Carrier Expertise - Epistemic and Social Standards - 2018

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

Topoi (2018) 37:55–66

https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9407-y

Scientific Expertise: Epistemic and Social Standards—The


Example of the German Radiation Protection Commission
Martin Carrier1 • Wolfgang Krohn1

Published online: 13 July 2016


 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Abstract In their self-understanding, expert committees from an extra-scientific point of view. Thus, the term is
solely draw on scientific knowledge to provide policy understood in a rather narrow way and is intended to define
advice. However, we try to show, first, on the basis of attempts to deal with problems that arise within a practical
material related to the German Radiation Protection context on the basis of scientific knowledge. Speaking
Commission that much of their work consists in active generally, we distinguish between three types of experts:
model building. Second, expert advice is judged by criteria technical, professional, and scientific. Technical experts
that diverge from standards used for judging epistemic apply a fixed canon of rules to cases that are rather similar
research. In particular, the commitment to generality or in kind. Consider the food control routines performed by
universality is replaced by the criterion of specificity, and health authorities or the regular examination of motorcars.
the value of precision gives way to epistemic robustness. Technical experts operate by the books and don’t need to
Third, non-epistemic considerations are included in the employ a lot of discretion. Professional expertise is asso-
reasoning—albeit hesitantly. Manageability and social ciated with the work of physicians, lawyers, managers etc.,
robustness, understood as compatibility with widespread in which dealing with particular cases is at the focus of
value attitudes in society, affect the content of the attention and in which rules and general knowledge are of
recommendations. little help for handling them appropriately. Instead, pro-
fessional experts proceed on the basis of exemplars, para-
Keywords Scientific expertise  Epistemic and non- digms (in the pre-Kuhnian sense) or precedents (Krohn
epistemic standards for expert advice  Science and 2008, 2010). Scientific expertise is based on scientific
society  Radiation protection commission knowledge and responds to demands from society—in
particular, politics, economy, and the general public—on
how to deal with concrete, typically unprecedented prob-
1 Scientific Expertise in Society lems. Frequently, such advice is elaborated by expert
committees. Such committees contribute to devising, say,
We use the term ‘‘scientific expertise’’ in a terminological national energy supply systems or advise governments
sense to designate science-based assessments of and rec- about economic policies. Scientific expertise is deeply
ommendations for problems that are considered important influential on the lives of many Western citizens.
We want to elucidate characteristic features of scientific
expertise. Our example is the German Radiation Protection
& Martin Carrier Commission, the Strahlenschutzkommission (SSK), which
martin.carrier@uni-bielefeld.de is appointed by the German government and is supposed to
Wolfgang Krohn give advice regarding risks arising from the exposure to
wolfgang.krohn@uni-bielefeld.de ionizing and non-ionizing radiation. The commission
1 consists of scientists from the relevant disciplines (such as
Department of Philosophy, Institute for Interdisciplinary
Studies of Science (I2SoS), Bielefeld University, medicine, physics, and engineering). They are expected to
P.O.B. 100 131, 33501 Bielefeld, Germany give their ‘‘independent’’ expert opinion on the hazards of

123
56 M. Carrier, W. Krohn

radiation and thus to promote the ‘‘protection’’ of the We wish to defend three claims in this paper. First,
population. The statute of the commission commits it to expert judgment is often produced by building de-idealized
giving advice on the demand of the government and and complex models. In many cases, experts are unable to
requires its members to pursue a ‘‘scientific discourse’’ derive their recommendations from the existing scientific
(SSK 2012). Thus, the statute explicitly distinguishes sci- knowledge; they rather have to create new knowledge. This
entific knowledge as the relevant basis of judgment. On the production of expert knowledge is governed by specific
international level, the SSK cooperates with the ‘‘Interna- epistemic and non-epistemic criteria of judgment that are
tional Commission on Radiological Protection’’ (ICRP), different from those appealed to in scientific research
which seeks to evaluate and standardize radiation protec- proper. Satisfying such requirements makes the models
tion. The SSK was founded in 1973 in the time of a heated relevant for addressing complex practical problems. Epis-
public debate about the use of nuclear energy. However, temic standards or values are used to assess the merits of
the spectrum of relevant items soon included radiation assumptions as contributions to scientific knowledge.
protection issues at the workplace, in medical contexts, or Empirical adequacy is a core value of this sort, but others
in daily life. Such problems concern, for instance, the appreciated in the scientific community are explanatory
radiation risks involved in mammograms, cell phones or power (a few premises cover a broad domain of facts
tanning devices. We have conducted a 4-year study of the precisely) or causal understanding. The latter standards are
SSK in the framework of a DFG-sponsored research pro- non-empirical in that they refer to the way in which facts
ject. The study is intended to reconstruct epistemic and are accommodated, and they are epistemic in the sense that
non-epistemic commitments of the SSK work and to sug- they express supposed virtues of knowledge in general
gest characteristics that apply to other forms of expertise as (Carrier 2013). In contrast, non-epistemic values are rela-
well. Our research is based on the recommendations issued ted to the practical or social usefulness of knowledge.
by the SSK (now available on the SSK website http://www. Pragmatic virtues, such as manageability, or social con-
ssk.de/DE/Publikationen/VeroeffentlichungenderSSK/ver siderations, such as political realizability, belong in this
oeffssk_node.html), the anonymized minutes of the SSK non-epistemic realm. In this framework, our second claim
meetings supplied to us by the German Federal Ministry of is that the assessment of expert advice is governed by a
the Environment,1 interviews with former presidents and distinct set of epistemic values. Third, non-epistemic con-
members of the committee, and the scientific basis of the siderations are included in the reasoning as well and serve
SSK judgments (i.e., published articles) as made explicit in to improve the odds of acceptance in the sociopolitical
the recommendations or the recorded debates. This material realm.
provides first-hand access to the reasoning of the committee Our analysis suggests that the commission pursues three
and allows us to trace how scientific expertise is produced. major ambitions. First, they seek to be recognized by their
Although our material is confined to the SSK, we take some peers as a scientifically competent body. Their credibility
of these features to be generalizable to other examples of vis-à-vis their fellow scientists rests on their scientific
expert advice (see Sect. 6).2 reputation. This is why the committee is anxious to keep its
distance from politics and emphasizes the mentioned
‘‘scientific’’ character of its advice [as stipulated by its by-
1
This is our quotation scheme for the minutes: ‘‘P’’ signals an SSK laws (SSK 2012)]. Second, the SSK is eager to appear
protocol, followed by the year of the pertinent meeting and its number
trustworthy to the public. The committee addresses issues
(counted consecutively from the first meeting onward). Finally, the
item of the agenda is given (‘‘TOP’’); if a TOP number is missing, of public concern and strives to demonstrate its dedication
only a single topic was treated in the pertinent meeting. According to to the common good. Third, the SSK endeavors to appear
the statute article 14, Sect. 4 of the Strahlenschutzkommission, the relevant to politics. The committee wishes to exert some
meetings of the commission and the crisis management team are
influence on politics, which creates an inclination toward
confidential. According to article 14, Sect. 4, subsection 2 of the
statute, the attendants of a meeting may not give information to third including socio-political considerations, albeit reluctantly,
parties about statements of individual members, voting results and the in order to enhance their clout. They want to see their
contents of the minutes. The Federal Ministry for the Environment, advice being heeded even if social interests and lobby
Nature Conservation, Building and Nuclear Safety has granted
groups pull politics in a different direction. In sum, we see
Bielefeld University within the framework of the DFG-research
project ‘‘Science based policy advice. Epistemic-institutional charac- the self-image of the SSK characterized by the three goals
teristics of expert commissions using the example of the radiation of scientific reputation, public trustworthiness, and political
protection commission’’ the right to use the unpublished minutes of
the SSK to a certain degree and under the conditions of article 39
GGO. We gratefully acknowledge the permission to use this material
for research purposes. Footnote 2 continued
2
We want to thank our research assistant Hannah Dickmann who the SSK and by screening, structuring, and ordering the protocols and
helped us tremendously by wading through the material supplied by the recommendations.

