ~elevant occurs offitage-the murder ofLaius, the self-blinding

I of Oedipus. All that is shown onstage are the f!.ffects of these acts, never
the acts themselves.
tou biou] free from pain. H
Regarding this concluding formulation, Jebb notes that "the use of
Where, then, does this leave the synoptic understanding that trao-- episkopounta is peculiar" and concludes that "the exact sense" must be:

I
edy, according to Aristotle, is supposed to provide? And what is its ''fixing one's eye Oil the final day (as on a point towards which one is
relation to the opsis that, according to him, is to serve only as its means n1oving), that one should see it," 15 However, as Oedipus at Colonus will
and neutral medimn? make explicit, the temza tau biou is not something that can be "seen,"
In response, it is important to remember that, although there is no not directly at least. Whence, perhaps, the effort and tension implied

I 262 263


PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

in Sophocles' use here of episkopounta: the "fmal day" must be Nevertheless, the staging of a plot, however unified it may seem,
"watched out for," but its "crossing" will never be seen as such. is never as unified and integrated as Aristotle would like to believe.
Not, that is, by the one who "crosses" over. But perhaps by others. Theater never stages a plot directly precisely because it involves staging.
This may explain, in part, why one takes such pleasure in seeing the It can do without a narrator, but it cannot do without the stage and
spectacle of such a life staged. Whereas "mortal man must always look those who act upon it. The fact that theatrical acting is never the pure
to the fmal day," seeing cannot be equated to, or subordinated to representation of acts but rather the actualization of acting upon a
knowing. What one "learns" in beholding a tragedy such as Oedipus stage drives a wedge between "acting" and '"action" that remains "ac-
could therefore be that as a mortal being, one always sees without tive" even in contemporary English. This is even more powerfully at
knowing just what one is seeing. And therefore that the irreducible work in Aristotle's Greek when it describes, however ambiguously,
secret of whatever one sees is that it could n1ean something entirely how the "acting" of the prattolltes actualizes nothing so much as the
different from what one expects. This secret but ubiquitous possibility split constitutive of all mimesis. Neither actor nor role can function
is not only responsible for the theatrical peripeteia-it makes it indistin- without the other, but they do not necessarily add up to a whole.
guishable from the anagnOrisis that Aristotle sought to separate from it. That Aristotle is acutely aware of this danger is indicated by his persis-
The peripeteia is the anagnonSis. But that means that what is thereby tent attempt to subordinate everything having to do with the distinc-
recognized is the possibility of a "turn" whose singularity can never be tive medium of theater, and, a fortiori, of tragedy, to the "'goal" of
stabilized or exhausted in a predication, in a "this one is that," which presenting a unified action qua plot.
in turn suggests that anagnorisis always contains the possibility of turn- Thus, Aristotle's Poetics constitutes the ambivalent beginning of a
ing out itself to be a peripeteia. powerful tradition that seeks to subordinate the medium of theater to
This is why the "recognition" of this secret, which is inseparable a conception of drama as a poetic genre serving the representation of
from a life that is always incomplete, often proceeds by its dissinlula- action structured as a coherent and com.plete narrative. It is in chal-
tion. Thus, theater can create the semblance of a meaningful whole, lenging this powerful tradition that Freud's approach to the uncon-
especially when it displays a story that is ostensibly complete, with scious defines itsel£ This can be demonstrated in two ways: first, by
"beginning, middle, and end." It does not so much matter what the indicating briefly several instances in which Freud explicitly or, more
story portrays, nor if what it portrays involves suffering and death. On often, implicitly shows how a continuous, coherent narrative func-
the contrary, for those spectators who seen1 to be "taking it :in at a tions to conceal the far less coherent, far n1ore disruptive workings of
single, uninterrupted glance," the experience, according to Aristotle, the unconscious; second, by examining one instance in Freud's writ-
can be as pleasurable as the images of lowly animals and corpses. It is ing where theatricality and narrative interact to reveal a dimension
the pleasure of recognizing, in the lives of others, what we will never that he himself might have preferred to ignore, even if, in a certain
be able to see in our own. The pleasure produced by such recognition sense, like Dora "he knew it all the time."
is the pleasure of surviving. 16 This is why Aristotle placed so much First, then, to indicate how closely Freud's discovery of the uncon-
emphasis on the importance of plot, asserting that it constitutes noth- scious is associated with a move toward a theatrical conception of the
ing less than "the goal [telos, end] of tragedy, and the goal is the great- psyche that implicitly challenges the Aristotelian tradition we have
est thing of all" (50 a 23-24)-' 7 Plot alone allows the divergent been reviewing, we can begin with The Interpretation of Dreams. Lacan
elen1ents of a fragn1entary individual existence to be ordered in a man- was well advised to suggest that the third element of the dream
ner that suggests totality, wholeness, and thus meaningfulness-under work-in Gerrnan, Riicksicltt arif Darstellbarkeit, usually translated as
the condition that the plot as a whole be accessible to an uninterrupted "considerations of representability"-be translated into French as
perception. Precisely such accessibility constitutes for Aristotle the "\~gards sur la mise en scene [considerations of staging]." 18 Lacan's
privilege of tragedy with respect to epic, which is nwre extended, less sucrcrestion was incisive because this aspect of the dream work, like all
bb •
unified, and therefore les~ intrinsically meaningful. the others, is theatrical insofar as it is undertaken with the spectator n1

