Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

A CRITIQUE OF MIDDLE-RANGE THEORY IN ARCHAEOLOGY

Christopher Pierce

For the past decade, several archaeologists have advocated the development of middle-range theory as a way to
give objective meaning to the archaeological record (e.g., Bettinger 1987; Binford 1977, 1983b; Thomas 1983,
1989; Torrence 1986). They argue that we must translate the static archaeological record into behaviorally
dynamic terms by documenting causal linkages between relevant behaviors and their static material by-products.
This is accomplished, they argue, by making observations today that establish signature patterns allowing the
unambiguous recognition of particular dynamics from their static by-products, and inferring past dynamics from
identification of signature patterns in the archaeological record. Further, it has been emphasized that the
operations and products of middle-range theory must remain logically independent of the general theory we use to
explain the past to avoid automatically confirming our ideas about the past through a tautology. This approach to
middle-range research is flawed in two major respects. First, the justification of inferences relies on the
establishment of universal behavioral laws and unambiguous signature patterns to validate the use of
uniformitarian assumptions, neither of which can be accomplished in the manner proposed. Second, the tautological
relationship between description and explanation is not only an unavoidable, but also a necessary aspect of science.
Solutions to these problems lie in using the physical characteristics of the archaeological record itself as our source
of knowledge about the past rather than translating the record into untestable behavioral reconstructions.

Shortly after Western scholars accepted the building in archaeology. Binford (1977,
potential for great human antiquity in 1859, a 1983b: 10) argues that theory building is
series of Tertiary age deposits were found to needed on two levels -- middle-range and
contain crudely chipped stones or eoliths. general. To Binford, general theory includes
These chipped stones were initially argued to ideas concerning the causes of change in the
be the earliest stone tools produced by people. organization of living systems while middle-
However, the simplicity and exceedingly great range theory addresses the inferential link
antiquity of these objects led many to question between the unobservable past organizational
the interpretation of these eoliths as artifacts of dynamics treated in general theory and the
human manufacture. Thus, the young static material patterns formed by those
discipline of prehistoric archaeology became dynamics and observable in the archaeological
embroiled in its first debate over the meaning record.
attributed to objects thought to be part of the In this scheme, general or explanatory
archaeological record (Grayson 1986). Given theory determines the relevance of knowledge
that archaeologists are interested in learning of dynamics generated by the application of
about the human past by observing the middle-range theory. For this reason, Binford
archaeological record as it exists today, the argued in 1977 that development of general
issue of how we give meaning to observations and middle-range theory must proceed
of this record has been a recurring theme. together so that time is not wasted building
Most recently, discourse over the methods of irrelevant middle-range theory. However,
inference in archaeology has focused on the since that time, Binford has stressed the view
role of middle-range theory. that general and middle-range theory must be
In 1977, Lewis Binford introduced the logically independent if we are to objectively
term "middle-range theory" into the published evaluate our ideas about the past (Binford
archaeological literature in a volume on theory 1981b: 29, 1982b). In other words, we must

Christopher D. Pierce – Department of Anthropology, University of Washington, Seattle, Wa, 98195


This paper was written in 1989 and never published.

1
acquire objective knowledge of what the past the organizational arrangements of behavior
was like based on different theory than we use and not discrete behaviors per se. As a first
to explain the past. As a result, Binford's work step in the investigation of the organizational
over the last ten years has been almost properties of past cultural systems, a link must
exclusively concerned with the methodology be established between these organizational
of inference in the form of middle-range dynamics and their static material by-products.
research. Because it is only in the present where both
Although other archaeologists have dynamics and statics are available for
employed a concept of middle-range theory, observation, these linkages must be established
sometimes in the same sense as Binford through what Binford (1981b: 27) calls
(Bettinger 1987; Thomas 1983, 1989; actualistic research. This is research carried
Torrence 1986) and sometimes not (Goodyear, out in the present using ethnographic,
Raab and Klinger 1978; Raab and Goodyear experimental or historical sources of
1984; Schiffer 1988), it is Lewis Binford who information to document the relations between
has contributed the most to middle-range relevant dynamics and observable statics.
theory's development and been its most
outspoken advocate. Therefore, this review
focuses on the structure and logical
consequences of Binford's view of middle-
range theory in archaeology.