123
Scientific Expertise: Epistemic and Social Standards—The Example of the German Radiation… 57

relevance. We attempt to show in what follows that these features judged to be of lesser importance. Idealized
goals do not always fit together smoothly. models are false, strictly speaking, but they nevertheless
We first address characteristics of model-building as bring out the central features of the phenomenon in ques-
accomplished by the SSK. An important objective of such tion and thus advance understanding (Weisberg 2013,
endeavors is to capture the complexity of the relevant sit- 98–106). However, expertise is often compelled to take the
uation. In Sect. 3, we spell out epistemic values that can be full complexity of the phenomena into account. What
used for assessing the quality of expert recommendations. matters is not a qualitative understanding of the general
In particular, the commitment to generality or universality, conditions but the evaluation of a peculiar, complex
as expressed, for instance, in the commitment to explana- situation.
tory power, is replaced by the criterion of specificity (or the For instance, the risk associated with ionizing radiation
ambition to capture the particulars of individual cases), and is typically assessed on the basis of the dose absorbed by a
the value of precision gives way to what we call epistemic particular organ, the organ dose, weighted by factors that
robustness. The relevant epistemic values do not always express the ‘‘relative biological effectiveness’’ of the
point in the same direction, and their application some- radiation in question, for one, and the susceptibility of the
times requires a trade-off between competing demands. In relevant tissue, for another. However, following a request
Sect. 4, we discuss non-epistemic standards underlying the from the German Federal Ministry of the Environment and
committee’s reasoning. Manageability (or ease of imple- suggestions from the literature (Behrens et al. 2009), the
mentation) and social robustness, used by us in the sense of SSK needed to address the suspicion that the hazard of b-
compatibility with widespread value attitudes in society, radiation (i.e., electron radiation) hitting the eye had been
affect the content of the recommendations. The values we grossly underestimated. Since most of this radiation is
attempt to identify are categories of analysis and apparently absorbed in the front part of the eye lens, the customary
not consciously invoked by the SSK. Section 5 deals with procedure of averaging the effect across the whole eye (the
the communication strategies of the SSK which can be organ dose) is faulty. The incoming energy is deposited in
reconstructed as reflecting a growing concern for social a narrow stretch, rather than spread across the eye. This
robustness. problem is highly relevant for the medical staff involved in
administering certain kinds of therapy and for aircraft
crews. On the new approach to modeling the energy
2 Expert Advice Produced by Active Model absorption in the eye, the risk of contracting an eye cataract
Building comes out considerably higher. The point is that in order to
assess the detrimental impact of such conditions, the SSK
Expert committees in general are supposed to elaborate the had to transcend the usual accounts. The commission
state of scientific knowledge for addressing a given prac- needed to de-idealize the received models and supply
tical problem. As to the SSK, such problems are mostly additional details. The scientific models proceeded on the
raised by politics (or the German Federal Ministry of the basis of mono-energetic electrons and did not take the
Environment at that). However, right from its start in 1973, complex geometry of the human head into account (where
the commission was authorized to identify matters of ambient bones shield off radiation coming from above, for
concern on its own, and did so increasingly after ca. 2000 instance). As a result, gauging the energy deposited in the
(see Sect. 5). The problems posed are framed with regard relevant parts of the eye required constructing new models;
to social relevance; they derive from outside of science. such models could not just be imported from science (SSK
For this reason, answers are typically not found within the 2010) (see Sect. 3 for additional aspects of this case).
body of accepted knowledge. Rather, the general truths of Similarly, the diagnostic use of positron–electron
science need to be developed such that they are able to tomography (PET) posed new radiological challenges since
deliver on these concrete practical demands. We want to the procedure was mostly employed in combination with
sketch in this section what this means precisely. computer tomography (CT). PET works by detecting c-
Scientific expertise is required to come up with specific rays originating from positron–electron pair annihilation in
or tailor-made recommendations that address the particu- the body (and produced by administering a suitable radio
lars of the problem at hand. Scientific knowledge addresses nuclide), while CT operates by sending X-rays through the
general conditions, whereas expert advice is typically human body. Both methods provide complementary phys-
directed at particular situations. Along these lines, it is a iological information and are best used in combination for
recurrent challenge of the SSK to face the complexity of this reason. However, this combined application exposes
individual cases appropriately. Scientific model-building the patients to the joint effect of c-rays and X-rays, which
often benefits from focusing on idealized conditions that are similar in nature but exhibit different energies. No
highlight the explanatorily relevant factors and strip away model was available for assessing the combined impact of