264 265
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

I mind. If the dream must be rendered in what seem to be easily accessi-


ble scenes, that is, first, because it is made to provide a certain spectacle
for a spectator and, second, because that spectacle must dissimulate
is to "revise" or "work over [bearbeiten]" the "rough spots" in the
dream, which would otherwise reveal, through illogic and incoher-
ence, its unconscious and confl.ictual origins. This is how Freud de-
what it really has to say or to show. This means that it n1ust ultimately scribes its function:

I conceal that it is concealing. The formula that best describes this situa-
tion is that the dream is not just a wish fulfillment, nor even a distorted
(entstellte) wish ful:fillment, but rather a distorted wish fulfilln1ent that
It fills up the gaps in the drean1 stniCture with shreds and
patches. & a result of its efforts, the dream .loses its appearance
of absurdity and disconnectedness and begins to approach the
dissitnulates its own distortions. 19 The fact that both of the German
I verbs Freud uses to describe this double duplicity are derived from
the same verb root, namely, stellen, "to place," only underscores the
ideal model [dem Vorbilde] of an intelligible experience. But such
an effort is not always crowned witl1 success. Dreams thus
emerge that to superficial observation may seem t~ be i~lpe~ca­
theatrical nature of the tnasquerade. If the initial function of the drean1
bly logical and reasonable; they start from ~ pos~tble sttuat:I?n,
I is to protect the sleep of the dreamer, as Freud frequently asserts, it
can only fulfill this function by disguising itself, then by disguising its
own disguise--which is to say, by presenting itself (to the memory of
develop it throucrh
0
a chain of consistent modiftcat:Ions, and bnng
it-although far less frequently-to a conclusion that is neither
troubling nor irritating [zu cifzem nicht bifremdcnden AbschlujJJ.
the dreamer) as being perfectly transparent. It is like a mirror on a
I door that suggests that the door behind it is open, while in fact what it
shows is only a reflection of what is in front of it.
These dreams are the ones that have been most profoundly
worked over by the psychical function that is most akin to wak-
ing thought: they appear to have a meaning, but that n1eaning
The dream, however, is not simply a distorting mirror presenting
is as far removed as possible from the re~l significance of the
I itself to the dreamer as though it were a transparent window. It also
addresses the consciousness of the nondreamer, who is (or will be)
awake. The latter may be-and in fact to some extent always is-the
dream. 20
This operation of "secondary revision" is, of course, well known.
"same" person, but this person, remembering and retelling the dream, What has been largely overlooked, to my knowledge at least, is that it

I. is nO\v in a very different position. She is now a participant through


memory and narration, even ·while experiencing herself as a mere
can accomplish its ends only by revising the dream in a veq partic~lar
way: namely, so that it appears to be a coherent and complete 11d~TallVC,
observer. The way the dream creates this impression will be familiar with beginning, middle, and end, as Aristotle wo~ld h.ave .s~ud. As

I after the discussion of Aristotle's Poetics: it creates the illusion of being


a more or less unified and coherent spectacle that can be observed and
taken in at a single viewing.
Freud writes: Such revisions "start out from a posstble SltuatlOn, de-
velop it through a chain of consistent modifications, and ... bring it
to a conclusion that is neither troubling nor irritating." Freud's term,
It does this through a variety of devices, none of which is more in Gennan, is stronger: the conclusion to the narrative in1posed by

