Blots, Landscape and Image

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 19

Alexander Cozens's New Method: The Blot and General Nature

Author(s): Charles A. Cramer


Source: The Art Bulletin, Vol. 79, No. 1 (Mar., 1997), pp. 112-129
Published by: College Art Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3046232 .
Accessed: 12/09/2014 11:12

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

College Art Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Art
Bulletin.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Alexander Cozens's New Method:
The Blot and General Nature
CharlesA. Cramer

Born in 1717 to English parents in Peter the Great's Russia, influence on many of the most celebrated landscape artists of
Alexander Cozens was educated from the age of ten in the English tradition.
London, where he remained until a brief return to Russia in Cozens was the author of four major treatises on what could
the late 1730s or early 1740s.1 In 1746 he was among the first be called "practical aesthetics." In his treatise on The Shape,
English artists to go to Italy, where he studied under Claude- Skeleton and Foliage of Thirty-twoSpecies of Treesfor the Use of
Joseph Vernet. Between 1749 and 1754 Cozens was drawing Painting and Drawing (1771) he attempted to fix the basic
master to Christ's Hospital in London, and by the mid-1760s forms characterizing trees for the use of landscape painters.
he was at Eton, where he taught both Sir George Beaumont His Principles of Beauty Relative to the Human Head (1777-78)
and the famous autobiographer Henry Angelo. Although was an exemplar of expression, consisting mostly of nineteen
only nine oil paintings can be attributed to him with any plates, one showing the "Simple Beauty" of a woman in
certainty, Cozens exhibited regularly at the Society of Arts, the profile (Fig. 1) and the other eighteen showing various
Free Society of Artists, and the Royal Academy. It is not for his formal modifications to that profile that would serve to
finished oils, however, that Cozens is remembered today, but illustrate some specific "character" (for example, "The
for his drawings and theories, and for his direct or indirect Artful," Fig. 2). Another of his major treatises, The Various

---'
1/,,, ,7
:"?~ I

1 Alexander Cozens, SimpleBeauty,burin engraving, from 2 Cozens, TheArtful,burin engraving, from Principlesof Beauty,
Principlesof Beauty,London, 1777-78, pl. 1. New Haven, London, 1777-78, pl. 16. New Haven, Beinecke Rare Book and
Beinecke Rare Book and Manuscript Library,Yale University Manuscript Library,Yale University (photo: Beinecke Library)
(photo: Beinecke Library)

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 113

Speciesof Compositionof Landscape in Nature, has survived only appearance of the blots, to the exclusion of the theory of
in fragments. artistic process that produced their forms.7
Today, the best known of Cozens's theories is his descrip- Recent theoretical treatments have not been much more
tion of how to form landscape compositions starting from a successful. In a double fallacy, James B. Twitchell's Romantic
blot. This method was first published by Cozens in 1759 as An Horizons suggests that Cozens's method resulted from "youth-
Essay to Facilitate the Inventing of Landskips, Intendedfor Students ful impetuosity" (Cozens was already forty-two by the time he
in the Arts, and again with a more thorough theoretical first codified his system of blotting in 1759) and repeats the
apparatus in 1785 under the title A New Method of Assisting the commonplace assertion that "there is something singularly
Invention in Drawing Original Compositionsof Landscape.2 It is romantic about Cozens."8 Even Jean-Claude Lebensztejn, in
with the last-mentioned that I will be principally concerned his exhaustive "Introduction to the New Methodof Alexander
here. The blot (Figs. 3, 7, 8, 9) was a sort of first indication of a Cozens," finds it necessary to account for Cozens from
landscape, hastily produced in thick, black ink on white outside his "historical anchorage." Although meticulous in
paper, from which the artist could later elaborate a finished its primary research, Lebensztejn's first chapter concedes, "if
composition. In Cozens's own words, the blot is "swift," the object that we are attempting to situate is first and
"suggestive," "instantaneous," "accidental," "casual," and foremost an object of surprise, of eccentricity, we must not
"rude." Our eyes confirm these adjectives; his blots are forget that 'surprise' brings with it the depths [fond] in which
among the most surprising artistic products of the century. that object is anchored."' Cozens's work, it seems, is so
Both the method of blotting and the product seem utterly theoretically and formally suggestive that at any moment, with
anomalous to the contemporaneous context of the highly or perhaps without the intention of the historian, it evades the
rational classicism of the newly founded Royal Academy context of its own culture and turns up in other centuries and
under the presidency ofJoshua Reynolds. Indeed, the method other places.
and the product are only slightly less surprising when consid- I will argue here that it is possible to understand Cozens's
ered in the context of the highly inventive and fruitful school technique of blotting within its "historical anchorage," that
of British landscape painting around the turn of the century. of the burgeoning picturesque school of English landscape
Symptomatically, art historians have had the utmost diffi- and even that of the classically inclined Royal Academy. In
culty in dealing with Cozens and his blots, tending to displace fact, understanding the relation of the blot to contemporane-
them to nearly any period and culture other than his own.3 In ous British academic classicism-counterintuitive as it seems-
the 1950s in France, Henri Lemaitre asserted that "Alexander will help to restore to that most long-lived of Western art styles
Cozens's experiments of the 1740s and 50s presaged the art some of the adaptive flexibility that was certainly a condition
that we would later call 'abstract,' " and also cited the of its longevity. The displacement of Cozens from his classiciz-
influence of "the Far East" on his technique.4 Louis Hawes in ing culture is symptomatic of the tendency of modernism and
1969 compared Cozens's depictions of cloudy skies to "a modernist historiography to arrogate all formal innovation to
Clyfford Still canvas turned on its side.'"5 E. H. Gombrich and itself and its privileged history, leaving academic classicism an
Henri Zerner both linked the blots to the famous psychologi- improbably stale and spent art form for much of its life. My
cal test introduced by Hermann Rorschach in 1921, and reconsideration of Cozens in this article will center on the
Zerner complemented this anachronism by citing the roots of importance of what I will call the "techniques of generaliza-
Cozens's method in the seventeenth-century practice of tion" proper to classicism in the context of eighteenth-
Baroque artists who would "throw the first thoughts of their century empirical epistemology (the theory of knowledge).
compositions in masses of light and shade."6 The problem Cozens's New Method is a rather disjunctive mixture of very
underlying these anachronistic attempts to account for Coz- concrete technical issues (such as how to make drawing ink)
ens's work is the emphasis placed on the final formal and very abstruse philosophical issues (such as the nature of

The ideas in this essay are further elaborated in my Ph.D. dissertation, rule, although the context she explores is a very broad contemporaneous
"Formal Reduction and the Empirical Ideal, 1750-1914," intended for European debate on the semiotics of the accidental, and is perhaps less
completion by the summer of 1997. Unless otherwise indicated, translations aesthetic than scientific; Stafford, "Characters in Stones, Marks on Paper:
are mine. Enlightenment Discourse on Natural and Artificial Taches," ArtJournal, XLIV,
1. The following brief biography is based on Kim Sloan's extensive primary no. 3, 1984, 233-40.
research in her two-part "New Chronology for Alexander Cozens," Burlington 4. Henri Lemaitre, Lepaysage anglazs d l'aquarelle, 1760-1851, Paris, 1955, 11,
Magazzne, cxxvii, nos. 983 and 987, 1985, 70-75 and 354-63; and in her book 93-94.
Alexander and John Robert Cozens: The Poetry of Landscape, New Haven/London, 5. Louis Hawes, "Constable's Sky Sketches," Journal of the Warburg and
1986. Courtauld Instztutes,xxxII, 1969, 349 n. 20.
2. A transcription of Cozens's New Methodis available in Adolph Paul Oppe, 6. E. H. Gombrich, Art and Illuszon: A Study zn the Psychology of Pzctorial
Alexander andJohn RobertCozens,Cambridge, Mass., 1954, 165-87; in Joshua C. Representatzon,Princeton, N.J., 1989, 183; Henri Zerner, "Alexander Cozens et
Taylor, ed., Nineteenth-Century Theorzesof Art, Berkeley/Los Angeles/London, sa methode pour l'lnvention des paysages," L'Oeil, no. 137, 1966, 29, 32-33.
1987, 63-71; and in Jean-Claude Lebensztejn's L'art de la tache:Introductzond la 7. The methodological underpinnings of this article, which can broadly be
Nouvelle methode d'AlexanderCozens,Paris, 1990, 467-84 and plates. Citations seen as an attempt to describe "style" through a typology of artistic "process"
from the New Method in this essay are taken from Lebensztejn's text but will rather than a taxonomy of the final formal appearance of artistic "products,"
carry Cozens's page numbers (included in the margins of Lebensztejn's is suggested in Kendall L. Walton, "Style and the Products and Processes of
reprint). Lebensztejn's text is the preferable source, since it also includes Art," in The ConceptofStyle, ed. Berel Lang, rev. ed., Ithaca, N.Y./London, 1987,
reproductions of all the aquatint plates accompanying the original publication 72-103.
and a very extensive primary and secondary bibliography, which is invaluable 8. James B. Twitchell, RomantzcHorizons:Aspectsof the Sublimezn EnglzshPoetry
to the general scholarship of the eighteenth century as well as to the "Cozens and Pazntzng, 1770-1850, Columbia, Mo., 1983, 138, 157. The New Method,
problem." which Twitchell cites, was published when Cozens was sixty-eight.
3. Barbara Mana Stafford's work on Cozens is a significant exception to this 9. Lebensztejn (as in n. 2), 29.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
114 ART BULLETIN MARCH 1997 VOLUME LXXIX NUMBER 1

1167

-4,.

