Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 8

|

RESEARCH ARTICLE   PSYCHOLOGICAL AND COGNITIVE SCIENCES

Autism attenuates the perception of the mind-body divide


Iris Berenta,1 , Rachel M. Theodoreb, and Erick Valenciaa

Edited by Susan Goldin-Meadow, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL; received July 12, 2022; accepted September 20, 2022

People are intuitive Dualists—they tacitly consider the mind as ethereal, distinct from
the body. Here we ask whether Dualism emerges naturally from the conflicting core Significance
principles that guide reasoning about objects, on the one hand, and about the minds of
agents (theory of mind, ToM), on the other. To address this question, we explore Dualist Across cultures, people consider
reasoning in autism spectrum disorder (ASD)—a congenital disorder known to com- the mind as ethereal, distinct
promise ToM. If Dualism arises from ToM, then ASD ought to attenuate Dualism and from the body. But whether
promote Physicalism. In line with this prediction, Experiment 1 shows that, compared to Dualism arises only from culture
controls, people with ASD are more likely to view psychological traits as embodied—as (nurture) or also spontaneously
likely to manifest in a replica of one’s body. Experiment 2 demonstrates that, unlike (from human nature) is
controls, people with ASD do not consider thoughts as disembodied—as persistent in unknown. To address this
the afterlife (upon the body’s demise). If ASD promotes the perception of the psyche as
question, here, we turn to autism
embodied, and if (per Essentialism) embodiment suggests innateness, then ASD should
spectrum disorder (ASD)—a
further promote Nativism—this bias is shown in Experiment 3. Finally, Experiment
4 demonstrates that, in neurotypical (NT) participants, difficulties with ToM corre- congenital disorder that
late with Physicalism. These results are the first to show that ASD attenuates Dualist compromises intuitive reasoning
reasoning and to link Dualism to ToM. These conclusions suggest that the mind-body about the minds of others
distinction might be natural for people to entertain. (theory of mind, ToM). If ToM
promotes Dualist reasoning, then
autism | theory of mind | innateness | intuitive psychology Dualist reasoning ought to be
attenuated in ASD. Our results
A large literature suggests that people are intuitive Dualists—they consider the mind as
show that, compared to controls,
ethereal, distinct from the material body (1–17). For example, adults believe that a person’s
people with ASD are more likely
thoughts will likely persist in the afterlife (3), but they are unlikely to manifest in a replica
of one’s body (compared to physical traits, such as a scar (2)). to view bodies and minds alike
Intuitive Dualist reasoning has been further documented in children (18, 19) and across (in line with Physicalism).
multiple cultures (4, 5, 13, 14, 17, 20–25); it has been implicated in reasoning about the Moreover, a Physicalist stance is
brain (11), psychiatric disorders (8, 26, 27), morality (28, 29), and one’s true self (9). linked to difficulties with ToM.
Why people are Dualists, however, remains unknown. One possibility is that Dualism These results shed light on ASD
is strictly a social invention that arises via cultural transmission alone. On an alternative and on the mind-body distinction
account (1), Dualism emerges naturally, from the tension between two intuitive systems in humans.
of core knowledge that are evident in young infants (30, 31), and arguably, nonhuman
animals (32–39).
One system—intuitive physics, suggests that objects are cohesive entities that can move
only by immediate contact with other objects (40–42). Another system, theory of mind
(ToM), suggests to us that, unlike objects, agents can move by their own accord, guided
by their mental states—their beliefs, desires, and goals (43–45). Thus, seeing a person
reach toward their coffee mug is hardly noteworthy (one tacitly assumes that the movement
was caused by the agent’s desire for coffee), but seeing the converse (a mug moving toward Author affiliations: aNortheastern University, Boston, MA
20115; and bUniversity of Connecticut, Storrs, CT 06269-
the person) would be surprising indeed. The distinct causal principles we invoke to explain 1085
the behavior of agents, on the one hand, and objects (on the other) could lead us to
conclude that minds are ethereal, distinct from the material body.
Dualism, then, could be natural to humans—it could arise, in part from ToM. The Author contributions: I.B. conceived the project; I.B.
hypothesis of “natural Dualism” could further explain why Dualist thinking is prevalent designed the experiments; I.B. contributed to data
analysis;  E.V. performed research; I.B. and R.M.T.
across cultures (46). But precisely because of its prevalence, the roots of Dualism—nature analyzed data; E.V. programmed the experiments and
(ToM) or nurture (cultural transmission)—are difficult to disentangle. curated the data; and I.B. wrote the paper.
To shed light on the origins of Dualism, here, we examine Dualist thinking in adults The authors declare no competing interest.
with an autism spectrum disorder (ASD). ASD is a heritable disorder (47) that compro- This article is a PNAS Direct Submission.
mises ToM (43, 48–58). If Dualism indeed arises naturally, from ToM, then a congenital Copyright © 2022 the Author(s). Published by PNAS.
This article is distributed under Creative Commons
impairment to ToM ought to attenuate Dualist thinking in ASD. This is the hypothesis Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives License 4.0
we evaluate here. (CC BY-NC-ND).
This hypothesis does not necessarily mean that ASD ought to utterly abolish Dualism. 1
To whom correspondence may be addressed. Email:
I.berent@northeastern.edu.
First, many individuals on the autism spectrum (AS) can reason about the mental states
This article contains supporting information online at
of others (49, 52, 54, 58–60), and this partial sparing of ToM could give rise to partial https://www.pnas.org/lookup/suppl/doi:10.1073/pnas.​
intuitive Dualism. In addition, Dualist reasoning could also emerge by cultural transmis- 2211628119/-/DCSupplemental.
sion, independently of ToM. Either way, we expect that, compared to NT controls, Published November 30, 2022.