I revealing than that designated by Freud as the fourth and last constit-
uent of the dream work, "last" not just because Freud discusses it at
the end of the chapter, but, more importantly, because it seems struc-
secondary revision is, he writes, in no way bifremdend: which is to s~y,
literally, "alienating, estranging." In short, the imposition of a narrat1ve
continuum upon the dream makes it familiar, and therefore acc~pt~ble

I
turally to presuppose the other three. Such an impression, however, to our waking consciousness. Such a continumn tends to assmlliate
may already be part of the self-dissimulation of the dream. Freud rein- the nicrht dream to a daydream, a fantasy. The difference between
forces this impression \\·hen he designates this component as a "sec- daydre~m and night drean1 has to do with the positioning of the pro-
ondary elaboration [seku~diirc Bearbeitung]" of the drean1. Since it is tagonist. The subject of the daydream or fantasy finds herself.con-

I called "secondary," it presun1ably presupposes a "primary" part of the


dream. Freud's discussion reveals that things are not so simple. What
seconda1y elaboration (or "revision," as it is translated in English) does
fronted vvith the kind of theater that Aristotle sought to valonze: a
spectacle that stages a coherent and complete story. The attr~ctiveness
of this fom1 of spectacle, however, is no\.v tied to the desire of the

I 266 267
I
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY
I
subject to avoid anything that might threaten the unity and stability to find the san1e struggle going on, not just in the materials described
of its position. Through the continuity of this narrative, the subject is
reassured that, despite "constant n1odifications," it stays the same over
tin1e. This is, of course, one aspect of the ego. The ego thus emerges
by Freud, but in the very theoretical discourse in which he is analyz-
ing those materials.
This is what we find at work when we move from The Interpretation
I
as stnlCturally dependent upon the kind of move we have seen at of Dreams to a somewhat later text of Freud's, "The Passing of the
work in Aristotle's Poetics, \Vhich could be designated as the narrativi-
zation qf the theatrical, or, to echo the Greek \vord, its mythologizing.
Oedipus Complex. " 23 This essay seeks to interpret the disappearance
of the Oedipus and castration complexes during the "latency" period.
I
•I
The latter term seems preferable, since it distinguishes between narra- Although Freud's account of the latter is well known, a reexamination
tive in general and the specific kind of self-contained narrative Aris- can be illuminating for the questions we have been discussing. On the
totle associates with the tenn·nwthos. Thus, what is at stake is not one hand, the castration complex involves an experience that Freud
narrative in general, but rather a notion of narrative in which "begin- describes as being essentially visual: the child discovers, with its own
ning, middle, and end" add up to a meaningful whole. t\vo eyes as it were, that significant adult women, such as a nurse or
It is precisely this semblance of wholeness that secondary revision mother, do not possess the male sexual organ, and this discovery has a
seeks to associate with the dream. Without it or, rather, since it is traumati~ effect. As Freud writes, "the observation that breaks the
never entirely absent, even when it has not fully succeeded, "we find disbelief of the child"-disbelief that the phallus is not universal-"is
ourselves helplessly face to face with a meaningless heap of fragmen-
tary material," as Strachey translates. Freud's Gern1an is less elegant
but more powerful: '\vie hilflos vor einem sinnlosen Haufen van
that of the female genital." According to hin1, then, a visual percep- ·
tion plays the decisive role in castration. And it does so insofar as it
involves a surprise, a sort of peripeteia, an unexpected turn of events.
I.
lnhaltsbrocken"-nwre literally, "faced with bits of content sense- All of this is familiar, perhaps over-familiar to anyone who has ever
lessly piled up. "2 1
In short, the model of intelligibility and meaningfulness specific
to \vak.ing, conscious thought is that of a coherent, consistent, self-
read much Freud. What is less so, however, is this: the initial reaction
of the child to its observation of the anatomical sexual difference is to
deny it fundamental and lasting value through a device already dis-
I
contained story, whereas the contrary model of unconscious articula-
tion is that of "bits of content sl!nselessly piled up" without any dis-
cernible fonn or purpose. In this context, another comparison made
cussed. The child tells itself, and whon1ever else will listen, a story,
precisely the kind of story we have encountered previously, with be-
ginning, middle, and end. It is a story designed to deny sexual differ-
I

by Freud seems quite significant. In tl1e dreams that appear to be ence by subordinating it to sexual san1.eness or identity. The story is
the most meaningful, "secondary revision has played about with the sin1ple and can be quickly paraphrased: Once upon a time, all adults
material the nwst freely and has retained the relations present in that possessed a penis. Now I discover that certain adults (my mother,