/ II? I 1%
.,..
Atb

b'- "C i YR s
.- -'1

%, 3 Cozens, A Blot,aquatint,
from New Method,London,
1785, pl. 37. New Haven,
Beinecke Rare Book and
Manuscript Library,Yale
University (photo:
Beinecke Library)

artistic genius). The concept of "generalization" links these methodological text. The printmaker made every attempt to
issues, describing Cozens's interventions in both issues of maintain the gestural origin of the marks and the thick liquid
technique (and hence form) and epistemological issues quality of their medium.
common also to contemporaneous academic classical art. The third step of Rule III suggests composing a large
number of blots from which to select "whenever you are
The "Blot," the "Sketch" and the Landscape Drawing disposed to make a composition of landscape from any one of
We will begin here with the technical aspects of Cozens's them" (24). The unfinished sketch after the blot is defined as
method in order to shift our emphasis from the blot as final "a landscape drawing without sky or keeping" (25 n). In
formal product to the blot as a stage in an overall artistic eighteenth- and nineteenth-century British criticism, keeping
process. We will then better be able to compare that process indicates the "subordination of lights" in a work (Cozens's
with the academic classical process and the picturesque definition, 29), or the transitional values that define mass and
process, even if its product seems at first sight incompatible unify the lighting of a work. Cozens's example of a sketch
with both. The technical aspects of blotting are outlined by
(Fig. 4, which is derived from the blot in Fig. 3) includes two
Cozens in five "Rules" following the epistemological appara-
ground planes defined by light to dark gradations that are not
tus of the New Method (20-31). Rule I describes how "to make established in the blot. This aspect of keeping is permitted
Drawing Ink." Rule II tells how "to make Transparent Paper," when forming a sketch from a blot, as detailed in the third
which would be laid over the blot to make the sketch based on
step of Rule IV. Once the original blot is dry, a new sheet of
its forms. Rule III gives instruction on how to make a blot,
semitransparent paper is placed on it. Starting with a nearly
Rule IV how to extrapolate the blot into a landscape sketch, black drawing ink, the practitioner should "consider which
and Rule V how to "finish" that sketch.
way the general light should come on the scene most
Cozens lists three steps to the formation of a blot in Rule
properly" (that is, from left to right, front to back, or vice
III. The first, "Possess your mind strongly with a [general] versa) and then should "make out and improve the light and
subject," is deferred by Cozens to "The Descriptions of the dark masses that appear in the first or fore ground of the
Kinds of Landscape Composition" (23 n), and we will also
blot," which is visible through the semitransparent paper.
consider it below. The second step is described as follows (23):
This step translates the original "accidental" forms of the blot
into the landscape components that they suggest: you should
2. Take a camel's hair brush, as large as can be conve-
" [study] every individual form with attention till you produce
niently used, dip it in a mixture of drawing ink and water
some proper meaning, such as the blot suggests." The
... and with the swiftest hand make all possible variety of
shapes and strokes upon your paper, confining the disposi- foreground color, once dry, should be reinforced and deep-
tion of the whole to the general subject in your mind. ened in parts-" (especially the trees and shrubs, &c.) "-with
a second pass of the brush, and then the ink should be
Fig. 3 is an aquatint of one such blot that accompanied his thinned a little with water and the "second ground" made

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 115

C b; At-

f-
~ (
i~?- Vz?I

~~'4k

IIF
?MIAIII

4 Cozens, A print,
representinga sketchmadeout
with a brush,from the
precedingblot,aquatint,
from New Method,London,
1785, pl. 38. New Haven,
Beinecke Rare Book and
Manuscript Library,Yale
University (photo:
Beinecke Library)

out, and so on for "the rest of the divisions or grounds in the Eighteenth-Century Classical Art Theory and Empirical
drawing" (26-27). Epistemology
Up to this point the sketch is broadly defined in black and Even contextualizing the blot as a moment in an overall
white. Although the reinforcement of certain areas and the process rather than isolating it as a final formal product, this
articulationof ground planes allow some definition of middle brief sketch of the technical aspects of Cozens's New Method
tones (keeping), the unfinished sketch appears mostly as a has raised several points that seem directly contrary to
series of stage flats.The drawing,or "finished sketch," is to be received notions of academic classical process. Perhaps the
made by adding the sky and the more subtle aspects of the most evident include the "suggestiveness" of form that
keeping, which serve to "destroyflatness" (30) and to unify mediates between the blot and the sketch (and "suggestion"
the atmosphere and lighting of all the ground planes. The is, of course, a major trope of the Romantic aesthetic) and the
process of "finishing" startswith the thinnest mixture of ink description of form through "masses" rather than the tradi-
and water,with which the practitioner is to "wash the whole tional classical terrain of "line." Nonetheless, Cozens's episte-
landscape [all the ground planes], except those parts which mological apparatus from the beginning is explicitly directed
are intended to be in the first degree of light." Once dry, this toward a contemporaneous classical aesthetic (2):
process is to be repeated as often as the ink will still mark the
paper, each time leaving more and more parts untouched; Composing landscapes by invention, is not the art of
and then a little more ink is to be added to the mixture and imitating individual nature; it is more; it is forming
the process repeated again. The overriding principle to this artificial representations of landscape on the general
Rule is that "whatevercolour or degree of shade is in use, principles of nature, founded in unity of character, which
retain it as long as you can; that is, shade as much of the is true simplicity; concentring in each individual composi-
drawingwith it as possible before you make the tint that is in tion the beauties, which judicious imitation would select
the cup darker" (28-30)-that is, work the whole of the from those which are dispersed in nature.10
composition, not the individual parts. The "finished sketch"
(Fig. 5) defines its forms purely through chiaroscuro, the Cozens's idea of "invention" is neither about the artist's
description of the masses and shapes of objects through value fantasy (the terrain of Romanticism) nor about "individual
alone (although the aquatint differentiates the texture of the nature" (the terrain of Realism), but about the "general
rocks with thick lines and breaks the masses of foliage with principles" of nature (the terrain of classicism). Unity, simplic-
thinner lines). ity, and the selection and concentrating of dispersed beauties

10. As Lebensztejn notes (ibid., 46), Cozens has in fact borrowed this then, the genealogy of this passage suggests how widespread and precisely
definition from William Burgh's commentary to the 1783 edition of William formulated the contrast between "individual" and "general" nature was by
Mason's poem "The English Garden." Although not Cozens's own words, the 1780s.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
116 ART BULLETIN MARCH 1997 VOLUME LXXIX NUMBER 1

"
,, /.',
, •,
o
...
:,.
• Or
. , . .. ,• ...
~ ?u..~

"• •:.
, , ,,

, ..• • . ,, .. •

"X~e1~5:'s ,,

5 Cozens, A print,
representingthesamesketch,
madeinto afinished drawing,
aquatint, from New Method,
London, 1785, pl. 39. New
Haven, Beinecke Rare
Book and Manuscript
Library,Yale University
(photo: Beinecke Library)

through "judicious" imitation is the aim of Cozens's new New Method against three specific causes to which "bad, or
method. Compare Reynolds's ideas of the "Grand Manner," indifferently good" artistic productions may be attributed
the highest style of art: (2-3):

If it has been proved that the Painter, by attending to the 1. To the deficiency of a stock of ideas originally laid up in
invariable and general ideas of Nature, produce [s] beauty, the mind, from which might be selected such as suit any
he must, by regarding minute particularities, and acciden-
particular occasion;
tal discriminations, deviate from the universal rule, and
2. To an incapacity of distinguishing and connecting ideas
pollute his canvass [sic] with deformity." so treasured up;
[The artist's] eye being enabled to distinguish the acciden- 3. To a want of facility, or quickness, in execution; so that
tal deficiencies, excrescences, and deformities of things, the composition, how perfect soever in conception, grows
from their general figures, he makes out an abstract idea of faint and dies away before the hand of the artist can fix it
their forms more perfect than any one original. ... upon the paper, or canvas.
Thus it is from a reiterated experience, and a close
comparison of the objects in nature, that an artist becomes The three periods of artistic pedagogy outlined in Reynolds's
possessed of the idea of that central form, if I may so second Discourse (delivered in December 1769) are nearly
express it, from which every deviation is deformity.'2 identical: 1) learning "the rudiments": "the power of draw-
ing, modelling, and using colours"; 2) amassing a "stock of
[P]erfect form is produced by leaving out particularities,
and retaining only general ideas. (4, 57) ideas" from "perfections which lie scattered among various
masters," which are later to be "combined and varied as
Is Cozens's insistence on the "general" as opposed to the occasion may require"; and, finally, 3) (conditional) "emanci-
"particular" in nature a mere concession to the rhetoric of pation," in which the student learns "to discriminate perfec-
the time, designed to lend ethosto his method, or did Cozens tions that are incompatible with each other" (2, 25-27).
truly direct that method toward what we could understand as Curiously, for both theorists, only one of the three aspects of
a classical aesthetic? The answer to this question is best pedagogy seems to pertain specifically to art. The other two
explored through a consideration of the pedagogical and are the domain of epistemology, or what the eighteenth
epistemological underpinnings of British academic classi- century called "human understanding": for both theorists,
cism, and particularly through the widespread calls for the art product must be created by a mind possessed of a
"generalization" in art and epistemology. "stock of ideas," which it is capable of properly "distinguish-
Cozens's pedagogical aims closely parallel those of Rey- ing" and "combin[ing]" (or "distinguishing and connect-
nolds's three "periods" of artistic study. Cozens directs his ing" and "discriminat[ing]") and from which might be

