Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

CHAPTER

What Is Routine Dynamics?


1
MARTHA S. FELDMAN, BRIAN T. PENTLAND,
L U C I A N A D’ A D D E R I O , K A T H A R I N A DI T T R I C H ,
CLAUS RERUP AND DAVID SEIDL

1.1 Introduction Dynamics perspective and how they have


developed over time. This chapter aims to provide
Over the last two decades, Routine Dynamics has the reader with a solid grasp of the Routine
emerged as an international research community Dynamics approach as well with suggestions for
that shares a particular approach to organizational further reading to deepen the understanding of
phenomena. At the heart of this approach is an particular aspects of this approach.
interest in examining the emergence, reproduc-
tion, replication, and change of recognizable pat-
terns of actions. In contrast to other research 1.2 A Brief Genealogy of Research on
communities interested in those phenomena, Organizational Routines
Routine Dynamics studies are informed by a dis-
tinctive set of theories (e.g., practice theory and To understand Routine Dynamics research, it is
related process-informed theories) that directs important to consider how research on routines
researchers’ attention to particular aspects of has developed historically (see also Felin and
these phenomena (e.g., actions), yielding distinct- Foss, 2009; Mahringer, 2019; Parmigiani and
ive insights about them (e.g., routines are Howard-Grenville, 2011). Situated in a particular
dynamic). historical context, various scholars have
In this chapter, we offer an introduction to developed the concept in response to specific
Routine Dynamics as a particular approach to questions at the time. One of the first to explore
studying organizational phenomena. For this pur- the role of routines in organizations was
pose, we provide a brief description of the geneal- Frederick Taylor. Even though he did not use
ogy of research on routines; starting with the work the term ‘routine’ his book The Principles of
of the management scholar Fredrick Taylor Scientific Management, published in 1911, laid
(1911) and the pragmatist philosopher John the foundations for the standardization of work
Dewey (1922) at the beginning of the last century, and thus the use of routines as a means for man-
to the works of the Carnegie School on standard agerial control, supervision, and efficiency.
operating procedures around the middle of the last Taylor applied scientific methods to identify the
century, to the economics-based Capabilities ‘best’ way to complete a task and encouraged
approach and the practice-based approach of managers to provide instructions and supervision
Routine Dynamics that emerged around the turn to ensure that workers are using the most efficient
of the century. We also discuss the advantages of way of working. A few years later, Stene (1940:
conceptualizing patterns of action as ‘routines’, as 1129), who was interested in collective coordin-
compared to ‘practices’, ‘processes’, ‘activities’ ation in organizations, explicitly referred to rou-
or ‘institutions’. In particular, we highlight that tines as ‘activities which ha[ve] become habitual
the concept of routines directs the researcher’s because of repetition and which [are] followed
attention to certain features of action patterns, regularly without specific directions or detailed
such as task orientation, sequentiality of actions, supervision’.
recurrence, and familiarity as well as attempts at In a different line of work, the concept of rou-
reflexive regulation. We also introduce and tines also appeared in the works of the pragmatist
explain the key concepts of the Routine John Dewey (1922) (more on pragmatism can be