123
58 M. Carrier, W. Krohn

both types of radiation. The SSK felt obliged in 2005 to rather forced them to adjust such models or to construct
commission research specifically on this problem them afresh. This finding supports the conclusion that expert
(P_05_204 TOP 9). committees do not simply bring scientific knowledge to bear
Another challenge to the SSK is to harmonize conflict- on practical problems, but often need to elaborate and
ing scientific accounts. For instance, the damage done to expand such knowledge in order to cope with the complex
human tissue by ionizing radiation can be estimated on the challenges at hand. Such specificity is an important epis-
basis of three different approaches. One approach is epi- temic aspiration of the committee work which requires
demiological and proceeds from the observed effects building de-idealized and complex models.
among the victims of the atomic bomb explosions of Hir-
oshima and Nagasaki and the Chernobyl nuclear accident.
A second approach is based on experiments with single 3 Epistemic Evaluation Standards for Expert
cells subjected to controlled radiation. The third one is Recommendation
likewise experimental and considers animals exposed to
known doses of radiation. The predicament was that these We wish to elaborate in this section how model-building
three approaches suggested different estimates of the car- proceeds that is prompted by politics but intended to
cinogenic effect produced by long-term low-dose radiation. comply with the demands of scientific theorizing. The
Neither of these approaches is clearly superior to the oth- reconstruction of model-building practices of the SSK in
ers. The epidemiological approach concerned short-term the preceding section suggests that such endeavors are
high-dose exposure, which is different from the conditions governed by the objective of coping with complexity.
under scrutiny, but dealt with human tissue, which agrees Constructing models that are adequate to the complex
with the problem at hand. The two experimental settings challenges in question is an epistemic value that charac-
had the advantage of administering controlled doses of terizes the work of the committee. This value is in harmony
radiation and of being able to approach the long-term low- with the self-understanding of the SSK to the effect that its
dose scenario in question. However, they either concerned judgment relies on scientific standards alone. In a debate on
isolated human cells, thus leaving out possible effects of the potential hazards associated with the long-term use of
the interaction among cells, or they addressed animal cells. cell phones in 2001, the committee was anxious to
In particular, DNA repair mechanisms were supposed to demarcate its work from the domain of politics. In their
differ among various types of cells and different doses and eyes, it was their duty to examine whether there are sci-
to vary between tissue and single cells. Consequently, the entific reasons to suspect such a detrimental influence, as
differences between the three approaches really seemed to being judged by known causal processes or epidemiologi-
matter, with the result that the relative credentials were cal studies. By contrast, individual cases fail to provide
unclear. What the committee did eventually was ‘‘inter- sound evidence and cannot justify any reduction of the
polating’’ the incoherent outcomes. The conflicting maximum permissible radiation intensity (see Sect. 5). Any
accounts were stitched together.3 such reduction would have to be based on the precaution-
These examples show that although the SSK does not ary principle which, however, is said to belong in the realm
seek to establish new knowledge, it is sometimes compelled of politics. It is politics, not science that needs to decide
to further develop the state of research. Facing complexity which level of protection is desirable. In the view of the
often requires de-idealizing existing models so as to make SSK, their mandate is confined to questions that can be
them rich enough for tackling the question at hand. De- addressed on a purely scientific basis (P_01_172 TOP 7).
idealization involves adding context-specific features and In a similar vein, the SSK commits itself to scientific, or
details that are characteristic of the particular case in ques- epistemic, standards such as objectivity, causality, and
tion (Weisberg 2013, 99–100). A second strategy for reproducibility. Again, reports about individual cases do
arriving at a practically useful account is to consider models not provide legitimate reasons for recommending anything.
dealing with particular aspects of a problem and models Such reports cannot serve as a basis of judgment but only
emerging from particular experiential contexts as frag- reveal the need for further research (SSK 2001, 6–7, 16, see
mentary descriptions that need to be combined in order to Sect. 5). Along the same line, the SSK argued in the con-
produce appropriate judgments. In both cases, facing the text of assessing more accurately the detrimental impact of
intricacy of the real world prevented the SSK from simply low energy b-radiation on the eye lens (to be considered in
importing models from the existing knowledge base and greater detail below) that ‘‘protection’’ is not a scientific
category and that, consequently, placing limit values is not
3 a scientific but a political task. The SSK claimed that its
P_77_14; P_83_49B; SSK (1984), 7; Interview conducted with
Günther Dietze, a former SSK chairman on June 16, 2010; see also own role in this business is confined to establishing the
Carrier (2010), 202–203. pertinent factual basis, while drawing value-laden

123
Scientific Expertise: Epistemic and Social Standards—The Example of the German Radiation… 59

conclusions and setting limit values is to be left to the Epistemic robustness opens up an avenue for dealing
responsible political body, that is, the Ministry (P_09_233). with uncertainty. Since scientific expertise is often forced
This conception is in line with Roger Pielke’s view of the to face particularly intricate issues, it might be suspected
scientific expert as an ‘‘honest broker.’’ In this view, it is that expert advice suffers from serious epistemic short-
the task of the scientific expert to clarify and broaden the comings. The expectation is that the models constructed
range of options for action. No values ought to be adopted are superficial and provide only insecure estimates. How-
by the expert; rather, alternative value choices should be ever, this potential deficiency need not hurt the usefulness
presented to politics, along with their consequences and of an analysis or recommendation. More often than not,
side-effects. Politicians, not scientists, make choices. Sci- dealing successfully with practical challenges does not
ence is no legitimate source of values (Pielke 2007, 1–7; require accounting for the details. Addressing the minute
Pielke 2015, 60–64; see also Lackey 2007). particulars is often immaterial for deciding about how to
However, other instances demonstrate that the SSK is respond to a practical challenge. The situation needs to be
unable to maintain this line. On one occasion, the com- clarified only to an extent that allows experts to develop a
mittee appeals to the precautionary principle without much clear and unambiguous recommendation. The gist of such a
ado in the context of assessing carcinogenic risks associ- recommendation is often independent of the particulars.
ated with ionizing radiation. The principle is said to sug- Accordingly, epistemic robustness is an important objec-
gest to better overestimate than underestimate risks (SSK tive for scientific expertise. We explained that the model-
1984, 7). This is in line with explanations to the effect that building activities of the commission are aimed at de-ide-
while the precautionary principle is political and should be alization and, correspondingly, driven by the ambition to
left out of consideration, prudence regarding threshold cope with the complexity of the pertinent situation. How-
values can legitimately be recommended by the SSK. Such ever, epistemic robustness is a competing value that serves
latter deliberations are said to be the result of acknowl- to limit the degree of intricacy the models need to exhibit.
edging uncertainty and thus to be part of scientific rea- The implicit commitment of the SSK to epistemic
soning proper (P_01_172 TOP 7). robustness can be identified in various arguments. We want
These preliminary considerations show that the self- to discuss two such patterns, namely, generously placed
declared exclusive commitment to scientific knowledge as threshold values and pragmatic protection devices. In both
the basis of judgment is not upheld. In fact, analyzing the cases, the intention is to decouple the gist of the recom-
practice of passing judgments within the SSK suggests that mendation from the uncertainty of the knowledge base.
epistemic and non-epistemic values play an important role. First, a pattern frequently found in recommending
We address epistemic values in this section, and non- threshold values for various exposure scenarios encom-
epistemic values in the subsequent section. passes two steps. The first is to establish a degree of
An important epistemic value the SSK tacitly appeals to is exposure for which a relevant effect can be measured.
epistemic robustness. We claim that epistemic robustness is a Second, 10 % or at times 1 % of this intensity is recom-
quality standard that is specific to scientific expertise and is mended as a threshold value (Trott 1983, 181; P_83_49B).
not part of the assessment procedures of fundamental The underlying reasoning is that in case some unknown
research. ‘‘Robustness’’ is meant to express that the main effect occurs or some additional factor is influential, this
thrust of an analysis or recommendation remains unchanged rectification should be inconsequential. Accordingly, epis-
if the relevant influences vary to some degree. ‘‘Epistemic temic robustness sometimes overrides the criterion of
robustness’’ designates the invariance of the outcome even if precision that characterizes parts of epistemic research. It is
the pertinent causal factors and factual conditions fluctuate not possible to evaluate the relevant impact precisely, and
or are unknown; ‘‘social robustness’’ expresses the same for this reason the recommendation is adjusted such that it
invariance with respect to a range of interests and value need not be precise in the first place.4 In other words,
commitments (see Sect. 4). Robustness in general outlines epistemic robustness is the means expert committees use
the scope of acceptability in the face of ignorance of the for dealing with the threat of unknowns, either known
precise circumstances and in being confronted with a unknowns or unknown unknowns.
diversity of non-epistemic commitments. Epistemic robust-
ness delineates the kind of reliability that is relevant for
expertise and designates the leeway of feasibility; social 4
However, there are limits to sidelining the commitment to
robustness refers to the room left for the societal compati- precision. Epistemically robust judgments remain unchanged within
bility of a recommendation and respects or at least lays open a corridor of uncertainty or fluctuation of the underlying causal
factors. If the values of these factors approach the boundaries of this
the constraints involved in its social or political implemen-
corridor, precision becomes important again. If changes among the
tation (Weingart et al. 2007, 299–304; Carrier 2010, 204; underlying influences would have an impact on the ways of dealing
Droste-Franke et al. 2015, 13, 38–39). with the relevant situation, epistemic robustness is of no help.