Binford’s Structure for Middle-Range


Theory

Middle-range theory can be seen as consisting


of four components: 1) documentation of
causal relations between relevant dynamics
and observable statics; 2) recognition of
signature patterns in static remains; 3)
inference of past dynamics from observation
of signature patterns in archaeological record;
and, 4) evaluation of these inferences. Figure 1
depicts the relations among these four
components and their relations to general
theory. The arrows represent an idealized
sequence of operations within this structure.
Figure 1. A conceptual model of Binford's
Dynamics and Statics middle-range theory.
A critical aspect of these dynamics-statics
Binford (1981b; 1982b) argues that while the
linkages is that they must be causal. For
archaeological record is composed only of
Binford (1981b: 26; 1983b: 223), cause must
static arrangements of matter, we are
be demonstrated on two levels. First, the
interested in studying the dynamic
energy of the organizational dynamics must be
characteristics of past cultural systems.
shown to cause in a mechanical sense the static
Recently, Binford (1983b: 222, 1987) has
material by-products observed during
made it quite clear that by dynamics he means
actualistic research. This eliminates the

2
possibility that the linkage is coincidental and in the present. In other words, a uniformitarian
leads to the development of signature patterns assumption is required.
discussed in the next section. Cause must also
be demonstrated in a functional sense. The Evaluation of Inferences
organizational dynamics that produce the
statics must be explainable in functional, Because the inferences are reconstructions of
systemic terms. This forms a central part of the past dynamics that are no longer observable,
evaluation process discussed below. the evaluation of the validity of these
inferences rests entirely on the validity of the
Signature Patterns methods used to generate them. No empirical
tests are possible because there are no
The utility for archaeologists of linkages empirical products. This has led Binford
established between dynamics and statics is (1981b, 1982a, 1982b, 1983b: 12-17) to stress
dependent on the identification of criteria for that it is the methods of inference that must be
recognizing material traces of the dynamics tested and not the results of those methods.
likely to be preserved in the archaeological Binford (1981b: 27) contends that two
record. Binford (1981b: 26) refers to these related aspects of middle-range theory must be
traces as "signature patterns" and he argues true for the inferences to be valid. First, cause
that to be diagnostic of particular dynamics, and effect relations between statics and
they must be redundant and unambiguous. As dynamics must be firmly established and
Grayson (1982) has pointed out, the second, the uniformitarian assumptions must
establishment of signature criteria takes the be justified. As I stated earlier, cause and
form of "if and only if" statements. Much of effect must be both mechanical (result of
Binford's recent empirical work (e.g., 1978, interaction of energy and matter) and
1981b, 1983a, 1983b, 1989) has been devoted functional (explainable in terms of its relations
to constructing and recognizing signature to other parts of the system). These causal
patterns. relations cannot be tested through observations
of the archaeological record or through
Inference of Past Dynamics ethnographic research alone (Binford 1987),
but must involve actualistic middle-range
Once signature patterns have been established, research.
inferences can be made. In middle-range In 1977, Binford recognized that the
theory, inference is the procedure by which we validity of uniformitarian assumptions is
give dynamic meaning to the static limited when considering human behavior
arrangements of matter in the archaeological over the vast span of archaeological time.
record. It involves a translation process in However, he also suggested that there are at
which observations of matter in the least three domains or classes of data available
archaeological record are converted into to archaeologists for which uniformitarian
statements or concepts regarding the dynamic assumptions may be justified. These are the
conditions that brought them into being use of space by people and the resulting spatial
(Binford 1981b: 26-28, 1982b:30-31). These structure of material by-products, and the
inferences require the recognition of ecology and anatomy of still extant animals
established signature patterns in the with which people interacted. Binford (1977,
archaeological record and the assumption that 1981b:44, 238) warrants his use of these
the static-dynamic link identified by the domains by reference to the existence of
signature patterns existed in the past as well as apparent functional limitations or constraints