PNAS  2022  Vol. 119  No. 49  e2211628119 https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2211628119   1 of 8


individuals with ASD would show an attenuated Dualism, rather Results and Discussion: Body Replication (Experiment 1). In this
than strict Physicalism (the view of body and mind as one and and all subsequent experiments, we excluded outliers (participants
the same). whose responses fell 2.5 SD beyond the group mean). Two
In what follows, we examine Dualist reasoning in adults with participants were removed from Experiment 1 (one per group).
ASD. We focus on two hallmarks of Dualism, documented in NT An inspection of the grand means (the proportion of “will trans-
individuals. The first is the belief that certain mental traits (e.g., fer to the replica” responses, calculated over by-subject means,
thoughts) are ethereal—they are less likely to manifest in the body which were averaged across items, see Fig. 1) suggests that both
(in life) and more likely to persist in its absence (in the afterlife); groups considered epistemic traits as less embodied (i.e., less likely
Experiments 1–2 evaluate embodiment and disembodiment, to emerge in the body-replica) relative to non-epistemic traits.
respectively. However, the ASD group considered both types of psychological
The second hallmark of Dualism concerns its effects on nativ- traits as more strongly embodied than NT controls.
ist intuitions. Past research (discussed below) has shown that a. Group comparison. To evaluate these observations, we first
psychological traits that are perceived as strongly anchored in submitted the binary trial responses (1  =  will transfer to the
the physical body are also perceived as innate. For example, replica; 0 = will not transfer) to a generalized linear mixed effects
people believe that seeing and walking (which are linked to the model with the binomial response family, as implemented with
eyes and legs) are innate, whereas thoughts (which are perceived the glmer function of the lmer4 package (62). This model specifies
as disembodied) are not (61). If Physicalism promotes innate- response to be predicted by the fixed effects of trait, group, and
ness intuitions, and people with ASD lean toward Physicalism their interaction, with the random effects structure consisting of
(and away from Dualism), then people with ASD should be random slopes for trait by subject, random intercepts by subject,
further biased toward Nativism—this bias is evaluated in and random intercepts by item. Because subject identifier codes
Experiment 3. Finally, Experiment 4 examines whether difficul- are unique (i.e., individuals in the ASD and NT groups have
ties with ToM are linked to participants’ intuitions about bodies distinct subject codes), this model adequately captures the nested
and minds. structure of individual participants within each group. The model
We predict that, compared to NT participants, individuals with syntax (also employed in Experiments 2–4) is shown below:
ASD should be a) less likely to consider psychological traits as
embodied, and consequently b) they should also be more likely response∼ trait ∗ group + (trait|subject)
to view them as innate. Furthermore, c) difficulties with ToM + (1|item), family = "binomial".
should be associated with a more Physicalist stance.
The significant effect of Group indicates that the mean “embod-
The Embodiment of Psychological Traits iment” (i.e., “will transfer”) responses of the ASD group were
(Experiments 1–2) higher than NT controls (β = 1.50, SE = 0.67, Z=−2.24, P = 0.02).
The significant effect of Trait confirms that epistemic traits were
Experiments 1–2 examine whether individuals with ASD consider considered less embodied than non-epistemic traits (β = 0.89,
psychological traits as more strongly embodied (compared to NT SE = 0.26, Z = 3.34, P < 0.001). The interaction was not signifi-
individuals). In each experiment, participants were presented with cant (β = 0.41, SD = 0.00, Z = 1.24, P > 0.21).
a list of 80 psychological traits—either thoughts (e.g., having a b. Comparison against chance. To further investigate the perception
concept of ‘person’, symbolic reasoning)—hereafter, epistemic of psychological traits as embodied, we next examined whether the
states, or traits that correspond to actions (e.g., walking, sitting) proportion of “will transfer to the replica” responses for each of the
and emotions (e.g., happiness, sadness)—collectively, non-epis- four cells (2 Group x 2 Trait) differed from chance. For each cell,
temic traits. we thus constructed a logistic mixed effect regression model that
Experiment 1 evaluated the embodiment of these traits. To this predicted the “will transfer” (i.e., embodiment) responses from
end, we presented participants with a hypothetical scenario, random slopes by subjects and by items. Of interest is whether
whereby it would be possible to create a replica of one’s body. the intercept differed from chance (0.5; 0 in log odds).
Participants were asked to determine whether each trait would ASD participants responded to all traits above chance—both
likely transfer to the replica. If ASD attenuates Dualism, then non-epistemic (β = 2.81, SE = 0.62, Z = 4.53, P < 0.001) and
people with ASD should consider psychological traits as more
strongly embodied, hence, as more likely to transfer to the bodily
replica.
In Experiment 2, participants judged the converse, disembod-
iment. Here, participants evaluated the persistence of the same
traits after the body’s demise, in the afterlife. If people with ASD
are less Dualist, then they should now consider psychological traits
as less likely to persist (i.e., as less disembodied).
As explained above, we expect ASD to attenuate Dualist rea-
soning, but not necessarily abolish it altogether. Accordingly, ASD
participants might not categorically reject the persistence of the
psyche in the afterlife nor might they fully embrace its embodi-
ment (in the living). Additionally, like NT participants, the ASD
group may well consider epistemic traits as disembodied relative
to non-epistemic traits, such as actions and emotions (traits that
can be readily linked to specific body organs). Nonetheless, ASD Fig. 1. The perceived embodiment of psychological traits, as gauged by the
“will transfer to the replica” responses. Bars show grand means calculated
participants should consider epistemic traits as more likely to over by-subject averages. In this and all figures, asterisks mark a significant
manifest in the body (in Experiment 1), and as less likely to persist difference between the group mean and chance (indicated by the dotted line)
in the afterlife (in Experiment 2). and error bars indicate SE of the subject means.