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 117

"selected" (or "combined and varied") such ideas as "occa- jingling of words that will not be accounted folly."'15 In
sion may require" (or "as suit any particular occasion"). general, any discursive or aesthetic technique that operates
Indeed, for eighteenth-century British empirical epistemol- additively, on the "likeness" of objects or forms, is denigrated
ogy in general, the ability of "distinguishing and connecting" (at least in epistemological, if not in aesthetic consider-
ideas from a "stock of ideas originally laid up in the mind" ations), while techniques that operate subtractively, carefully
defines the minimum parameters of rationality. John Locke, establishing "difference," are lauded. Indeed, for Locke
in his highly influential Essay ConcerningHuman Understanding (among others), the faculty of the additive "wit" is the cause
(1690), had outlined three basic functions that the mind of both errors and madness, the opposites of rational under-
could apply to perceived reality (particular nature). The role standing: "Mad Men ... having joined together Ideas very
of these functions was to "sort" perceptions into an ordered wrongly... mistake them for truths."'16This creates a "disor-
"stock of general ideas," which constitutes knowledge. The derly jumbling" (2, 11, 13, 161) in the stock of ideas in the
first thing the mind must do is "discern" a given idea or sense mind, which, Locke elsewhere notes, "gives Sence [sic] to
impression from the welter of contextual ideas and/or Jargon, Demonstration to Absurdities, and Consistency to
impressions.'" "Discerning" gives the mind a "simple idea," Nonsense, and is the foundation of the greatest, I had almost
the fundamental unit of empirical epistemology. Once this said, of all the Errors in the World" (2, 33, 18, 401).
has been achieved, the mind can do only one of two things: it As the philosophers' metaphors suggest (the "additive"
can put ideas together through the additive faculty of "wit" or and "subtractive" functions of the mind, the "jumbling" of
separate them out through the subtractive faculty of "judg- ideas), the contemporaneous theory of the operation of the
ment" (2, 11, 2, 156): mind was largely materialist. Ideas were said to arise through
the physical stimulus of perception and were "stored" in the
Wit l[ies] most in the assemblage of Ideas, and putting mind in fluid "sacs" of "animal spirits" or at the nodes of a
those together with quickness and variety, wherein can be network of nervous fibers. In turn, these ideas were thought
found any resemblance or congruity, thereby to make up to be connected through the stimulation of certain of these
pleasant Pictures, and agreeable Visions in the Fancy: sacs or nodes, causing the "animal spirits" to run from one
Judgment, on the contrary, lies quite on the other side, in node to another, or causing a distribution of tensions in the
separating carefully, one from another, Ideas, wherein can network of nervous fibers, making up "trains of thought."17
be found the least difference, thereby to avoid being The eighteenth century formulated a distinct branch of
misled by Similitude, and by affinity to take one thing for epistemology that explored the way in which "trains" of ideas
another. could be connected through the additive faculty of "wit,"
piloted by the subtractive "judgment," in a way more or less
There is a qualitative as well as functional difference between conducive to rationality and to aesthetic process: the doctrine
the two faculties: although it makes "pleasant Pictures" of associationism. First formulated by Hobbes in his epistemo-
through its additive operation, wit "misleads"; it is judgment logical-political treatise Leviathan (1651), associationism took
that carries the burden of "carefully" establishing truth. This on increasing importance to the critical and aesthetic thought
qualitative difference between "wit" (associated with the of the subsequent century, as WalterJackson Bate noted in his
"fancy" or "imagination") and "judgment" is the foundation seminal text From Classic to Romantic:
of much eighteenth-century criticism and aesthetic theory.
The psychological criticism of this period was either
Concomitant with the mistrustful attitude toward "wit" is the
determined or, more often, strongly colored by the doc-
denigration of metaphor (which explains one object through trine of "the association of ideas"; it may be questioned,
reference to another with which it has some resemblance) as a
indeed, whether any philosophical or psychological doc-
highly suspicious if also highly pleasing rhetorical device.14 trine has since permeated critical thought in so great a
The poetic devices of alliteration and punning (which oper-
ate on the formal similarities among words) are similarly degree as did that of the association of ideas at this time.'8
regarded with suspicion: Thomas Hobbes remarks that in Martin Kallich has most thoroughly traced the extensive
formal contexts, and outside familiar company, "there is no influence of associationism from its roots in empirical episte-

11.Joshua Reynolds, Letter to the Idler, no. 82, Nov. 10, 1759, reprinted in "wit") can please by adorning discourse, "without steadiness, and direction to
Reynolds, Dzscourses,London, 1992, 358 (app. B). some end, a great fancy is one kind of madness. .. ." Cf. also Etienne Bonnot,
12. Reynolds, Discourse 3, 44-45. Further references to the Dzscourseswill be abb6 de Condillac, Essai sur l'origine des connoissances humaines (1746), bk. 1,
cited in the body of the text with a figure indicating the particular discourse chap. 2, sec. 34, in Oeuvresphilosophiquesde Condillac, I, Paris, 1947, 18: the man
followed by Wark's page numbers. whose wit is too strong "will have too much memory and too much
13. Locke, bk. 2, ch. 11, sec. 1, 155-63. Further references to Locke's Essay imagination. ... He will barely have the ability to reflect; he will be a fool
will occur in the text, in the form (2, 11, 1, 155-63). Locke points out that [fou]."
sense impressions are also epistemologically to be considered ideas, since 17. Instances of this type of explanation include: ("animal spirits") Rene
despite their presumed extramental origin we really know them only as they Descartes's Les passions de l'me, Amsterdam/Paris, 1649; and ("pressing")
appear to our minds. Hobbes's Leviathan, London, 1651. The most thorough subsumption of
14. For example, Oliver Goldsmith, in his essay "On the Use of Metaphors," aesthetic considerations to this materialist philosophy ("nervous fibers") is
notes that while metaphor can be used with "almost every verb, noun that of Edmund Burke, A Philosophical Enquzry znto the Origin of Our Ideas of the
substantive, or term of art ... with admirable effect," its extreme is hazardous: Sublime and Beautzful (London, 1757), rev. ed., London, 1759, althoughJoseph
"the danger is in sowing metaphors too thick, so as to distract the imagination Addison had already considered the operation of Cartesian "animal spirits" in
of the reader, and incur the imputation of deserting nature, in order to hunt aesthetic phenomena in his essays "The Pleasures of the Imagination,"
after conceits"; Works,I, NewYork/Chicago, 1837, 301-2. Spectatornos. 411-21,June 21-July 3, 1712.
15. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, Indianapolis, 1994, bk. 1, chap. 8, 40. 18. Walter Jackson Bate, From Classzc to Romantic: Premises of Taste zn
16. Cf. ibid., bk. 1, chap. 8, 39- while "fancy" (Hobbes's technical term for Eighteenth-CenturyEngland, New York/London, 1961, 96.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
118 ART BULLETIN MARCH 1997 VOLUME LXXIX NUMBER I

mology to its popular application by such critics as Isaac Watts, 395-96). Determining the difference between the two formed
George Turnbull, Henry Home (Lord Kames),James Beattie, a large part of the eighteenth-century epistemological project.
Alexander Gerard, Archibald Alison, and FrancisJeffrey.'9 Tristram's "animal spirits"-and hence his text-have
It is to this context of "associationism" that Cozens's and been set a-going through a particularly disjunctive association
Reynolds's insistence on the proper "connections" of ideas of ideas. His father had formed the habit of winding the clock
must be related. Since our main concern here is with aesthetic on the same night of the month that he made love to his wife.
practice, we will consolidate and explore the relevance of As a result of her husband's odd association of these ideas in
associationism to both the production of art and to contempo- the dubiously rational category of "family concernments,"
raneous assessments of the mind's basically antirational ten- Tristram's "poor mother could never hear the said clock
dencies through that most famous of associationist texts, wound up, but the thoughts of some other things unavoidably
Lawrence Sterne's Life and Opinions of TristramShandy (pub- popped into her head-& vice versa."21At the climax of Mr.
lished in installments between 1759 and 1767). The very first Shandy's lovemaking, then, Mrs. Shandy pops out with the
chapter contains a covert reference to Locke's doctrine of apparently unrelated question, "Pray, my dear ... have you
associationism and cites rampant associationism as the cre- not forgot to wind up the clock?" Mr. Shandy is startled, and
ative device behind the text: as a result, the "animal spirits" that were to conduct Tris-
tram's preembryonic "HOMUNCULUS" to its place of recep-
... you have all, I dare say, heard of the animal spirits, and tion were "scattered and dispersed." The homunculus ar-
how they are transfused from father to son &c. &c.-and a rived at its destination "ruffled beyond description,-and ...
great deal to that purpose:-Well, you may take my word, in this sad and disordered state of nerves, he had laid down a
that nine parts in ten of a man's sense or his nonsense, his prey to sudden starts, or a series of melancholy dreams and
successes and miscarriages in this world depend upon their fancies for nine long, long months together."'22 Again, the
motions and activity, and the different tracts and trains you joke is related to Locke's pedagogy, where dire results were
put them into, so that when they are once set a-going, said to attend on the improper association of ideas, and it was
whether right or wrong, 'tis not a halfpenny matter,-away accordingly the responsibility of the parents "diligently to
they go cluttering like hey-go-mad; and by treading the watch, and carefully to prevent the undue Connexion of Ideas
same steps over and over again, they presently make a road in the Minds of young People" (2, 33, 18, 401). The startlingly
of it, as plain and smooth as a garden-walk, which, when disjunctive association, inculcated at such an unfortunately
they are once used to, the Devil himself sometimes shall formative moment, resulted in Tristram's own permanent
not be able to drive them off it.20 state of distraction and hence in his digressive style.
Tristram Shandy, of course, is a fictional text, but the
Anyone who has read TristramShandy will confirm that the complex stance toward and knowledge of associationism
narrative trajectory is as "cluttering" and "hey-go-mad" as required for appreciating it establishes at once the logical
"animal spirits ... set a-going." Tristram is not even born extreme of and the general cultural knowledge of the
until the fourth book of the serial publication, as he is "associationist problem." The issue is one of "distraction"
constantly distracted by the sidetracks and groundwork neces- and the fundamental tendency of the mind to make multiple
sary to explain his odd stance toward life and narrative. The irrational leaps, especially when the (additive) "fancy" is
text is a precise index of the "disorderlyjumbling" (as Locke uncontrolled by the (subtractive) "judgment." It is in direct
put it) of Sterne/Shandy's random mental associations. relation to the associationist problem that we should under-
Significantly, Tristram's odd stance toward narrative is stand the need to generalize our ideas, which, as we have
specifically located to an exaggerated Lockean crisis of seen, both Reynolds and Cozens emphasize.
associationism. The last phrase of the above citation is directly This necessity is predicated first of all on the overabun-
derived from Locke's Essay ConcerningHuman Understanding dance and fundamental particularity of sense data and
(2, 33, 6, 396): "simple ideas." As Locke noted (2, 32, 6, 385-86),

