The American Society For Aesthetics, Wiley The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 8

Wittgenstein's Theory of Picture Representation

Author(s): James D. Carney


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 40, No. 2 (Winter, 1981), pp.
179-185
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/430409
Accessed: 27-06-2016 06:50 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/430409?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 131.247.112.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 06:50:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
JAMES D. CARNEY

Wittgenstein's Theory of
Picture Representation

WHAT IS IT for one thing to be a picture of This view seems to imply that if P resembles
another thing? It seems that most paintings x more than anything else, then P represents
and pictures represent or depict things. For x. But as Nelson Goodman and others have
example, a Georgia O'Keeffe painting rep- pointed out, resemblance is a symmetrical
resents or depicts a cow's skull, or Cezanne's relation.5 That is, if P resembles x, then x
The Card Players represents or depicts three resembles P. So if P depicts x if P resembles
men playing cards. What must be true for x, then any tree, for example, represents
a picture P to represent or depict x? And any naturalistic picture of a tree. Also, noth-
of what importance for art criticism and art ing resembles a painting so much as a re-
appreciation is this question? In this paper production of it, but a reproduction of P
I will outline and defend the theory of pic- does not depict P. Perhaps P represents x
ture representation found in Ludwig Witt- if and only if the artist intends P to be
genstein's early work, Tractatus Logico- about x. But this view is also open to grave
Philosophicus.1 objections. An artist's intentions may mis-
As Nelson Goodman has remarked, "Noth- fire, so on this analysis P could depict x
ing is intrinsically representational; status even if nothing in the painting warrants us
as representational is relative to symbol sys- to suppose it depicts x. Also even if some-
tems."2 Attempts to answer the question one, for example, puts a dot on paper and
what it is for a picture to depict something intends this to be a picture of three men
that do not posit rules or conventions as playing cards, this is not sufficient for the
necessary for picture depiction seem open dot on the paper to depict three men play-
to grave objections. Max Black has reviewed ing cards. No theory of representation can
some of these attempts and has commented be fully convincing unless it accommodates
effectively on their weaknesses.3 For exam- or explains our intuition that not any pic-
ple, to suppose that P depicts x if and only ture can represent or depict anything. Any
if P imitates x or looks as if one is actually adequate theory of representation, it seems,
seeing x, Plato's view, is open to the objec- ought to accommodate our intuition that for
tion that most pictures that depict some- P to represent x some sort of resemblance
thing do not look like what they depict. between P and x is needed.
Monroe Beardsley proposes Ithat P repre- The recent promising attempts to analyze
sents x if and only if P contains an area representation, by Goodman and Kendall
that is more similar to the visual appearance Walton have made rules or conventions cen-
of x than to objects of any other class.4 tral to picture representation.6 Representa-
JAMES D. CARNEY is professor of philosophy at Ari- tion or depiction is seen as something we do
zona State University. with objects. So, independently of conven-

This content downloaded from 131.247.112.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 06:50:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
180 CARNEY

tions, nothing could represent anything. x without looking like x. For example, dia-
But these promising attempts have been gram 2
justly criticized as having the consequence
that any picture can represent anything.7
The reason for this is that both Goodman
and Walton reject resemblance between a
depicting picture and what it depicts as a
necessary condition for depicting. Walton
writes that his theory "does not itself postu-
late any resemblance between pictures and
what they depict."8 Goodman writes that
"the plain fact is that a picture, to represent
an object, must be a symbol for it, stand
for it, refer to it; and that no degree of
resemblance is sufficient to establish the req-
uisite relationship of reference ... Denota-
tion is the core of representation and is
independent of resemblance." 9
Neither Goodman nor Walton considers
the abstract or formal kind of resemblance Diagram 2.
that occurs when P has what Wittgenstein
calls the "logical form" of x (2.18).10 I be- does not look like a cat on a mat, yet it can
lieve that the best way to explain Wittgen- depict a cat on a mat. How? We can tak:
stein's theory of picture representation is by the square to stand for a mat, the circle to
making use of some simple diagrams.1' What stand for a cat, and the relation between
relation must exist between the diagram be- the circle and the square in the diagram to
low stand for x being physically on y.
We may be inclined to say that though
diagram 2 could depict a cat on a mat if
we suppose appropriate rules, diagram 1
just naturally depicts a cat on a mat without
our having to suppose any rules at all, since
it looks like a cat on a mat. This account
is also rejected by Wittgenstein. On his
analysis of picture depiction, rules are sup-
posed if a picture is to depict. Rules are
thus supposed with diagram 1 if it depicts,
but the rules we suppose with diagram 1
are simply better known and more easily
read from the picture. If we make explicit
these better known rules, what would they
look like? We take diagram 1 to depict how
a cat on a mat might look from such-and-
such a perspective, thus stands
for the mat (a rule), for the
Diagram 1. cat (a rule), and the relations in the diagram
stand for the relations we could see from a
and a cat being on a mat, for diagram 1 to certain perspective if we looked at a cat on
be a picture that depicts a cat on a mat?12 a mat (additional rules).
Wittgenstein rejects the answer that a pic- Let us consider another diagram consist-
ture must look like a cat on a mat. And ing of a dot with no other distinguishable
he should, since surely a picture can depict parts:

This content downloaded from 131.247.112.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 06:50:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Wittenstein's Theory 181

represented. (Wittgenstein calls these rules


"laws of projection" [4.0141].) Representa-
tion in pictures, on the theory of Wittgen-
stein, is, in part, a function of conventions,
and is, in part, a function of what is found,
so to speak, in nature. That is, natural ob-
jects and artifacts provide Wittgenstein's
. theoretically required multiplicity in P for
P to represent x. Wittgenstein uses the ex-
pression "logical form" in the statement of
his theory. "What any picture, of whatever
form, must have in common with reality,
to be able to depict it . . . is logical form."
(2.18) "Logical pictures can depict the
world." (2.19) Simply put: P can represent
Diagram 3. or depict x if and only if P has the same
logical form as x. A P does represent or
Let us not count the space enclosed around depict x when we choose a set of rules which
the dot as a part of the picture. For Witt- correlate the elements and relations of x
genstein diagram 3 cannot represent or de- with elements and relations of P. It is mis-
pict a cat on a mat, for, according to his leading and inaccurate to state Wittgen-
theory, we need at least two distinguishable stein's theory of representation simply in
parts and a relation between the parts in these terms: P represents or depicts x if and
order to establish the appropriate rules. Ac- only if P has the same logical form as x.
cording to Wittgenstein, diagram 3 lacks For a picture can depict any reality whose
the needed "logical multiplicity" to repre- form it has (2.172). Thus diagram one can
sent or depict a cat on a mat. Even if dia- depict a cat on a mat or a pink elephant
gram 3 cannot represent a cat on a mat, on a cloud or a cloud on a pink elephant,
a part of a picture may in fact be a dot depending on how we choose to set up the
which represents a cat on a mat, but only rules. Nelson Goodman in his review of
in the context of the whole picture. For E. H. Gombrich's Art and Illusion suggests
example, a picture can include a series of that with suitable principles of correlation,
pictorial representations of cats reclining on "Constable's landscape painting could pro-
mats and becoming smaller and eventually vide an enormous amount of information
fading off into the far distance, appearing about a pink elephant." 14 On Wittgenstein's
as a dot at the end of the series. In such a theory, if we suppose such rules, Constable's
context, a dot can represent a cat on a mat.13 landscape would represent a pink elephant.
However, such a part of a pictorial structure It is worth noting that on Wittgenstein's
can acquire representational status only from theory, representation is not a symmetrical
the context provided by the entire composi- relation. For the chosen rules typically cor-
tion. On any theory of picture representa- relate elements of P to elements of x and
tion, including Wittgenstein's, the theory is not vice versa.

about whole picture depiction. Categories of art, in a Wittgenstein analy-


The theory of pictorial representation sis of representation, would be construed as
which emerges from these examples may be different sets of rules or conventions. Imag-
simply stated as follows: A picture repre- ine a cat on a mat as it would be depicted
sents or depicts a subject when and only in a Fifth-dynasty Egyptian style, or as it
when the parts of the picture have the same would be depicted in an analytical Cubist
logical multiplicity as the parts in the sub- painting. The Egyptian painting would be
ject represented, and appropriate rules are strongly linear, where the artistic image is
assumed relating picture parts and relations an assembly of the most obvious parts of
to the parts and relations of the subject cats and mats. Here the elements in the