123
60 M. Carrier, W. Krohn

Second, an even more striking example is the handling This approach to the new and worrisome data was
of the mentioned increased susceptibility of the eye to unmistakably guided by the commitment to epistemic
long-term low-intensity b-ray exposure that is relevant for robustness. As the SSK argued, de-idealization is possible
specific occupations such as radiological staff or aircrews. only to a limited degree and the precise evaluation of the
We mentioned this case before as an example of active relevant quantities is very difficult to achieve (SSK 2010,
model-building and an attempt of de-idealization: identi- 6–17). Fortunately enough, optimization does not demand
fying and measuring the relevant quantities demands the precise knowledge of these quantities. Using simple pro-
construction of particular models that have no counterpart tection devices is sufficient for diminishing the hazard. In
in the realm of physics in general (see Sect. 2). Yet, the other words, in dealing with this hazard, the epistemic
case reveals further aspects of expert reasoning. The SSK uncertainty can be ignored. We need not know in detail
was alerted in 2009 by epidemiological studies that what damage would occur without taking precautionary
revealed an elevated incidence of cataract among persons measures. The only fact that counts is that by applying
whose exposure had probably remained below the existing certain protective procedures, the relevant dose will remain
minimum threshold. Follow-up studies had shown that b- well below the threshold (P_09_239 TOP 7; SSK 2010, 5).
rays deposit their energy in a more localized way in the eye The SSK argumentation is striking by its dispropor-
lens, thus causing more damage than anticipated. Accord- tionality between the revolutionary tone used for charac-
ingly, one might have expected that the SSK would suggest terizing the change in the scientific description and the
a reduction of this threshold value. This expectation is small-scale practical adjustments recommended. As to the
strengthened by the additional finding that the lifetime former, the SSK speaks of a ‘‘paradigm shift’’ in assessing
dose, rather than the annual dose, is the quantity relevant to the risks of radiation-induced cataract (SSK 2009, 5) and
gauging the detriment produced by b-rays (P_09_233 TOP argues for a profound revision of the received mode of
7). Actually, in 2012, i.e., 2 years later, the ICRP indeed understanding and evaluating such damage
recommended a significant reduction of the allowed annual (P_09_234_TOP 7). By contrast, when it comes to concrete
eye-lens dose for persons occupationally exposed to radi- action, more restricted provisions such as wearing glasses
ation (ICRP 2012). are called for. Nothing practical follows from de-idealiza-
But this is not what the SSK did upon discussing the tion and extensive modeling endeavors. They are vital for
new situation in 2009 and 2010. They placed emphasis on understanding the situation, but this changed understanding
optimization rather than reduction. Optimization is one of does not fully translate into new recommendations. The
three principles issued by the ICRP (in addition to justifi- latter are rather inspired by considerations of epistemic
cation and limitation) and adopted by the SSK in 1984. robustness. In fact, epistemic robustness means for the case
Optimization means, in the interpretation of the SSK, to in question that for practical purposes the critical magni-
strive for a level of protection in which the sum of tudes need not be evaluated precisely. They only need to
expenditure and damage attains a minimum (SSK 1984, 9). remain within a safety corridor. This is much easier to
This principle suggests for the case at hand adjusting the accomplish than realizing accurate values. Seeking epis-
particular circumstances rather than the general legal temically robust advice is intended to separate the gist of
threshold. The underlying argument runs as follows. First, expert recommendations from the intricacy of the practical
it is not easy to measure the pertinent quantities. The new challenge at hand.
findings suggest that electrons give off their energy within On the whole, scientific expertise is often required to
a layer of 3 mm in the eye lens. There is no established address complex circumstances so that the level of uncer-
procedure for measuring this dose. Legal metrology in tainty experts face is elevated as compared to epistemic
many countries only acknowledges the surface dose research. This is where the need arises to de-idealize sci-
deposited in the outer 0.07 mm and the depth dose at entific models. However, this uncertainty need not hurt the
10 mm (P_09_234 TOP 7; SSK 2009, 4–5). The SSK usefulness of a recommendation. Epistemic robustness may
recommended to adhere to the surface dose and thus to the serve to decouple epistemic uncertainty from the leeway
established protocol. The reason given is that this quantity left to action. The latter can be addressed without actually
will overestimate the energy deposited in the eye lens. In satisfying the epistemic demands and without developing
this framework, the surface dose is used for averaging the de-idealized models. In the case at hand, epistemic
radiation impact in the outer 3 mm rim, and since robustness disconnects the major reorientation in scientific
absorption abates in the deeper eye regions, this means outlook from the small-scale pragmatic solution recom-
overrating the relevant dose. In addition, the SSK advo- mended in response. On the whole, then, the goal of doing
cated protective measures such as wearing glasses made of justice to real-world complexity is sometimes abrogated or
suitable material and keeping one’s distance from the made superfluous by confining oneself to the objective of
radiation source (SSK 2010, 12–13). epistemic robustness.