2 of 8   https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2211628119 pnas.org
epistemic (β = 2.81, SE = 0.62, Z = 4.53, P < 0.001) traits. In of Group (β  =  0.61, SE  =  0.59, Z  =  1.04, P  >  0.30) and the
contrast, NT participants’ responses to non-epistemic traits were interaction (β = 0.08, SE = 0.25, Z < 1) were not significant.
above chance (β = 0.99, SE = 0.34, Z = 2.95, P < 0.01), but this b. Comparison against chance. A comparison of the choices
was not the case for epistemic traits (β = −0.06, SE = 0.40, against chance (following the model described in Experiment
Z = −0.16, P = 0.87). 1) nonetheless suggested that the two groups exhibited different
To evaluate whether this at-chance performance reflects evi- patterns of responses. NT participants’ responses to epistemic
dence for the null hypothesis (as opposed to the absence of evi- traits were significantly above chance (β  =  1.00, SE  =  0.31,
dence), we also submitted the responses to a Bayes Factor analysis Z = 3.23, P < 0.01), whereas responses to non-epistemic traits were
(for further details, see SI Appendix). Results showed that for at chance (β = 0.29, SE = 0.38, Z < 1). For ASD participants, by
non-epistemic traits, there was strong evidence for the alternative contrast, responses to epistemic traits hovered at chance (β = 0.41,
hypothesis (H1: that the means differed from chance) for NT SE = 0.32, Z = 1.26, P = 0.21), in line with responses to non-
participants (BF1 = 13.39); for the ASD group, the evidence was epistemic traits (β = –0.23, SE = 0.57, Z = –0.40, P > 0.6), and
extreme (BF1 = 5,124.76). Considering epistemic traits, however, contrary to the choices of NT participants.
for NT participants, we found anecdotal support for the null We next evaluated the strength of the support for these conclu-
hypothesis (H0: the mean does not differ from chance: BF0 = 0.43). sions using Bayes Factor analysis. For non-epistemic traits, we
ASD participants, in contrast, yielded anecdotal evidence to the found moderate evidence for the null hypothesis that responses
contrary—that performance differed from chance (BF1 = 2.39). are at chance (for NT: BF0= 0.32; for ASD: BF0= 0.19).
Summarizing, both groups considered epistemic traits as less Considering epistemic traits, however, the support for these con-
likely to be anchored in the body, in line with Dualism. clusions differed for the two groups. Here, for NT participants,
Nonetheless, the two groups differed with respect to the strength there was extreme evidence for the alternative hypothesis (i.e., that
of this Dualist bias. First, the ASD group considered all psycho- response differ from chance: BF1= 107.33), whereas this was not
logical traits as more firmly anchored in the body than the control the case for ASD participants; in fact, there was anecdotal evidence
group. Additionally, NT participants were uncertain about the to the contrary (for the null hypothesis that responses to epistemic
embodiment of epistemic traits, but this was not the case for ASD traits were at chance: BF0= 0.85).
participants. Thus, both groups considered epistemic traits as less embodied
Experiment 2 further investigated the Dualist bias by presenting than non-epistemic traits, and responses to the two trait types did
participants with the converse of embodiment. Participants here not differ reliably by group. But when the choice was evaluated
were asked to determine whether psychological traits would persist categorically—as indicating whether or not traits would persist in
after the demise of the body, in the afterlife. If people with ASD the afterlife (relative to chance level), here, the behaviors of the
are less Dualist, then now, they should not consider psychological two groups diverged. NT participants stated that epistemic traits
traits as likely to persist. would persist in the afterlife, but this was not the case for ASD
participants. Thus, unlike NT participants, ASD participants did
Results and Discussion: The Afterlife (Experiment 2). One NT not consider psychological traits as disembodied.
participant was identified as an outlier and removed from the
analyses. An inspection of the means (the proportion of “will The Innateness of Psychological Traits
persist” responses, calculated over by-subject means, which (Experiment 3)
were first averaged across items, see Fig. 2) suggested that, in
considering the afterlife, both groups viewed epistemic traits Experiments 1–2 suggest that people on the ASD spectrum con-
as relatively disembodied—as more likely to persist than non- sider psychological traits as more firmly anchored in the body than
epistemic traits. But while the NT group viewed epistemic traits NT participants: they believe that psychological traits are more
as categorically disembodied (i.e., choices were above chance), this likely to manifest in the living body, and (unlike controls), they
was not the case for the ASD group. Thus, unlike controls, ASD do not expect thoughts to persist in its absence (in the afterlife).
participants did not view thoughts as disembodied. In Experiment 3, we explore how this Physicalist stance affects
a. Group comparison. The mixed effect model (following the reasoning about the origins of the psyche—its innateness.
structure described in Experiment 1) yielded a reliable effect of Previous research in neurotypical (NT) individuals suggests that
Trait (β  =  −0.76, SE  =  0.31, Z  =  −2.48, P  =  0.01). The effect to intuitively perceive a psychological trait as innate, people must
perceive that trait as firmly anchored in the body (8, 10, 26,
63–65). For example, people believe that a person’s thoughts are
ethereal (10), and they arise by learning from experience (61, 66),
whereas walking, seeing, and happiness—traits that can be readily
linked to the body (e.g., to legs, eyes, and face, respectively)—are
likely innate (10, 65). Moreover, the link between embodiment
and innateness is causal. Specifically, when people are presented
with evidence that a psychological trait is embodied (e.g., it man-
ifests in the brain), people become more likely to consider that
trait as innate (compared to when the same trait manifests in
behavior) (8, 10, 26, 65). Conversely, when informed that a psy-
chological trait is innate, people now become more likely to view
that trait as embodied (compared to when the same trait is pre-
sented as learned) (10).
The bias to link embodiment and innateness could arise from
the interaction between two principles of intuitive psychology—
Fig. 2. The perceived disembodiment of psychological traits, as gauged by
the “will emerge in the afterlife” responses. Bars show grand means calculated Essentialism and Dualism (63, 64). A large literature has attrib-
over by-subject averages. uted innateness intuitions to Essentialism (67, 68), and per

PNAS  2022  Vol. 119  No. 49  e2211628119 https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2211628119   3 of 8