•I
material to the least extent. They are dreams that might be said to nurse) do not have one. And if! an1 not careful, the same thing could
have been already interpreted once, before being submitted to waking happen to 1ne. Beginning, middle, and (possibly catastrophic) end.
interpretation. " 22 In short, secondary revision, which operates The averting of this end becomes the burden of"castration anxiety."
through the imposition of a continuous, totalizing narrative, is not But the "complex" upon which such anxiety depends has the struc-
just a story-teller, it is also an editor and an interpreter, working in ture of the self-contained narrative already discussed.
ways akin to those we take when we are awake. In this sense it entails The "threat of castration," which is triggered by reiterated obser-
a theoretical activity as well as a narratif,e one or, rather, an activity in vations but ultimately depends upon a narrative construction, puts an
which narration and interpretation are just two sides of the same effort end to the "phallic genital organizati01l" of the child. The child now
to impose meaningful form on resistant, confiictualmaterial. Because finds itself in an impasse. If it follows the dictates of its desire and seeks
this tendency is shared both by the unconscious, in its self-dissimulat- "to take the place of the father" in what Freud calls an "active,"
ing function, and by theoretical thought,. we should not be surprised "n1ascu.line manner," it runs the risk of being punished, that is, cas-

268 269
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

trated, by the one it tries to displace. If, ho,vever, it seeks to take the daydream but the night dream. or the ~.oke, w~i~h, Freud insi.sts, is
place of the nwther, in a feminine m.anner, it must assume the burden "social" in its appeal to a "third person. Its sociality, h~w~ver, lS .also
of her "castration." "Castration," here, it should be noted, makes eminently theatrical, insofar as theater exemplifies a tnaclic re~at:lon-
sense only within a narrative framework that supposes an original, mti- . in which the "audience" plays an indispensable role. This role,
sh lp . . . li

I versal identity-"in the beginning '\vas the Phallus"-as the condition


of being able to interpret d!fference as a negative mode cif identity. Thus,
anatonllcal sexual difference, a relationship, is transformed into the
however, remains diverse and heterogeneous m 1ts p~tent:la ty.
Therefore, the move from a binary to a ternary structure mvolves a
far m.ore radical change than the mere addition of one more element
negative perception of a lack or absence, which presupposes that there to a structure might suggest. Rather, qua ternary the structure n_o

I must have been a peills, "once upon a time." "Castration" is thus not
simply a "cmnplex" but above all a story the child tells itself in order
to protect its narcissisn1 from engaging the challenge of a difference
loncrer is or~nized on the basis of an underlying identity. The audi-
enc~, it tu~s out, is no more--or less-identical with itself than the
"actors" are with their roles.
Another place in Freud's writings where the discov_ery of di~erence
I that cannot simply be equated with an object of perception.
In tllls context, the Untergm1s or "downfall" of the Oedipus com-
plex reveals its significance. Instead of maintaining its position as a
rithin the identical links psychoanalysis to cheater IS the penpheral
"region known as the uncanny (m · Gennan: d~ U~ h. elm l"h)"Th
tc e · .e
detached spectator, at a safe distance from the sights it observes, the essay bearing that title has remained largely margmal m psycho~alync
I child suddenly finds its position invaded, as it were, by the very forces
and dangers that it had sought to keep out. From tllls invasion results
the ambivalent instance that Freud will designate the superego. Its
literature, a fate for which it was carefully prepared by Freud himself
He broached this topic only with the greatest reluctance, and wh~n
he had finally finished his essay on it, it would play no further role In
his writings-no obvious, manifest role at least. The ~ssa.y thus ~es
I entry, as it were, into the psychic household of the child marks the
downfall of the Oedipus complex and the start of the latency period.
But at the same time it marks the emergence of a different paradigm
on the air of a final Abrechmmg, one that is also an exercise m exorcism.
Freud seems to have entertained a special relationship ~o the ur:-
of psychic topology, one that is n;:-\solutely spatial, involving a multi- ca1my. His essay is constructed almost entirely out ~f ston~s, and ~n
I plicity of relations between "instances" that cannot be reduced to a
unified whole, least of all to that of an ego. The ego now comes to
designate, not the subject as a \\:hole, but only a particularly ambiva-
the process of telling them, it recounts its own ~uto?wgraphical~pl~il­
ological story as well. The essay begins with a disclauner: Fr~ud Insists
that the topic involves an area of experience that has rema~ned very
lent part of it, a role it must play. This part or role can no longer be
I that of a detached observer, since the observation now goes on
"within" the space of an irrevocably riven psyche. The psyche has
"ren1ote [abseils liegendes, more literally, "peripheral]" for hi~. It has
been a long tin1e, he asserts, since he last "encountere~ anythmg that
impressed him as being uncanny," and there~ore a particular effort on
become a kind of "stage" or "arena," a divided site \V here conflicting
his part is required to enter into the feelings Involved (12:230). Ernest
I forces play themselves out. The ego has now become as much a lis-
tener as a viewer, as much a receiver of messages as a teller of tales,
and this involves, not just a shift from sight to sound, but, even more
]ones, on the other hand, recounts how Freud showed hims.elfto.be
profoundly fascinated by the uncanny, and how he delighte~ m tellin.,~
stories of patients for whom such experiences played~ le.ading role.-
significant, a fundamentally difrerent relationship to itself and to