123
Scientific Expertise: Epistemic and Social Standards—The Example of the German Radiation… 61

We emphasize in this section the importance of epis- The SSK shrank back from launching such a large-scale
temic robustness for useful scientific policy advice. But endeavor. Recording the surface dose relies on an estab-
another, contrasting virtue is relevant for such advice as lished procedure and the resulting value will overestimate,
well, namely, opportuneness. Robustness aspires to be safe and not underestimate, the newly identified risk (SSK 2010,
against bad surprises. Opportuneness means that we are 5, 12–13).
able to take advantage of technological opportunities that This line of argument testifies again the SSK’s appeal to
open up unexpectedly. Expert advice should also enable epistemic robustness by following the recipe to proceed in
politicians to benefit from pleasant surprises. Opportune- such a way that the unknown details do not matter
ness as a guiding principle can be identified in various regarding action. Yet, it also reveals the influence of the
expert judgments (Ben-Haim 2006, 3–4, 37–39; Droste- two non-epistemic virtues of manageability and social
Franke et al. 2015, 9–12), and is apparent in the reasoning robustness. Manageability means that a recommendation
of the SSK as well. should be easy to handle in practice. Its results should be
In the early 2000s, positron–electron tomography (PET) consistent and reproducible, and the efforts required should
emerged as a new diagnostic tool that promised to be be in proportion to the probable effect. This consideration
effective and efficient. Against this background, the SSK comes out clearly in the proposal to adhere to the received
took the initiative to criticize the existing regulations for dosimetry because any change would demand a large-scale
releasing PET devices to the market. The SSK actively endeavor in building new instruments and in introducing
advocated the use of such instruments as enhancing diag- changed protocols at an international level. As a result,
nostic quality and reducing radiation exposure (as com- manageability, just like epistemic robustness, is a value
pared to alternative diagnostic tools). On the whole, the that may stand in tension with the value of constructing
SSK actively nudged the medical system to be more wel- models that are up to the complexity of the situation.
coming to this innovative procedure (P_02_182 TOP 13; Another domain governed by the virtue of manage-
P_03_184 TOP 12; P_06_213 TOP 8; P_07_214 TOP 6). ability is the problem of the admissible collective dose, i.e.,
Such a recommendation testifies the concern of the SSK the long-term radiation exposure of the general public that
not to pass up an important technical opportunity. can be considered safe. This amounts to the issue whether a
cut-off dose can be identified below which ionizing radi-
ation can be trusted to be harmless. Following Trott (1983),
4 Non-Epistemic Values Expected from Expert the SSK adopted the position that such a threshold value
Recommendations cannot be established on scientific grounds. First, this is a
consequence of the particulate nature of radiation, with the
Epistemic robustness delineates the kind of reliability that result that even under low-dose conditions a particle or
is relevant for expertise; it designates the room left by photon may hit a cell and stimulate the onset of cancer.
scientific knowledge to concrete actions. Non-epistemic Scientific understanding of the mechanism of how radia-
considerations respond to practical constraints. Giving tion-induced damage is produced militates against the
heed to such constraints does not enhance the scientific existence of a minimum threshold.
quality of expert advice, but increases the odds of getting it Second, the idea appealed to is the relation of the radi-
implemented. The room left for resolving an issue from an ation in question to the natural background radiation. If
epistemic angle can also be filled by taking political con- radiation exposure remains within the variability of this
straints, social interests, and value commitments into con- natural background, no detrimental effects are to be
sideration. We wish to discuss two non-epistemic expected. The SSK is quite explicit in acknowledging that
considerations that turn out to guide expert recommenda- this is a purely pragmatic principle. The reason is that
tions, namely, manageability and social robustness. epidemiological studies are incapable of ascertaining that
The value of manageability is highlighted by the eye- such changes and variations really have no adverse impact.
lens example. As we explained, the new scientific findings Any such risk would be masked by all sorts of additional
had suggested an unfamiliar measuring procedure for influences and would be too weak to leave statistically
establishing the risk of contracting radiation-induced cat- identifiable marks. Thus, it is a purely pragmatic maxim
aract. This risk is adequately estimated by the amount of that all differences in radiation exposure that are compa-
energy deposited within the outer 3 mm layer of the eye rable to natural fluctuations are not supposed to produce
lens. However, rather than adopting a new protocol, the any hazard. Otherwise, one would have to assume that
SSK adheres to the established surface dose that measures moving to a different region or to a differently constructed
the energy within a 0.07 mm layer (see Sect. 3). The rea- house is a risky matter in terms of radiation exposure and
son given is that switching to a new protocol is an intricate this would violate common sense (Trott 1983; P_77_14;
process and would demand international harmonization. P_77_15; P_83_49B; SSK 1984).

123
62 M. Carrier, W. Krohn

Manageability obviously takes a major role in these more quickly toward lower doses, the case of primary
considerations. Given the lack of a secure knowledge base, interest, so that low-dose long-term radiation would come
it would be unjustified to have people leave certain regions out less detrimental as compared to a linear relationship. The
or abandon their houses. The SSK eventually settled on the assumption was that cellular repair mechanisms exist which
notion of ‘‘insignificant level of risk,’’ which means that the are able to cope with low-dose radiation. On the whole, the
hazard associated with an increased level of radiation is commission was faced with conflicting results whose rela-
negligible relative to other risks of civilization. This notion tive credentials were unclear. What the SSK did in stitching
is justified by appeal to the so-called ALARA-principle, together these incoherent accounts was placing emphasis on
issued by the ICRP in 1977, which says that the risk should being on the safe side. That is, they adopted a basically
be ‘‘as low as reasonably achievable.’’ This principle is said linear relationship and thus intentionally assumed an ele-
to include social and economic considerations (P_77_15; vated hazard of low-dose long-term exposure. They
P_83_49B). In its meeting (P_83_49B), but not in its approved a relationship they thought themselves to be
published recommendation (SSK 1984), the SSK explicitly inaccurate. The SSK explicitly opted for rather overesti-
acknowledged that the alignment of threshold values of mating than underestimating the risks involved (P_83_49B;
radiation exposure toward the natural background radiation SSK 1984, 7). It can be expected that such a stricter regu-
is based on practical, economic, and social reasons. Man- lation is more apt to find support among political bodies and
ageability carries the day. the public—although it tended to ignore insecure knowledge
The second non-epistemic consideration is social about how cells respond to radiation. Thus, it is the com-
robustness. Social robustness is taken into account since mitment to social robustness that governed this choice.
the compatibility of the gist of a recommendation with the Another way of expressing this emphasis on being on the
prevalent interests and value attitudes in society affects the safe side and on rather overrating than underrating risks is a
odds of the acceptance and realization of this recommen- shift in preference from false negatives to false positives. In
dation. Frequently, the scientific assessment leaves room the former case, an assumption is erroneously rejected: a
for more than one political approach to be taken. Taking certain effect or phenomenon exists, in fact, but the relevant
non-epistemic values into account will neither improve nor scientists fail to recognize it due to insufficient data or other
invalidate the epistemic quality of an expert advice but conflicting considerations. False positives mean, by contrast,
enhance the prospects of a recommendation to be practi- that a hypothesis is mistakenly accepted: although some
cally implemented and acceptable to the public. effect or phenomenon fails to obtain, in fact, it is incorrectly
Epistemic robustness may be used for enhancing social assumed. A methodological maxim of scientific research is
robustness and for reassuring the public. This is the strat- to prefer false negatives to false positives. The Popperian
egy we encounter in the eye-lens case. Retaining the sur- reason behind this judgment is that a false negative can be
face dose as indicating exposure is justified by the fact that seen as growing out of due epistemic care: a hypothesis is
this procedure tends to overestimate the relevant hazard only accepted if it has passed severe tests. A severe test can
(see Sect. 3). This argument visibly represents an attempt be expected to reveal mistakes if there are any (Popper 1949,
to remain on the safe side. It means building bridges to 353–354). An erroneous assumption is unlikely to meet such
more skeptical or more anxious persons. Building in a a demanding standard so that no false positives should occur
safety margin means to comply with worries among social in properly conducted research. By contrast, a false negative
groups and to demonstrate the willingness to meet possible means that a correct assumption has not yet been tested
critics halfway. thoroughly enough to warrant acceptance. Accordingly,
The same approach is found in arguments used by the false negatives are taken as signifying a praiseworthy critical
SSK for crafting a dose–effect relation for low-dose long- attitude in science, while false positives are seen as indi-
term radiation exposure. The relevant impact on human cating rash and premature endorsement and as growing out of
tissue cannot be ascertained directly, and the SSK reached a lack of severe standards in scrutinizing assumptions
its conclusion by interpolating the results of the diverse (Carrier 2010, 198, 205; Droste-Franke et al. 2015, 43–44).
methods on which such a relationship could be based (see The practical relevance of scientific expertise may
Sect. 2). We explained before that the evidence pointed in induce a shift in this relation. Assume that much greater
different directions. What we want to consider here in risks are incurred by erroneously dismissing a true
addition are the criteria used for giving preference to certain hypothesis (i.e., by a false negative) than by its mistaken
evidence and neglecting other data. The salient point is that approval (i.e., by a false positive). Under such circum-
epidemiological data intimated a linear dose–effect rela- stances, it is plausible to adjust the standards for embracing
tionship, while exposing individual cells and animal tissue and discarding hypotheses. In contradistinction to epis-
to controlled low-dose radiation suggested a so-called temic research, false positives could become preferable to
quadratic relationship. In the latter case, the effect drops off false negatives. In fact, this shift follows from an argument