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


2 Martha S. Feldman et al.

found in Dionysiou [Chapter 5], this volume). (1982) Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change.
Dewey was primarily interested in learning, both The authors drew on evolutionary economics and
at the individual and collective level, and the framework of variation, selection, and retention
developed the notion of habit as reflective action. to counter traditional neoclassical assumptions of
Dewey (1922) distinguished between intelligent how firms develop and change over time. Defining
habit and dead or mindless habit, highlighting that routines as ‘regular and predictable behavior pat-
except for the pathological extreme (the dead rou- terns of firms’ (Nelson and Winter, 1982: 14),
tine), routines are lively, infused with emotions, Nelson and Winter defined three roles for routines:
reflection, and morality (Cohen, 2007; Winter, (1) Routines as genes: here, routines determine
2013). Even though Dewey and others suggest which firms are selected by the environment and
using the term ‘routine’ only for the pathological thus survive. (2) Routines as organizational
extreme of a dead routine, Routine Dynamics has memory: organizations store knowledge in routin-
instead chosen to keep the term ‘routine’ and show ized activities and thus ‘remember by doing’
how it is lively, dynamic, and only in rare circum- (Nelson and Winter, 1982: 99). (3) Routines as
stances dead or mindless. truces: because of the diverging interests of organ-
Between the mid-forties and mid-sixties, a dis- izational members, routines serve as comprehensive
tinctive view, known as the Carnegie School, truces that prevent intraorganizational conflict in
developed, primarily as an effort to overcome repetitive activities (see also D’Adderio and Safavi
the limitations of classical economic theory that [Chapter 15], this volume). In addition to outlining
was dominant at the time (see also Rerup and the role of routines, Nelson and Winter also identi-
Spencer [Chapter 33], this volume). Simon’s fied the importance of organizational capabilities,
(1947) Administrative Behavior, March and broadly defined as ‘the range of things a firm can
Simon’s (1958) Organizations, and Cyert and do at any time’ (Nelson and Winter, 1982: 52).
March’s (1963) Behavioral Theory of the Firm Capabilities are seen as bundles of routines that give
were all concerned with opening up the black- rise to a firm’s competitive advantage (see also
box of the firm and developing theory on how Salvato [Chapter 34], this volume).
firms behave as a result of lower-level processes, Subsequently, two strands of research developed
such as routines (see also Gavetti, Greve, almost independently of each other: the Capabilities
Levinthal, and Ocasio, 2012). Simon (1947) was perspective and the Routine Dynamics perspective
interested in decision-making of boundedly (Parmigiani and Howard-Grenville, 2011). The
rational individuals and argued that routines, Capabilities perspective, grounded in organizational
understood as simple rules, develop to save time economics and drawing heavily on the work of
and attention. March and Simon (1958) described Nelson and Winter, was primarily interested in
routines as ‘performance programs’, that is, a understanding how capabilities as bundles of rou-
fixed response to a defined stimulus that has been tines relate to firm performance (Dosi, Faillo, and
learned over time. Thus, in the case of a routine, Marengo, 2008; Dosi, Nelson, and Winter, 2000;
search has been eliminated and choice simplified. Peng, Schroeder, and Shah, 2008). Authors working
In Cyert and March (1963), reliable, stable stand- within this perspective thus ‘black-boxed’ routines
ard operating procedures (SOPs) are important and assumed that individuals execute routines as
because they allow firms to cope with uncertainty designed. From this perspective, organizational
and enable effective decision-making. Overall, change was explained by so-called dynamic cap-
being concerned with bounded rationality, the abilities, that is, meta-routines that change operating
Carnegie School foregrounded the cognitive routines (Winter, 2003).
dimension of routines and their ability to stabilize, In contrast, the Routine Dynamics perspective
and conserve resources (see also Lazaric developed from an interest in what happens inside
[Chapter 18], this volume). the routine. It ‘altered the grain size or granularity
Another important milestone in the development of analysis and moved the unit of analysis from the
of routines research was Nelson and Winter’s firm and the routines that constitute them to the