I others.
The traditional interpretation of vision operates with binary oppo-
Prominent amoncr such experiences were those of predictiOns of death
that came true after many years. Perhaps this explains why Freud,
having begun work on this essay many years before, appear~ to have
sitions-inside and outside, here and there, subject and object-that
set it aside until he had reached the age of sixty-three. Unnl h~ had
I suppose a neutral and transparent space within which each element is
positioned as viewer and viewed, spectator and spectacle. The nevv
psychic topography is not binary but ternary: its nwdel is not the
attained that age, Freud had believed he might die at the age of SIXty-
two, the year of his father's death. The number sixty-two also crops

I 270
271
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY


up in his essay as an example of an uncanny coincidence, without any again, to disreputable figures of desire-figures that, however, share
mention of his own beliefS, of course. with actresses the quality of being heavily "made up," geschminkt, and
In short, there is good extratextual reason to suspect that Freud, who offer themselves to be seen, and quite possibly to more than just


despite his disclaimers, felt himself to be profoundly implicated in the being seen. The position of the observer is suddenly called into ques-
question of the uncanny. Of course, no one knew better than he how tion by the unexpected repetition: the observer ceases to be a casual
such contradictions can become the medium of unconscious articula- passerby and becomes himself a character, open to observation as a
tion. Turning now to the text itself, we find at least two explicitly possible participant, a potential protagonist. The story _has become a


autobiographical passages, whose implications go far beyond Freud's scenario in which the separation of spectator and actor IS undercut by
individual person. In a text that draws most of its material not fron1 a repetition that undermines all simple linearity.
the clinic but from fictional narratives, what is striking about these The second passage, which is not a story but simply a scene, is


t\:vo passages is that they function more in the mode of a scene than in relegated by Freud quite literally to the margins of his text, since he
that of a story. To be more precise, they begin by telling a story, which recounts it in a footnote devoted to the uncanny dimension of the
soon reveals itself to be more scenic than narrative. The first passage Doppelgiinger. Freud remembers:
occurs in the context of Freud's discussion of "the repetition of the
similar as a source of uncanny feelings" (12:249). Freud admits that I was sitting alone in the compartment of a sleeping car when,
not everyone will agree with this and, moreover, that it is not al~~ays following a sudden jolt of the train, the door to the adjoining
the case. This is a problem that haunts all of Freud's efforts in this essay toilette opened and an elderly gentlemen in a bathrobe, wearing
to analyze the uncanny by means of examples: the exemplarity of his a bonnet on his head, stepped into nly sleeper. Assuming that


examples will repeatedly be called into question. Hence, the recourse he had confused the two doors as he was leaving the toilette and
to personal, autobiographical experience. One of the most memorable had nllstakenly entered my compartment, I leapt up to explain
anecdotes that Freud recounts "reminds one of the helplessness of the situation, but inm1ediately had to recognize, to my chagrin,


certain dr;!am situations." Here is the story: that the invader [Ei11dringliHg] was n1y own image, reflected in
As, once on a hot surm11er afternoon, I strolled through the
the tnirror of the door to the toilet. I still remember that I found
unknown, empty streets of a small Italian city, I found myself in the appearance [of the figure] deeply displeasing. (12:262-63 n.)
an area about whose character I could not long be in doubt.


