Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 22

Rational Decision Making in Business Organizations

Author(s): Herbert A. Simon


Source: The American Economic Review , Sep., 1979, Vol. 69, No. 4 (Sep., 1979), pp. 493-
513
Published by: American Economic Association

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1808698

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Economic
Review

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Rational Decision M\4aking in
Business Organizations
By HERBERT A. SIMON*

In the opening words of his Principles, I. Decision Theory as Economic Science


Alfred Marshall proclaimed economics to be
a psychological science: The density of settlement of economists
over the whole empire of economic science is
Political Economy or Economics is a
very uneven, with a few areas of modest size
study of mankind in the ordinary busi-
holding the bulk of the population. The
ness of life; it examines that part of
individual and social action which is economic Heartland is the normative study of
most closely connected with the attain- the international and national economies and
ment and with the use of the material their markets, with its triple main concerns of
requisites of wellbeing. full employment of resources, the efficient
Thus it is on the one side a study of allocation of resources, and equity in distribu-
wealth; and on the other, and more tion of the economic product. Instead of the
important side, a part of the study of ambiguous and over-general term "econom-
man. For man's character has been ics," I will use "political economy" to desig-
moulded by his every-day work, and the
nate this Heartland, and "economic sciences"
material resources which he thereby
to denote the whole empire, including its most
procures, more than by any other
influence unless it be that of his religiousremote colonies. Our principal concern in this
ideals. paper will be with the important colonial
territory known as decision theory. I will have
In its actual development, however, eco- something to say about its normative and
nomic science has focused on just one aspect descriptive aspects, and particularly about its
of man's character, his reason, and particu- applications to the theory of the firm. It is
larly on the application of that reason to through the latter topic that the discussion
problems of allocation in the face of scarcity.will be linked back to the Heartland of
Still, modern definitions of the economic political economy.
sciences, whether phrased in terms of allocat- Underpinning the corpus of policy-oriented
ing scarce resources or in terms of rational normative economics, there is, of course, an
decision making, mark out a vast domain for impressive body of descriptive or "positive"
conquest and settlement. In recent years there theory which rivals in its mathematical
has been considerable exploration by econo- beauty and elegance some of the finest theo-
mists even of parts of this domain that were ries in the physical sciences. As examples I
thought traditionally to belong to the disci- need only remind you of Walrasian general
plines of political science, sociology, and equilibrium theories and their modern
psychology. descendants in the works of Henry Schultz,
Samuelson, Hicks, and others; or the subtle
and impressive body of theory created by
Arrow, Hurwicz, Debreu, Malinvaud, and
*Carnegie-Mellon University. This article is the
lecture Herbert Simon delivered in Stockholm, Sweden, their colleagues showing the equivalence,
December 8, 1978, when he received the Nobel Prize in under certain conditions, of competitive equi-
Economic Science. The article is copyright e the Nobel librium with Pareto optimality.
Foundation 1978. It is published here with the permission
The relevance of some of the more refined
of the Nobel Foundation.
The author is indebted to Albert Ando, Otto A. Davis, parts of this work to the real world can be,
and Benjamin M. Friedman for valuable comments on an and has been, questioned. Perhaps some of
earlier draft of this paper. these intellectual mountains have been

493

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
494 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

climbed simply because they were there gy, from psychology, and from political
because of the sheer challenge and joy of science. Respected and distinguished figures
scaling them. That is as it should be in any in economics Edward Mason, Fritz Mach-
human scientific or artistic effort. But regard- lup, and Milton Friedman, for example-
less of the motives of the climbers, regardless have placed it outside the Pale (more accu-
of real world veridicality, there is no question rately, have placed economics outside its
but that positive political economy has been Pale), and have offered it full autonomy
strongly shaped by the demands of economic provided that it did not claim close kinship
policy for advice on basic public issues. with genuine economic inquiry.
This too is as it should be. It is a vulgar Thus, Mason, commenting on Papan-
fallacy to suppose that scientific inquiry dreou's 1952 survey of research on the behav-
cannot be fundamental if it threatens to ioral theory of the firm, mused aloud:
become useful, or if it arises in response to
problems posed by the everyday world. The ... has the contribution of this litera-
real world, in fact, is perhaps the most fertile ture to economic analysis really been a
large one? . . . The writer of this critique
of all sources of good research questions
must confess a lack of confidence in the
calling for basic scientific inquiry.
marked superiority, for purposes of
economic analysis, of this newer concept
A. Decision Theory in the Service of of the firm, over the older conception of
Political Economy the entrepreneur. [pp. 221-22]

There is, however, a converse fallacy that And, in a similar vein, Friedman sums up
deserves equal condemnation: the fallacy of his celebrated polemic against realism in
supposing that fundamental inquiry is worth theory:
pursuing only if its relevance to questions of
policy is immediate and obvious. In the Complete "realism" is clearly unat-
contemporary world, this fallacy is perhaps tainable, and the question whether a
theory is realistic "enough" can be
not widely accepted, at least as far as the
settled only by seeing whether it yields
natural sciences are concerned. We have now
predictions that are good enough for the
lived through three centuries or more of
purpose in hand or that are better than
vigorous and highly successful inquiry into predictions from alternative theories.
the laws of nature. Much of that inquiry has [p. 41, emphasis added]
been driven by the simple urge to understand,
to find the beauty of order hidden in complex- The "purpose in hand" that is implicit in
ity. Time and again, we have found the "idle" both of these quotations is providing decision-
truths arrived at through the process of theoretic foundations for positive, and then
inquiry to be of the greatest moment for for normative, political economy. In the views
practical human affairs. I need not take time of Mason and Friedman, fundamental inquiry
here to argue the point. Scientists know it, into rational human behavior in the context of
engineers and physicians know it, congress- business organizations is simply not (by defi-
men and members of parliaments know it, the nition) economics that is to say, political
man on the street knows it. economy unless it contributes in a major
But I am not sure that this truth is as way to that purpose. This is sometimes even
widely known in economics as it ought to be. I interpreted to mean that economic theories of
cannot otherwise explain the rather weak and decision making are not falsified in any inter-
backward development of the descriptive esting or relevant sense when their empirical
theory of decision making including the predictions of microphenomena are found to
theory of the firm, the sparse and scattered be grossly incompatible with the observed
settlement of its terrain, and the fact that data. Such theories, we are told, are still
many, if not most, of its investigators are realistic "enough" provided that they do not
drawn from outside economics from sociolo- contradict aggregate observations of concern

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 495

to political economy. Thus economists who B. Decision Theory Pursued for its
are zealous in insisting that economic actors Intrinsic Interest
maximize turn around and become satisficers
when the evaluation of their own theories is Of course the definition of the word "eco-
concerned. They believe that businessmen nomics" is not important. Like Humpty
maximize, but they know that economic theo- Dumpty, we can make words mean anything
rists satisfice. we want them to mean. But the professional
The application of the principle of satisfic- training and range of concern of economists
ing to theories is sometimes defended as an does have importance. Acceptance of the
application of Occam's Razor: accept the narrow view that economics is concerned only
simplest theory that works.' But Occam's with the aggregative phenomena of political
Razor has a double edge. Succinctness of economy defines away a whole rich domain of
statement is not the only measure of a theo- rational human behavior as inappropriate for
ry's simplicity. Occam understood his rule as economic research.
recommending theories that make no more I do not wish to appear to be admitting that
assumptions than necessary to account for the the behavioral theory of the firm has been
phenomena (Essentia non sunt multiplicanda irrelevant to the construction of political
praeter necessitatem). A theory of profit or economy. I will have more to say about its
utility maximization can be stated more relevance in a moment. My present argument
briefly than a satisficing theory of the sort I is counterfactual in form: even if there were
shall discuss later. But the former makes no present evidence of such relevance, human
much stronger assumptions than the latter behavior in business firms constitutes a highly
about the human cognitive system. Hence, in interesting body of empirical phenomena that
the case before us, the two edges of the razor calls out for explanation as do all bodies of
cut in opposite directions. phenomena. And if we may extrapolate from
In whichever way we interpret Occam's the history of the other sciences, there is every
principle, parsimony can be only a secondary reason to expect that as explanations emerge,
consideration in choosing between theories, relevance for important areas of practical
unless those theories make identical predic- application will not be long delayed.
tions. Hence, we must come back to a consid- It has sometimes been implied (Friedman,
eration of the phenomena that positive deci- p. 14) that the correctness of the assumptions
sion theory is supposed to handle. These may of rational behavior underlying the classical
include both phenomena at the microscopic theory of the firm is not merely irrelevant, but
level of the decision-making agents, or aggre- is not even empirically testable in any direct
gative phenomena of concern to political way, the only valid test being whether these
economy. assumptions lead to tolerably correct predic-
tions at the macroscopic level. That would be
true, of course, if we had no microscopes, so
'The phrase "that works" refutes, out of hand, Fried-
that the micro-level behavior was not directly
man's celebrated paean of praise for lack of realism in
assumptions. Consider his example of falling bodies
observable. But we do have microscopes.
(pp. 16-19). His valid point is that it is advantageous to There are many techniques for observing
use the simple law, ignoring air resistance, when it gives a decision-making behavior, even at second-
"good enough" approximation. But of course the condi- by-second intervals if that is wanted. In test-
tions under which it gives a good approximation are not
ing our economic theories, we do not have to
at all the conditions under which it is unrealistic or a
"wildly inaccurate descriptive representation of reality." depend on the rough aggregate time-series
We can use it to predict the path of a body falling in a that are the main grist for the econometric
vacuum, but not the path of one falling through the mill, or even upon company financial state-
Earth's atmosphere. I cannot in this brief space mention, ments.
much less discuss, all of the numerous logical fallacies
that can be found in Friedman's 40-page essay. For
The classical theories of economic decision
additional criticism, see Simon (1963) and Samuelson making and of the business firm make very
(1963). specific testable predictions about the con-