3
and the extreme regularity of patterns observed differences by arguing that the same behavior,
in the present. In other words, Binford (1973, the treatment of low utility anatomical parts, is
1987) appeals to the existence of laws or law- integrated differently into the logistic
like propositions to justify his uniformitarian Nunamiut system and the foraging strategy of
assumptions. the Aborigines. Thus for Binford, the apparent
Recently, Binford (1987) has proposed the ambiguity in these two cases led to new
recognition of ambiguity as another approach knowledge of static-dynamic linkages when
to the evaluation of inferences. Ambiguities the signature patterns were employed as a
between the inferred meanings of different frame of reference rather than as ethnographic
classes of data (i.e., site structure and analogs.
anatomical part frequencies) can lead to the
recognition of unknown organizational Relations between General and Middle-Range
strategies or isolate areas of inadequate Theory
knowledge. This form of evaluation is
depicted in Figure 1 as the line moving from In Binford's scheme then, middle-range
the evaluation step back to the establishment research produces objective descriptions of
of static - dynamic linkages. past organizational dynamics that are
An example of Binford's linking and warranted by the validity of uniformitarian
evaluation process is in order. While assumptions and by their independence of
conducting ethnoarchaeological investigations general theory or our ideas about the factors
among the Nunamiut of Alaska, Binford that condition those dynamics. Binford
(1978) observed that kill sites and hunting believes the intellectual separation of general
camps are dominated by distal limb elements and middle-range theory is necessary to avoid
(phalanges and metapodials). Binford a tautological relationship between our alleged
explained this pattern by reference to the knowledge of the past and our explanations of
economic utility of different anatomical parts the past. He (Binford 1983b: 223, 1987)
and their likelihood of being transported away argues that only after we have successfully
from procurement locations in a logistically diagnosed the nature of past systems through
organized system. The pattern observed at middle-range research is it possible to evaluate
hunting sites had been created by the our general theoretical ideas and begin to seek
differential transport of anatomical parts based explanations for inferred differences and
on economic decisions that balanced transport similarities.
costs with the utility of different anatomical It is here in the relations between general
parts. A functionally causal link is established and middle-range theory that the logic of
between economic utility of particular Binford's arguments is best displayed. Since
anatomical parts and their likelihood of for Binford, general theory involves the
transport from logistic hunting sites to explanation of the functioning and
residential sites, and a signature pattern is organization of cultural systems, our
established in the form of differential faunal descriptive or observational language must
element frequencies. measure these variables. However, the
Since Binford's Nunamiut experiences, archaeological record, our only access to
similar studies in Australia yielded different prehistoric cultural systems, consists only of
results (Binford 1987). An Aboriginal arrangements of matter. Binford's solution to
residential site was found to contain similar the dilemma is the development of middle-
anatomical part frequencies to the Nunamiut range theory as the method of translating the
hunting sites. Binford explained these static facts of the archaeological record into

4
the dynamic systemic terms addressed by that middle-range theory refers to lower level
general theory. Because the products of theories that are subsumed under higher-level
middle-range theory cannot be evaluated theories in a system of hierarchically related
empirically, Binford argues for the logical archaeological principles. I believe this
independence of general and middle-range hierarchical rather than independent concept of
theory to avoid committing the fallacy of middle-range theory has much to offer, but a
confirming the consequent (Binford 1981b: thorough analysis is beyond the scope of this
29). paper.

Other Forms of Middle-Range Theory Critique of Binford’s Middle-Range Theory

At this point it is worthwhile to briefly In this critique of Binford's middle-range


compare Binford's middle-range theory to theory, I examine two issues – how inferences
forms of middle-range theory discussed by are evaluated, and the role of general theory.
other archaeologists. Mark Raab and Albert The validity of inferences made in middle-
Goodyear (1984) have argued for the adoption range research rests primarily on the
of the concept of middle-range theory as appropriateness of the assumption that the
developed by the sociologist Robert Merton static - dynamic relations observed today
(1949). Merton perceived a gap between necessarily existed in the past and that these
empirical products of sociological research relationships are recognizable unambiguously
and highly abstract sociological theories and through signature patterns. That is, the
proposed middle-range theories as a way to arguments used to connect the statics and
link these two domains. This mini-theory dynamics must be laws that are true at any
approach has not received much attention by time or place (i.e. theoretical laws). Because
archaeologists and has recently been criticized Binford is interested in differences and
by Schiffer (1988) for its reliance on a single similarities in the organization of behavior in
hierarchy. Raab and Goodyear (1984) past systems, these laws must pertain to human
recognize that their approach bears little behavior.
resemblance to Binford's. To what extent, then, do Binford's
Schiffer's Behavioral Archaeology with its functional explanations of static - dynamic
emphasis on behavioral correlates and linkages observed in the present constitute
formation processes shares much in common universal theoretical laws? To be universally
with Binford's middle-range theory despite true, Binford's laws must state definitionally
arguments to the contrary (Binford 1981a; true relations between invariant classes.
Schiffer 1985a, 1985b). Like Binford, Schiffer However, Binford's statements are actually
(1976, 1987) believes that we must first empirical relations based on specific
reconstruct past behavior in a valid and observations for which an economic rationale
unambiguous fashion before reasonable has been provided. Although these relations
explanatory theories can be offered. However, may occur with great regularity, they are not
they apparently disagree on the form the necessary or true by definition nor are the
reconstruction is to take and the relation of classes invariant since this would preclude the
general theory to the middle-range or kind of change, the development of new
transformation theory employed in inference. forms, of interest to archaeologists. Therefore,
More recently, Schiffer (1988) offers a view of Binford's relational statements are not
middle-range theory that may diverge universal laws, but empirical generalizations
considerably form Binford's. Schiffer suggests regarding the kind of static archaeological