Custom settles habits of Thinking in the Understanding The natural tendency of the Mind being toward Knowl-
... which seems to be but Trains of Motion in the Animal edge; and finding that, if it should proceed by, and dwell
Spirits, which once set a going continue on in the same upon only particular Things, its Progress would be very
steps they have been used to, which by often treading are slow, and its Work endless: Therefore to shorten its way to
worn into a smooth path, and the Motion in it becomes Knowledge, and to make each Perception the more com-
easy and as it were Natural. prehensive; the first Thing it does, as the Foundation of
the easier enlarging its Knowledge, either by Contempla-
There is a dangerous similarity between the "as it were tion of the things themselves, that it would know; or
Natural" connections of ideas that are the result of mere conference with others about them, is to bind them into
"custom" and Locke's just previous (but largely unexplored) Bundles, and rank them so into sorts, that what Knowledge
assertion that some ideas are "ally'd by Nature" (2, 33, 5, it gets of any of them, it may thereby with assurance extend

19. See Martin Kallich, The Assoczatzon of Ideas and Critzcal Theory zn 644-67; and "The Argument against the Association of Ideas in Eighteenth-
England. A Hzstoryof a PsychologicalMethod in Englzsh Critzctsm,
Ezghteenth-Century Century Aesthetics," Modern Language Quarterly, xv, 1954, 125-36. Mv one
The Hague, 1970. See also Kallich's articles "The Associationist Crisis of major objection to Kallich's work is that he fails to allow for the incorporation
Frances Hutcheson and David Hume," Studzes zn Phzlology,XLIII,no. 4, 1946, of "associationism" into "classical" aesthetics: he only grudgingly and in

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 119

to all of that sort; and so advance by larger steps in that, sentatives of all of the same kind, and their Names general
which is its great Business, Knowledge. This, as I have Names, applicable to whatever exists conformable to such
elsewhere shewed, is the Reason, why we collect Things abstract Ideas.
under comprehensive Ideas, with Names annexed to them
into Generaand Species;i.e. into kinds, and sorts. Even though its primary aim is (additively) to "bundle"
similar simple ideas under the aegis of a representative type,
The "particular" ideas of sensation are variously grouped and the "abstractive" formation of the general idea is founded on
ranked into more comprehensive ideas; it is only thus that an the process of subtraction-the subtraction of contextual
inductive knowledge of horses-in-general can be achieved in ideas and of accidental and contingent qualities from the
lieu of the particular habits and form of every specific horse.
perceived object. We are not concerned here with the names
By means of this "bundling," various levels of knowledge can used to mark such general/abstract ideas-the name is
be reached. Fig. 6 shows a graphic representation of how the
arbitrary (as Locke recognized), and thus there is no motiva-
mind can impose a structure of general categories on its tion obtaining between signifier (word) and signified (gen-
ideas, a structure corresponding to the general order of eral idea) in verbal language, and therefore there is no
nature that underlies the particular perceived instances. The motivation between the signifier (word) and the referent
mind at its most basic level is a disorderly jumble of current
(general nature). The case is otherwise for the visual arts,
sense impressions and the random associative deflections where there can be conformity between the signifier (visual
arising out of those sense impressions. The duty of the mind is re-presentation) and the signified (idea), inasmuch as the
to re-form that chaotic network of ideas into a rational
signified is itself visual, and therefore between the signifier
pyramid of levels of knowledge, by first discerning distinct (visual representation) and the referent (general nature, or
ideas from the complex wholes of sense perceptions, then the ideal). Along these lines it is significant that Locke notes
regrouping similar ideas into bundles and ranks presided that abstract ideas "are in the Mind such Appearances." The
over (as we shall see) by "general ideas" that represent the name marks the appearance of the image-based abstract/
distilled essence of the ideas falling under a given category.
general idea; nor is this appearance vague and equivocal (2,
The categories "species, genus, family," and so on, utilized in 11, 9, 159):
the binomial taxonomy of the eighteenth-century Swedish
scientist Carl von Linnaeus, were used by Locke to rank other Such precise, naked Appearances in the Mind, without
sorts of ideas as well. Thus, the red of a particular piece of
considering, how, whence, or with what others they came
cloth is a simple idea; it is part of the "species" red, which is
there, the Understanding lays up (with Names commonly
part of the "genus" color, which is part of the "family" annexed to them) as the Standards to rank real [i.e.,
quality, and so on (see 3, 4, 16, 428). particular] Existences into sorts [i.e., general ideas], as
In the pursuit of knowledge, the mind will refer to its
they agree with these Patterns [i.e., the image-based
"general ideas" rather than to any given particular idea or to ideas]....
an exhaustive survey of all similar particular ideas. Now the
question becomes: How does the mind form the "general The "general idea," according to Locke, is formed by the
ideas" that are the ambassadors of a bundle of similar
process of subtraction and is stored as an image in the mind.
"particular ideas"? The formation of general ideas of what- (Indeed, the image-based model of the idea in eighteenth-
ever referential level is predicated on the function of "abstrac-
tion." The following passage from Locke shows the relation century epistemology is one of the most persistent and
characteristic tenets of the philosophy of the period.) It is on
between "abstraction" and the "general ideas" that are
this limited collection of "general ideas" and the relatively
necessary to broaden empirical knowledge and gives us an fewer, and more controlled, associative deflections possible at
idea of how the function of abstraction operates on the data
the higher levels of the referential pyramid that rational
of the senses (2, 11, 9, 159):
epistemology and rational art are predicated.
The use of Words then being to stand as outward Marks of
our internal Ideas, and those Ideas being taken from Reynolds's Theory of "Generalization"
particular things, if every particular Idea that we take in, and the Problem of Associationism
would have a distinct Name, Names must be endless. To Reynolds essentially took over this epistemology and applied
prevent this, the Mind makes the particular Ideas, received it to a cogent art theory founded on "generalization"-again,
from particular Objects, to become general; which is done specifically responsive to the dangers of "associationism"--in
by considering them as they are in the Mind such Appear- which the only remaining problem is the "fixing" of the
ances, separate from all other Existences, and the circum- general idea on the canvas, a process that for Reynolds was
stances of real Existence, as Time, Place, or any other largely mechanical. We have already noted that his three-stage
concomitant Ideas. This is called ABSTRACTION,whereby pedagogy is concerned more with issues of "human under-
Ideas taken from particular Beings, become general Repre- standing" than with issues of technique. Reynolds explicitly

passing notes that "it must be admitted, the psychology only reinforced 21. Ibid., bk. 1, chap. 4, 39.
neoclassic rules of cnticism and standards of taste" (Association of Ideas, 34). 22. Ibid., bk. 1, chap. 2, 36-37.
20. Lawrence Sterne, The Life and Opznions of Trstram Shandy, New
York,1985bk 1, chap. 1, 35.,