This content downloaded from 131.247.112.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 06:50:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
182 CARNEY

picture are taken to stand for objects and one as imitative and thus take the relations
relations as known rather than as they ap- in diagram one to stand for relations we see
pear. In the Cubist painting the three di- when we view a cat on a mat from a certain
mensional cat and mat is reduced to two di- perspective. It is natural to think that there
mensional shapes, where a cat on a mat is are no rules since we have never thought
shown from more than one viewpoint at of any rules in our recognizing what is de-
one time and where aspects, especially angu- picted in imitative pictures. They have been
lary aspects of cats and mats, are empha- internalized as part of cultural condition-
sized. It is easy to see the rules involved if ing. But following a rule need not be an
we construe the Cubist style within the explicit, conscious act. A regularity in ac-
Wittgenstein theory. tion can be convention-following behavior
Representation is creative, rather than without the convention needing to be con-
imitative, on Wittgenstein's theory of rep- sciously thought, if certain conditions are
resentation. The artist must either suppose fulfilled. David Lewis has outlined such con-
some system of conventions or modify or ditions in his Convention.15 Briefly and
create new conventions. In turn the viewer roughly, a regularity in behavior, R, is a
needs to understand the historical conven- convention for members of a population,
tions to grasp what is depicted in a picture. P, if the behavior of members of P con-
Many who first see a Cubist portrait do not forms to R, if members of P expect others
realize that the squarish shapes no more to conform to R, and if members of P prefer
to conform to R.
represent angularity of facial structure than
do the thin sculptured figures of Giacometti Second objection: The Wittgensteinian
represent very thin and very long bodies. analysis of picture depiction is circular or
Understanding rules in representation is like incomplete since it supposes an unanalyzed
learning a new language. And often when "stand for" relation with respect to rules
one learns new rules the viewer may notice connecting elements and relations between
aspects and features of subjects that he may a depicting picture and the thing depicted.
never have noticed before. By employing The analysis is not circulzr since the "stand
new rules for representation the artist can for" relation is not same logical form but
alter our perception of the world, can get rather a denotational relation, the kind of
us to notice certain features that we may relation that exists, for example, between
have overlooked. In short, many by now the word "cat" and cats. And this relation
commonplace insights about art find sup- seems unproblematical in the context of art
port in Wittgenstein's theory. theory.
Even though Wittgenstein's analysis of Third objection: An adequate theory of
picture-depicting may have certain attrac- picturing should not exclude representing
tions, is it not also open to grave objections? an object with a nonrelational or monadic
It does have its difficulties, but, I believe, property, for example, blackness. As the
none of them are fatal. I will now briefly theory is characterized above, properties rep-
consider some objections to the theory. Ob- resented by a picture must be relations
jection one: It is implausible to say that among the parts of x. This seems to rule
we follow rules or conventions with respect out representing monadic relations such as
to pictures like diagram one where the pic- x is black, and surely no such theory of
ture looks like what it depicts. Perhaps rules picture representation is adequate. Wilfrid
are supposed in Cubism and Egyptian art, Sellars has proposed that the picture theory
but not in imitative art. The reply that can of propositions can accommodate such rep-
be given to this objection is that look-alike resentation (and thus the Tractatus need not
pictures are as conventional as any other be committed to bare particulars).16 Apply-
sort of picture. It is merely that the con- ing this to pictures, we need to suppose pro-
ventions governing such pictures are better jection rules which correlate a monadic
known and more easily read than with property of a part of the picture with a
Egyptian or Cubist art. As part of our West- monadic property of x. This can be done,
ern cultural inculcation, we take diagram for example, by correlating the black of a