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
496 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

crete behavior of decision-making agents. there are no direct observations that individu-
Behavioral theories make quite different als or firms do actually equate marginal costs
predictions. Since these predictions can be and revenues. The empirically verified conse-
tested directly by observation, either theory quences of the classical theory are almost
(or both) may be falsified as readily when always weaker than this. Let us look at four of
such predictions fail as when predictions the most important of them: the fact that
about aggregate phenomena are in error. demand curves generally have negative
slopes; the fact that fitted Cobb-Douglas
C. Aggregative Tests o Decision Theory: functions are approximately homogeneous of
Marginalism the first degree; the fact of decreasing returns
to scale; and the fact that executive salaries
If some economists have erroneously vary with the logarithm of company size. Are
supposed that micro-economic theory can these indeed facts? And does the evidence
only be tested by its predictions of aggregate support a maximizing theory against a satis-
phenomena, we should avoid the converse ficing theory?
error of supposing that aggregate phenomena Negatively Sloping Demand Curves.
are irrelevant to testing decision theory. In Evidence that consumers actually distribute
particular, are there important, empirically their purchases in such a way as to maximize
verified, aggregate predictions that follow their utilities, and hence to equate marginal
from the theory of perfect rationality but that utilities, is nonexistent. What the empirical
do not follow from behavioral theories of data do confirm is that demand curves gener-
rationality? ally have negative slopes. (Even this "ob-
The classical theory of omniscient rational- vious" fact is tricky to verify, as Henry
ity is strikingly simple and beautiful. More- Schultz showed long years ago.) But nega-
over, it allows us to predict (correctly or not) tively sloping demand curves could result
human behavior without stirring out of our from a wide range of behaviors satisfying the
armchairs to observe what such behavior is assumptions of bounded rationality rather
like. All the predictive power comes from than those of utility maximization. Gary
characterizing the shape of the environment Becker, who can scarcely be regarded as a
in which the behavior takes place. The envi- hostile witness for the classical theory, states
ronment, combined with the assumptions of the case very well:
perfect rationality, fully determines the
behavior. Behavioral theories of rational Economists have long been aware that
some changes in the feasible or opportu-
choice theories of bounded rationality-do
nity sets of households would lead to the
not have this kind of simplicity. But, by way
same response regardless of the decision
of compensation, their assumptions about rule used. For example, a decrease in
human capabilities are far weaker than those real income necessarily decreases the
of the classical theory. Thus, they make amount spent on at least one commodi-
modest and realistic demands on the knowl- ty... It has seldom been realized, how-
edge and computational abilities of the ever, that the change in opportunities
human agents, but they also fail to predict resulting from a change in relative prices
that those agents will equate costs and returns also tends to produce a systematic
at the margin. response, regardless of the decision rule.
In particular, the fundamental theorem
of traditional theory-that demand
D. Have the Marginalist Predictions
curves are negatively inclined largely
Been Tested?
results from the change in opportunities
alone and is largely independent of the
A number of empirical phenomena have decision rule. [p. 4]
been cited as providing more or less conclu-
sive support for the classical theory of the Later, Becker is even more explicit, saying,
firm as against its behavioral competitors (see "Not only utility maximization but also many
Dale Jorgensen and Calvin Siebert). But other decision rules, incorporating a wide

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 497

variety of irrational behavior, lead to nega- top corporate executives grow with the loga-
tively inclined demand curves because of the rithm of corporate size (see David Roberts).
effect of a change in prices on opportunities" This finding has been derived from the
(p 5).2 assumptions of the classical theory of profit
First-Degree Homogeneity of Pro- maximization only with the help of very
duction Functions. Another example of an particular ad hoc assumptions about the
observed phenomenon for which the classical distribution of managerial ability (see Robert
assumptions provide sufficient, but not neces- Lucas, 1978). The observed relation is
sary, conditions is the equality between implied by a simple behavioral theory that
labor's share of product and the exponent of assumes only that there is a single, culturally
the labor factor in fitted Cobb-Douglas pro- determined, parameter which fixes the aver-
duction functions (see Simon and Ferdinand age ratio of the salaries of managers to the
Levy). Fitted Cobb-Douglas functions are salaries of their immediate subordinates (see
homogeneous, generally of degree close to Simon, 1957). In the case of the executive
unity and with a labor exponent of about the salary data, the behavioral model that
right magnitude. These findings, however, explains the observations is substantially
cannot be taken as strong evidence for the more parsimonious (in terms of assumptions
classical theory, for the identical results can about exogenous variables) than the classical
readily be produced by mistakenly fitting a model that explains the same observations.
Cobb-Douglas function to data that were in Summary: Phenomena that Fail to
fact generated by a linear accounting identity Discriminate. It would take a much more
(value of goods equals labor cost plus capital extensive review than is provided here to
cost), (see E. H. Phelps-Brown). The same establish the point conclusively, but I believe
comment applies to the SMAC production it is the case that specific phenomena requir-
function (see Richard Cyert and Simon). ing a theory of utility or profit maximization
Hence, the empirical findings do not allow us for their explanation rather than a theory of
to draw any particular conclusions about the bounded rationality simply have not been
relative plausibility of classical and behav- observed in aggregate data. In fact, as my last
ioral theories, both of which are equally two examples indicate, it is the classical
compatible with the data. rather than the behavioral form of the theory
The Long-Run Cost Curve. Somewhat that faces real difficulties in handling some of
different is the case of the firm's long-run cost the empirical observations.
curve, which classical theory requires to be Failures of Classical Theory. It may
U shaped if competitive equilibrium is to be well be that classical theory can be patched
stable. Theories of bounded rationality do not up sufficiently to handle a wide range of
predict this fortunately, for the observed situations where uncertainty and outguessing
data make it exceedingly doubtful that the phenomena do not play a central role that
cost curves are in fact generally U shaped. is, to handle the behavior of economies that
The evidence for many industries shows costs are relatively stable and not too distant from a
at the high-scale ends of the curves to be competitive equilibrium. However, a strong
essentially constant or even declining (see positive case for replacing the classical theory
Alan Walters). This finding is compatible by a model of bounded rationality begins to
with stochastic models of business firm emerge when we examine situations involving
growth and size (see Y. Ijiri and Simon), but decision making under uncertainty and
not with the static equilibrium model of imperfect competition. These situations the
classical theory. classical theory was never designed to handle,
Executive Salaries. Average salaries of and has never handled satisfactorily. Statisti-
cal decision theory employing the idea of
subjective expected utility, on the one hand,
2In a footnote, Becker indicates that he denotes as
irrational "[A]ny deviation from utility maximization." and game theory, on the other, have contrib-
Thus, what I have called "bounded rationality" is "irra- uted enormous conceptual clarification to
tionality" in Becker's terminology. these kinds of situations without providing