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
120 ART BULLETIN MARCH 1997 VOLUME LXXIX NUMBER 1

etc. attention, and to counteract his great design of speaking to


the heart. (3, 50)

family etc. The attention should never be drawn aside by trifles. (4,
general 69)
nature
genus etc. The mind is apt to be distracted by a multiplicity of objects;
and that scale of perfection which I wish always to be
species species preserved, is in the greatest danger of being totally
disordered, and even inverted. (5, 77)
bundleof'simpleideas' bundleof 'simpleideas' particular
S nature(s.i.= The detail of particulars, which does not assist the expres-
.. s..
s.i. s.. sense-
s. s.. s.. s.i.
s..
impression) sion of the main characteristick, is worse than useless, it is
s.i. s.i. s.i. s.i. s.i.
s.i. s.i. s.i. mischievous, as it dissipates the attention, and draws it
s.i.
from the principal point. (11, 192)
6 Diagram of the organization of "particular nature" into
Indeed, the concept of "General Ideas" is "the presiding
"general nature" according to taxonomic "general ideas"
principle which regulates every part of Art" (4, 5). It is for this
reason that ideas of "general nature" are of crucial impor-
tance to Reynolds's theory, and to the eighteenth-century
applies the Lockean concept of "abstraction" to his theory of desires for a rational epistemology and a rational art. Follow-
the generalization of form (3, 50): ing Reynolds and the eighteenth-century empirical philoso-
phers, I am contrasting "general nature" with the "particular
[The Grand Manner painter] will permit the lower painter, nature" that is formed by sense perception and is problemati-
like the florist or collector of shells, to exhibit the minute
cally inflected by the (usually) irrational metonymic deflec-
discriminations, which distinguish one object of the same tions of the associationist mind. General nature is the truth;
species from another; while he, like the philosopher, will and the art that exhibits it is valuable inasmuch as it helps to
consider nature in the abstract,and represent in every one consolidate and order the "disorderly jumble" of particular
of his figures the character of its species [emphasis added]. nature in the public's mind.
And for Reynolds, this function of abstraction/generalization
is explicitly mobilized against the problems of associationism.
Cozens's Epistemology:
The goal of art is to help the audience to control the mad,
The Blot and "The Art of Seeing Properly"
disjunctive metonymic deflections of the stimulated stock of Above, I have suggested a way of understanding the classicism
ideas. His advice to the artist to learn from privileged past
of the late-eighteenth-century British Royal Academy that is
artworks (6, 99-100) is aimed not simply at adding to the
not transhistorical but highly specific to contemporaneous
"stock of ideas" but also at reducing that stock to a more
limited and controlled distillation: epistemological concerns. The empirical concept of "general-
ization" preserves many of the traditional aims of classical
A mind enriched by an assemblage of all the treasures of art-its supposedly cross-cultural and transhistorical ontologi-
ancient and modern art, will be more elevated and fruitful cal status (as we subtract out the contingent data of time and
in resources, in proportion to the number of ideas which place), its postulate of improving the audience of art, and
have been carefully collected and thoroughly digested.... even its insistence on formal simplicity-but at the same time
The addition of other men's judgment is so far from it is a highly temporally and culturally specific description of
how to meet those aims. With this redescription of the idea of
weakening our own, as is the opinion of many, that it will
classicism in late-eighteenth-century Britain, we can better
fashion and consolidate those ideas of excellencewhich lay in
understand the historical intent of Cozens's method of
embryo,feeble, ill-shaped,and confused,but which are finished
and put in order by the authority and practice of those blotting.
whose works may be said to have been consecrated by As in Reynolds's Discourses,issues of human understanding-
the ability of the mind to distinguish and select such ideas as
having stood the test of ages [emphasis added].
suit any particular occasion-are given a central place in
Art's object is thus to teach the audience (the general public Cozens's pedagogy. After explaining what a blot is and how
as well as the tyro artist) to "fashion and consolidate" the the idea of blotting came to him (through a casual elabora-
particular, empirical contents of their minds. The artist is to tion of stains on a piece of paper, a practice later validated by
produce images of "general nature," which teach the audi- his reading of Leonardo's observations on wall stains), Coz-
ence the scope and application of "general ideas," as op- ens returns to his three "problems" (12-13):
posed to images of "particular nature," which merely contrib-
ute to and stimulate random associative deflections. This, ... to each of these defects, the art of blotting, here
then, is why Reynolds constantly inveighs against the "particu- explained, affords, in some degree, a remedy. For it
lar" in art: increases the original stock of picturesque ideas;
It soon enables the practitioner to distinguish those
[The painter will not] waste a moment upon those smaller which are capable of being connected, from those which
objects which only serve to catch the sense, to divide the seem not naturally related; and

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 121

It necessarily gives a quickness and freedom of hand in so on to the largest. The curious spectator of landscape
expressing the parts of a composition, beyond any other insensibly acquires a habit of taking notice, or observing all
method whatever. the parts of nature, which is strengthened by exercise. It
may be perceived, that the application of this notice in
Let us consider these three achievements separately. The first youth is directed to the smaller parts ... from which it is
relates the art of blotting to the "picturesque"-a connection gradually transferred to the larger as we approach to age,
we shall consider below. The third relates to the formal at which time we generally take notice of whole composi-
appearance of the blot, its gestural "swiftness" and "rude- tions. By the means of this propensity we lay up a store of
ness," which we are ultimately attempting to account for ideas in the memory, from whence the imagination selects
within the context of the contemporary classical aesthetic of those which are best adapted to the nature of her opera-
"generalization." We shall here consider how that odd form is tions. All the particular parts of each object may not be
conducive to the solution of Cozens's second problem, the preserved in the memory, yet general ideas of the whole
empirical/associationist issue of the due "connections" and may be thrown as it were into the repository, and there
"relations" of ideas. retained.
Cozens's first step to the formation of the blot, we will
recall, was, "Possess your mind strongly with a [general] What Cozens is describing is the formation of the rational
subject." The beginning artist, who may not be possessed of a mind, which starts with particular ideas of "parts" (toward
"general subject," is referred by Cozens to his "Descriptions which the mind of youth is naturally directed) and progres-
of the Kinds of Landscape Composition," a series of sixteen sively forms larger ideas of "wholes," for example, gradually
aquatints appended to the end of the New Method.These types relating and subsuming the minutiae of leaves to the general
represent the minimal degree of "design" that is to be pattern of their forms and growth on a branch, and then the
introduced in the making of the blot. Although Cozens does pattern of branches to the general form of the tree, and so on,
not explicitly cite the problem, a more spontaneous blot until the idea of the (compositional) "whole" of a species of
would probably center itself on the page, avoiding the landscape is reached that is adequate to but does not
edges-not an easy beginning for a landscape composition. enumerate its individual parts. Reynolds implies the same
So the sixteen "Descriptions of the Kinds of Landscape gradual attainment of rationality through the formation of
Composition ... will be of use in furnishing the mind with an the subtractive 'judgment." Whereas in the second period of
idea of a subject" (24 n). Perhaps the most remarkable aspect study, the amassing of a "stock of ideas," the student "must
of these "kinds" is the generality that they represent, which is still be afraid of trusting his own judgment," the third period
highly referentially inclusive. Type nine, for example (Fig. 7), marks the conditional emancipation from authority: the
is described as "Two hills, mountains, or rocks, near each student may "confid[e] now in his own judgment" (2, 26).
other" (32). The words chosen to define the forms on the This emancipation is conditional because the rules of art are
paper determine the significance of the details: if they are not to be dispensed with, they have simply been internalized;
mountains, the masses of light and dark represent huge areas the judgment has been trained; the rational ordering of ideas
of outcropping or vegetation; if they are rocks, then those has taken place; and the artist may be trusted to make valid
masses represent small geological strata or faults. As Cozens connections between general ideas.
asserts, the general forms of these blots, operating together However, where Reynolds's pedagogy is founded on the
with the intention to derive geomorphic objects from those "long, laborious" training of the judgment, after which the
forms, have "a direct tendency to recal [sic] landscape ideas" proper art product follows almost as a matter of course,
(16). Cozens's method offers more immediate gratification. Clearly,
Although they are obviously "general," then, it is this anyone can make a blot, and, as Cozens notes, the elaboration
suggestivenessof the blot that has offered the greatest impedi- of the blot into the finished landscape does not require any
ment to locating Cozens within his intellectual milieu. Since special capability. This is because such elaboration is an
"one artificial blot will suggest different ideas to different additive exercise easily performed by the fundamentally
persons" and, indeed, since "one and the same designer associationist mind; it does not require any of those difficult
likewise may make a different drawing from the same blot" "abstract" or "general ideas," but only particular ideas (16):
(11), then the blot can indeed be related to a Romantic
aesthetic of "suggestion." Or, if we posit a subconscious On the foregoing principles, very few can have reason to
motivation to the individual's interpretation of the blot, it is suspect in themselves a want of capacity sufficient to apply
related to the Rorschachian inkblot test. Although such the use of blotting to the practice of drawing, nor can they
associations hold out a seductive theoretical interest for be totally ignorant of the parts of composition in nature,
current thinkers, their historical validity is dubious. Cozens's for as they are previously prepared with ideas of parts, as
idea of the utility of the blot is thoroughly empirical and before proved, so [blotting] affords an opportunity of
explicitly designed to "order" the parts into their proper calling them forth.... Previous ideas, however acquired
"classes," as in Lockean empirical epistemology (14-15): (ofwhich every person is possessed more or less) will assist
the imagination in the use of blotting [i.e., in elaborating a
[I]t may be remarked, that there is to be discerned, in all composition from the blot]....
whole compositions in nature, a gradation of parts, which
may be divided into several classes; for instance, the class of Blotting succeeds in artificially fixing the whole, the general,
the smaller parts, the class of those larger dimensions, and to which the relatively unproblematic "stock of ideas of

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
122 ART BULLETIN MARCH 1997 VOLUME LXXIX NUMBER 1