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


What Is Routine Dynamics? 3

routine and the actions that constitute them’ produces new ways of thinking about routines.
(Feldman, 2016: 27). It also moved the focus away Often, different theories have more in common than
from formal procedures and cognition to the we think, but in order to draw on them and combine
actions taken by specific people in specific times them in generative ways, one needs to be familiar
and places. By drawing on different methods, in with them. Many works of Routine Dynamics can
particular ethnographic observations, interviews, be understood in a deeper and more interesting way
and archival data (see also Dittrich [Chapter 8], if understood with these theories in the background.
this volume), Routine Dynamics scholars started We hope that the chapters contained in the first part
to challenge received wisdom about routines. For of this Handbook provide the theoretical toolkit to
example, Pentland and Rueter (1994) found that better understand Routine Dynamics.
there was more variety in performing routines than The new way of theorizing routines based on
previous research acknowledged. And Feldman this latticework has shifted the focus from routines
(2000) found that routines were sources of change as ‘entities’ in early works to routines as being
over time – a finding that challenged the dominant constituted of parts, that is, the ostensive and per-
view of routines as sources for stability and inertia. formative aspects of routines (Feldman and
In search of an alternative understanding of rou- Pentland, 2003). It has also shifted the emphasis
tines, one that accounts for human agency, variety, from routines as inherently static to routines as
and change, scholars also started to draw on differ- generative and dynamic (Howard-Grenville and
ent theoretical resources. Even though the common Rerup, 2017; Parmigiani and Howard-Grenville,
saying is that Routine Dynamics is primarily 2011). Theorizing the dynamic aspects of routines
informed by Giddens’ (1984) structuration theory, has helped to see that stability and change in rou-
in fact from the outset and in the ensuing years, the tines are not opposites but that in fact they are
field has been influenced by a plethora of theories, mutually constituted (Farjoun, 2010; Tsoukas and
a true latticework of ideas. For example, Martha Chia, 2002). This relation is captured in the ‘para-
Feldman (in Feldman and Orlikowski, 2011), dox of the (n)ever-changing world’ (Birnholtz,
reflecting on her early studies in Routine Cohen and Hoch, 2007: 316), that is, the assump-
Dynamics, describes how she drew on various tions that ‘one does not step into the same river
theories of practice (e.g., Bourdieu, 1977; 1990; twice’ and that ‘there is no new thing under the
Bourdieu and Wacquant, 1992; Giddens, 1976; sun’ can coexist in routines. Routine dynamics has
1979; 1984; for more see Feldman [Chapter 2], been progressively moving towards ‘stronger pro-
this volume), on phenomenology (Schutz, 1967; cess theorizing’, and further progress has been
1970), on ethnomethodology (Garfinkel, 1967; achieved through the rhetorical shift from osten-
see Lopez-Cotarelo [Chapter 4], this volume), and sive and performative to ‘performing’ and ‘pattern-
on actor-network theory (ANT) (Latour, 1986, ing’ – or in other words ‘the doing involved in the
2005; see Sele [Chapter 6], this volume) to theorize creating of both performative and ostensive
the findings from her fieldwork. All these theories aspects’ (Feldman 2016: 39).
are forms of process theorizing (Tsoukas Overall, the conceptual development in research
[Chapter 3], this volume) that have enabled on routines over the last one hundred years has led
Routine Dynamics to shift towards a more proces- to significant changes in the way we use the term
sual focus of how routines are enacted and change ‘routine’. In common language, the term ‘routine’
over time. Subsequently, Routine Dynamics is primarily used as an adjective to describe the
scholars also drew on pragmatism (Dionysiou ordinary/mundane and the automatic/mindless and
[Chapter 5], this volume) and socio-materiality repetitious character of something. In the Carnegie
(D’Adderio [Chapter 7], this volume) to theorize School and evolutionary theory that sees routines
the dynamics of routines. as ‘fixed things’, the adjective and the noun ‘rou-
This latticework or ‘stew’ (Feldman and tine’ were the same thing, i.e., the automatic, mind-
Orlikowski, 2011: 1244) of ideas is important less execution of a task. With Routine Dynamics,
because the blending and mixing together of ideas we moved ‘beyond routines as things’ (Feldman