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
498 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

satisfactory descriptions of actual human oped, the names of Dantzig, Kantorovich, and
behavior, or even, for most cases, normative Koopmans being prominent in the early
theories that are actually usable in the face of development of that tool.
the limited computational powers of men and Now the salient characteristic of the deci-
computers. sion tools employed in management science is
I shall have more to say later about the that they have to be capable of actually
positive case for a descriptive theory of making or recommending decisions, taking as
bounded rationality, but I would like to turn their inputs the kinds of empirical data that
first to another territory within economic are available in the real world, and perform-
science that has gained rapidly in population ing only such computations as can reasonably
since World War II, the domain of normative be performed by existing desk calculators or,
decision theory. a little later, electronic computers. For these
domains, idealized models of optimizing
E. Normative Decision Theory entrepreneurs, equipped with complete cer-
tainty about the world-or, at worst, having
Decision theory can be pursued not only for full probability distributions for uncertain
the purposes of building foundations for polit- events are of little use. Models have to be
ical economy, or of understanding and fashioned with an eye to practical computa-
explaining phenomena that are in themselves bility, no matter how severe the approxima-
intrinsically interesting, but also for the tions and simplifications that are thereby
purpose of offering direct advice to business imposed on them.
and governmental decision makers. For Model construction under these stringent
reasons not clear to me, this territory was very conditions has taken two directions. The first
sparsely settled prior to World War II. Such is to retain optimization, but to simplify
inhabitants as it had were mainly industrial sufficiently so that the optimum (in the
engineers, students of public administration, simplified world!) is computable. The second
and specialists in business functions, none of is to construct satisficing models that provide
whom especially identified themselves with good enough decisions with reasonable costs
the economic sciences. Prominent pioneers of computation. By giving up optimization, a
included the mathematician, Charles Bab- richer set of properties of the real world can
bage, inventor of the digital computer, the be retained in the models. Stated otherwise,
engineer, Frederick Taylor, and the adminis- decision makers can satisfice either by finding
trator, Henri Fayol. optimum solutions for a simplified world, or
During World War II, this territory, by finding satisfactory solutions for a more
almost abandoned, was rediscovered by scien- realistic world. Neither approach, in general,
tists, mathematicians, and statisticians con- dominates the other, and both have continued
cerned with military management and logis- to co-exist in the world of management
tics, and was renamed "operations research" science.
or "operations analysis." So remote were the Thus, the body of theory that has developed
operations researchers from the social science in management science shares with the body
community that economists wishing to enter of theory in descriptive decision theory a
the territory had to establish their own colony, central concern with the ways in which deci-
which they called "management science." sions are made, and not just with the decision
The two professional organizations thus outcomes. As I have suggested elsewhere
engendered still retain their separate identi- (1978b), these are theories of how to decide
ties, though they are now amicably federated rather than theories of what to decide.
in a number of common endeavors. Let me cite one example, from work in
Optimization techniques were transported which I participated, of how model building
into management science from economics, in normative economics is shaped by compu-
and new optimization techniques, notably tational considerations (see Charles Holt,
linear programming, were invented and devel- Franco Modigliani, John Muth, and Simon).

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 499

In face of uncertain and fluctuating pro- reduced significantly by the introduction of


duction demands, a company can smooth and formal procedures for calculating reorder
stabilize its production and employment levels points and quantities.
at the cost of holding buffer inventories. What
kind of decision rule will secure a reasonable II. Characterizing Bounded Rationality
balance of costs? Formally, we are faced with
a dynamic programming problem, and these The principal forerunner of a behavioral
generally pose formidable and often intoler- theory of the firm is the tradition usually
able computational burdens for their solu- called Institutionalism. It is not clear that all
tion. of the writings, European and American,
One way out of this difficulty is to seek a usually lumped under this rubric have much
special case of the problem that will be in common, or that their authors would agree
computationally tractable. If we assume the with each other's views. At best, they share a
cost functions facing the company all to be conviction that economic theory must be
quadratic in form, the optimal decision rule reformulated to take account of the social and
will then be a linear function of the decision legal structures amidst which market transac-
variables, which can readily be computed in tions are carried out. Today, we even find a
terms of the cost parameters. Equally impor- vigorous development within economics that
tant, under uncertainty about future sales, seeks to achieve institutionalist goals within
only the expected values, and not the higher the context of neoclassical price theory. I will
moments, of the probability distributions have more to say about that a little later.
enter into the decision rule (Simon, 1956b). The name of John R. Commons is promi-
Hence the assumption of quadratic costs nent-perhaps the most prominent-among
reduces the original problem to one that is American Institutionalists. Commons' diffi-
readily solved. Of course the solution, though cult writings (for example, Institutional
it provides optimal decisions for the simplified Economics) borrow their language heavily
world of our assumptions, provides, at best, from the law, and seek to use the transaction
satisfactory solutions for the real-world deci- as their basic unit of behavior. I will not
sion problem that the quadratic function undertake to review Commons' ideas here,
approximates. In-principle, unattainable op- but simply remark that they provided me with
timization is sacrificed for in-practice, attain- many insights in my initial studies of organi-
able satisfaction. zational decision making (see my Adminis-
If human decision makers are as rational as trative Behavior, p. 136).
their limited computational capabilities and Commons also had a substantial influence
their incomplete information permit them to on the thinking of Chester I. Barnard, an
be, then there will be a close relation between intellectually curious business executive who
normative and descriptive decision theory. distilled from his experience as president of
Both areas of inquiry are concerned primarily the New Jersey Bell Telephone Company,
with procedural rather than substantive and as executive of other business, govern-
rationality (Simon, 1978a). As new mathe- mental, and nonprofit organizations, a pro-
matical tools for computing optimal and satis- found book on decision making titled The
factory decisions are discovered, and as Functions of the Executive. Barnard pro-
computers become more and more powerful, posed original theories, which have stood up
the recommendations of normative decision well under empirical scrutiny, of the nature of
theory will change. But as the new recommen- the authority mechanism in organizations,
dations are diffused, the actual, observed, and of the motivational bases for employee
practice of decision making in business firms acceptance of organizational goals (the so-
will change also. And these changes may have called "inducements-contributions" theory);
macro-economic consequences. For example, and he provided a realistic description of
there is some agreement that average inven- organizational decision making, which he
tory holdings of American firms have been characterized as "opportunistic." The numer-

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
500 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

ous references to Barnard's work in Adminis- then decisions will be judged against subordi-
trative Behavior attest, though inadequately, nate goals that can be so connected. There is
to the impact he had on my own thinking no unique determination of these subordinate
about organizations. goals. Their formulation will depend on the
knowledge, experience, and organizational
A. In Search of a Descriptive Theory environment of the decision maker. In the
face of this ambiguity, the formulation can
In 1934-35, in the course of a field study of also be influenced in subtle, and not so subtle,
the administration of public recreational ways by his self-interest and power drives.
facilities in Milwaukee, which were managed The phenomenon arises as frequently in
jointly by the school board and the city public individual as in social decision making and
works department, I encountered a puzzling problem solving. Today, under the rubric of
phenomenon. Although the heads of the two problem representation, it is a central
agencies appeared to agree as to the objec- research interest of cognitive psychology.
tives of the recreation program, and did not Given a particular environment of stimuli,
appear to be competing for empire, there was and a particular background of previous
continual disagreement and tension between knowledge, how will a person organize this
them with respect to the allocation of funds complex mass of information into a problem
between physical maintenance, on the one formulation that will facilitate his solution
hand, and play supervision on the other. Why efforts? How did Newton's experience of the
did they not, as my economics books apple, if he had one, get represented as an
suggested, simply balance off the marginal instance of attraction of apple by Earth?
return of the one activity against that of the Phenomena like these provided the central
other? theme for Administrative Behavior. That
Further exploration made it apparent that study represented "an attempt to construct
they didn't equate expenditures at the margin tools useful in my own research in the field of
because, intellectually, they couldn't. There public administration." The product was
was no measurable production function from actually not so much a theory as prolegomena
which quantitative inferences about marginal to a theory, stemming from the conviction
productivities could be drawn; and such qual- "that decision making is the heart of adminis-
itative notions of a production function as the tration, and that the vocabulary of adminis-
two managers possessed were mutually trative theory must be derived from the logic
incompatible. To the public works adminis- and psychology of human choice." It was, if
trator, a playground was a physical facility, you please, an exercise in problem representa-
serving as a green oasis in the crowded gray tion.
city. To the recreation administrator, a play- On examination, the phenomenon of
ground was a social facility, where children subgoal identification proved to be the visible
could play together with adult help and guid- tip of a very large iceberg. The shape of the
ance. iceberg is best appreciated by contrasting it
How can human beings make rational deci- with classical models of rational choice. The
sions in circumstances like these? How are classical model calls for knowledge of all the
they to apply the marginal calculus? Or, if it alternatives that are open to choice. It calls
does not apply, what do they substitute for for complete knowledge of, or ability to
it? compute, the consequences that will follow on
The phenomenon observed in Milwaukee is each of the alternatives. It calls for certainty
ubiquitous in human decision making. In in the decision maker's present and future
organization theory it is usually referred to as evaluation of these consequences. It calls for
subgoal identification. When the goals of an the ability to compare consequences, no
organization cannot be connected operation- matter how diverse and heterogeneous, in
ally with actions (when the production func- terms of some consistent measure of utility.
tion can't be formulated in concrete terms), The task, then, was to replace the classical