Essentialism, the innate essence of living things is perceived as innateness of epistemic traits. This outcome is expected by the
embodied (69–72). But since, per Dualism, people tend to view hypothesis that people essentialize psychological traits that they
the psyche as disembodied, they conclude that psychological traits consider embodied. Since (as shown in Experiments 1–2)
are unlikely to be innate. Thoughts (i.e., epistemic traits) are the ASD participants consider psychological traits as more strongly
psychological traits perceived as least embodied (less than sensa- embodied, they are also more likely to consider them innate.
tions, actions, and emotions). Accordingly, people perceive epis-
temic traits as the least likely to be innate. Fig. 3. Is Dualism Linked to ToM (Experiment 4)?
This hypothesis suggests a novel prediction for ASD. If ASD
participants consider psychological traits as more strongly embod- The results of Experiments 1–2 suggest that, compared to NT
ied, and if embodiment triggers Nativism, then ASD participants controls, individuals with ASD are Physicalists, and, perhaps for
ought to also show a stronger Nativist bias—they should be more this reason, they also tend to be Nativists, as indeed was shown in
likely to view psychological traits as innate (relative to NT partic- Experiment 3. We hypothesize that these biases arise from diffi-
ipants). Experiment 3 evaluates this prediction. culties with ToM—a known characteristic of autism (43, 48–58).
But whether this Physicalist stance is indeed linked to ToM is
Results and Discussion. Two outliers were removed (one unknown—Experiments 1 - 3 do not speak to this question.
per group). An inspection of the means suggested that both To shed light on this matter, we next assessed sensitivity to ToM
groups considered non-epistemic traits as more likely to be in a large group of participants—ASD and NT (N = 84 per group)
innate (relative to epistemic traits). ASD participants, however, and correlated these outcomes with the two measures of Dualism—
considered psychological traits as more likely to be innate than Embodiment and Disembodiment (using the replication and
NT participants. In addition, when compared against chance, NT afterlife tasks, as in Experiments 1–2, respectively). All participants
participants denied the innateness of epistemic traits, but this was were further administered the Autism Quotient (AQ, from
not the case for ASD participants. ref. 73).
a. Group comparison. The mixed effect model (following the To evaluate ToM, we presented participants with a statement
structure described in Experiment 1) yielded a reliable effect of about a protagonist’s false belief (adapted from ref. 74). In half
Group (β = −0.89, SE = 0.29, Z = −3.02, P < 0.01) and Trait of the responses, this statement corresponded to a false belief
(β = 2.20, SE = 0.35, Z = 6.27, P < 0.001). The interaction was that the protagonist likely holds (e.g., “Lisa believes Jacob is
not significant (β = 0.31, SE = 0.33, Z < 1). sleeping”; Lisa is likely to hold this belief as she last saw Jacob
b. Comparison against chance. Responses to non-epistemic traits asleep on the beach, but alas, this belief is false—in reality, Jacob
were significantly above chance for both the ASD (β=1.54, has since gone swimming). The other half captured true beliefs
SE=0.35, Z = 4.46, P < 0.001) and NT (β = 0.88, SE = 0.36, that the protagonist is unlikely to hold (e.g., “the girls believe
Z = 2.42, P < 0.02) groups, suggesting that non-epistemic traits the ice-cream in the fridge is melted”; this belief is actually true,
are considered innate. A Bayes factor analysis confirmed that as a power outage occurred overnight, but the girls have no
the support for this (alternative) hypothesis was very strong for reason to hold that belief, as they were meanwhile sleeping).
NT participants (BF1= 51.57) and extremely strong for ASD Participants were asked to quickly evaluate whether or not the
participants (BF1= 32,8715.1). protagonist holds this belief. Sensitivity to ToM was measured
The two groups, however, differed in their responses to epis- by response accuracy speed.
temic traits. Here, NT participants’ innateness judgments were Since, in high-functioning people with ASD, difficulties with
significantly below chance (β = −1.43, SE = 0.337, Z = −4.25, ToM are typically subtle (49, 52, 54, 58–60), and they can be
P < 0.001), and the evidence for this conclusion was extreme masked by compensatory analytic strategies that do not rely on
(BF1= 49,889.37). In contrast, the innateness judgments of ASD intuitive ToM (58), we did not necessarily expect our ASD group
participants hovered at chance (β = −0.46, SE = 0.28, Z = −1.63, to score lower on the ToM task or for their ToM performance to
P > 0.10) and the support for the alternative hypothesis was anec- correlate with the Dualism probes. Thus, in the ASD group, per-
dotal (BF1= 1.15). Thus, unlike controls, ASD participants did formance on the ToM probe may not reflect intuitive ToM
not deny the innateness of epistemic traits. transparently.
Summarizing, participants with ASD showed stronger nativist NT participants, by contrast, are more likely to solve the ToM
beliefs than controls—they were more likely to view psychological problem by relying on their (intact) intuitive ToM competence.
traits as innate, and, unlike NT controls, they did not reject the We thus asked whether their performance on the ToM probe
correlates with Dualism (Embodiment/Disembodiment). We
hypothesize that NT participants who are sensitive to the minds
of others (i.e., those with faster responses/fewer errors on the ToM
task) ought to lean toward Dualism: they should be more likely
to perceive psychological traits as disembodied—as likely to
emerge in the afterlife, but not in the replication task. This selec-
tive pattern would suggest a link between ToM and intuitive
Dualism.

Results and Discussion


As expected, the ASD group scored significantly higher (more
autistic-like) than controls on the AQ, and this significant group
difference emerged in both the Embodiment (i.e., replication;
(t(118) = 7.93, P < 0.001; d = 7.10) and Disembodiment (i.e.,
Fig. 3. The perceived innateness of psychological traits, as gauged by the
“innate” responses. Bars show grand means calculated over by-subject afterlife) conditions (t(118) = 11.32, P < 0.001; d = 7.17; for
averages. additional details, see SI Appendix, Table S4). In the ToM task,

4 of 8   https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2211628119 pnas.org
however, the two groups did not differ on either accuracy or cor- faithfully reflect their perception of the mind-body link. And
rect response time (RT) (hereafter, “speed”; in both cases, t < 1). since, by hypothesis, ASD participants lean toward Physicalism,
We note that RT data from one NT participant were excluded in the ASD group, Physicalism is associated with more accurate
because they fell over six SD away from the mean. ToM responses.
We next asked whether difficulties in ToM are linked to partic- Ultimately, then, intuitive ToM could have contributed to the
ipants’ Dualist stance. The arrows in the margins of Fig. 4 depict performance of both groups (see Fig. 5). But in NT participants,
the directions of the predicted links between intuitive ToM and intuitive ToM directly constrained performance on both the
responses to the Afterlife and Replication probes (color-coded by Dualism and ToM probes, whereas in the ASD group, the link to
probe). To the extent responses to the ToM probe rely on intuitive ToM was indirect. Specifically, the difficulties of ASD participants
ToM, then participants who excel on the ToM task (i.e., faster with intuitive ToM elicited a Physicalist stance (in responses to
responses) should lean toward Dualism: they should consider psy- the Replication task), but they also encouraged compensatory
chological traits as more likely to emerge in the afterlife probe (but response strategies (in the ToM task), and it is these strategies (not
not the replication probe). intuitive ToM) that engendered the association between perfor-
This was indeed the case for NT participants. NT participants mance on the ToM and Dualism probes. How ASD participants
who excelled on ToM (i.e., had a faster response) were more likely approached the experimental tasks is not a matter we can ascertain,
to state that psychological traits would emerge in the afterlife but our findings clearly show that ToM performance is linked to
(r(57) = −0.307, P < 0.02). And as would be expected, this corre- Dualism.
lation was primarily due to epistemic traits (r(57) = −0.353,
P < 0.01)—the ones typically perceived as least embodied, hence, General Discussion
most likely to persist upon the body’s demise (for non-epistemic
traits: r(57) = −0.229, P = 0.08). No other correlations between A large literature shows that people are intuitive Dualists—they
ToM and the Dualist probes were significant for NT participants consider the mind as ethereal, distinct from the material body
(for the full correlation matrix, see SI Appendix, Table S5). Thus, (1–17). Here, we asked whether this Dualist stance might emerge
in NT participants, sensitivity to ToM was associated with Dualism. naturally—from the core knowledge systems that guide reasoning
This, however, was not the case for ASD participants. In fact, about objects, on the one hand, and the minds of agents (ToM),
ASD participants who excelled on ToM (i.e., had faster responses) on the other (1).
were more likely to state that psychological traits would emerge To evaluate this hypothesis, we turned to ASD—a disorder that
in the body-replica(r(58) = −0.291, P < 0.03)—in line with is known to disrupt the development of ToM (43, 48–58). We
Physicalism (and contrary to Dualism). Upon closer inspection, reason that, if Dualism arises, in part, from ToM, then people
this link appeared to be stronger for non-epistemic traits—the with ASD should be less likely to exhibit Dualism, and instead,
ones typically seen as most embodied (SI Appendix, Table S5). lean toward Physicalism—the view of the mind and body as one
Moreover, participants who considered non-epistemic traits as and the same.
embodied also exhibited fewer errors on the ToM task Results from Experiments 1–2 were in line with this possibility.
(r(58) = −0.268, P = 0.04)—a mirror image of the findings from Compared to controls, ASD participants were more likely to
NT participants. expect one’s psychological traits to persist in a manipulation that
We suggest that the performance of ASD participants reflects preserves the body (in body replication), and, unlike controls, they
not their intuitive ToM but rather analytic compensatory strat- did not expect thoughts to persist in its absence (in the afterlife).
egies. Indeed, many individuals with ASD exhibit superior sys- Since our experimental tasks did not assess Dualism explicitly,
tematization and attention to detail (75), and such these results are inexplicable by differences in Dualism judgments
(domain-general) skills have been shown to allow ASD partic- per se. And since the responses of the two groups are doubly
ipants to solve ToM questions even when their intuitive ToM dissociated, depending on the probe (embedment/disembodi-
is demonstrably impaired (49, 52, 54, 58–60). Critically, these ment), they are also inexplicable by response biases. Accordingly,
skills are likely to boost performance across tasks. Thus, partic- these findings suggest that people with ASD consider the psyche
ipants who are attentive to the ToM task are also likely to attend as more strongly embodied, in line with Physicalism (and contrary
to the Dualism probes, so their performance is more likely to to Dualism).