Here we find the Aristotelian mix of a peripeteia associated with an
The only people visible were heavily made-up women in the ahnost simultaneous recognition. The coup de theatre, however, resides
windows of the small houses, and I hastened to leave the narrow in the singular character of that recognition. It is not just that Freud
street at the next corner. But after I had wandered around for a takes his own mirror image for the appearance of someone else, but
while, '-Vithout a guide, I found myself suddenly again in the that, once having recognized his error, he continues to find the image
same street, in which I now began to excite some attention alien, troubling, "deeply displeasing." Like King Oedipus, he would

..
[Aufiehen zu erregen], and my hurried departure had as its only have preferred to have found another instead of himself, and when he
result that new detours led me back to the area for the third is forced to acknowledge the other as himself, his self has become
time. At that point, however, I was seized by a feeling that I irrevocably alien.
can only designate as uncanny, and I was glad when, having The uncanny, which in Gennan refers to the "hon1e" rather than
abandoned all thoughts of further exploration [Entdeckungs- to knowledge, as does the English canny, demonstrates how and why
reisen], I found myself back at the Piazza from which I had de-
the space of a certain familiarity is permeated by the alterity from
parted. (12:248)
which it seeks to set itself ofE This applies to the familial no less than
Freud starts off in the hope of making discOveries, but soon finds to the familiar. In the story that occupies much of Freud's attention in
himself caught in an infernal repetition that leads him back, again and this essay, Hoffmann's tale "The Sandman," the other intrudes in the

272 273
PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY PSYCHOANALYSIS AND THEATRICALITY

form of the enigmatic figure of Copp~lius, the unwanted but re!!lllar to give. It is that in the former tale we are not focused [eingestellt]
visitor in the house of a family he finally destroys. However, Fr;ud's upon the feelings of the Princess but rather on the superior cun-
own attempt to appropriate the uncanny for psychoanalysis is over- ning 9f the "master thief." The Princess may not have escaped
shadow~d by a predecessor, who may not have the uncanny stature of

I
the uncanny feeling, we are even ready to believe that she
Coppelius but \:vho seems to haunt Freud's essay no less than the fainted, but we ourselves feel nothing uncanny since we do not
str~ge lawyer ?aunts Hoffmann's story. Although Freud begins by put ourselves in her position but rather in that of the other.
notmg the pauc1ty of literature on the uncanny, he nevertheless ho1.s to (12:267)

I acknowledge at least one significant predecessor, in a certain EmSt


Jentsch, who in a previously published article interprets the uncanny
~ a form of "intellectual uncertainty." Freud rejects this theory as too
The uncanny thus emerges, not as a property of objects or works,
themes or motifs, but rather of their qfocts, which in turn depend upon
mtellectual, too tied to consciousness, and he seeks to replace it by a the manner in which they are positioned ·with respect to others and

I ~ore properly psychoanalytic reference to the return of the repressed,


m the form of castration an.xiety, displaced in Hoflinann's story from
the male sexual organ to the eyes. However, every ti1ne Freud seeks
ho'\v these others are positioned-in Gennan, Freud's word is einge-
stellt, literally, "placed, accorded, disposed." This sort of reciprocal
positioning, however, constitutes an eminently theatrical n1oment, in-
asmuch as a spectacle can be said to be emphatically theatrical to the
I to identifY a motif, a theme, as being an indispensable manifestation
of the uncanny, he winds up conceding that his hypothesis cannot be
satisfactorily demonstrated. The "return of the repressed," for in-
extent that it exceeds the narration and representation it contains by
presenting thetn to those others we call "audience," who in fact are
stance, in the fonn of ocular anxiety may be Ullcamzy, but is not 11 ecessar- as n1uch witnesses as mere spectators or listeners. To the extent that

I ily so, for there can be instances of anxieties and of "returns of the
repressed" that will not be associated with uncanny situatiot~s or feel-
ing. It is as if the uncanny evades every attempt by Freud to bind it
this reciprocal positioning involves the potential recognition of alter-
ity in the recurrence of the same, the uncanny comes into play. To
return to the instance cited by Freud: so long as the reader can identifY
with the "master thief," ...vho seems to be in control, there is no place
I to a general characteristic from which it cannot be separated. Freud
t~erefore s~ifi:s his focus or, rather, expands it to include not just indi-
vtdual m?tlfs o~ themes, but the context itl which they emerge and conse-
for the uncanny. This in a certain sense is what happened to Freud
himself after he had exorcised the uncanny by publishing his essay on
quently m whtch they have hitherto been concealed. He therebv it. Psychoanalysis was thus spared further experience of the uncanny,