This content downloaded from 131.247.112.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 06:50:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Wittenstein's Theory 183

square with the black of the cat, or a style supposed (the art category) when the pic-
of painting the square with the black of the ture is produced. If in order to properly
cat-say thick, dark lines. And a simple and appreciate a depicting picture one must
obvious restatement of the explication of know what it depicts, then to properly ap-
"representation" on page 181 would accom- preciate a depicting picture, one must un-
modate such monadic representation. derstand the category of art in which the
Fourth objection: For a depicting picture picture was produced. These last remarks
and what it depicts, is having the same should not be taken to suggest that one is
logical form or same anything really needed? somehow cut off from appreciating a work
After all, we can have cases of P depicting of art unless one knows its correct historical
x but misdepicting or misrepresenting x. art category. Art criticism can be equally
For example, a portrait of Washington creative as art production in that the art
which depicts him may represent a stylized critic can implicitly or explicitly suppose
Caesar with hardly any resemblance at all new rules in interpreting the art, and in
to Washington. A portrait of Washington this way construe P as depicting something
need not have a likeness-that is, it may that it does not depict, supposing historical
attribute any number of qualities to Wash- rules. In this way there can be more in a
ington which Washington did not have. But, work of art than the artist might have imag-
again, can anything be a picture of Wash- ined.

ington? If human intentions were sufficient Sixth objection: The Tractatus account of
for a picture to depict its subject, then any- picturing is intended to show how language
thing can represent the subject. But, as ar- works. The picture theory of the Tractatus
gued earlier, this view of representation is covers pictures and representations of all
open to grave objections. It seems that some sorts. But will it do to talk about representa-
minimal sameness or resemblance is needed tion in art in the same terms as technical
for a picture to depict Washington, and the drawings, diagrams, language, and all these
same logical form provides the absolute other things? E. H. Gombrich in Art and
minimal sameness. In addition, this mini- Illusion proposed that P represents or de-
mal sameness is sufficiently flexible so that picts x when P is a kind of illusion for x
almost anything can represent anything so where no error in belief occurs. That is, for
long as it meets the logical multiplicity re- Gombrich P depicts x where one can see
quirement. P as x. When Gombrich uses the term "illu-
Fifth objection: A depicting picture may sion" he is referring to the "seeing-as" phe-
have the same logical multiplicity as the nomenon. Illusion is, of course, the typical
subject depicted, and yet it is usually the kind of depiction that occurs in objective
case that both the picture and the subject art. Wittgenstein in the Philosophical In-
depicted have further discernible parts. For vestigations suggests that seeing-as typically
example, diagram one represents a cat on involves both seeing and thinking. In a key
a mat, yet cats have claws while the picture- passage he writes: "What I perceive in the
cat has no claws. Also, we can discern that drawing of an aspect is not a property of
the picture-cat is located a certain distance the object, but an internal relation between
from the diagram frame, yet this is not true it and other objects." 17 When things appear
of the subject of diagram one. So how does as if they have to be connected, this shows
one determine which parts and relations of that we are bringing them under a rule, and
the picture are components of logical form we have an internal relation. So rules are
-and which parts of the subject depicted seen as necessary for certain kinds of visual
are parts of logical form? The answer is experience. If rules are to be brought in
that the viewer needs to single out whatever for Gombrich type illusions, then the kind
feature or features the depictor desires. An of representation connected with ordinary
audience learns what features of a picture objective art is subsumed under the kind of
and depicted subject are relevant by know- representation found in diagrams, language,
ing the rules assumed by the artist. We and many other nonart t)pe representation.
thus need to come to understand the rules Final objection: How is Wittgenstein's

This content downloaded from 131.247.112.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 06:50:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
184 CARNEY