5
record produced by particular sets of behavior. post hoc character to the inferences derived
In middle-range theory, these generalizations from middle-range theory. Although the
function as interpretive algorithms for middle-range interpretations may appear more
translating static facts of the archaeological plausible, they actually have no more secure
record into relevant statements of past claim for validity than the interpretations of
dynamics. archaeologist employing traditional
When seen in this light, Binford's middle- approaches. Binford (1983:75) occasionally
range theory suffers from two serious flaws. recognizes this deficiency in his approach to
First, because the inferences of past dynamics middle-range theory, but he seems to believe
are based on empirical generalizations rather that relevant laws of human behavior will
than universal laws, the validity of eventually develop out of actualistic research
uniformitarian assumptions is questionable. It (Binford 1987). However, because universal
is doubtful that empirical generalizations will laws are part of the theoretical realm and the
ever yield unambiguous signature patterns units or nouns of those laws cannot change, it
because other dynamics that have not yet been is impossible for empirical generalizations of
observed may result in the same static record behavior to yield universal laws.
(see Lyman 1985 and Grayson 1988 for This last point leads us directly to a
examples of such a situation). In this context, consideration of the role of general theory.
it appears that the best that can be hoped for is Binford argues strongly for the intellectual
the establishment of equifinality. separation of general and middle-range theory.
The second and perhaps most serious flaw This belies a notion of an objective
involves the tautological relation that exits archaeological past that can be reconstructed
between the functional systemic notions of independent of our interest in it -- a position
organized behavior which appear to compose Binford (1986) has argued strongly against
Binford's general theory and the inferences or and, as we have seen, has not attained it in his
translations produced by middle-range theory. own work. However, concern with the fallacy
Although Binford argues for the independence of confirming the consequent which led
of general and middle-range theories, the Binford to his position on general theory is
tautology is clearly shown by the role that something to be taken seriously. In
economic functionalism plays in determining archaeology and other social sciences as well,
both the validity and relevance of middle- what passes for general theory consists of a set
range translations (Binford 1981b:145-147; of assertions about how people behave which
Binford, Mill and Stone 1988). However, this are usually based at least in part on empirical
tautological relationship is not debilitating in generalizations and common sense (Dunnell
and of itself. The problem lies in that middle- 1982; Willer and Willer 1974). If the theory is
range theory as proposed by Binford does not robust, for example optimal foraging theory, it
yield an empirically testable product. In provides certain expectations about how
science, the necessary tautology between people behave under given circumstances. If
explanation and description, that the rules for the theory is employed in a context where
both come from the same body of theory, is behavior can be observed, it can yield
made harmless by the requirement of empirical powerful results. However, if it is used as part
testability within a framework of falsification of an interpretive algorithm for giving
(Dunnell and Simek 1984). behavioral meaning to material remains, we
The lack of universal behavioral or commit the very fallacy Binford tried to avoid.
cultural laws and empirical verification of The reason Binford's solution fails is that
knowledge claims gives an accommodative, his identification of the problem is misplaced.