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


4 Martha S. Feldman et al.

et al., 2016: 505). While we still use nouns to refer activity systems conceptualize these action patterns
to routines, these nouns are no longer the same as as ‘activities’, where an activity is defined as ‘a
the adjective ‘routine’ because we see routines as discrete economic process within the firm, such as
dynamic and generative. With an even stronger delivering finished products to customers or
processual orientation, we are now moving from training employees, that can be configured in a
the noun to the verb, that is, from ‘routines’ to variety of ways’ (Porter and Siggelkow, 2008:
‘patterning’ and ‘performing’ (the verb ‘routiniz- 34). Many institutional scholars, in turn, conceptu-
ing’, however, is not what we mean here because alize these patterns as ‘institutions’; highlighting
‘routinizing’ typically refers to managerial efforts that ‘there is, and has been, a general understand-
to turn patterns of action into formalized, standard- ing that institutions are . . . patterns of action
ized, controllable and stable procedures). These (behavior)’ (Mayhew, 2008: 28) and defining insti-
changes in how the term ‘routine’ is used can be tutions as ‘stable, valued, recurring patterns of
confusing at first, but once clarified this language behavior’ (Huntington, 1968: 9).
can become very generative for understanding While it might seem irrelevant whether we
organizational phenomena. Before we discuss in label such action patterns ‘routines’, ‘practices’,
more depth the key terminology used in Routine ‘processes’, ‘activities’, ‘institutions’ or whatever
Dynamics research, we first turn to why it can be else, these labels tend to be associated with dif-
useful to call an empirical phenomenon a ‘routine’. ferent theoretical perspectives, which direct the
researcher’s attention to particular aspects of
these patterns and away from others. This begs
1.3 What Is to Be Gained from the question of what can be gained from studying
Conceptualizing an Empirical action patterns as routines. This question is par-
Phenomenon as a ‘Routine’? ticularly acute when it comes to the concepts of
routines and practices, as Routine Dynamics is
Routine Dynamics scholars are not the only ones to explicitly based on a practice perspective
examine recurrent patterns of interdependent (Feldman and Pentland, 2003).
actions (Parmigiani and Howard-Grenville, 2011). The relation between the concept of routines and
There are many other research communities who that of practices is somewhat complex, which has
take an interest in action patterns, but they capture something to do with the fact that the concept of
them with other concepts. For example, many practices is defined differently in different practice
practice scholars conceptualize action patterns as theories. Most practice theorists, such as Giddens
‘practices’, such as when Reckwitz (2002: 249) (1984) or Reckwitz (2002), would probably concur
defines practices as ‘a routinized type of behaviour that ‘while not all practices are routines, all rou-
which consists of several elements, interconnected tines are practices’ (Feldman [Chapter 2], this
to one other: forms of bodily activities, forms of volume). For example, the hiring routine can be
mental activities, “things” and their use, a back- considered a practice, while the practice of a hand-
ground knowledge in the form of understanding, shake or gift-giving would not be considered a
know-how, states of emotion and motivational routine. Thus, from this perspective, routines are
knowledge’. Similarly Rasche and Chia (2009: conceptualized as a sub-category of practices.
721) highlight that practices ‘are first of all an Other practice theorists, such as Schatzki (2002),
observed patterned consistency of bodily activities; would at least agree that routines are an important
coherent clusters of activities that are condensed element of practices, that is, they are a part of
through repetition’. In business process manage- larger practices. In line with both interpretations,
ment, such activity patterns are referred to as ‘pro- the Routine Dynamics perspective can be
cesses’ (Weske, 2019). Benner and Tushman described as a practice perspective that sensitizes
(2003: 240), for example, define processes as ‘col- the researcher to certain specificities of particular
lections of activities that, taken together, produce action patterns; analogously to the way that organ-
outputs for customers’. Scholars concerned with ization theories tend to sensitize researchers better