Fig. 4. The correlation between performance on the ToM task (speed and errors) and Dualism. Errors are mean proportions (across items); the RT is the mean
correct response (in seconds, averaged across items). Significant correlations are indicated by bolded lines. The arrows in the margins indicate the patterns of
performance predicted by each probe. Thus, for the Afterlife probe, higher choice proportions are associated with Dualism, whereas in the Replication task,
they suggest Physicalism.

PNAS  2022  Vol. 119  No. 49  e2211628119 https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2211628119   5 of 8


Fig. 5. The hypothesized link between intuitive ToM and performance on the ToM and Dualism probes.

Experiment 3 explored another consequence of Dualism—its and bodies is not solely a cultural invention. Dualism might be
potential to promote Empiricism (8, 10, 26, 63–65). We rea- natural for humans to entertain.
soned that if Dualism typically begets Empiricism, then, if the
mind-body divide is attenuated (in ASD), then people with ASD Materials and Methods
should be less likely to show the Empiricist bias (found in NT
people), and consequently, they should be more likely to lean Experiment 1–3

toward Nativism. Accordingly, compared to NT controls, indi- Participants. Each experiment was administered to two distinct groups of Prolific

viduals with ASD should be more likely to state that psycholog- participants: ASD participants and NT controls. Altogether, then, Experiments 1–3
ical traits are innate—this is precisely what was found in were administered to six distinct samples (2 ASD/NT x 3 Experiment). Within
Experiment 3. each experiment, the ASD group consisted of individuals who self-identified as
having obtained a formal clinical diagnosis of autism spectrum disorder by a
Taken as a whole, the findings from Experiments 1– 3 suggest
psychiatrist, psychologist, or other qualified medical specialist. Participants in the
that, compared to controls, people with ASD are indeed inclined control group self-identified as not having had such a diagnosis. In addition, both
toward Physicalism, and perhaps for this reason, they also lean groups were native English speakers, free of reading and language disorders. For
toward Nativism. The conclusion that ASD promotes Physicalist additional characteristics, see SI Appendix, Table S1.
reasoning agrees with past anecdotal observations (1, 76). To Informed by past research with NT participants using the same tasks (10, 61),
the best of our knowledge, our results are the first to support we set the target sample size in Experiments 1–3 to N = 30 participants per group.
this conclusion experimentally. As such, these findings shed One participant in Experiment 1 did not complete the task. As noted, outlier removal
new light on how people with ASD reason about bodies and further excluded 2 additional participants from Experiment 1 (one per group), one NT
minds. participant from Experiment 2, and two participants (one per group) from Experiment
Experiment 4 next asked whether this Physicalist stance and its 3. Accordingly, the analysis of Experiment 1 was based on 29 ASD and 28 NT partici-
converse, Dualism, are linked to ToM. We found such associations pants; in Experiment 2, the analysis included 30 ASD and 29 NT participants, and in
in both groups, but their directions differed. We suggest that, in Experiment 3, the analyses included 29 participants per group.
both groups, responses to the ToM probe were linked to the per- Materials and procedure. The materials in Experiments 1–3 consisted of a list
ceptions of the mind-body divide. However, in NT participants, of 80 psychological traits (from refs. 10 and 61); half captured epistemic states
intuitive ToM directly constrained performance on the two exper- (e.g., recalling past events, hereafter epistemic traits); the other half consisted of
imental probes (ToM and Dualism), whereas in ASD participants, actions and emotions (e.g., sitting, walking, hereafter non-epistemic traits). The
performance was mediated by compensatory strategies. trait order was randomized. For the full list of traits, see SI Appendix, Appendix I.
Consequently, in NT participants, sensitivity to the ToM probe In Experiment 1, participants were invited to suppose it was possible to grow
was associated with stronger Dualism, whereas in the ASD group, a replica of the body of an adult human donor. The replica preserves every aspect
it was linked with a greater likelihood that participants’ Physicalist of the human body and brain. With this in mind, participants were asked to deter-
mine whether or not a given trait would likely emerge in the replica. In Experiment
stance would manifest.
2, participants were invited to judge whether or not each trait is to persist in the
If congenital difficulties with ToM indeed suppress Dualist
afterlife. In Experiment 3, participants evaluated whether these traits are inborn
reasoning (in ASD), then it is possible that its typical emergence
in humans. Participants were told that “inborn traits are ones that develop in
(in NT individuals) could occur naturally—from the collision humans spontaneously. Some of these traits (e.g., having five fingers) are present
between ToM and core physics (1). Whether Dualism is, in fact in birth, but others (e.g., facial hair in men) can appear later in development. All
natural, is not a question we can fully settle here. In particular, inborn traits, however, emerge in the typical course of development, even if an
the correlation we have documented between ToM and Dualist individual has never had the opportunity to witness these behaviors in other
reasoning does not establish causation. Nonetheless, the hypoth- people.” Participants were asked to give a binary response as to whether or not
esis that Dualism arises from ToM can readily explain why a dis- each trait is inborn in humans. For the full list of instructions in Experiments 1– 3,
ruption to ToM, in ASD, is associated with a reduction in both see SI Appendix, Appendix II.
the Dualism and Empiricist biases that plague NT cognition (8,
10, 26, 65). When it comes to reasoning about minds and bodies,
then, ASD presents a silver lining. This is in line with past research,
suggesting that the reduction in ToM could confer children with *We note that the putative role of Dualism in reasoning about the supernatural does not
imply that supernatural creatures ought to be seen as utterly ethereal, devoid of any
ASD with cognitive strengths (e.g., in counterfactual reasoning physicalist properties nor does it predict that Dualist reasoning ought to arise at birth (79).
(77)). The latter (“at birth”) challenge is a red herring, as innate traits (e.g., secondary sexual
characteristics) can demonstrably develop later in life. Likewise, supernatural creatures
Moreover, the hypothesis that ToM begets Dualism can further need not be seen as utterly disembodied (contrary to the first challenge above)—this would
explain why Dualist reasoning is so pervasive in humans—why only follow if Dualism were were the sole determinant of intuitive reasoning about the
supernatural, and if it were further inviolable. But, Dualism could well be a “soft”, violable
beliefs about disembodied supernatural beings (e.g., gods, ghosts, constraint. And as noted, Dualist reasoning often interacts with Essentialism (64) (8–10, 12,
disembodied minds (4, 5, 13, 14, 17, 21–25, 46, 78)) are common 26, 63, 65), which mandates essence to be embodied (69–72). Such interaction would explain
across cultures, including those that exercise mind opacity(14)*. why, on the one hand, the dead is believed to preserve primarily epistemic states (as
expected by Dualism), yet its artifacts (e.g., sweater) can be disgusting, even though disgust
Our findings thus open the possibility that the separation of minds typically requires bodily contact (80–82)—the disgust is predicted by Essentialism.