I distinguishes two major types of context: the uncanny oflived experi~


ence (Erlebens) and that encountered in fictional texts. In the latter he
insists, w~ can best examine the various ways the uncanny is tied, 'not
although it is not certain that it has profited from this fact.
Freud's essay, however, suggests that there are other ways in which
the encounter with the uncanny can be pursued. One involves pre-
cisely the shift '\Ve have been discussing, which leads fron1 self-en-
I
to an ObJ.ect, but to the manner in which it is presented and, above
all, perceived by the reader. An example cited by Freud is the motif closed narrative to the exposure of theater. Theater, in this sense, need
of severed bodily members-a head, hands, feet. These can be experi- be identified neither with tragedy nor even with comedy but rather
enced as unc~nny, but need not always be so experienced. Only at the with farce: in German, Posse. In a last example I will cite from a text

I very end ofhxs essay does Freud venture an explanation of this curious
phenomenon. He does so by comparing two literary texts in which it
occurs:
studded with inconclusive and elusive examples, Freud alludes to a
well-known piece by the nineteenth-century Austrian playwright Jo-
hannes Nepomuk (Nestroy), entitled, hardly by coincidence, Der Zer-
rissene (The Tortt Person). Ln the passage quoted by Freud, the main
I We asked previously \vhy the severed hand in the "Rhampseni-
tus ,s T reasure " d oes not seem uncanny the way it does in
Hauff's "Story of the Severed Hand." ... The answer is easy
character of the play is on the run because he falsely believes that he
has murdered someone: "Suddenly he sees the supposed ghost of his
victim rising out of a trap-door \V hose cover he has just opened, and

I 274
275

li
PSYCHOANALYSIS
AND THEATRICALITY

calls out in despair 'I onl did a . .


multiplication?' w~ knowyth way ':t.th one; why thts atrocious 11
. e precondtttons of this scene do not
sh are t h e error of th 't , d '
. . . e orn one, an thus what is uncann for him .
trreststtb~y comical for us" (12:267). y ts
nThe Virtual Reality of Theater":
1 N~t~~n~ less than the tension between the uncanny and the ridicu-
ous e trmts the force field alluded to here which p h .
ought to be-one of the . ] d d . , er aps ts-or Antonin Artaud
fi Id pnvt ege omams of psychoanalysis. It is a
~:t btraversed by _tale~ of all sorts, but one that can never be mapped
eri y them. ~hteh _ts why it is situated off the beaten track, on the
p p~ery, absezts. Wtth respect to this strange field off to the side
trage y and farce turn out to be two sides of the same play. ,
I N A N A G E when the relation of violence to the media has
become a widespread concern, the words with which Antonin Artaud
introduced his notion of a "theater of cruelty" in the fateful year 1933
acquire a particular resonance:
The question is to know what we want. If we are prepared
for war, plagues, famine, and massacres, we don't even need to
say so, all we have to do is carry on. Carry on behaving like
snobs, rushing en masse to hear this or that singer, to see this or
that admirable show ... this or that exhibition in which impres-
sive forn1s burst forth here and there, but at random and without
any true conscience of the forces they could stir up ....
I am not one of those who believe that civilization has to
change in order for theater to change; but I do believe that
theater, utilized in the highest and most difficult sense possible,
has the power to influence the aspect and formation of
things ....
That is why I am proposing a theater of cruelty.... Not the
cruelty we can exercise upon each other by hacking at each
other's bodies, carving up our personal anatomies, or, like Assyr-
ian emperors, sending parcels of human ears, noses, or neatly
severed nostrils through the mail; but the much more terrible
and necessary cruelty which things can exercise against us. We
are not free. And the sky can still fall on our heads. And theater
has been created to teach us that, first of all. 1
Artaud's words seem both uncannily appropriate and utterly out-
moded. Utterly outmoded in the political and cultural importance he
attaches to theater. Uncannily appropriate in his vision of "war,
plagues, famine, and massacres" that are the result, not of any special
276
277

You might also like