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


What Is Routine Dynamics? 5

to the particularities of organizations than general contain many routines, such as particular treatment
social theories. routines, diagnostic routines (Goh et al., 2011) or
One aspect that characterizes routines as particu- handoff routines (LeBaron et al., 2016), but as a
lar practices is the fact that routines are ostensibly whole this practice cannot be described as a regular
directed at the accomplishment of particular tasks – sequence of actions. Thus, taking a routines lens
even though routines do not always accomplish directs the researcher’s attention to the different
these tasks and not everyone involved in these rou- patterns of action sequences and their variations,
tines necessarily wants the task accomplished. As which can be described and visualized in the form
Feldman (2016: 24) writes, ‘organizational routines of narrative networks (see Pentland and Kim
are enacted in order to do something in and for the [Chapter 13], this volume). In line with the
organization’. For example, a hiring routine emphasis on sequences of actions and how patterns
(Feldman, 2000; Rerup and Feldman, 2011) is of actions evolve over time, studies of Routine
directed at the task of hiring someone, a pricing Dynamics are also process studies (Feldman,
routine (Zbaracki and Bergen, 2010) is directed at 2016; Howard-Grenville and Rerup, 2017).
setting prices, a garbage collection routine (Turner A third aspect that characterizes routines as
and Rindova, 2012) is directed at the task of collect- particular practices is the recurrent nature of the
ing garbage, a shipping routine (Dittrich et al., action pattern which results in some kind of famil-
2016) is directed at shipping something or a road- iarity with the routine. One would typically not
mapping routine (Howard-Grenville, 2005) is speak of an organizational routine if an action
directed at developing and reviewing a roadmap. pattern was just enacted once in the organization.
Because of this task orientation, routines are often This familiarity has important implications for the
associated with organizations or work contexts – enactment of routines as the participants’ earlier
i.e., accomplishing some subtasks of the organiza- experiences with the routine provide them with
tion. In contrast, some practices might lack a clear particular competence and points of reference for
focus on specific tasks. For example, the practice of the enactment (Birnholtz et al., 2007; Deken et al.,
marriage (Whittington, 2007) is not directed at the 2016; Turner and Fern, 2012). In contrast, some
accomplishment of a particular task; instead, prac- practices, while recurring in wider society, might
tising the marriage is a purpose in itself. Similarly, be enacted just once in the immediate context and
the practice of horse betting (Schatzki, 2010) is not thus be entirely novel to all participants. To be
oriented at accomplishing a task which could then sure, this difference is just a matter of degree as
be measured as having been accomplished well or all practices presuppose at least some rudimentary
not. Thus, taking a routine lens directs the research- familiarity with the practice. Thus, by highlight-
er’s attention to the way that these tasks are accom- ing this repetitiveness and familiarity, a routine
plished and how orientation to the tasks affects the lens directs the researcher’s attention to the par-
way the routines are enacted. ticipants’ experiences with earlier enactments of
A second aspect that characterizes routines as the action pattern and how this affects future
particular practices is the significance of the par- routine enactments.
ticular sequences in which actions are performed A fourth aspect characterizing routines as par-
(see Mahringer and Pentland [Chapter 12], this ticular practices are attempts at their reflective
volume). Some practice theorists such as Schatzki regulation. Because routines are directed at accom-
(2002: 2017) stress that the concept of practice plishing particular tasks and tend to be repetitively
does not focus on particular action sequences. As enacted, we often find explicit attempts at ‘man-
he writes, ’he doings and sayings that compose a aging’ the action sequences of which the routines
practice need not be regular’ (Schatzki, 2002: are made. We often find standard operating pro-
73–74). The regular action sequences described cedures or if-then statements providing instructions
by routines are then just a particular type of prac- for the way routines are supposed to be enacted
tice or even just an element of practices. For (Cyert and March, 1963). Managers and employ-
example, the practice of medicine can be said to ees often also try to adapt routines (e.g., Salvato,