6
The circular connections between theory and wrong. The utility of radiocarbon dating stems
description, which Binford finds so appalling, from its basis in universal physical laws that
are, in fact, unavoidable (Lewontin 1974:8). allow the estimation of the time since a
Description involves classification and discrete event (isolation of an organism from
classification requires a priori input in the carbon reservoir) with a specifiable
defining the field of interest and the relevant certainty. A basis in theoretical laws is, in fact,
descriptive attributes (Dunnell 1971). Despite the strength of all archaeometry. That these
Binford's (1981b:290) beliefs to contrary, this laws are independent of anthropological or
is how all science proceeds although the a archaeological theories is largely irrelevant.
priori input may be implicit and non- When seen in this light, it is clear that the
theoretical as is often the case in archaeology. physical characteristics of the archaeological
The problem arises when there are no record itself can give us access to the past. No
empirical phenomena against which to test our translation of the static record into untestable
expectations. Because Binford's middle-range behavioral dynamics is necessary. This
theory does not solve this problem, he ends up solution makes empirical testing and
committing the same error as most traditional falsification possible and trivializes Binford's
approaches to giving meaning to the tautology problem. At the same time, we are
archaeological record. forced to look more closely at the role of
We may ask whether it is possible to solve general theory. For the development of
this problem in archaeology or must we be scientific archaeology to proceed, we need
content with plausible reconstructions. I think robust and explicit general theory to help
it is solvable, and the solution includes many structure our observations and expectations of
of the arguments and proposals made by the empirical archaeological record. In
Binford and others. That we study a science, it is general theory that provides the
contemporary material record that is devoid of terms in which both description and
inherent meaning relevant to the past is explanation are accomplished.
incontrovertible. Because our interests are in
the past, we must give meaning to the record. Conclusions
That the process by which we give meaning to
the record involves uniformitarian At the beginning of this paper, I mentioned the
assumptions, I believe is also beyond dispute. eolith debate as the first time scholars working
However, for these assumptions to be justified, on human prehistory confronted the problem
they must be based on universal theoretical of giving meaning to the archaeological
laws. Such laws can only pertain to the record. Grayson (1986) has pointed out that
physical world since change in organic the methods developed to address the eolith
systems excludes the possibility of invariant problem are essentially the same as those
classes required in universal laws. Binford is recently proposed by Binford. It is informative
fond of citing radiocarbon dating as an to recognize that the eolith debate was not
example of the linking process involved in resolved by these methods. All that could be
middle-range theory. He argues that said based on the actualistic research
radiocarbon dating works for archaeology conducted on flint fracture was that there are
because its theoretical basis is independent of several agents that can produce chipped
theories we may be testing by acquiring stones. This is demonstrated by the debate,
information on elapsed time (Binford which continues today, over the chipped
1981b:290-291, 1982b:134-135). Although stones at the Calico Site in southern California.
this reasoning is superficially appealing, it is

7
The resolution of the European eolith 1973 Interasseblage Variability: The
debate in the 1930s stemmed from Mousterian and the 'Functional
improvements in our knowledge of hominid Argument.' In The Explanation of Culture
paleontology and a change in the way Change: Models in Prehistory, edited by
archaeologists gave meaning to the record. C. Renfrew, pp. 227-254. Duckworth,
The growth of culture history in the 1920s and London.
1930s brought about a shift away from the 1977 General Introduction. In For Theory
analogical use of ethnographic and Building in Archaeology, edited by L. R.
experimental information in favor of formal BInford, pp. 1-13. Academic Press, New
comparisons of archaeological assemblages to York.
one another. The goal was to give 1978 Nunamuit Ethnoarchaeology. Academic
chronological and homologous or ethnic Press, New York.
meaning to differences and similarities 1981a Behavioral Archaeology and the
observed in the archaeological record (Binford "Pompeii Premise." Journal of
1968; Dunnell 1986a, 1986b). Anthropological Research 35:195-208.
The recent return of concern with middle- 1981b Bones: Ancient Men and Modern
range kinds of issues grew out of the New Myths. Academic Press, New York.
Archaeology's interests in giving analogous or 1982a Meaning, Inference and the Material
functional meaning in anthropological terms to Record. In Ranking, Resource and
patterns of similarity and difference in the Exchange, edited by C. Renfrew and
archaeological record. These goals required S.Shennan. Cambridge University Press,
that better methods be developed for Cambridge.
unambiguously reconstructing past behavioral 1982b Objectivity -- Explanation --
dynamics. I have tried to demonstrate that Archaeology -- 1981. In Theory and
Binford's middle-range theory approach will Explanation in Archaeology, edited by C.
be no more successful at this task than the Renfrew, M. J. Rowlands, and B. A.
methods devised to distinguish naturally from Seagraves, pp. 125-138. Academic Press,
artificially chipped stones over 100 years ago. London and New York.
1983a In Pursuit of the Past. Thames and
Acknowledgements. I wrote this paper in 1989 while in Hudson, New York.
my first year of graduate school at the University of 1983b Working at Archaeology. Academic
Washington, and it benefitted from discussions with
Robert Dunnell and Donald Grayson and commentss Press, New York.
from several fellow graduate students. However, I take 1986 In Pursuit of the Future. In American
full responsibility for any errors in the analysis and Archaeology Past and Future, edited by
critique. D. J. Meltzer, D. D. Fowler, and J. A.
Sabloff, pp. 459-479. Smithsonian
References Cited Institution Press, Washington D.C.
1987 Researching Ambiguity: Frames of
Bettinger, R. L. Reference and Site Structure. In Method
1987 Archaeological Approaches to Hunter- and Theory for Activity Area Research,
Gatherers. Annual Review of edited by S. Kent, pp. 449-512. Columbia
Anthropology 16:121-142. University Press, New York.
Binford, L. R. 1989 Debating Archaeology. Academic
1968 Archaeological Perspectives. In New Press, Orlando.
Perspectives in Archaeology, edited by S.
R. Binford and L. R. Binford, pp. 5-32.
Aldine, Chicago.