123
Scientific Expertise: Epistemic and Social Standards—The Example of the German Radiation… 63

developed by Rudner (1953). Rudner suggested that SSK is to contribute to the political regulation of radiation
weighing the practical or non-epistemic consequences of protection. The commission wants to see its advice heeded
both kinds of potential errors should decide about what by politicians. However, sustained controversies about
amount of evidence is required for accepting a hypothesis. radiation risks among the general public led the committee
A high threshold of acceptance reduces the risk of adopting to adopting communication strategies that were directed at
mistaken hypotheses, i.e., it serves to avoid false positives, concerned lay people. The SSK actively and visibly took
but increases the hazard of erroneously rejecting true up concerns assumed to be present in the population and
assumptions, i.e., of false negatives; and vice versa. It is sought to convey the impression that it acts on behalf of the
contentious whether this argument rightly characterizes the public. The self-understanding of being a neutral arbiter of
process of hypothesis acceptance in science in general. The political strife gives way, in part, to the self-image of
relations between adopting an assumption and acting in a acting as an attorney of the public. This double orientation
certain way are variegated and ambivalent. That is, the toward political or administrative bodies in charge of reg-
same set of beliefs can generate different actions, and the ulatory issues and toward lay opinions can be reconstructed
same action can grow out of different beliefs. For instance, as two sorts of social robustness: Value attitudes of deci-
the assumption that the risk of cataract associated with sion-makers and the general public are both taken into
sustained exposure to b-radiation is higher than anticipated account in order to enhance the odds of being listened to. In
may lead to adjusting the relevant threshold value or to the following we depict the commission’s turn toward the
introducing safety devices such as special eye glasses. public around the year 2000, when the rapid spread of new
Conversely, placing the threshold for exposure to ionizing devices triggered concerns about the hazards of non-ion-
radiation in the vicinity of the natural background radiation izing radiation. We seek to explore, in particular, how the
can arise from the justified assumption that such doses are commission strives to reconcile its advocatory role with the
innocuous or, alternatively, from the pragmatic considera- competing self-understanding of representing the epistemic
tion that any such risk is small as compared to other risks of authority of science.
civilization (see above). Worse yet, no specific actions are In the literature on scientific expertise, social participa-
connected to the acceptance of many hypotheses. Errors in tion is proposed, for one, as a means of enhancing the pro-
identifying the Higgs particle or in reconstructing prehis- spects of acceptance of a recommendation by the public,
toric Indo-European migration patterns are not likely to and, for another, as an instrument for upgrading the epis-
spawn any practical consequences (Carrier 2013). temic viability of such a recommendation. Thus, incorpo-
However that may be, such practical, non-epistemic rating local points of view may serve to increase social
considerations regarding the impact of error are certainly robustness and to expand the empirical basis of expert
relevant for scientific expertise. When experts give advice on advice. First, social participation demands that scientific
a question of practical importance, they legitimately take the experts take local interests and value-attitudes into account.
consequences of a possible error into account. This evidently The underlying motive is to increase the odds of being
applies to the two cases mentioned, i.e., the allowed b-ra- heeded. Second, scientific experts are well advised to pay
diation exposure of the eyes of professional staff and the attention to lay knowledge as a form of experience-based
assessment of the detrimental impact of low-dose long-term expertise. Lay people are familiar with the circumstances on
ionizing radiation on the general population. The safety site and may thus be able to adduce specific information.
margins introduced in the two cases indicate that the damage Accordingly, giving heed to local experience tends to sup-
supposedly done by being overly strict and by imposing port the reliability of the conclusions. Both kinds of par-
superfluous, unnecessary safety rules (i.e., false positives) is ticipation are distinct conceptually, but including local
judged to be less significant than the risk of hurting people’s voices is apt to serve both ends (Collins and Evans 2002,
health by being overly lenient (i.e., false negatives). In other 249–251, 255, 258–259, 267; Brown 2009, 240–243; Whyte
words, the amount of evidence required for adopting an and Crease 2010, 415–417; Carrier 2010, 208–209).
assumption whose falsity would have a severe negative The SSK did not accept lay expertise as a factor that
practical impact is enlarged—which is tantamount to shift- could influence their conclusions. However, it recognized
ing preferences from false negatives to false positives. individual, experience-based reports as stimuli for further
research. The commission took up worries from the pop-
ulation as sources of information. This policy of openness
5 Communication Strategies Adopted by the SSK toward the public served as a communication strategy that
was supposed to promote the social robustness of the
We explained in Sect. 1 that the SSK seeks to appear recommendations.
respectable to its scientific peers, trustworthy to the general In particular, in 2001, the SSK introduced three cate-
public, and relevant to politics. A primary objective of the gories for evaluating studies and reports about detrimental