6 of 8   https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2211628119 pnas.org
All materials and procedures were reviewed and approved by the Institutional the different responses to the Replication and Afterlife probes do not arise
Review Board at Northeastern University. All participants signed (electronically) from individual differences between group members. A separate analysis of
an informed consent form. the within-group outcomes fully matched the total sample, so here, we report
the full sample
Experiment 4
After the Dualism probes, participants were given the ToM task. In the ToM
Participants. Two groups of Prolific participants (ASD and NT controls, N = 84
test, participants were randomly presented with 20 short vignettes in which
each) were assigned to each of the two Dualism manipulations (Embodiment/
a protagonist has acquired a false belief. These materials were adapted from
Afterlife).
ref. 74, so as to dissociate the presence of true/false belief from its veracity.
Materials and design. Participants in this experiment took part in three tasks:
Thus, in half of the vignettes, the belief was false, and the protagonist was
Dualism task, ToM task, and an AQ quotient test.
likely to hold that belief (under the circumstances detailed in the vignette),
The Dualism task featured the Replication and Afterlife manipulations,
whereas in the others, the belief was true, but the protagonist was unlikely
described in Experiments 1–2. One subgroup of participants (N = 96) took
to hold it. Participants were instructed to quickly determine whether the
part in the Replication/Afterlife tasks in a between-group fashion (2 (ASD/NT) x 2
probe sentence was true or false (for the full materials and instructions, see
task (Replication/Afterlife) x 24 participants per group). This subgroup included
SI Appendix, Appendix III).
primarily participants who had previously taken part in Experiments 1–2 (their Finally, participants were given the AQ (from ref. 73; this test asks participants
responses therein were used as their Dualism score), and it was complemented to respond to fifty short sentences, related to their social skills, attention switching,
by additional Prolific participants who were given the Dualism probes sepa- attention to detail, communication, and imagination.
rately (prior to the ToM and AQ probes). The remaining 72 participants were
administered the Dualism and Replication probes in a within-group fashion
(such that each task featured half of the traits, and tasks were counter-balanced Data, Materials, and Software Availability. The data accompanying this sub-
for order; see SI Appendix, Table S2); this design was adopted to ensure that mission is included as a supplementary data file and SI Appendix.