8
Binford, L. R., M. G. L. Mills, and N. M. 1988 Last Supper Cave. In Danger Cave,
Stone Last Supper Cave, Hanging Rock Shelter:
1988 Hyena Scavenging Behavior and Its The Faunas, edited by D. K. Grayson, pp.
Implications for the Interpretation of 44-74. Anthropological Papers Vol. 66,
Faunal Assemblages from FLK 22 (the Pt. 1. American Museum of Natural
Zinj Floor) at Olduvai Gorge. Journal of History.
Anthropological Archaeology 7:99-135. Lewontin, R.C.
Dunnell, R. C. 1974 The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary
1971 Systematics in Prehistory. Free Press, Change. Columbia University Press, New
New York. York.
1982 Science, Social Science, and Common Lyman, R. L.
Sense: The Agonizing Dilemma of 1985 Bone Frequencies: Differential
Modern Archaeology. Journal of Transport, in situ Desturction, and the
Anthropological Research 38(1):1-25. MGUI. Journal of Archaeological Science
1986a Five Decades of American 12:221-236.
Archaeology. In American Archaeology Merton, R.K.
Past and Future, edited by D. J. Meltzer, 1949 Social Theory and Social Structure. The
D. D. Fowler, and J. A. Sabloff, pp. 23- Free Press, New York.
49. Raab, L. M. and A. C. Goodyear
1986b Methodological Issues in American 1984 Middle-Range Theory in Archaeology:
Artifact Classification. In Advances in A Critical Review of Origins and
Archaeological Method and Theory, Vol. Applications. American Antiquity
9, edited by M. B. Schiffer, pp. 149-207. 49(2):255-268.
Academic Press, New York. Schiffer, M. B.
Dunnell, R. C. and J. F. Simek 1976 Behavioral Archaeology. Academic
1984 What does the Archaeological Record Press, New York.
Mean? Reviews in Anthropology 11(1):1- 1985a Is there a "Pompeii Premise" in
11. Archaeology? Journal of Anthropological
Goodyear, A. C., L. M. Raab and T. Klinger Research 41:18-41.
1978 The Status of Archaeological Research 1985b Review of Working at Archaeology by
Design in Cultural Resource L. R. Binford. American Antiquity
Management. American 50(1):191-193.
Antiquity 43(2):159-173. 1987 Formation Processes of the
Grayson, D. K. Archaeological Record. University of
1982 Review of Bones: Ancient Men and New Mexico Press, Albuquerque.
Modern Myths, by L. R. 1988 The Structure of Archaeological
Binford. American Theory. American Antiquity 53(3):461-
Anthropologist 84:439-440. 485.
1986 Eoliths, Archaeological Ambiguity, and Thomas, D. H.
the Generation of "Middle-Range" 1983a The Archaeology of Monitor Valley: 1.
Research. In American Archaeology Past Epistemology. Anthropological Papers
and Future, edited by D. J. Meltzer, D. D. Vol. 58, Pt. 1. American Museum of
Fowler and J. A. Sabloff, pp. 77-133. Natural History.
Smithsonian Institution Press, 1983b The Archaeology of Monitor Valley: 2.
Washington, D.C. Gatecliff Shelter. Anthropological Papers

9
Vol. 59, Pt. 2. American Museum of Torrence, R.
Natural History. 1986 Production and Exchange of Stone
1988 The Archaeology of Monitor Valley: 3. Tools. Cambridge University Press,
Survey and Additional Excavation. Cambridge.
Anthropological Papers Vol. 66, Pt. 3. Willer, D and J. Willer
American Museum of Natural History. 1974 Systematic Empiricism: Critque of a
1989 Archaeology. 2nd ed. Holt, Rinehart Pseudoscience. Prentice-Hall, Englewood
and Winston, Inc. New York. Cliffs, N.J.

10

You might also like