analysis of picture depicting important for expression and representation could be lo-
art criticism? The important consequences cated in terms of what is represented.
for art criticism that follow from Wittgen- Though Goodman writes that no degree
stein's analysis are the same that follow of resemblance is necessary for a picture to
from any rule analysis of picture depicting represent or depict x, he also adds that "al-
such as Nelson Goodman's and Kendall most anything" can represent anything.
Walton's. For example, one cannot dismiss Why, for Goodman, cannot anything rep-
unfamiliar pictures as not depicting any- resent anything? According to Goodman,
thing. The unfamiliar picture may be a de- the distinguishing mark of pictures, as con-
picting picture, but the conventions may trasted with symbol systems in language, is
not be widely known or not easily read from "density."20 A scheme, according to Good-
the picture. Since an important element in man, is dense if "it provides for infinitely
the proper appreciation of a depicting pic- many characters so ordered that between
ture is to understand what is depicted, one each two there is a third."21 On this ac-
may be cut off from proper appreciation of count if a depicting scheme is dense, as pic-
unfamiliar pictures unless one can come to tures are for Goodman, differences in pic-
understand the supposed conventions (its torial aspects make a difference with respect
art category). Consider abstract expression- to what is depicted. For example, the dif-
ism, for example, Jackson Pollack's Number ferences in size, color, and spatial relations
12. For many of us, this painting does not make no difference in symbols used in lan-
seem to be a depicting painting. Yet Pollack guage-only same spelling matters-but such
reports that when he poured the paints for differences can be relevant in representation.
such a painting he allowed his hands to To have a dense symbol system, one needs
wander freely across the surface of his can- rules connecting a dense set of elements
vas, permitting himself to be directed by with denotata; though the rules may not
inner impulses. His method of painting was result in an actual denotata for the sym-
his way to express his basic emotions in the bols.22 We need now merely add that some
most vivid and direct way that he could. elements in a dense set are relations in order
If our basic emotions have a logical multi- for it not to be the case that anything can
plicity, then one could interpret Number 12 represent anything, and, interestingly in
as an attempt at depicting emotions on order to obtain "same logical form" and
Wittgenstein's analysis of picture represen- thus a minimal resemblance between pic-
tation. For Susanne K. Langer a work of tures and what they depict.
art is an expressive form where what is ex- Walton construes picture depicting in
pressed is human feelings. A work of art terms of make-believe games. As children
expresses a feeling, for Langer, when it is make-believe that a stone in a pile of mud
an iconic symbol for a feeling. Her account is a pie with a raisin in it, so when a picture
of expressive form is, or should be, Witt- is regarded as depicting x we in a make-
genstein's account of logical form.'8 Wheth- believe way see x when we look at the pic-
er it is intelligible to think of emotions as ture. But in either case such make-believe
having the requisite logical multiplicity is presupposes rules or conventions. It is nec-
a question I will not go into in this paper. essary for the children to let the stone stand
Some recent work in psychology suggests for a raisin and the mud to stand for a pie.
that it may be plausible to regard emotions So for different categories of art there would
as having the needed logical multiplicity.19 be supposed different sets of rules in order
Even so, one is left with the puzzling pros- to make the make-believe seeing possible.
pect that there is a method of rule projec- Walton writes that "P-depicting does not
tion that could "decode" a Jackson Pollack's require P-resemblance but that some rules
of make-believe are more natural, simpler,
painting. In any case Wittgenstein's theory
of picture representation first opens up the and easier to learn, remember, and inter-
intriguing possibility that nonobjective art nalize, and more likely to be adopted (ex-
can be, after all, representational art. Sec- plicitly or otherwise) than others" if P re-
ond, on his theory the difference between sembles x.23 So, to use his examples, the

This content downloaded from 131.247.112.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 06:50:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Wittenstein's Theory 185