7 Cozens, Twohills,
mountains,or rocks,neareach
otheraquatint, from New
Method,London, 1785, pl.
9. New Haven, Beinecke
Rare Book and Manuscript
Library,Yale University
(photo: Beinecke Library)

particular nature" can be referred. Indeed, Cozens describes general disposition of these masses, producing one compre-
the elaboration of the blot into the landscape drawing as the hensiveform [emphasis added]....
successive "embellishment and consolidation" of the work
Cozens always insists on this singularity of the idea or the
(13). "Embellishment" is doubtless performed when the
practitioner extrapolates landscape elements from the rude subject suggested by the blot, as indeed he must, for if the
forms of the blot (Rule IV); and "consolidation" when the same constituent mark in a blot were in the same mind at
once a group of trees and a fissure in a rock, then his blots
practitioner unifies the "keeping" of the work through
overall washes (Rule V). That the blot represents the crucial would be ineffective, associationist, and would produce non-
sense landscapes. This limited "suggestive" interpretation of
"general whole" is confirmed in Cozens's description of the
formation of the blot (6-7), where "the attention of the the blots is thoroughly compatible with the eighteenth-
performer must be employed on the whole, or the general century counterassociationist classical aesthetic as I am con-
form of the composition, and upon this only; whilst the struing it, for the blot does not suggest different ideas to the
subordinate parts are left to the casual motion of the hand." same mind at once (like punning, Hobbes's "jingling" of
There is always the danger, of course, that "the person is words) and thus confuse that mind, or constituent parts of
inclined to direct his thoughts to the object, or particular different wholes at once (like metaphor), and thus distract
the mind, stimulating an ever expanding web of less and less
parts, which constitute the scene or subject, as well as to the
general disposition of the whole." In itself, this "superabun- compatible associations. If it is justifiable to consider the
dance of design" is not bad, but it means that the drawing classical project of the time as a response to the dangers of
later to be made from the blot must be done "with judg- associationism to the discovery of the truth (a response best
ment"-that is, the performer has in this case destroyed the seen in the "classing" of objects into their "general" referen-
tial types), then Cozens's blots are consistent with that project.
very purpose of blotting, which is to serve the function of
Indeed, although the method requires no special capacities
judgment (or, rather, to elide its necessity).
Here we can confirm the basically classical tenor of Coz- or training on the part of the practitioner, Cozens argues that
ens's epistemology of blotting. The proper blot will exhibit it is thoroughly consonant with the principles of artistic
only one idea, one "whole" at a time, and thus there is no genius (17-20). He even avers that the practice of blotting
need to reduce its deflections through the subtractive judg- helps to form the rational mind: the "art of blotting" is
ment (17). "extremely conducive to the acquisition of a theory, which
will always conduct the artist in copying nature with taste and
A true blot is an assemblage of dark shapes or masses made propriety." He goes on to claim, "This theory is, in fact, the
with ink ... and likewise of light ones produced by the art of seeing properly" (13). The very practice of blotting
paper being left blank. All the shapes are rude and trains the eye to subsume the details of observed nature to the
unmeaning.... But at the same time there appears a "whole" of the composition. Reynolds's art process is thus

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 123

reversed: instead of gradually learning to "distinguish the blotting; that blotting is a subtractive process applied to
accidental deficiencies, excrescences, and deformities of copious, overly free expression; and, curiously, that although
things" through "long laborious" comparative observation of Swift notes that the Tale required only "a very few blots," it
particular parts (3, 44), the artist starts with the "general" would require "a year or two" to execute those blots-that is,
blot and learns to view particular nature as a blot and thus blotting is a long, laborious task.
reform its minute digressiveness. The practice of making In his Life ofJohnson,John Boswell suggests the exact place
physical blots enables the eye to blot "when taking views from of blotting in the production of the art product. Discussing
nature" (13-14): literary imposture, Boswell refers to a Mr. Eccles's appropria-
tion of Henry Mackenzie's novel A Man of Feelingfor his own.
In short, whoever has been used to compose landscapes by Eccles "had been at the pains" of providing fraudulent proof
blotting, can also draw from nature with practice. But he of his authorship in the form of a falsified manuscript
cannot arrive at a power of composing by invention, by the
transcribed from the finished text. As evidence of the mental
means of drawing views from nature, without a much
processes by which he supposedly authored the novel, Eccles's
greater degree of time and practice.
manuscript included "blottings, interlineations, and correc-
tions, that it may be shown to several people as an original.''26
Blotting is asserted by Cozens as an immediate, if slightly
surreptitious, way to teach the mind to "generalize" empirical Reynolds makes precisely the same triadic assessment of the
functions of the mind as they are applied to particular
objects (either the immediately perceived or the "stock of
ideas" in the memory).23 empirical data: the mind of the mature artist is "enabled to
distinguish the accidental deficiencies, excrescences, and
deformities of things, from their general figures ... [to] make
Classical Practice: The Blot as Technique of Generalization out an abstract idea of their forms more perfect than any one
The argument that I have presented above, which exposes the original" (3, 44). "Interlineation" is a tool applicable to
practice of blotting as a solution to the same associationist "deficient" nature; "correction" to "deformed" nature; and
problem as that which Reynolds was addressing in his theory "blotting" to "excrescent" nature.
of the Grand Manner, may account for Cozens's method in its The idea that the blot was applicable to the problem of
contemporaneous context-but the solution of blotting may overabundant "particular" nature and the excessive associa-
still seem surprising, eccentric, idiosyncratic to Cozens. This is tive deflections of the mind was not, then, idiosyncratic to
not so. Indeed, the contemporaneous meaning of to blotwas to Cozens but a current figure of speech at the time. In fact, we
edit, with strong emphasis on the subtraction of excess. The can also account for the painterly form of the blot with
first definition for the word in Samuel Johnson's Dictionary reference to contemporaneous art theory. Again, curiously, it
(1755) is metaphoric: "To obliterate; to make writing invis- is Reynolds who can illuminate Cozens's technique of general-
ible, by covering it with ink." Johnson illustrates the meaning ization through the formal attributes of the blot. I noted that
with a significant example from Alexander Pope, "Even one of the aspects of the blot that we would have to account
copious Dryden wanted, or forgot, / The last and greatest art, for was its painterliness-the definition of form through
the art to blot."24The OxfordEnglish Dictionary lists a specifi- visible brushwork, in this case, a brushwork of chiaroscuro.
cally eighteenth-century usage of blot as "an obliteration by The painterly chiaroscuro of the blot contradicts our received
way of correction." One of its examples (expanded here to ideas of the "linearity" and "transparency" of classical art,
give context) is from Jonathan Swift's "Author's Apology" to which should offer access to the realm of the ideal unprob-
his 1704 Taleof the Tub:
lematized by issues of the artist's handiwork.27 It was Heinrich
He [Swift] was then a young gentleman much in the world, Wolfflin who most thoroughly inculcated the view of classical
and wrote to the taste of those who were like himself; art as inevitably characterized by a "linear" and "multiplici-
therefore, in order to allure them, he gave liberty to his tous" (as opposed to the Baroque "painterly" and "unified")
formal appearance.28 In the eleventh Discourse, however,
pen, which might not suit with maturer years, or graver
characters, and which he could have easily corrected with a Reynolds follows a chain of reasoning connecting the smooth
very few blots, had he been master of his papers, for a year (W6lfflin's "linear") surface to a "minute" reality of parts
or two before their publication.25 (W6lfflin's "multiplicity"), which is a dangerous agent of
distraction, of associative deflection. Indeed, for Reynolds,
We recognize several motifs in these citations: that the the "high finish" of the linear paradoxically implies more
younger are pleased by more associative, particular, unblotted manual labor-is less transparent to higher reality-than a
texts, whereas the more mature appreciate the value of a good painterly generalization (11, 202):

23. Nor is the art of blotting confined in utility to the genre of landscape. referred to himself in the third person here.
Although Cozens does not elaborate on the thought, he notes (10), "I 26.John Boswell, The Lzfe of Johnson, Oxford, 1989, 300 (discussed in
conceive, that this method of blotting may be found to be a considerable reference to the year 1761).
improvement to the arts of design in general; for the idea or conception of any 27. I borrow the term "transparency," signifying the exclusion of all
subject, in any branch of the art, may be first formed into a blot. Even the evidence of handwork from the surface of the artwork, from Philippe Junod,
historical, which is the noblest branch of painting, may be assisted by it; Transparence et opaczti: Essaz sur les fondements thioriques de l'art moderne,
because it is the speediest and surest means of fixing a rude whole of the most Lausanne, 1976.
transient and complicated image of any subject in the painter's mind." 28. Heinrich W61fflin, KunstgeschichtlhcheGrundbegnffe, 1915; translated by
24. The reference is to Pope's "First Epistle of the Second Book of Horace." M. D. Hottinger in 1932 as Prznczplesof Art Hzstory. The Problemof theDevelopment
25.Jonathan Swift, The WorksofJonathan Swzft, x, London, 1883, 15; Swift of Style zn LaterArt, New York, 1950.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
124 ART BULLETIN MARCH 1997 VOLUME LXXIX NUMBER I