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


6 Martha S. Feldman et al.

2009; Salvato and Rerup, 2018), design artifacts to aware that there may be terms that change more
change routines (e.g., Glaser, 2017; Pentland and rapidly or substantially and terms that extend, chal-
Feldman, 2008) or switch between routines as a lenge or perhaps even replace established termin-
way of influencing the outcomes produced by ology. After two decades, the field may be
those routines. In contrast, there are many practices stabilizing but it also remains open, both to
where such attempts at reflective regulation would retaining established meanings and interpretations
appear somewhat at odds. Practices such as mar- and towards developing new vocabularies. In these
riage or dining are just taken for granted and changes we are guided by our questions and the
attempts at reflectively regulating these practices world we explore.
would be rather unusual – even though not entirely In the following we discuss several terms that
impossible. Thus, taking a routines lens directs the have grown to have specific meanings within
researcher’s attention to the role that explicit Routine Dynamics and concepts that readers not
attempts at managing or influencing routines already immersed in Routine Dynamics or related
through artifacts, such as standard operating pro- communities (like practice theory or relational
cedures or explicit rules, have on the enactment of sociology) might find confusing. While we
routines as well as the co-evolution between those describe these concepts here, they are best under-
artifacts and actual routine performances. stood through the many detailed empirical
accounts of Routine Dynamics where these con-
cepts come to life. Moreover, there are many other
1.4 Key Concepts of Routine Dynamics concepts that are important to Routine Dynamics
and used in Routine Dynamics studies that we do
In this section we review some of the key con- not discuss here. Temporality is a good example.
cepts used in Routine Dynamics, focusing on Though clearly important to our understanding of
their origins and evolution over time. Many of routines and to the development of Routine
the concepts were imported into Routine Dynamics (see Turner and Rindova [Chapter 19],
Dynamics from neighbouring theories, at times this volume), the Routine Dynamics community
being reproduced faithfully, and at other times draws on ways of talking about time that one
being modified or reinvented. We note that the would readily understand without having read
vocabulary has grown substantially over time (we other Routine Dynamics studies.
have a garden with old and new flowers) coming
to form today an expressive, evolving language.
1.4.1 Effortful and
One clear trend has been the progressive move
Emergent Accomplishments
towards a more deeply processual and performa-
tive language. This has allowed us to reveal the That routines are both effortful and emergent has
dynamics of routines and successively unravel become a cornerstone of Routine Dynamics, in con-
the forces within Routine Dynamics. Next, we trast with earlier understandings of routines as auto-
review some of the most common meanings that matic or executed without explicit deliberation or
people in Routine Dynamics associate with effort (March and Simon 1958; Nelson and Winter
this language. 1982). Citing Giddens (who refers to both Goffman
Despite having identified some distinct trends in and Garfinkel), Pentland and Reuter note that ‘rou-
the Routine Dynamics vocabulary, we also tinized social activity is not mindless or automatic
acknowledge that part of the success behind the but, rather, an effortful accomplishment’ and that
topic has been the lightness and flexibility with ‘[e]ven some of the most routinized kinds of
which we have so far held our terminology. It is encounters, such as fast food service (Leidner,
true that there are some meanings that have more 1993) and buying stamps (Ventola, 1987), exhibit
or less stabilized and gathered substantial consen- a considerable amount of variety and require effort
sus, as described in the previous section and in on the part of the participants to accomplish suc-
Feldman et al. (2016). At the same time, we are cessfully’ (1994: 488). Picking up on the notion of

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


What Is Routine Dynamics? 7

effort, Feldman identified several kinds of effort that often one that is in the eyes of the beholder. As
people make in the process of repeating routines, Deken et al. (2016) showed in their study of three
different kinds of ‘routine work’, what feels like a
When actions do not produce the intended out-
come, or produce an unintended and undesirable small change to one person may feel like a lot of
outcome, participants can respond by repairing the change to another person. In practice, effortful and
routine so that it will produce the intended and emergent accomplishments are entangled.
desired outcome. The result may be to restore the
routine to a stable equilibrium and may not be
1.4.2 Performative and Ostensive Aspects
associated with continued change. When the out-
comes enable new opportunities, participants have and the Shift to Performing
the option of expanding. They can change the and Patterning
routine to take advantage of the new possibilities. Another important set of concepts is the idea of
Finally, when outcomes fall short of ideals, they
performative and ostensive aspects. Compared to
can respond by striving. (Feldman, 2000: 620)
effortful and emergent accomplishments these con-
In identifying these types of effort, it also became cepts are less intuitive. The ostensive/performative
clear that ‘work practices such as organizational distinction was initially introduced to the study of
routines are not only effortful but also emergent routines as a way of distinguishing an emic and
accomplishments. They are often works in pro- etic orientation,
gress rather than finished products’ (Feldman,
Latour uses these terms in describing power, but
2000: 613). As a result, new patterns of action
the concepts apply as well to routines. An osten-
(change) may emerge through the gradual accre- sive definition of a concept is one that exists in
tion of actions required to reproduce the same (i.e., principle (Sevon 1996). It is created through the
stable) pattern of action. While expanding and process of objectification as it is studied.
striving are particularly oriented to change, even A performative definition is one that is created
repairing may result in the emergence of new ways through practice. ‘Society is not the referent of
of accomplishing goals or tasks. Numerous studies an ostensive definition discovered by social sci-
in Routine Dynamics show that repetition and rep- entists despite the ignorance of their informants.
lication are not straightforward. Repetition intro- Rather it is performed through everyone’s efforts
duces opportunities for changes that overcome to define it’ (Latour 1986, p. 273). (Feldman,
2000: 622)
minor or temporary obstacles but also introduces
opportunities to do the routine differently or better. In this use – as in Latour’s use – ostensive and
The result may be more or less effective communi- performative are separable and there can be per-
cation (Bucher and Langley, 2016; LeBaron et al., formative routines and ostensive routines.
2016); better or worse products (Cohendet and ‘Ostensive routines may be devoid of active think-
Simon, 2016; Deken et al., 2016; Sele and Grand, ing, but routines enacted by people in organizations
2016); or more or less efficient processes (for inevitably involve a range of actions, behaviors,
better or worse) (Aroles and McClean, 2016; thinking, and feeling’ (Feldman, 2000: 622).
Eberhard et al., 2019; Turner and Rindova, 2012). In Feldman and Pentland (2003), these terms
The distinction between effortful and emergent were repurposed and integrated more completely
can be used to orient us to the difference between with practice theory.
variance in performance and change in practices
We adopt language proposed by Latour (1986) in
and their results. In that case, effortful accomplish-
his analysis of power, in which he pointed out that
ments often refer to variations in performance in
power exists both in principle and in practice. He
order to do the same thing or produce stability, referred to the former as the ostensive aspect of
whereas emergent accomplishment refers to the power and the latter as the performative aspect.
effort involved in doing something different or We propose that organizational routines also con-
producing change in routines or outcomes sist of ostensive and performative aspects, which
(Feldman et al., 2016). But this distinction is also are closely related to the concepts of structure and