rule that the pie contains a raisin if the 9 Languages, op. cit., p. 5.
10Wittgenstein's account of picture depicting is
glob of mud contains a pebble is just more found in 2.12-2.19 of the Tractatus. Important clar-
natural than the rule that the pie contains ifying remarks and examples are found in his 1929
a raisin if the glob does not contain a paper, "Some Remarks on Logical Form," Aristote-
pebble or the rule that the pie contains a lean Society Supplementary, vol. 9, Knowledge, Ex-
raisin if the glob of mud is light-colored. perience, and Realism (London, 1929), pp. 162-71.
No doubt in the latter two cases there is an 11 Jay F. Rosenberg in an excellent article on
Wittgenstein's picture theory of language makes use
absence of visual P-resemblance. Bult, nev- of such diagrams to explain the theory, "Wittgen-
ertheless, the mud has the needed logical stein's Theory of Language," American Philosoph-
multiplicity and with appropriate rules has ical Quarterly, vol. 5, no. 1 (January, 1968), 18-30.
12Wittgenstein's theory of picture representation,
the same logical form as what it depicts- like the theories mentioned earlier, are attempts to
a pie with a raisin. In the latter case there give an account of what obtains when a picture rep-
is the mud glob and color, while in the resents or depicts something. But, as almost all
former case there is the glob and there is writers on this subject have pointed out, saying what
a pebble-free glob. Nothing Walton writes a picture depicts or represents is highly ambiguous.
Sometimes we state what kind of picture P is. Some-
provides a reason to think that P-resem- times we state that P denotes something. There are
blance in the formal, abstract sense of same pictures of centaurs, but there are no actual cen-
logical form need not be present for his taurs to picture. Many pictures of cats are such that
P-depicting. And each of his examples can there are no cats which they picture. For example,
Andre Masson's The Cat is not a picture of any
be construed as having P-resemblance of the
actual cat, but it is correctly described as a picture
Wittgenstein kind. of a cat. When one says that P is a picture of x, we
In recent literature, conventional or rule sometimes suppose that there is an actual x, and
theories of how a depicting picture depicts sometimes we do not. If a picture is a picture of
have received a great deal of attention. Such some actual existing x, we can say it denotes x. If a
picture is a picture of a cat in the sense in which
theories have interesting consequences for its being a picture of a cat does not depend on there
art criticism and appreciation. However, a being an actual cat which it pictures, we can say P
difficulty found in these theories is that they is a cat-depicting picture. Theories of representa-
appear to have the consequence that any tion, including Wittgenstein's theory, are primarily
picture can depict or represent anything. concerned with representation in the sense of pic-
ture kind, x-depicting pictures, for, presumably, the
Wittgenstein's analysis of picture depicting analysis of P denoting x presupposes that P is an
in the Tractatus is an analysis where rules x-depicting picture. That is, to say that P denotes x
or conventions play a key role that avoids would be at least to say that P is an x-depicting
this consequence. On this analysis of picture picture and x actually exists.
'1 This example appears in Robert Howell's "Or-
representation, same logical form, a mini-
dinary Pictures, Mental Representations, and Log-
mal, abstract kind of nonimitative resem-
ical Forms," Synthese, 33 (1976), 149-74.
blance, is required between a depicting pic- 14 Nelson Goodman, "Review of Gombrich's Art
ture and what it depicts in order for the and Illusion," The Journal of Philosophy (Septem-
ber, 1960), 598.
picture to depict or represent.
'1 David Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study
(Harvard University Press, 1969), p. 42.
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philo- 6 Wilfrid Sellars, "Naming and Saying," Philos-
ophy of Science, vol. 29, no. 1 (1962), 7-26.
sophicus (London, 1961).
2Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art (Indianap- 7 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investiga-
tions (New York, 1958), p. 212.
olis, 1968), p. 226.
3 Max Black, "How Do Pictures Represent," E. H. 1 Susanne K. Langer, Problems of Art (London,
1957).
Gombrich, Julian Hochberg, and Max Black, Art,
Perception, and Reality (The Johns Hopkins Uni- 1 Michael M. Piechowski, "The Logical and the
versity Press, 1970), pp. 95-129.
Empirical Form of Feelings," The Journal of Aes-
thetic Education (January, 1981).
4 Monroe Beardsley, Aesthetics (New York, 1958),
p. 270. 2o Languages, op. cit., pp. 225-28.
21 Ibid., p. 136.
Languages, op. cit., p. 4.
8 Kendall Walton, "Pictures and Make-Believe," Ibid., p. 228.
23 "Pictures," op. cit., p. 318.
Philosophical Review, vol. 32, no. 3 (1973), 283-319.
7 W. E. Kennick makes this criticism in Art and
I wish to thank this journal's referee for some
Philosophy, 2nd ed. (New York, 1979), pp. 379-80. valuable corrections and for raising several objec-
8 Ibid., p. 226.
tions that I try to meet in this paper.

This content downloaded from 131.247.112.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 06:50:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like