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 501

model with one that would describe how of specific decision-making episodes. Exam-
decisions could be (and probably actually ples are my study, with Guetzkow, Kozmet-
were) made when the alternatives of search sky, and Tyndall (1954), of the ways in which
had to be sought out, the consequences of accounting data were used in decision making
choosing particular alternatives were only in large corporations; and a series of studies,
very imperfectly known both because of with Richard Cyert, James March, and
limited computational power and because of others, of specific nonprogrammed policy
uncertainty in the external world, and the decisions in a number of different companies
decision maker did not possess a general and (see Cyert, Simon, and Donald Trow). The
consistent utility function for comparing hete- latter line of work was greatly developed and
rogeneous alternatives. expanded by Cyert and March and its theo-
Several procedures of rather general appli- retical implications for economics explored in
cability and wide use have been discovered their important work, A Behavioral Theory
that transform intractable decision problems of the Firm.
into tractable ones. One procedure already At about the same time, the fortuitous
mentioned is to look for satisfactory choices availability of some data on businessmen's
instead of optimal ones. Another is to replace perceptions of a problem situation described
abstract, global goals with tangible subgoals, in a business policy casebook enabled DeWitt
whose achievement can be observed and Dearborn and me to demonstrate empirically
measured. A third is to divide up the decision- the cognitive basis for identification with
making task among many specialists, coordi- subgoals, the phenomenon that had so
nating their work by means of a structure of impressed me in the Milwaukee recreation
communications and authority relations. All study. The businessmen's perceptions of the
of these, and others, fit the general rubric of principal problems facing the company
"bounded rationality," and it is now clear that described in the case were mostly determined
the elaborate organizations that human by their own business experiences-sales and
beings have constructed in the modern world accounting executives identified a sales prob-
to carry out the work of production and lem, manufacturing executives, a problem of
government can only be understood as internal organization.
machinery for coping with the limits of man's Of course there is vastly more to be learned
abilities to comprehend and compute in the and tested about organizational decision
face of complexity and uncertainty. making than can be dealt with in a handful of
This rather vague and general initial studies. Although many subsequent studies
formulation of the idea of bounded rationalityhave been carried out in Europe and the
called for elaboration in two directions: United States, this domain is still grossly
greater formalization of the theory, and undercultivated (for references, see March,
empirical verification of its main claims. 1965; E. Johnsen, 1968; G. Eliasson, 1976).
During the decade that followed the publica- Among the reasons for the relative neglect of
tion of Administrative Behavior, substantial such studies, as contrasted, say, with labora-
progress was made in both directions, some of tory experiments in social psychology, is that
it through the efforts of my colleagues and they are extremely costly and time consum-
myself, much of it by other research groups ing, with a high grist-to-grain ratio, the meth-
that shared the same Zeitgeist. odology for carrying them out is primitive,
and satisfactory access to decision-making
B. Empirical Studies behavior is hard to secure. This part of
economics has not yet acquired the habits of
The principal source of empirical data patience and persistence in the pursuit of
about organizational decision making has facts that is exemplified in other domains by
been straightforward "anthropological" field the work, say, of Simon Kuznets or of the
study, eliciting descriptions of decision- architects of the MIT-SSRC-Penn economet-
making procedures and observing the course ric models.

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
502 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

C. Theoretical Inquiries Organizational Equilibrium. Barnard


had described the survival of organizations in
On the theoretical side, three questions terms of the motivations that make their
seemed especially to call for clarification: participants (employees, investors, customers,
what are the circumstances under which an suppliers) willing to remain in the system. In
employment relation will be preferred to some Administrative Behavior, I had developed
other form of contract as the arrangement for this notion further into a motivational theory
securing the performance of work; what is the of the balance between the inducements that
relation between the classical theory of the were provided by organizations to their par-
firm and theories of organizational equilib- ticipants, and the contributions those partici-
rium first proposed by Chester Barnard; and pants made to the organizations' resources.
what are the main characteristics of human A formalization of this theory (Simon,
rational choice in situations where complexity 1952; 1953) showed its close affinity to the
precludes omniscience? classical theory of the firm, but with an
The Employment Relation. A funda- important and instructive difference. In
mental characteristic of modern industrial comparing the two theories, each inducement-
society is that most work is performed, not by contribution relation became a supply sched-
individuals who produce products for sale, nor ule for the firm. The survival conditions
by individual contractors, but by persons who became the conditions for positive profit. But
have accepted employment in a business firm while the classical theory of the firm assumes
and the authority relation with the employer that all profits accrue to a particular set of
that employment entails. Acceptance of participants, the owners, the organization
authority means willingness to permit one's theory treats the surplus more symmetrically,
behavior to be determined by the employer, at and does not predict how it will be distributed.
least within some zone of indifference or Hence the latter theory leaves room, under
acceptance. What is the advantage of this conditions of monopoly and imperfect compe-
arrangement over a contract for specified tition, for bargaining among the participants
goods or services? Why is so much of the (for example, between labor and owners) for
world's work performed in large, hierarchic the surplus. The survival conditions positive
organizations? profits rather than maximum profits also
Analysis showed (Simon, 1951) that a permit a departure from the assumptions of
combination of two factors could account for perfect rationality.
preference for the employment contract over Mechanisms of Bounded Rationality. In
other forms of contracts: uncertainty as to Administrative Behavior, bounded rationality
which future behaviors would be advanta- is largely characterized as a residual cate-
geous to the employer, and a greater indiffer- gory rationality is bounded when it falls
ence of the employee as compared with the short of omniscience. And the failures of
employer (within the former's area of accep- omniscience are largely failures of knowing
tance) as to which of these behaviors he all the alternatives, uncertainty about rele-
carried out. When the secretary is hired, the vant exogenous events, and inability to calcu-
employer does not know what letters he will late consequences. There was needed a more
want her to type, and the secretary has no positive and formal characterization of the
great preference for typing one letter rather mechanisms of choice under conditions of
than another. The employment contract bounded rationality. Two papers (Simon,
permits the choice to be postponed until the 1955; 1956a) undertook first steps in that
uncertainty is resolved, with little cost to the direction.
employee and great advantage to the Two concepts are central to the characteri-
employer. The explanation is closely analo- zation: search and satisficing. If the alterna-
gous to one Jacob Marschak had proposed for tives for choice are not given initially to the
liquidity preference. Under conditions of decision maker, then he must search for them.
uncertainty it is advantageous to hold Hence, a theory of bounded rationality must
resources in liquid, flexible form. incorporate a theory of search. This idea was

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 503

later developed independently by George a significant number of empirical studies had


Stigler in a very influential paper that took as been carried out that showed actual business
its example of a decision situation the decision making to conform reasonably well
purchase of a second-hand automobile. with the assumptions of bounded rationality
Stigler poured the search theory back into the but not with the assumptions of perfect
old bottle of classical utility maximization, rationality, and key components of the the-
the cost of search being equated with its ory-the nature of the authority and employ-
marginal return. In my 1956 paper, I had ment relations, organizational equilibrium,
demonstrated the same formal equivalence, and the mechanisms of search and satisfic-
using as my example a dynamic programming ing-had been elucidated formally. In the
formulation of the process of selling a remaining parts of this paper, I should like to
house. trace subsequent developments of decision-
But utility maximization, as I showed, was making theory, including developments com-
not essential to the search scheme-fortu- petitive with the theory of bounded rational-
nately, for it would have required the decision ity, and then to comment on the implications
maker to be able to estimate the marginal (and potential implications) of the new
costs and returns of search in a decision descriptive theory of decision for political
situation that was already too complex for the economy.
exercise of global rationality. As an alterna-
tive, one could postulate that the decision lll. The Neoclassical Revival
maker had formed some aspiration as to how
good an alternative he should find. As soon as Peering forward from the late 1950's, it
he discovered an alternative for choice meet- would not have been unreasonable to predict
ing his level of aspiration, he would terminate that theories of bounded rationality would
the search and choose that alternative. I soon find a large place in the mainstream of
called this mode of selection satisficing. It economic thought. Substantial progress had
had its roots in the empirically based psycho- been made in providing the theories with
logical theories, due to Lewin and others, of some formal structure, and an increasing
aspiration levels. As psychological inquiry body of empirical evidence showed them to
had shown, aspiration levels are not static, but provide a far more veridical picture of deci-
tend to rise and fall in consonance with sion making in business organizations than
changing experiences. In a benign environ- did the classical concepts of perfect rational-
ment that provides many good alternatives, ity.
aspirations rise; in a harsher enviornment, History has not followed any such simple
they fall. course, even though many aspects of the
In long-run equilibrium it might even be Zeitgeist were favorable to movement in this
the case that choice with dynamically adapt- direction. During and after World War II, a
ing aspiration levels would be equivalent to large number of academic economists were
optimal choice, taking the costs of search into exposed directly to business life, and had
account. But the important thing about the more or less extensive opportunities to observe
search and satisficing theory is that it showed how decisions were actually made in business
how choice could actually be made with organizations. Moreover, those who became
reasonable amounts of calculation, and using active in the development of the new manage-
very incomplete information, without the ment science were faced with the necessity of
need of performing the impossible-of carry- developing decision-making procedures that
ing out this optimizing procedure. could actually be applied in practical situa-
tions. Surely these trends would be conducive
D. Summary to moving the basic assumptions of economic
rationality in the direction of greater real-
Thus, by the middle 1950's, a theory of ism.
bounded rationality had been proposed as an But these were not the only things that
alternative to classical omniscient rationality, were happening in economics in the postwar