1. P. Bloom, Descartes’ Baby: How the Science of Child Development Explains What Makes Us Human 29. A. F. Shariff et al., Free will and punishment: A mechanistic view of human nature reduces
(Basic Books, New York, 2004), pp. xv, 271. retribution. Psychol. Sci. 25, 1563–1570 (2014).
2. M. Forstmann, P. Burgmer, Adults are intuitive mind-body dualists. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 144, 30. V. A. Kuhlmeier, P. Bloom, K. Wynn, Do 5-month-old infants see humans as material objects?
222–235 (2015). Cognition 94, 95–103 (2004).
3. J. Bering, K. McLeod, T. Shackelford, Reasoning about dead agents reveals possible adaptive trends. 31. E. S. Spelke, A. Phillips, A. L. Woodward, “Infants’ knowledge of object motion and human action”
Hum. Nat. 16, 360–381 (2005). in Causal Cognition: A Multidisciplinary Debate, D. Sperber et al., Eds. (Clarendon Press/Oxford
4. E. Cohen, J. Barrett, When minds migrate: Conceptualizing spirit possession. J. Cognit. Cult. 8, University Press, New York, NY, US, 1995), pp. 44–78.
23–48 (2008). 32. A. Martin, Belief representation in great Apes. Trends Cognit. Sci. 23, 985–986 (2019).
5. E. Cohen, E. Burdett, N. Knight, J. Barrett, Cross-cultural similarities and differences in person-body 33. R. Báez-Mendoza, Z. M. Williams, Monkeys show theory of mind. Cell Rep. 30, 4319–4320
reasoning: Experimental evidence from the United Kingdom and Brazilian Amazon. Cognit. Sci. 35, (2020).
1282–1304 (2011). 34. S. Pika, M. J. Sima, C. R. Blum, E. Herrmann, R. Mundry, Ravens parallel great apes in physical and
6. M. Forstmann, P. Burgmer, T. Mussweiler, “The mind is willing, but the flesh is weak”: The effects of social cognitive skills. Sci. Rep. 10, 20617 (2020).
mind-body dualism on health behavior. Psychol. Sci. 23, 1239–1245 (2012). 35. D. J. Horschler, L. R. Santos, E. L. MacLean, How do non-human primates represent others’ awareness
7. N. A. Heflick, J. L. Goldenberg, J. Hart, S. M. Kamp, Death awareness and body–self dualism: A why of where objects are hidden? Cognition 212, 104658 (2021).
and how of afterlife belief. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. 45, 267–275 (2015). 36. L. Lonardo, C. J. Völter, C. Lamm, L. Huber, Dogs follow human misleading suggestions more often
8. I. Berent, M. Platt, Laypeople’s misconceptions towards psychiatric disorders: Brain disorders are when the informant has a false belief. Proc. Biol. Sci. 288, 20210906 (2021).
presumed innate. Cognit. Sci. 45, e12970 (2021). 37. K. McAuliffe et al., Cleaner fish are sensitive to what their partners can and cannot see. Commun.
9. I. Berent, M. Platt, The true “me”—Mind or body? J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 93, 104100 (2021). Biol. 4, 1127 (2021).
10. I. Berent, M. Platt, G. M. Sandoboe, “Empiricism is natural: It arises from dualism and essentialism” 38. L. Regolin, G. Vallortigara, Perception of partly occluded objects by young chicks. Percept.
in Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, T. Lombrozo, J. Knobe, S. Nichols, Eds. (Oxford Psychophys. 57, 971–976 (1995).
University Press, 2021), vol. 4, chap. 5, pp. 112–154. 39. S. E. G. Lea, A. M. Slater, C. M. E. Ryan, Perception of object unity in chicks: A comparison with the
11. G. Sandoboe, I. Berent, The seductive allure of the brain: Dualism and lay perceptions of human infant. Infant Behav. Dev. 19, 501–504 (1996).
neuroscience. Cognit. Neuropsychol. 38, 205–230 (2021). 40. E. S. Spelke, Initial knowledge: Six suggestions. Cognition 50, 431–445 (1994).
12. I. Berent, Can the mind command the body? Cognit. Sci. 45, e13067 (2021). 41. E. S. Spelke, K. D. Kinzler, Core knowledge. Dev. Sci. 10, 89–96 (2007).
13. E. Slingerland, M. Chudek, The prevalence of mind-body dualism in early China. Cognit. Sci. 35, 997 42. E. S. Spelke, K. Breinlinger, J. Macomber, K. Jacobson, Origins of knowledge. Psychol. Rev. 99,
(2011). 605–632 (1992).
14. M. Chudek, R. A. McNamara, S. Birch, P. Bloom, J. Henrich, Do minds switch bodies? Dualist 43. S. Baron-Cohen, A. M. Leslie, U. Frith, Does the autistic child have a "theory of mind"? Cognition 21,
interpretations across ages and societies. Religion Brain Behav. 8, 354–368 (2018). 37–46 (1985).
15. K. E. Stanovich, Implicit philosophies of mind: The dualism scale and its relation to religiosity and 44. A. M. Leslie, Pretense and representation: The origins of ‘theory of mind’. Psychol. Rev. 94, 412–426
belief in extrasensory perception. J. Psychol. 123, 5–23 (1989). (1987).
16. K. Weisman, C. S. Dweck, E. M. Markman, Rethinking people’s conceptions of mental life. Proc. Natl. 45. A. M. Leslie, O. Friedman, T. P. German, Core mechanisms in "theory of mind". Trends Cognit. Sci. 8,
Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 114, 11374–11379 (2017). 528–533 (2004).
17. K. Weisman et al., Similarities and differences in concepts of mental life among adults and children 46. P. Boyer, Minds Make Societies: How Cognition Explains the World Humans Create (Yale University
in five cultures. Nat. Hum. Behav. 5, 1358–1368 (2021), 10.1038/s41562-021-01184-8. Press, New Haven, 2018).
18. J. M. Bering, D. F. Bjorklund, The natural emergence of reasoning about the afterlife as a 47. B. Tick, P. Bolton, F. Happé, M. Rutter, F. Rijsdijk, Heritability of autism spectrum disorders: A meta-
developmental regularity. Dev. Psychol. 40, 217–233 (2004). analysis of twin studies. J. Child Psychol. Psychiatry 57, 585–595 (2016).
19. B. Hood, N. L. Gjersoe, P. Bloom, Do children think that duplicating the body also duplicates the 48. S. Baron-Cohen et al., The "Reading the mind in the eyes" test: Complete absence of typical sex
mind? Cognition 125, 466–474 (2012). difference in ~400 men and women with autism. PLoS One 10, e0136521 (2015).
20. P. Boyer, Minds Make Societies: How Cognition Explains the World Humans Create (Yale University 49. A. Senju, V. Southgate, S. White, U. Frith, Mindblind eyes: An absence of spontaneous theory of
Press, New Haven, 2018). mind in asperger syndrome. Science 325, 883–885 (2009).
21. R. E. Watson-Jones, J. T. A. Busch, P. L. Harris, C. H. Legare, Does the body survive death? Cultural 50. G. Atherton, L. Cross, Animal Faux Pas: Two legs good four legs bad for theory of mind, but not in the
variation in beliefs about life everlasting. Cognit. Sci. 41, 455–476 (2017). broad autism spectrum. J. Genetic Psychol. 180, 81–95 (2019).
22. J. D. Lane, L. Zhu, E. M. Evans, H. M. Wellman, Developing concepts of the mind, body, and afterlife: 51. F. I. Thiébaut et al., Does faux pas detection in adult autism reflect differences in social cognition or
Exploring the roles of narrative context and culture. J. Cognit. Cult. 16, 50–82 (2016). decision-making abilities? J. Autism Dev. Disord. 46, 103–112 (2016).
23. J. M. Bering, C. H. Blasi, D. F. Bjorklund, The development of "afterlife" beliefs in religiously and 52. T. Zalla, A.-M. Sav, A. Stopin, S. Ahade, M. Leboyer, Faux pas detection and intentional action
secularly schooled children. Br. J. Dev. Psychol. 23, 587–607 (2005). in Asperger Syndrome. A replication on a French sample. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 39, 373–382
24. P. L. Harris, M. Giménez, Children’s acceptance of conflicting testimony: The case of death. J. Cognit. (2009).
Cult. 5, 143–164 (2005). 53. M. Buon et al., The role of causal and intentional judgments in moral reasoning in individuals with
25. R. Astuti, P. L. Harris, Understanding mortality and the life of the ancestors in rural madagascar. high functioning autism. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 43, 458–470 (2012).
Cognit. Sci. 32, 713–740 (2008). 54. J. M. Moran et al., Impaired theory of mind for moral judgment in high-functioning autism. Proc.
26. I. Berent, M. Platt, Public misconceptions about dyslexia: The role of intuitive psychology. PLoS One Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 108, 2688–2692 (2011).
16, e0259019 (2021). 55. B. Rogé, E. Mullet, Blame and forgiveness judgements among children, adolescents and adults with
27. W.-K. Ahn, N. S. Kim, M. S. Lebowitz, “The role of causal knowledge in reasoning about autism. Autism 15, 702–712 (2011).
mental disorders” in Oxford Library of Psychology. The Oxford Handbook of Causal 56. L. Jameel, K. Vyas, G. Bellesi, S. Crawford, S. Channon, Thinking about other’s mistakes:
Reasoning, M. R. Waldmann, Ed. (Oxford University Press, 2017), pp. 603–617, 10.1093/ Contrasting patterns of performance in groups high or low in autistic or psychopathic traits. Cognit.
oxfordhb/9780199399550.013.31. Neuropsychiatry 24, 369–385 (2019).
28. J. Greene, J. Cohen, For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything. Philos. Trans. Biol. 57. G. Bellesi, K. Vyas, L. Jameel, S. Channon, Moral reasoning about everyday situations in adults with
Sci. 359, 1775–1785 (2004). autism spectrum disorder. Res. Autism Spectr. Disord. 52, 1–11 (2018).