As [painting] is an art, [the ignorant] think they ought to The important thing for Reynolds is not what to represent but
be pleased in proportion as they see that art ostentatiously what to leave out: "When [the artist] knows his subject, he will
displayed; they will, from this supposition, prefer neatness, know not only what to describe, but what to omit: and this skill
high-finishing, and gaudy colouring, to the truth, simplic- in leaving out, is, in all things, a great part of knowledge and
ity, and unity of nature. wisdom" (11, 199). "Judgment" and the "skill in leaving
out"-aspects of fundamental necessity to eighteenth-
Here is a place, then, where the epistemological necessity of
century empirical epistemology in general, and to Reynolds's
"simplification"-a constant trope of the classical aes-
theory in particular-are best performed by a few elisive/
thetic-is connected to a formal product rather contrary to
comprehensive strokes.
our received ideas of the classical. It is possible, in other Curiously-and this fact is underrepresented in the scholar-
words, to speak of a painterly classical form; for Reynolds, the ship-contemporaneous criticism makes much of Reynolds's
expression of the "true, simple and unified whole" is best "painterliness." Thomas Warton's "Verses on Joshua Rey-
performed through a "few, well-chosen strokes" (11, 193- nolds's Painted Window at New-College Oxford" (1782) very
94): significantly singles out the handwork, the brushwork, as a
... the pleasure we receive from imitation is not increased major agent of that work's ability to "reform" the viewer from
the "capricious maze" (compare with the "associationist
merely in proportion as it approaches to minute and
detailed reality; we are pleased, on the contrary, by seeing problem") of traditional Gothic stained glass to the "chaste
ends accomplished by seemingly inadequate means.... Design" of Reynolds's classicism. The first lines of the poem
already contain a reference to Reynolds's hand (although the
Carry this principle a step further. Suppose the effect of author is at first reluctant to quit his seductive Gothic taste):
imitation to be fully compassed by means still more
inadequate; let the power of a few, well-chosen strokes, Ah, stay thy treacherous hand, forbear to trace
which supercede labour by judgment and direction [i.e., Those faultless forms of elegance and grace!
the direction of means to an end], produce a complete Ah, cease to spreadthe bright transparent mass,
impression of all that the mind demands in an object; we With Titian's pencil, o'er the speaking glass!
are charmed with such an unexpected happiness of execu- Nor steal, by strokesof art with truth combin'd,
tion The fond illusions of my wayward mind!
....
It is of the utmost significance to remark that here the [emphasis added]
visibility of the "few, well-chosen strokes" does not indicate Toward the end of the poem Warton, his mind reformed,
the manual labor of the painter, as is problematic in most
again returns to the brushwork:
Renaissance and academic classical "antimechanic" theories
of art and of the "liberal" status of the artist in society. Behold, [Beauty] prints upon the crystal plain,
Instead, these marks "supercede labour" (the labor evident With her own energy, th' expressive stain!
in "high-finishing") in favor of mental "judgment"-and we The mighty Master spreadshis mimic toil
will recall the subtractive function of the 'judgment" in More wide...
eighteenth-century epistemology. The application of paint While in the warm enamel Nature lives
can in this case be seen as a "directed" index of the mind's [emphasis added].29
judgment, as performing an elision of detail, as gliding over
or through the minute particularities or "accidents" overly- By the early nineteenth century, indeed, William Hazlitt was
able to trace a direct cause-and-effect relationship between
ing the "substantial" form of nature.
So a "few lines or touches" are not mere manual labor but the ideas expressed in Reynolds's Discoursesand the fact that
"the English school of painting is universally reproached by
are the act whereby the artist performs-and the visible
guarantor of the artist's formation of-"one whole [out of] foreigners with the slovenly and unfinished state in which
what nature had made multifarious" (11, 201): they send their productions into the world...." He locates
the reason for this "slovenliness" in the suggestion that was
It is by this, and this alone, that the mechanical power is widely recognized as fundamental to Reynolds's theory: "[I]f
ennobled, and raised much above its natural rank.... the rule here objected to,-that the artful imitation of the
The great advantage of this idea of a whole is, that a parts injures the effect of the whole,-be at once admitted,
greater quantity of truth may be said to be contained and slovenliness would become another name for genius, and the
expressed in a few lines or touches, than in the most most unfinished performance would necessarily be the best."''3
laborious finishing of the parts where this is not regarded. In addition to the meaning of to blotas to edit, we have, I think,

29. Thomas Warton, Verseson Joshua Reynolds'sPainted Wzndowat New-College in Reynolds, 320, 327, app. 2.
Oxford (1782), Oxford, 1930, 1, 7-8. However, the brushwork that Warton 31. Malcolm Andrews's The Searchfor the Pzcturesque:Landscape Aesthetzcsand
makes so much of was not, in fact, executed by Reynolds but by Thomas Tourismin Brztazn,1760-1800, Stanford, Calif., 1989, is a recent example of this
Jervais. AlthoughJervais's name is also not mentioned in the poem, in a letter assessment of the picturesque; he follows the assessment of Christopher
thanking Warton for his tribute Reynolds insists that it is to his hand that this Hussey, The Pzcturesque:Studies zn a Poznt of Vzew,London, 1927.
work be attributed: "I am very sorry therefore my name was not hitchd in the 32. The "Claude Glass" was usually a convex mirror through which the
body of the Poem, if the title page should be lost it will appear to be addressd tourist could frame a landscape and bring it within a smaller purview. It was
to MrJervais"; ibid., iii. frequently tinted, both to reduce the details of the composition and to
30. William Hazlitt, "Essays on Reynolds's Dzscourses"(1814-15), reprinted simulate the mellow patina of old painting. See Andrews (as in n. 31), 68-69.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 125

lost the rather painterly approach to the performance of the the horizon below the bottom of the view" (Fig. 8); and "11.
ideal that Reynolds was seen as advocating, and which is better Objects, or groups of objects, placed alternately on both
able to account for Cozens's proposal of the act of blotting as hands, and gradually retiring from the eye. The horizon
a technique of generalization. above the bottom of the view" (Fig. 9). The numbers
correlate to sixteen plates showing exemplary blots of these
Cozens and the Picturesque types. The typical Claudean composition can be described as
Academic classicism is not the only contemporaneous context a balanced, gradual recession into space, formed by land-
into which Cozens's New Method fits both theoretically and scape elements projecting from the sides of the view, which
formally. In his second reference to the three achievements of culminates in a (hazy, golden) distance (Fig. 10). This most
blotting, Cozens refers to the "picturesque." The tradition of recognizable "picturesque" ("like a picture") composition-
the picturesque is usually described in the scholarship as the allowing for Claude's expansion of the left-hand side to
gradual emancipation of native landscape painting from the incorporate the narrative-is probably that shown in Cozens's
confining rules of Neoclassical (for example, Claudean) eleventh "type." If we accept the scholarly view that British
compositional techniques, especially when that emancipation landscape painting gradually liberated itself from this dog-
culminates in the celebration of the native English land- matic type (as it was practiced by Richard Wilson and his
scape.31 We can locate Cozens in this tradition without students around midcentury), then Cozens's fifteen other
disrupting the general academic classical logic that, as we types are literally an expansion of the Claudean convention.
have seen above, was integral to Cozens's theory of the blot. Type two, for example, with its high point of view and its
The Claudean landscape idiom represents the conventional, emphasis on rugged form, is perhaps recognizable as a
or the "active," knowledge of the artist (which can more or "sublime" landscape, although Cozens does not cite it as
less distort even the empirical contemplation of the land- such.
scape, as the tourist device of the "Claude Glass" dramatically The formal products of Cozens's method, and especially
demonstrates).32 The first achievement of blotting, we will the idea that the landscape drawing is an elaboration on a
recall, is that "it increases the original stock of picturesque previous, highly generalized form, can also be accounted for
ideas." The increase in the crucial empirical stock of ideas is through reference to picturesque theory. In plates accompa-
the result of the practitioner's efforts to extrapolate landscape nying the first of his ThreeEssays ("On Picturesque Beauty"),35
elements from the rude, unmeaning blot; confronted with William Gilpin shows two landscapes, one simple, smooth,
"unmeaning" form, the mind ransacks its store of ideas to and monotonous (Fig. 11), the other varied and roughened
find a plausible meaning. The artist thus draws on his or her with landscape "furniture" (Fig. 12). The figures illustrate
passive knowledge as well as his or her active (conventional) the following passage:
knowledge. By confronting the rude, unmeaning forms of the
blot, the artist is forced to account for compositional possibili- ... in landscapepainting smooth objects would produce no
ties and landscape "furniture" not part of the Claudean composition at all. In a mountain-scene what composition
could arise from the corner of a smooth knoll coming
idiom, and thus Cozens's new method expands the conven-
tional ideas of the "picturesque," or "that which is like a forward on one side, intersected by a smooth knoll on the
other; with a smooth plain perhaps in the middle, and a
picture."
In this way and in one other, Cozens's New Method can be smooth mountain in the distance. The very idea is disgust-
understood as expanding the conventional landscape idiom. ing. Picturesque composition consists in uniting in one
whole a variety of parts; and these parts can only be
Typical of his systematizing tendencies, Cozens published a
treatise on The Various Species of Composition of Landscape in obtained from rough objects. If the smooth mountains,
Nature: 16 Subjectsin four Plates togetherwith some Observations and plains were broken by different objects, the composi-
and Instructions (probably dating to the mid-1770s, as Kim tion may be good, on a supposition the great lines of it
Sloan suggests).33 The plates of that essay have been recov- were so before.36
ered, and Constable himself made copies of the sixteen Gilpin thus draws the formal conclusion that the "pictur-
"species," but the accompanying text remains lost. The idea, esque" is characterized by "roughness," differentiating it
however, is almost certainly the same as that included in the from the "smooth" (which is associated with the "beauti-
New Methodas "Descriptions of the various Kinds of Composi- ful")."7 This formal distinction presages Uvedale Price's more
tion of Landscape." In the New Methodthere are again sixteen unequivocal distinction between the "picturesque" and the
"kinds," nearly identical to the surviving plate list of the classical "beautiful" as the difference between "variety" and
Various Species's "styles" of landscape.34 The kinds are de- "unity" (or, rather, between variety and the "insipidity" of
scribed in such terms as "2. The tops of hills or mountains, failed beauty)."3 But the process that Gilpin cites as mediating

33. Sloan, "A New Chronology: Part II" (as in n. 1), 356.
Beautzful; and, on the use of Studyzng Pictures, for the Purpose of Improving Real
34. Sloan reproduces the plate list of The VariousSpeciesin facsimile in ibid., Landscape, 3 vols., London, 1810. On the interrelation of "beauty," the
358, fig. 18; cf. the plate list to the New Method, 31-33. "insipid" and the "picturesque," see I, 9-10, 72-74, 92, 103-5. For Price as for
35. William Gilpin, ThreeEssays: On PicturesqueBeauty, on Picturesque Travel; Cozens and Gilpin, the picturesque can be described through a dialectical
and on SketchingLandscape.., London, 1792. process of, or as a medium between, generalization and variegation: "As the
36. Ibid., 19. excess of those qualities which chiefly constitute beauty produces insipidity, so
37. Ibid., 4, 5, 36. likewise the excess of those which constitute picturesqueness produces
38. Uvedale Price, Essays on thePicturesque,as comparedwith the Sublimeand the deformity" (1, 175).