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
504 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

period. First, there was a vigorous reaction introduce search and information transfer
that sought to defend classical theory from explicitly as economic activities, with asso-
behavioralism on methodological grounds. I ciated costs and outputs, that could be
have already commented on these methodo- inserted into the classical production func-
logical arguments in the first part of my talk. tion. I have already referred to Stigler's 1961
However deeply one may disagree with them, paper on the economics of information, and
they were stated persuasively and are still my own venture in the same direction in the
influential among academic economists. 1956 essay cited earlier.
Second, the rapid spread of mathematical In theory of this genre, the decision maker
knowledge and competence in the economics is still an individual. A very important new
profession permitted the classical theory, direction, in which decisions are made by
especially when combined with statistical groups of individuals, in teams or organiza-
decision theory and the theory of games due tions, is the economic theory of teams devel-
to von Neumann and Morgenstern, to develop oped by Jacob Marschak and Roy Radner.
to new heights of sophistication and elegance, Here we see genuine organizational phenom-
and to expand to embrace, albeit in highly ena-specialization of decision making as a
stylized form, some of the phenomena of consequence of the costs of transmitting infor-
uncertainty and imperfect information. The mation-emerge from the rational calculus.
flowering of mathematical economics and Because the mathematical difficulties are
econometrics has provided two generations of formidable, the theory remains largely illus-
economic theorists with a vast garden of trative and limited to very simple situations in
formal and technical problems that have miniature organizations. Nevertheless, it has
absorbed their energies and postponed greatly broadened our understanding of the
encounters with the inelegancies of the real economics of information.
world. In none of these theories-any more than
If I sound mildly critical of these develop- in statistical decision theory or the theory of
ments, I should confess that I have also been a games-is the assumption of perfect maximi-
part of them, admire them, and would be zation abandoned. Limits and costs of infor-
decidedly unhappy to return to the premathe- mation are introduced, not as psychological
matical world they have replaced. My characteristics of the decision maker, but as
concern is that the economics profession has part of his technological environment. Hence,
exhibited some of the serial one-thing-at- the new theories do nothing to alleviate the
a-time character of human rationality, and computational complexities facing the deci-
has seemed sometimes to be unable to distri- sion maker-do not see him coping with them
bute its attention in a balanced fashion among by heroic approximation, simplifying and
neoclassical theory, macroeconometrics, and satisficing, but simply magnify and multiply
descriptive decision theory. As a result, not as them. Now he needs to compute not merely
much professional effort has been devoted to the shapes of his supply and demand curves,
the latter two, and especially the third, as one but, in addition, the costs and benefits of
might have hoped and expected. The Heart- computing those shapes to greater accuracy
land is more overpopulated than ever, while as well. Hence, to some extent, the impression
rich lands in other parts of the empire go that these new theories deal with the hitherto
untilled. ignored phenomena of uncertainty and infor-
mation transmission is illusory. For many
A. Search and Information Transfer economists, however, the illusion has been
persuasive.
Let me allude to just three of the ways in
which classical theory has sought to cope with B. Rational Expectations Theory
some of its traditional limitations, and has
even sought to make the development of a A second development in neoclassical
behavioral theory, incorporating psychologi- theory on which I wish to comment is the
cal assumptions, unnecessary. The first was to so-called "rational expectations" theory.

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 505

There is a bit of historical irony surrounding quadratic. I have suggested elsewhere


its origins. I have already described the (1978a) that it might therefore be less
management science inquiry of Holt, Modig- misleading to call the rule a "consistent
liani, Muth, and myself that developed a expectations" rule.
dynamic programming algorithm for the Perhaps even more important, Albert Ando
special (and easily computed) case of and Benjamin Friedman (1978, 1979) have
quadratic cost functions. In this case, the shown that the policy implications of the
decision rules are linear, and the probability rational expectations rule are quite different
distributions of future events can be replaced under conditions where new information
by their expected values, which serve as continually becomes available to the system,
certainty equivalents (see Simon, 1956; Henri structural changes occur, and the decision
Theil, 1957). maker learns, than they are under steady-
Muth imaginatively saw in this special case state conditions. For example, under the more
a paradigm for rational behavior under uncer- dynamic conditions, monetary neutrality-
tainty. What to some of us in the HMMS which in general holds for the static consistent
research team was an approximating, satisfic- expectations models-is no longer guaranteed
ing simplification, served for him as a major for any finite time horizon.
line of defense for perfect rationality. He said In the recent "revisionist" versions of
in his seminal 1961 Econometrica article, "It consistent expectations theory, moreover,
is sometimes argued that the assumption of where account is taken of a changing environ-
rationality in economics leads to theories ment of information, various behavioral
inconsistent with, or inadequate to explain, assumptions reappear to explain how expecta-
observed phenomena, especially changes over tions are formed what information decision
time... Our hypothesis is based on exactly makers will consider, and what they will
the opposite point of view: that dynamic ignore. But unless these assumptions are to be
economic models do not assume enough made on a wholly ad hoc and arbitrary basis,
rationality" (p. 316). they create again the need for an explicit and
The new increment of rationality that valid theory of the decision-making process
Muth proposed was that "expectations, since (see Simon, 1958a; B. Friedman, 1979).
they are informed predictions of future
events, are essentially the same as the predic- C. Statistical Decision Theory and
tions of the relevant economic theory" Game Theory
(p. 316). He would cut the Gordian knot.
Instead of dealing with uncertainty by elabo- Statistical decision theory and game theory
rating the model of the decision process, he are two other important components of the
would once and for all-if his hypothesis were neoclassical revival. The former addresses
correct-make process irrelevant. The subse- itself to the question of incorporating uncer-
quent vigorous development of rational expec- tainty (or more properly, risk) into the deci-
tations theory, in the hands of Sargent, Lucas,sion-making models. It requires heroic
Prescott, and others, is well known to most assumptions about the information the deci-
readers (see, for example, Lucas, 1975). sion maker has concerning the probability
It is too early to render a final verdict on distributions of the relevant variables, and
the rational expectations theory. The issue simply increases by orders of magnitude the
will ultimately be decided, as all scientific computational problems he faces.
debates should be, by a gradual winnowing of Game theory addresses itself to the "out-
the empirical evidence, and that winnowing guessing" problem that arises whenever an
process has just begun. Meanwhile, certain economic actor takes into account the possible
grave theoretical difficulties have already reactions to his own decisions of the other
been noticed. As Muth himself has pointed actors. To my mind, the main product of the
out, it is rational (i.e., profit maximizing) to very elegant apparatus of game theory has
use the "rational expectations" decision rule been to demonstrate quite clearly that it is
if the relevant cost equations are in fact virtually impossible to define an unambiguous