PNAS  2022  Vol. 119  No. 49  e2211628119 https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2211628119   7 of 8


58. U. Frith, Emanuel Miller lecture: Confusions and controversies about Asperger syndrome. J. Child. 72. K. A. Lindquist, M. Gendron, S. Oosterwijk, L. F. Barrett, Do people essentialize emotions? Individual
Psychol. Psychiatry 45, 672–686 (2004). differences in emotion essentialism and emotional experience. Emotion 13, 629–644 (2013).
59. S. Channon, D. Lagnado, S. Fitzpatrick, H. Drury, I. Taylor, Judgments of cause and blame: Sensitivity 73. S. Baron-Cohen, S. Wheelwright, R. Skinner, J. Martin, E. Clubley, The Autism-spectrum quotient
to intentionality in asperger’s syndrome. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 41, 1534–1542 (2011). (AQ): Evidence from asperger syndrome/high-functioning autism, males and females, scientists and
60. M. A. Gernsbacher, M. Yergeau, Empirical failures of the claim that autistic people lack a theory of mathematicians. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 31, 5–17 (2001).
mind. Arch. Sci. Psychol. 7, 102–118 (2019). 74. D. Dodell-Feder, J. Koster-Hale, M. Bedny, R. Saxe, fMRI item analysis in a theory of mind task.
61. I. Berent, M. Platt, G. M. Sandoboe, People’s intuitions about innateness. Open Mind: Dis. Cognit. NeuroImage 55, 705–712 (2011).
Sci. 3, 101–114 (2019). 75. S. Baron-Cohen, Autism: The empathizing-systemizing (E - S) theory. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 1156,
62. D. Bates, M. Mächler, B. Bolker, S. Walker, Fitting linear mixed-effects models using {lme4}. J. Statist. 68–80 (2009).
Sof. 67, 1–48 (2015). 76. S. Flusberg, H. Tager-Flusberg, Autism, language, and the folk psychology of souls. Behav. Brain Sci.
63. I. Berent, Can we get human nature right? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 118, e2108274118 (2021). 29, 473–473 (2006).
64. I. Berent, The Blind Storyteller: How We Reason About Human Nature (Oxford University Press, 2020). 77. F. J. Scott, S. Baron-Cohen, A. Leslie, "If pigs could fly": A test of counterfactual reasoning and
65. I. Berent, L. F. Barrett, M. Platt, Essentialist biases in reasoning about emotions. Front. Psychol. pretence in children with autism. Br. J. Dev. Psychol. 17, 349–362 (1999).
Cognit. Sci. 11, 562666 (2020), 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.562666. 78. C. Lomnitz-Adler, Death and the Idea of Mexico Princeton University Press, (2005), p. 581.
66. J. J. Wang, L. Feigenson, Is empiricism innate? Preference for nurture over nature in people’s beliefs 79. M. Barlev, A. Shtulman, Minds, Bodies, spirits, and gods: Does widespread belief in disembodied
about the origins of human knowledge. Open Mind 3, 89–100 (2019). beings imply that we are inherent dualists? Psychol. Rev. 128, 1007–1021 (2021).
67. S. A. Gelman, The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought (Oxford series in 80. C. Nemeroff, P. Rozin, The contagion concept in adult thinking in the United States: Transmission of
Cognitive Development, Oxford University Press, Oxford; New York, 2003), p. 382. germs and of interpersonal influence. Ethos 22, 158–186 (1994).
68. F. C. Keil, “The acquisition of natural kind and artifact term” in Language Learning and Concept 81. P. Rozin, C. Nemeroff, “Sympathetic magical thinking: The contagion and similarity ‘heuristics”
Acquisition, W. Demopoulos, A. Marras, Eds. (Ablex, Norwood, New Jersey, 1986), pp. 133–153. in Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment, T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, D.
69. I. Berent, On the matter of essence. Cognition 213, 104701 (2021). Kahneman, Eds. (Cambridge University Press, New York, NY, 2002), pp. 201–216, 10.1017/
70. G. E. Newman, F. C. Keil, Where is the essence? Developmental shifts in children’s beliefs about CBO9780511808098.013.
internal features. Child Dev. 79, 1344–1356 (2008). 82. P. Rozin, M. Markwith, C. McCauley, Sensitivity to indirect contacts with other persons: AIDS aversion
71. N. Haslam, B. Bastian, M. Bissett, Essentialist beliefs about personality and their implications. Per. as a composite of aversion to strangers, infection, moral taint, and misfortune. J. Abnorm. Psychol.
Soc. Psychol. Bull. 30, 1661–1673 (2004). 103, 495–504 (1994).

8 of 8   https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2211628119 pnas.org

You might also like