123
64 M. Carrier, W. Krohn

health effects. A scientific proof (wissenschaftlicher anecdotal evidence as signaling topics that receive public
Nachweis) is provided by clear statistical correlations and attention and thus allows such indications to raise new
an established causal mechanism. A scientific proof of an topics. As a result, although public concerns had no tan-
adverse impact necessitates some sort of action on the part gible impact on the substance of the recommendations,
of the committee regarding political regulation. A scien- they were influential on the topics the SSK singled out for
tifically justified suspicion (wissenschaftlich begründeter consideration. This is part of the role of acting as a public
Verdacht) is based on conspicuous correlations (without attorney: the SSK picks up worries of the population. Yet
any proven causal linkage). Under such conditions pre- in the second step, it insisted on deciding about their jus-
cautionary measures should be considered. A scientific tification on the basis of epistemic standards alone.
indication (wissenschaftlicher Hinweis) is afforded by This strategy of picking up concerns and addressing
reports about individual cases. The adequate response to them by stimulating or commissioning research can be seen
indications is doing research on the matter (P_01_172 TOP as part of a more general shift in the communication pat-
7; SSK 2001, 6–7). terns of the SSK around 2000. Another part of this switch is
The introduction of this third category of indication the committee’s 1997 decision to make its recommenda-
means that anecdotal evidence could be taken seriously as a tions available to the public, to use generally accessible
cause of concern. As a result, some activity was launched language, and to avoid any derogatory comments on
in such cases in order to demonstrate that the SSK attended allegedly groundless fears among the population
to the matter. For instance, press releases about a Bavarian (P_00_169 TOP 9). The SSK was becoming increasingly
peasant who suspected that the health condition of his dairy aware that not only politics, but also the general public
cattle had deteriorated under the influence of a nearby represents its audience. It is this move that prompts the
mobile transmission tower were taken up by the commis- distinction between social robustness regarding politics and
sion (P_98_152 TOP 3). Even though no concrete action regarding the lay audience.
was recommended, the commission had ostentatiously An important step in this communicative switch toward
demonstrated its willingness to go into such contentious the public was to emphasize the uncertainty involved in
issues and thus to act as attorney of the public. and the tentative character of the recommendations.
A move in the same direction was picking up the notion Around 2000, the SSK became increasingly aware of the
of ‘‘electrosensitive persons’’ from the public discussion. A risk that falsely negative judgments pose to its reputation
popular argument among the general audience was that and credibility. Such judgments prematurely discount
adverse health effects of high-voltage transmission lines hazards and uncertainties and backfire severely if their
and mobile transmission towers were concentrated on or deceptive character is later revealed in public. The SSK
even confined to a group of particularly sensitive persons. had experienced such a backlash after its hasty attempt to
The lack of any general, statistically significant correlation reassure the population in the face of the Chernobyl acci-
between the physical impact of such devices and public dent in 1986. This glaring misjudgment had done heavy
health was argued to still leave the possibility open that damage to the trustworthiness of the SSK (Krohn and
these sensitive persons were hurt. The SSK was seizing on Weingart 1987). In order to prevent another setback and to
such worries and encouraged studies on the existence of promote the credibility of its advice among the general
such electrosensitive persons (which, by the way, failed to public, the phrasing of its recommendations became much
trace any such people) (P_01_172 TOP 7; P_01_174 TOP more cautious. For instance, the SSK failed to recognize
13; SSK 1998, 10; SSK 2002, 13–14; SSK 2008, 7–8; SSK any hazardous effects of the radiation exposure connected
2011, 27–29). to cell phone use. They did not simply say so, however, but
Thus, whereas, on the one hand, the category of indi- rather considered various abstract risks (such as the
cation could be used as a means for demonstrating the superposition of numerous electromagnetic fields, potential
openness of the commission to popular concerns, the genetic effects of the radiation, unknown effects of long-
conclusions reached, on the other hand, remained unaf- term exposure, and the possibility of electrosensitive per-
fected by such considerations. Reports about individual sons). The conclusion was that at present no relevant risks
cases were not accepted as lay expertise; rather, their are known but that additional research is needed in order to
trustworthiness was estimated by a comparison with the learn more about possible unknown risks (P_01_173 TOP
state of knowledge. This meant in practice that the reports 3; SSK 2001, 17; SSK 2002, 13–14; SSK 2003, 7–8,
were often considered misleading and irrelevant. The rec- 11–13, 15–16).
ommendations were entirely based on results that fall into The intent to enhance the social robustness of its rec-
the upper two categories of proofs and suspicions. In the ommendations and, correspondingly, its political clout as
end, the SSK relied exclusively on the epistemic authority well as the concern for its own trustworthiness induced a
of science. It deserves notice, however, that the SSK took change in the strategies the SSK employs in risk

123
Scientific Expertise: Epistemic and Social Standards—The Example of the German Radiation… 65

communication. The earlier practice of inferring harm- case at hand, while the latter advises experts to make their
lessness without much ado from the state of knowledge has conclusions independent of these particulars as far as
given way to a more cautious attitude and the emphasis on possible. The trade-off between specificity and epistemic
avoiding falsely negative judgments. The epistemic robustness is conspicuous in the eye-lens example. This
authority of science is maintained, but it is now accom- example shows how epistemic robustness is used for
panied by stressing the limits of knowledge (P_01_173 establishing the practical relevance of scientific knowledge.
TOP 3; P_01_174 TOP 13; SSK 2003, 16–17). This Third, non-epistemic values come into play. Such values
emphasis on uncertainty matches the practice of building are not related to the scientific quality of the expert rec-
tentative models, performing interpolations between con- ommendations but are supposed to enhance their political
trasting partial accounts, and drawing on pragmatic max- significance and their social trustworthiness. Social
ims better than the idea that the reasoning of the SSK robustness is chief among such values. We have argued
proceeds from secure knowledge about matters of fact. that social robustness ramifies into two branches, one
However, the latter idea is retained in the self-image of the directed at politics, and another one directed at society at
SSK. large. The former is shaped by values such as manage-
ability and is thought to increase the odds of being noticed
by decision-makers. Social robustness with respect to the
6 Conclusion public is enhanced if the recommendations are visibly
receptive to fears and worries. This includes in particular
The self-understanding of the SSK is essentially based on the noticeable sensitivity to the risks of ignorance and the
the idea that radiation protection should be anchored in corresponding emphasis on avoiding false negatives. On
scientific knowledge. Expertise should apply reliable sci- the whole, the self-understanding of the SSK involves
entific knowledge to concrete, life-world problems. In its keeping its distance from politics, but the SSK is also
self-image, the SSK is committed to taking scientific anxious of being heeded and thus includes sociopolitical
knowledge as the sole source of expert advice. This com- considerations that make the recommendations more sus-
mitment translates into the three categories of preserving ceptible to politics and society. The position the commis-
the SSK’s scientific reputation, securing its trustworthiness sion adopts is taking up social concerns but building the
to the public, and maintaining the political relevance of its gist of its recommendations as far as possible upon scien-
recommendations (see Sect. 1). However, we have tific knowledge. This approach goes along with pursuing a
attempted to show that the actual work of the SSK exhibits communication strategy that seeks to take public concerns
additional dimensions that do not always square well with into account and emphasizes uncertainty and the limits of
this understanding of expert advice as applied scientific knowledge. This idea is difficult to harmonize with the
knowledge. That is to say, the work of the commission is mentioned notion, entertained at the same time, that the
governed by particular standards, but these standards are SSK is a neutral body of experts that stays out of political
not explicitly recognized by the commission and are rather and social affairs.
revealed by our analysis of its recommendations and A final question is to which extent our observations and
deliberations. conclusions are generalizable to similar science-based
Our first point is that the endeavors to build de-idealized expert judgments in other fields. We are unable to give an
and complex models show that the commission produces unambiguous answer, but we suggest two considerations.
new knowledge of a particular sort, namely, models tai- First, it is plausible that the same efforts to transform sci-
lored to specific circumstances. Accordingly, the commis- entific knowledge into specific recommendations and to
sion does not simply translate the state of knowledge into bring particular epistemic and non-epistemic values to bear
expert advice, but adds new elements. Second, the com- are present in other instances as well. Moreover, if pro-
mission appeals to epistemic standards that are character- tection from hazards and risks is the predominant objective,
istic of expertise and have no analog in scientific research the values can be expected to be similar to those we
proper. Epistemic commitments of the latter sort include identified. However, if the tasks at hand are widely dif-
precision, predictive power, and large scope, whereas ferent, such as strengthening economic innovation or
epistemic values that have turned out to be relevant for building up an integrative education system, other values
expert advice are specificity and epistemic robustness. may come to the fore. Second, the sustained efforts of the
Epistemic values often point in different directions when SSK to emphasize its status as a scientific body may be
being applied to particular cases (Kuhn 1977). As regards rooted in the intensity of public concerns about radiation
epistemic values governing expert judgments of the SSK, a hazards. This may be the reason why the commission took
tension arises between specificity and epistemic robustness: pains to keep its distance from changing policy goals and
the former value demands including the particulars of the stressed its role as a public advocate. Yet, the underlying