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
506 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

criterion of rationality for this class of situa- First, there has been work in the psycholog-
tions (or, what amounts to the same thing, a ical laboratory and the field to test whether
definitive definition of the "solution" of a people in relatively simple choice situations
game). Hence, game theory has not brought behave as statistical decision theory (maximi-
to the theories of oligopoly and imperfect zation of expected utilities) say they do.
competition the relief from their contradic- Second, there has been extensive psychologi-
tions and complexities that was originally cal research, in which Allen Newell and I
hoped for it. Rather, it has shown that these have been heavily involved, to discover the
difficulties are ineradicable. We may be able actual microprocesses of human decision
to reach consensus that a certain criterion of making and problem solving. Third, there
rationality is appropriate to a particular have been numerous empirical observations-
game, but if someone challenges the consen- most of them in the form of "case studies"-
sus, preferring a different criterion, we will of the actual processes of decision making in
have no logical basis for persuading him that organizational and business contexts. Fourth,
he is wrong. there have been reformulations and exten-
sions of the theory of the firm replacing
D. Conclusion classical maximization with behavioral deci-
sion postulates.
Perhaps I have said enough about the
neoclassical revival to suggest why it has been A. Utility Theory and Human Choice
a highly attractive commodity in competition
with the behavioral theories. To some econo- The axiomatization of utility and probabil-
mists at least, it has held open the possibility ity after World War II and the revival of
and hope that important questions that had Bayesian statistics opened the way to testing
been troublesome for classical economics empirically whether people behaved in choice
could now be addressed without sacrifice of situations so as to maximize subjective
the central assumption of perfect rationality, expected utility (SEU). In early studies, using
and hence also with a maximum of a priori extremely simple choice situations, it ap-
inference and a minimum of tiresome grub- peared that perhaps they did. When even
bing with empirical data. I have perhaps said small complications were introduced into the
enough also with respect to the limitations of situations, wide departures of behavior from
these new constructs to indicate why I do not the predictions of SEU theory soon became
believe that they solve the problems that evident. Some of the most dramatic and
motivated their development. convincing empirical refutations of the theory
have been reported by D. Kahneman and A.
IV. Advances in the Behavioral Theory Tversky, who showed that under one set of
circumstances, decision makers gave far too
Although they have played a muted role in little weight to prior knowledge and based
the total economic research activity during their choices almost entirely on new evidence,
the past two decades, theories of bounded while in other circumstances new evidence
rationality and the behavioral theory of the had little influence on opinions already
business firm have undergone steady develop- formed. Equally large and striking departures
ment during that period. Since surveying the from the behavior predicted by the SEU
whole body of work would be a major under- theories were found by Howard Kunreuther
taking, I shall have to be satisfied here with and his colleagues in their studies of individ-
suggesting the flavor of the whole by citing a ual decisions to purchase or not to purchase
few samples of different kinds of important flood insurance. On the basis of these and
research falling in this domain. Where other pieces of evidence, the conclusion seems
surveys on particular topics have been unavoidable that the SEU theory does not
published, I will limit myself to references to provide a good prediction-not even a good
them. approximation-of actual behavior.

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 507

Notice that the refutation of the theory has great deal has been learned, also, about
to do with the substance of the decisions, and professional level human tasks like making
not just the process by which they are medical diagnoses, investing in portfolios of
reached. It is not that people do not go stocks and bonds, and playing chess. In tasks
through the calculations that would be of these kinds, the general search mechanisms
required to reach the SEU decision-neoclas- operate in a rich context of information stored
sical thought has never claimed that they did. in human long-term memory, but the general
What has been shown is that they do not even organization of the process is substantially the
behave as if they had carried out those same as for the simpler, more specific tasks.
calculations, and that result is a direct refuta- At the present time, research in informa-
tion of the neoclassical assumptions. tion processing psychology is proceeding in
several directions. Exploration of profession-
B. Psychology of Problem Solving al level skills continues. A good deal of effort
is now being devoted also to determining how
The evidence on rational decision making is initial representations for new problems are
largely negative evidence, evidence of what acquired. Even in simple problem domains,
people do not do. In the past twenty years a the problem solver has much latitude in the
large body of positive evidence has also accu- way he formulates the problem space in which
mulated about the processes that people use he will search, a finding that underlines again
to make difficult decisions and solve complex how far the actual process is from a search for
problems. The body of theory that has been a uniquely determined optimum (see J. R.
built up around this evidence is called infor- Hayes and Simon).
mation processing psychology, and is usually The main import for economic theory of
expressed formally in computer programming the research in information processing psy-
languages. Newell and I have summed up our chology is to provide rather conclusive empir-
own version of this theory in our book, ical evidence that the decision-making process
Human Problem Solving, which is part of a in problem situations conforms closely to the
large and rapidly growing literature that models of bounded rationality described
assumes an information processing frame- earlier. This finding implies, in turn, that
work and makes use of computer simulation choice is not determined uniquely by the
as a central tool for expressing and testing objective characteristics of the problem situa-
theories. tion, but depends also on the particular
Information processing theories envisage heuristic process that is used to reach the
problem solving as involving very selective decision. It would appear, therefore, that a
search through problem spaces that are often model of process is an essential component in
immense. Selectivity, based on rules of thumb any positive theory of decision making that
or "heuristics," tends to guide the search into purports to describe the real world, and that
promising regions, so that solutions will the neoclassical ambition of avoiding the
generally be found after search of only a tiny necessity for such a model is unrealizable
part of the total space. Satisficing criteria (Simon, 1978a).
terminate search when satisfactory problem
solutions have been found. Thus, these theo- C. Organizational Decision Making
ries of problem solving clearly fit within the
framework of bounded rationality that I have It would be desirable to have, in addition to
been expounding here. the evidence from the psychological research
By now the empirical evidence for this just described, empirical studies of the
general picture of the problem solving process process of decision making in organizational
is extensive. Most of the evidence pertains to contexts. The studies of individual problem
relatively simple, puzzle-like situations of the solving and decision making do not touch on
sort that can be brought into the psychologi- the many social-psychological factors that
cal laboratory for controlled study, but a enter into the decision process in organiza-

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
508 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

tions. A substantial number of investigations of the use of this technique are G.P.E. Clark-
have been carried out in the past twenty years son's simulation of the decision making of an
of the decision-making process in organiza- investment trust officer, Cyert, E. A. Feigen-
tions, but they are not easily summarized. baum, and March's simulation of the history
The difficulty is that most of these investiga- of a duopoly, and C. P. Bonini's model of the
tions have taken the form of case studies of effects of accounting information and super-
specific decisions or particular classes of deci- visory pressures in altering employee motiva-
sions in individual organizations. To the best tions in a business firm. The simulation meth-
of my knowledge, no good review of this odology is discussed from a variety of view-
literature has been published, so that it is points in Dutton and Starbuck.4
difficult even to locate and identify the studies
that have been carried out.3 Nor have any D. Theories of the Business Firm
systematic methods been developed and
tested for distilling out from these individual The general features of bounded rational-
case studies their implications for the general ity-selective search, satisficing, and so on-
theory of the decision-making process. have been taken as the starting points for a
The case studies of organizational decision number of attempts to build theories of the
making, therefore, represent the natural business firm incorporating behavioral as-
history stage of scientific inquiry. They sumptions. Examples of such theories would
provide us with a multitude of facts about the include the theory of Cyert and March,
decision-making process facts that are al- already mentioned; William Baumol's theory
most uniformly consistent with the kind of of sales maximization subject to minimum
behavioral model that has been proposed profit constraints; Robin Marris' models of
here. But we do not yet know how to use these firms whose goals are stated in terms of rates
facts to test the model in any formal way. Nor of growth; Harvey Leibenstein's theory of
do we quite know what to do with the obser- "X-inefficiency" that depresses production
vation that the specific decision-making below the theoretically attainable; Janos
procedures used by organizations differ from Kornai's dichotomy between supply-driven
one organization to another, and within each and demand-driven management; Oliver Wil-
organization, even from one situation to liamson's theory of transactional costs; the
another. We must not expect from these data evolutionary models of Richard Nelson and
generalizations as neat and precise as those Sidney Winter (1973); Cyert and Morris
incorporated in neoclassical theory. DeGroot's (1974) models incorporating
Perhaps the closest approach to a method adaptive learning; Radner's (1975a,b) expli-
for extracting theoretically relevant informa- cit satisficing models; and others.
tion from case studies is computer simulation. Characterized in this way, there seems to
By converting empirical evidence about a be little commonality among all of these
decision-making process into a computer theories and models, except that they depart
program, a path is opened both for testing the in one way or another from the classical
adequacy of the program mechanisms for assumption of perfect rationality in firm deci-
explaining the data, and for discovering the sion making. A closer look, however, and a
key features of the program that account, more abstract description of their assump-
qualitatively, for the interesting and impor- tions, shows that they share several basic
tant characteristics of its behavior. Examples characteristics. Most of them depart from the
assumption of profit maximization in the
3For leads into the literature, see March and Simon; short run, and replace it with an assumption
March; Johnsen; J. M. Dutton and W. H. Starbuck.
However, there are large numbers of specific case studies, 4In addition to simulations of the firm, there are very
some of them carried out as thesis projects, some interesting and potentially important efforts to use simu-
concerned with particular fields of business application, lation to build bridges directly from decision theory to
which have never been recorded in these reference political economy. See G. Orcutt and R. Caldwell-
sources (for example, Eliasson, 1976). Wertheimer, and Eliasson (1978).