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
126 ART BULLETIN MARCH 1997 VOLUME LXXIX NUMBER 1

1)

8 Cozens, Thetopsof hills or


mountains,thehorizonbelow
the bottomof theview,
aquatint, from New Method,
London, 1785, pl. 2. New
Haven, Beinecke Rare
Book and Manuscript
Library,Yale University
(photo: Beinecke Library)

between the "smooth" and the "picturesque," like the Founded on the crucial epistemological concept of "general-
figures illustrating that difference, bears a remarkable similar- ization," the blot is coterminous with an idea of a "species"of
ity to Cozens's method: the "picturesque" is an elaboration or landscape, one of the more general of general ideas. At the
variegation of a basically monotonous form, just as Cozens's same time, it is not inappropriate to describe the blot as
landscape sketch is the "embellishment and consolidation" "abstract,"as we have seen, as long as we apply a Lockean,
of the blot. Although Gilpin cites the former figure as subtractive-mimeticmeaning to that word, as opposed to a
"without composition," the aesthetic effect of the latter modernist, additive-formalmeaning. The picturesque theory
figure is nonetheless predicated, he notes, on the general of the 1790s, like Cozens's New Method,incorporates this
composition shown in the "great lines" of the smooth highly generalized "abstract" form into its art process, as
rendition, just as the plausibility of the blot is dependent on though the dynamic, procedural revariegation of a basic
its conformity to some valid "type" or "species" of landscape. "monotonous" form guarantees to the picturesque "particu-
So for Cozens as for Gilpin, the foundation of the land- lar" its share in classicalideality.
scape drawing, the underlying condition of its success, is a If we return to the RoyalAcademy,we can in fact consoli-
"general idea" of great simplicity, illustrating a highly referen- date the odd connection between the monotonous and the
tially inclusive "species" of landscape composition. For Coz- classicalideal that appears to have been the startingpoint for
ens as for Reynolds, this "simplicity" is strongly associated Gilpin's and Price's interventions in picturesque theory.John
with a broad, painterly manner, and we could draw Gilpin into Opie (professor of painting at the academy, 1805-7) makes
the group by describing this painterly manner as more or less reference to the associationist problem and the role of
"monotonous." Picturesque variegation is best performed reductive generalization in reforming that problem in a
only after and is predicated on the simple whole, to which all lecture delivered in February1807:
parts must be subsumed-just as the large gestures of the blot
describe a whole, leaving what will become the "particular [A]ll possible license may be granted [to the artist], and a
parts" to the incidental markings of the brush.39 work elevated to any degree of the extraordinarywithout
incurring the censure of being extravagant,provided-but
Conclusions: Cozens in Context here the mighty labour lies, which may well deter any
An odd conclusion begins to emerge here-a conclusion that attempt much above the ordinary course of nature-
suggests that Cozens's blots are perhaps among the best provided that the trains of ideas are perfectly connected,
examples of the classical ideal of the eighteenth century. and the whole perfectly consistent with itself; that there is

39. Cozens's Principles of Beauty Relative to the Human Head, although slight emendations to or variationson that "simplicity"that illustratesome
predicated on a linear rather than painterly generalization, uses the same more specific "character"(Fig. 2).
dynamic of first defining "Simple Beauty" (Fig. 1) and then proposing the

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 127

9 Cozens, Objects,or
groupsof objects,placed
alternatelyon both
hands, and gradually
retiringfromtheeye,
aquatint, from New
Method,London,
1785, pl. 11. New
Haven, Beinecke
Rare Book and
Manuscript Library,
Yale University
(photo: Beinecke
Library)

10 Claude Lorrain,
TheJudgment of Paris,
1645/46, oil on
canvas. Washington,
D.C., National
Gallery of Art, Ailsa
Mellon Bruce Fund
(photo: ? Board of
Trustees, National
Gallery of Art)

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
128 ART BULLETIN MARCH 1997 VOLUME LXXIX NUMBER 1

11 William Gilpin, untitled "nonpicturesque" landscape, from ThreeEssays,London, 1792, pl. betw. pages 18 and 19. New Haven,
Beinecke Rare Book and Manuscript Library,Yale University (photo: Beinecke Library)

12 William Gilpin, untitled "picturesque" landscape, from ThreeEssays,London, 1792, pl. betw. pages 18 and 19. New Haven, Beinecke
Rare Book and Manuscript Library,Yale University (photo: Beinecke Library)

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ALEXANDER COZENS'S NEW METHOD 129

no break or opening between them, nothing of discordant College painted windows. The academic lectures of James
nature suffered to interpose, to check the progress of the Barry that I have cited were delivered in the mid-1780s, and
imagination, expose the illusion, and recall a different set Gilpin's "Essay on Picturesque Beauty" was published in
of principles to the mind: this is all that is meant by 1792. By the early nineteenth century, both Opie and Hazlitt
probability in the imitative arts. ... feared that the idea of painterly generalization would be
carried too far and result in muddy, unfinished productions.
This reductive response to associationism, however, courts an This sequence roughly sketches a history of painterly classical
odd problem for Opie:
"techniques of generalization," techniques which originate
as a response to the midcentury associationist crisis best
Instances have occurred of some [artists], who have even
illustrated in Sterne's playful Tristram Shandy (1759-67).
been so absurd as to think colouring, chiaro scuro, and all
These techniques, which climaxed in the 1780s, required the
that contributes to illusion in painting, as beneath their
dialectical corrective of picturesque "variegation" in the
attention; who, because they have heard that nature might
1790s; by the early nineteenth century they were seen as
be improved upon in some particulars, have fondly imag-
conventionalized and overapplied. It is doubtless significant
ined that their compositions approached the heroic and
to this history that Cozens felt that a republication of his
poetical in proportion as they receded from nature and method would be well received in the mid-1780s; indeed,
became muddy, tame, and monotonous in the effect .... 40
there are significant formal differences between the "black
William Hazlitt, we will recall, made the same objection to the Sketches and Outlines" of the 1759 Essay and the broader, less
determinate "blots" of the 1785 New Method.43 I have at-
"painterly" theory of classical generalization, tracing a direct
connection between Reynolds's theory and the "slovenly and tempted here to locate the epistemology underlying the New
unfinished" appearance of early-nineteenth-century English Methodin the context of the late-eighteenth-century "associa-
tionist problem" through specific comparison with Joshua
painting.
In his Lectures on Painting, James Barry (professor of Reynolds's epistemology and pedagogy, and to locate both
textual justifications for and figurative parallels with the odd
painting at the academy, 1782-99) is less troubled by the
counterassociationist epistemological logic that associates formal appearance of the blot from inside the academy and
from within the picturesque theory of the 1780s and 1790s. If
"beauty" with the "muddy, tame, and monotonous":
this exploration has (justifiably, I think) somewhat confused
[T]he desideratum (at least in all matters of elevated our expectations of the formal appearance of the classical, I
compositions) is, that the artist should possess a great and hope it compensates by locating Cozens well within the
noble mind, of ability to penetrate the depth, entire parameters of contemporary debate and artistic process.
compass, and capability of his subject; to discern in one
view all its possible circumstances, to select and unite
whatever is most essential, most interesting, and of the
greatest consequence to its energetic and happy elucida- Frequently Cited Sources
tion, and to be able at the same time judiciously and
severely to reject and suppress whatever useless exuber- Cozens, Alexander, A New Method of Asszstzngthe Invention zn Drawzng Onginal
ances may have arisen from the heat and fertility of his Composztzonsof Landscape (1785), in L'art de la tache:Introductzoni la Nouvelle
mithode d'AlexanderCozens,byJean-Claude Lebensztejn, Paris, 1990, 467-84.
imagination.41 Locke, John, An Essay ConcernzngHuman Understandzng (1690), ed. Peter H.
Nidditch, Oxford, 1990.
In another, though similar context, and with no sense of Reynolds, Joshua, Dzscourseson Art, ed. Robert R. Wark, New Haven/London,
1981.
drama, Barry concludes that "Mere Beauty then, (though
always interesting) is notwithstanding vague and indetermi-
nate ... ."42 Not only the anti-academic Hazlitt, but even the
academic theorists explicitly describe the classical ideal as CharlesA. Crameris a Ph.D. candidate at the Universityof Texas at
muddy, tame, monotonous, indeterminate, and vague. Austin, specializing in aesthetictheoryand issues of classicism and
Reynolds's eleventh Discourse on the "technique of gener- modernism in art. He is currently completing his dissertation,
alization" through a "few, well-chosen strokes" was delivered "FormalReduction and theEmpiricalIdeal, 1750-1914, "under the
in December 1782, the same year that Warton produced the advice of Prof. Richard Shiff [Departmentof Art and Art History,
poetic ode to Reynolds's (mediated) handwork in the New Universityof Texasat Austin, Austin, Tex. 78712].

40. John Opie, Lectureson Pazntzng.. ., London, 1809, 78, 17. 42. Barry, "Lecture on Design," in ibid., 398.
41. James Barry, "Lecture on Composition," in The WorksofJames Barry ..., 43. Cozens, An Essay... (1759), in facsimile in Sloan, "A New Chronology:
I, London, 1794, 456. Part II" (as in n. 1), 354.

This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Fri, 12 Sep 2014 11:12:20 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like