123
66 M. Carrier, W. Krohn

conflict between expectations of decision-makers and the Lackey RT (2007) Science, scientists, and policy advocacy. U.S.
desire to act on behalf of the general public presumably Environmental protection agency papers, paper 142, 12–17.
http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/do/search/?q=author_lname%3A%
emerges in other cases as well. The SSK attempted to 22Lackey%22%20AND%20author_fname%3A%22Robert%22&
resolve this conflict by hiding itself, as it were, behind the start=0&context=52045&sort=date_desc. Accessed 1 June 2014
authority of scientific knowledge. It is worthwhile to Pielke RA Jr (2007) The honest broker: making sense of science in
explore whether other expert committees took a different policy and politics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Pielke RA Jr (2015) Lessons from 50 years of science advice to the
path and defended particular values of expert judgment as US president. In: Weingart P, Wagner GG (eds) Wis-
standards of quality and relevance of their work. senschaftliche Politikberatung im Praxistest. Velbrück, Weil-
ers-wist, pp 51–65
Acknowledgments We wish to express our gratitude to the Deutsche Popper KR (1949) The bucket and the searchlight: two theories of
Forschungsgemeinschaft for sponsoring the project (Ca120/17-2). knowledge. In: Objective knowledge. An evolutionary approach.
Martin Carrier completed the paper while being a senior fellow at the Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 341–361
Alfried-Krupp Wissenschaftskolleg in Greifswald and extends his Rudner R (1953) The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments.
heartfelt thanks to this institution. Philos Sci 20:1–6
SSK (1984) Möglichkeiten und Grenzen der Anwendung der
Kollektivdosis. Empfehlung der Strahlenschutzkommission
SSK (1998) Vorschlag zur Weiterentwicklung der Forschung zum
References Schutz vor nichtionisierenden Strahlen. Empfehlung der
Strahlenschutzkommission
Behrens R, Dietze G, Zankl M (2009) Dose conversion coefficients SSK (2001) Grenzwerte und Vorsorgemaßnahmen zum Schutz der
for electron exposure of the human eye lens. Phys Med Biol Bevölkerung von elektromagnetischen Feldern. Empfehlung der
54:4069–4087 Strahlenschutzkommission
Ben-Haim Y (2006) Info-gap decision theory. Decisions under severe SSK (2002) Weiterentwicklung der Forschung zum Schutz vor
uncertainty. Elsevier, Amsterdam nichtionisierender Strahlung. Empfehlung der
Brown MB (2009) Science in democracy. Expertise, institutions, and Strahlenschutzkommission
representation. MIT Press, Cambridge SSK (2003) Forschungsbedarf im Sonderforschungsprogramm ,,Mo-
Carrier M (2010) Scientific knowledge and scientific expertise: bilfunk‘‘. Stellungnahme der Strahlenschutzkommission, vol
epistemic and social conditions of their trustworthiness. Analyse 2008
und Kritik 32:195–212 SSK (2008) Deutsches Mobilfunk-Forschungsprogramm. Stellung-
Carrier M (2013) Values and objectivity in science: value-ladenness, nahme der Strahlenschutzkommission. Empfehlung der
pluralism and the epistemic attitude. Sci Educ 22:2547–2568 Strahlenschutzkommission
Collins HM, Evans R (2002) The third wave of science studies: SSK (2009) Strahleninduzierte Katarakte. Empfehlung der Strahlen-
studies in expertise and experience. Soc Stud Sci 32:235–296 schutzkommission mit wissenschaftlicher Begründung (English
Droste-Franke B, Carrier M, Schreurs M, Weber C, Ziesemer T translation: Radiation-induced cataracts recommendation by the
(2015) Improving energy decisions. Towards better scientific German commission on radiological protection with scientific
policy advice for a safe and secure future energy system. reasoning)
Springer, Heidelberg SSK (2010) Überwachung der Augenlinsendosis, Stellungnahme der
ICRP (2012) ICRP statement on tissue reactions/early and late effects SSK mit wissenschaftlicher Begründung
of radiation in normal tissues and organs—threshold doses for SSK (2011) Biologische Auswirkungen des Mobilfunks-Ge-
tissue reactions in a radiation protection context, ICRP publica- samtschau. Empfehlung der Strahlenschutzkommission
tion 118. Ann ICRP 41(1/2):2012 SSK (2012) Satzung der Strahlenschutzkommission vom 8. August
Krohn W (2008) Epistemische Qualitäten transdisziplinärer For- 2012. http://www.ssk.de/DE/UeberSSK/Satzung/satzung_node.
schung. In: Bergmann M, Schramm E (eds) Transdisziplinäre html;jsessionid=9422F0FE0A3A151AED58B6EB15495737.1_
Forschung. Integrative Forschungsprozesse verstehen und bew- cid319. Accessed 4 Aug 2015
erten. Frankfurt, Campus, pp 39–68 Trott K-R (1983) Cut off Dosis—Theorie oder Wirklichkeit, oder:
Krohn W (2010) Interdisciplinary cases and disciplinary knowl- Gibt es einen Schwellenwert für Karzinogene? In: Radioaktive
edge—epistemic challenges of interdisciplinary research. In: Stoffe und ionisierende Strahlung. Deutsches Atomforum, Bonn,
Frodeman R, Thompson Klein J, Mitcham C (eds) Oxford pp 167–190
handbook of interdisciplinarity. Oxford University Press, Weingart P, Carrier M, Krohn W (2007) Experten und Expertise. In:
pp 31–49 idem, Nachrichten aus der Wissensgesellschaft. Analysen zur
Krohn W, Weingart P (1987) Nuclear power as a social experiment— Veränderung der Wissenschaft. Velbrück, Weilerswist,
European political ‘fall out’ from chernobyl meltdown. Sci pp 293–304
Technol Hum Values 12:52–58 Weisberg M (2013) Simulation and similarity. Using models to
Kuhn T (1977) Value judgment, objectivity, and theory choice. In: understand the world. Oxford University Press, Oxford
The essential tension. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, Whyte KP, Crease RP (2010) Trust, expertise, and the philosophy of
pp 320–339 science. Synthese 177:411–425

123

You might also like