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 509

of goals defined in terms of targets that is, that-before we draw policy conclusions from
they are to greater or lesser degree satisficing our theories, and particularly before we act on
theories. If they do retain maximizing those policy conclusions-we carry out sensi-
assumptions, they contain some kind of mech- tivity analyses to test how far our conclusions
anism that prevents the maximum from being would be changed if we made different
attained, at least in the short run. In the assumptions about the decision mechanisms
Cyert-March theory, and that of Leibenstein, at the micro level.
this mechanism can be viewed as producing If our conclusions are robust-if they are
"organizational slack," the magnitude of not changed materially by substituting one or
which may itself be a function of motivational another variant of the behavioral model for
and environmental variables. the classical model-we will gain confidence
Finally, a number of these theories assume in our predictions and recommendations; if
that organizational learning takes place, so the conclusions are sensitive to such substitu-
that if the environment were stationary for a tions, we will use them warily until we can
sufficient length of time, the system equilib- determine which micro theory is the correct
rium would approach closer and closer to the one.
classical profit-maximizing equilibrium. Of As reference to the literature cited earlier
course they generally also assume that the in this section will verify, our predictions of
environmental disturbances will generally be the operations of markets and of the economy
large enough to prevent the classical solution are sensitive to our assumptions about mech-
from being an adequate approximation to the anisms at the level of decision processes.
actual behavior. Moreover, the assumptions of the behavioral
The presence of something like organiza- theories are almost certainly closer to reality
tional slack in a model of the business firm than those of the classical theory. These two
introduces complexity in the firm's behavior facts, in combination, constitute a direct refu-
in the short run. Since the firm may operate tation of the argument that the unrealism of
very far from any optimum, the slack serves the assumptions of the classical theory is
as a buffer between the environment and the harmless. We cannot use the in vacua version
firm's decisions. Responses to environmental of the law of falling bodies to predict the
events can no longer be predicted simply by sinking of a heavy body in molasses. The
analyzing the "requirements of the situation," predictions of the classical and neoclassical
but depend on the specific decision processes theories and the policy recommendations
that the firm employs. However well this derived from them must be treated with the
characteristic of a business firm model corre- greatest caution.
sponds to reality, it reduces the attractiveness
of the model for many economists, who are V. Conclusion
reluctant to give up the process-independent
predictions of classical theory, and who do not There is a saying in politics that "you can't
feel at home with the kind of empirical beat something with nothing." You can't
investigation that is required for disclosing defeat a measure or a candidate simply by
actual real world decision processes. pointing to defects and inadequacies. You
But there is another side to the matter. If, must offer an alternative.
in the face of identical environmental condi- The same principle applies to scientific
tions, different decision mechanisms can theory. Once a theory is well entrenched, it
produce different firm behaviors, this sensi- will survive many assaults of empirical
tivity of outcomes to process can have impor- evidence that purports to refute it unless an
tant consequences for analysis at the level of alternative theory, consistent with the evi-
markets and the economy. Political economy, dence, stands ready to replace it. Such conser-
whether descriptive or normative, cannot vative protectiveness of established beliefs is,
remain indifferent to this source of variabilityindeed, not unreasonable. In the first place, in
in response. At the very least it demands empirical science we aspire only to approxi-

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
510 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

mate truths; we are under no illusion that we the more remote regions of the economic
can find a single formula, or even a moder- sciences? Is there then any reason why we
ately complex one, that captures the whole should give up the familiar theories? Have the
truth and nothing else. We are committed to a newer concepts of decision making and the
strategy of successive approximations, and firm shown their superiority "for purposes of
when we find discrepancies between theory economic analysis"?
and data, our first impulse is to patch rather If the classical and neoclassical theories
than to rebuild from the foundations. were, as is sometimes argued, simply powerful
In the second place, when discrepancies tools for deriving aggregative consequences
appear, it is seldom immediately obvious that held alike for both perfect and bounded
where the trouble lies. It may be located in rationality, we would have every reason to
the fundamental assumptions of the theory, retain them for this purpose. But we have
but it may as well be merely a defect in the seen, on the contrary, that neoclassical theory
auxiliary hypotheses and measurement postu- does not always lead to the same conclusions
lates we have had to assume in order to at the level of aggregate phenomena and
connect theory with observations. Revisions policy
in as are implied by the postulate of
these latter parts of the structure may be bounded rationality, in any of its variants.
sufficient to save the remainder. Hence, we cannot defend an uncritical use of
What then is the present status of the these contrary-to-fact assumptions by the
classical theory of the firm? There can no argument that their veridicality is unimpor-
longer be any doubt that the micro assump- tant. In many cases, in fact, this veridicality
tions of the theory-the assumptions of may be crucial to reaching correct conclu-
perfect rationality-are contrary to fact. It is sions about the central questions of political
not a question of approximation; they do not economy. Only a comparison of predictions
even remotely describe the processes that can tell us whether a case before us is one of
human beings use for making decisions in these.
complex situations. The social sciences have been accustomed
Moreover, there is an alternative. If to look for models in the most spectacular
anything, there is an embarrassing richnesssuccesses
of of the natural sciences. There is no
alternatives. Today, we have a large mass of harm in that, provided that it is not done in a
descriptive data, from both laboratory and spirit of slavish imitation. In economics, it has
field, that show how human problem solving been common enough to admire Newtonian
and decision making actually take place in a mechanics (or, as we have seen, the Law of
wide variety of situations. A number of theo- Falling Bodies), and to search for the
ries have been constructed to account for economic equivalent of the laws of motion.
these data, and while these theories certainly But this is not the only model for a science,
do not yet constitute a single coherent whole, and it seems, indeed, not to be the right one
there is much in common among them. In one for our purposes.
way or another, they incorporate the notions Human behavior, even rational human
of bounded rationality: the need to search for behavior, is not to be accounted for by a
decision alternatives, the replacement of handful of invariants. It is certainly not to be
optimization by targets and satisficing goals, accounted for by assuming perfect adaptation
and mechanisms of learning and adaptation. to the environment. Its basic mechanisms
If our interest lies in descriptive decision may be relatively simple, and I believe they
theory (or even normative decision theory), it are, but that simplicity operates in interaction
is now entirely clear that the classical and with extremely complex boundary conditions
neoclassical theories have been replaced by a imposed by the environment and by the very
superior alternative that provides us with a facts of human long-term memory and of the
much closer approximation to what is actually capacity of human beings, individually and
going on. collectively, to learn.
But what if our interest lies primarily in If we wish to be guided by a natural science
normative political economy rather than in metaphor, I suggest one drawn from biology

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 511

rather than physics (see Newell and Simon, Basis of Macroeconometric Models," paper
1976). Obvious lessons are to be learned from presented to the NSF-NBER Conference
evolutionary biology, and rather less obvious on Macroeconomic Modeling, Ann Arbor,
ones from molecular biology. From molecular Oct. 1978.
biology, in particular, we can glimpse a Chester 1. Barnard, The Functions of the Exec-
picture of how a few basic mechanisms the utive, Cambridge, Mass. 1938.
DNA of the Double Helix, for example, or the William Baumol, Business Behavior, Value and
energy transfer mechanisms elucidated so Growth, New York 1959.
elegantly by Peter Mitchell-can account for G. S. Becker, "Irrational Behavior and
a wide range of complex phenomena. We can Economic Theory," J. Polit. Econ., Feb.
see the role in science of laws of qualitative 1962, 70, 1-13.
structure, and the power of qualitative as well Charles P. Bonini, Simulation of Information
as quantitative explanation. and Decision Systems in the Firm, Engle-
I am always reluctant to end a talk about wood Cliffs 1963.
the sciences of man in the future tense. It Alfred Chandler, Strategy and Structure, Cam-
conveys too much the impression that these bridge, Mass. 1962.
are potential sciences which may some day be N. C. Churchill, W. W. Cooper, and T. Sainsbury,
actualized, but that do not really exist at the "Laboratory and Field Studies of the
present time. Of course that is not the case at Behavioral Effects of Audits," in C. P.
all. However much our knowledge of human Bonini et al., eds., Management Controls,
behavior falls short of our need for such New York 1964.
knowledge, still it is enormous. Sometimes we G. P. E. Clarkson, "A Model of the Trust
tend to discount it because so many of the Investment Process," in E. A. Feigenbaum
phenomena are accessible to us in the very and J. Feldman, eds., Computers and
activity of living as human beings among Thought, New York 1963.
human beings that it seems commonplace to John R. Commons, Institutional Economics,
us. Moreover, it does not always answer the Madison 1934.
questions for which we need answers. We R. M. Cyert, E. A. Feigenbaum, and J. G. March,
cannot predict very well the course of the "Models in a Behavioral Theory of the
business cycle nor manage the employment Firm," Behav. Sci., Apr. 1959, 4, 81-95.
rate. (We cannot, it might be added, predict and M. H. DeGroot, "Rational Expecta-
very well the time of the next thunderstorm in tions and Bayesian Analysis," J. Polit.
Stockholm, or manage the earth's climates.) Econ., May/June 1974, 82, 521-36.
With all these qualifications and reserva- and "Adaptive Utility," in R. H.
tions, we do understand today many of the Day and T. Groves, eds., Adaptive
mechanisms of human rational choice. We do Economic Models, New York 1975, 233-
know how the information processing system 46.
called Man, faced with complexity beyond his and James G. March, A Behavioral
ken, uses his information processing capaci- Theory of the Firm, Englewood Cliffs
ties to seek out alternatives, to calculate 1963.
consequences, to resolve uncertainties, and and H. A. Simon, "Theory of the Firm:
thereby-sometimes, not always-to find Behavioralism and Marginalism," unpub-
ways of action that are sufficient unto the lished work. paper, Carnegie-Mellon Univ.
day, that satisfice. 1971.
_ , and D. B. Trow, "Observation
of a Business Decision," J. Bus., Univ.
REFERENCES Chicago, Oct. 1956, 29, 237-48.
D. C. Dearborn and H. A. Simon, "Selective
A. A. Alchian, "Uncertainty, Evolution, and Perception: The Identifications of Execu-
Economic Theory," J. Polit. Econ., June tives,"' Sociometry, 1958, 21, 140-144;
1950, 58, 211-21. reprinted in Administrative Behavior, ch.
A. Ando, "On a Theoretical and Empirical 15, 3d ed., New York 1976.

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
512 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW SEPTEMBER 1979

J. M. Dutton and W. H. Starbuck, Computer Business Cycle," J. Polit. Econ., Dec. 1975,
Simulation of Human Behavior, New 83, 1113-44.
York 1971. _ , "On the Size Distribution of Business
G. Eliasson, Business Economic Planning, Firms," Bell J. Econ., Autumn 1978, 9,
New York 1976. 508-23.
, A Micro-to-Macro Model of the James G. March, Handbook of Organizations,
Swedish Economy, Stockholm 1978. Chicago 1965.
B. M. Friedman, "Optimal Expectations and and H. A. Simon, Organizations, New
the Extreme Information Assumptions of York 1958.
'Rational Expectations' Macromodels," J. Robin Marris, The Economic Theory of "Man-
Monet. Econ., Jan. 1979 5, 23-41. agerial" Capitalism, London 1964.
,_ "A Discussion of the Methodological Jacob Marschak, "Role of Liquidity under
Premises of Professors Lucas and Sargent," Complete and Incomplete Information,"
in After the Phillips Curve: The Persis- Amer. Econ. Rev. Proc., May 1949, 39,
tence of High Inflation and High Unem- 182-95.
ployment, Boston 1978. and Roy Radner, Economic Theory of
Milton Friedman, Essays in Positive Econom- Teams, New Haven 1972.
ics, Chicago 1953. Alfred Marshall, Principles of Economics, 8th
J. R. Hayes and H. A. Simon, "Understanding ed., New York 1920.
Written Problem Instructions," in W. E. S. Mason, "Comment," in Bernard T.
Gregg, ed., Knowledge and Cognition, Haley, ed., A Survey of Contemporary
Potomac 1974, 167-200. Economics, Vol. II, Homewood 1952, 221-
A. 0. Hirschman, Exit, Voice and Loyalty, 22.
Cambridge, Mass. 1970. J. M. Montias, The Structure of Economic
Charles C. Holt, Franco Modigliani, John F. Muth, Systems, New Haven 1976.
and Herbert A. Simon, Planning Production, J. F. Muth, "Rational Expectations and the
Inventories and Work Force, Englewood Theory of Price Movements," Econometri-
Cliffs 1960. ca, July 1961, 29, 315-53.
Y. Ijiri and H. A. Simon, Skew Distributions , "Optimal Properties of Exponentially
and the Sizes of Business Firms, Amster- Weighted Forecasts," J. Amer. Statist.
dam 1977. Assn., June 1960, 55, 299-306.
E. Johnsen, Studies in Multiobjective Decision R. R. Nelson, and S. Winter, "Toward an Evolu-
Models, Lund 1968. tionary Theory of Economic Capabilities,"
D. W. Jorgenson and C. D. Siebert, "A Compar- Amer. Econ. Rev. Proc., May 1973, 63,
ison of Alternative Theories of Corporate 440-49.
Investment Behavior," Amer. Econ. Rev., and , "Neoclassical vs. Evolu-
Sept. 1968, 58, 681-712. tionary Theories of Economic Growth,"
D. Kahneman and A. Tversky, "On the Psychol- Econ. J., Dec. 1974, 84, 886-905.
ogy of Prediction," Psychol. Rev., July Allen Newell and Herbert A. Simon, Human
1973, 80, 237-51. Problem Solving, Englewood Cliffs, 1972.
Janos Kornai, Anti-Equilibrium, Amsterdam and , "Computer Science as
1971. Empirical Inquiry: Symbols and Search,"
Howard Kunreuther et al., Disaster Insurance Communications of the ACM, Mar. 1976,
Protection: Public Policy Lessons, New 19,113-26.
York 1978. G. Orcutt, and R. Caldwells-Wertheimer II, Policy
Harvey Leibenstein, Beyond Economic Man, Exploration through Microanalytic Simu-
Cambridge, Mass. 1976. lation, Washington 1976.
J. Lesourne, A Theory of the Individual for A. Papandreou, "Some Basic Problems in the
Economic Analysis, Vol. 1, Amsterdam Theory of the Firm," in Bernard F. Haley,
1977. ed., A Survey of Contemporary Econom-
R. E. Lucas, Jr., "An Equilibrium Model of the ics, Vol. II, Homewood 1952.

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 69 NO. 4 SIMON: RATIONAL DECISION MAKING 513

E. H. Phelps-Brown, "The Meaning of the Econ. Rev., June 1959, 49, 223-83.
Fitted Cobb-Douglas Function," Quart. J. _ , "Discussion: Problems of Methodol-
Econ., Nov. 1957, 71, 546-60. ogy," Amer. Econ. Rev. Proc., May 1963,
R. Radner, (1975a) "A Behavioral Model of 53, 229-31.
Cost Reduction," Bell J. Econ., Spring , "From Substantive to Procedural
1975, 6, 196-215. Rationality," in Spiro J. Latsis, ed., Meth-
. (1975b) "Satisficing," J. Math. odological Appraisal in Economics, Cam-
Econ., June-Sept. 1975, 2, 253-62. bridge 1976.
David R. Roberts, Executive Compensation, , (1978a) "Rationality as Process and
Glencoe 1959. as Product of Thought," Amer. Econ. Rev.
P. A. Samuelson, "Discussion: Problems of Proc., May 1978, 68, 1-16.
Methodology," Amer. Econ. Rev. Proc., , (1978b) "On How to Decide What to
May 1963, 53, 231-36. Do," Bell J. Econ., Autumn 1978, 9, 494-
Henry Schultz, The Theory and Measurement 507.
of Demand, Chicago 1938. ,_ G. Kozmetsky, H. Guetzkow, and G.
Herbert A. Simon, Administrative Behavior, Tyndall, Centralization vs. Decentralization
New York 1947; 3d ed. 1976. in Organizing the Controller's Department,
,_ "A Formal Theory of the Employ- New York 1954; reprinted Houston 1978.
ment Relation," Econometrica, July 1951, and F. K. Levy, "A Note on the Cobb-
19, 293-305 Douglas Function," Rev. Econ. Stud., June
,_ "A Comparison of Organization 1963, 30, 93-94.
Theories," Rev. Econ. Stud., No. 1, 1952, G. J. Stigler, "The Economics of Information,"
20, 40-48. J. Polit. Econ., June 1961, 69, 213-15.
,_ "A Behavioral Model of Rational H. Theil, "A Note on Certainty Equivalence in
Choice," Quart. J. Econ., Feb. 1955, 69, Dynamic Planning," Econometrica, Apr.
99-118. 1957, 25, 346-49.
_ , "Rational Choice and the Structure
John von Neumann and Oscar Morgenstern,
of the Environment," Psychol. Rev., Mar. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior,
1956, 63, 129-38. Princeton 1944.
,"Dynamic Programming under Un- A. A. Walters, "Production and Cost Func-
certainty with a Quadratic Criterion Func- tions: An Econometric Survey," Economet-
tion," Econometrica, Jan. 1956, 24, 74- rica, Jan.-Apr. 1963, 31, 1-66.
81. Oliver Williamson, Markets and Hierarchies:
, Models of Man, New York 1957. Analysis and Antitrust Implications, New
,"The Compensation of Executives," York 1975.
Sociometry, 1957, 20, 32-35. S. Winter, "Satisficing, Selection, and the
_ , ""Theories of Decision Making in Innovating Remnant," Quart. J. Econ.,
Economics and Behavioral Science," Amer. May 1971, 85, 237-61.

This content downloaded from


132.248.9.8 on Wed, 28 Dec 2022 05:36:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like