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


8 Martha S. Feldman et al.

agency, as found in structuration theory (Giddens, from previous ways of thinking about routines. First,
1984). We adopt specialized terminology because, an insistence on the performative aspect – on identi-
in the domain of organizational routines, structure fying specific actions in specific times and places – is
and agency are mediated by the repetitive collect- a discipline that marks the empirical work in Routine
ive, interdependent nature of the phenomenon. Dynamics. Rather than describing dynamics in
(Feldman and Pentland, 2003: 100)
abstract terms, this discipline goes to the root of the
The two terms were defined in the following way, organizational dynamics and enables scholars to see
what others have missed. This discipline is very much
The ostensive aspect is the ideal or schematic form influenced by the focus in actor-network theory on
of a routine. It is the abstract, generalized idea of tracing actions and actants.
the routine, or the routine in principle. The per-
Second, as Feldman (2016: 27) writes, ‘the intro-
formative aspect of the routine consists of specific
duction of the term “ostensive” drew attention to the
actions, by specific people, in specific places and
times. It is the routine in practice. Both of these relationality of performances and patterns and the
aspects are necessary for an organizational routine constitutive nature of action in patterns. Similar to
to exist. (Feldman and Pentland, 2003: 101) Wittgenstein’s use of the term (2001), ostensive
implies that patterns are constituted of specific
That both aspects are necessary for an organiza- instances that can be pointed to as a referent.’ Take,
tional routine to exist was an important statement for instance, the example of the pattern that makes up
that further moved the field by placing performa- our everyday experience of a colour. ‘While there is
tive and ostensive aspects in a mutually constitu- a scientific definition of blue (for example, a range of
tive relation to one another. ‘[W]e have light wavelengths), on an everyday basis we know
emphasized that the ostensive and performative the color blue through the various blues (or objects
aspects of routines are mutually necessary. coloured blue) that exemplify blue. In other words,
Without the ostensive aspect, we cannot name or there are things we can point to that make up the
even see our patterns of activity, much less repro- pattern that we recognize as blue’ (Feldman, 2015:
duce them. Without the performative, nothing ever 321). Routine Dynamics makes a similar argument
happens’ (Feldman and Pentland, 2003: 115). about performances and their associated patterns.
Indeed, Feldman and Pentland (2003) connected Ostensive aspects of routines are always made up
the ostensive and performative not only to the of performances that we can point to.
duality of agency and structure highlighted by Latour has argued that the problem with ostensive
Giddens but also to the duality of subjective and definitions is that they become imbued with inde-
objective emphasized in Bourdieu’s work, pendence and mistaken as a cause of action – people
The ostensive aspect of a routine enables us to mistake ‘what is glued for the glue’ (Latour, 1986:
create an apparently objective reality through the 276). The way Routine Dynamics has used the
subjective acts of guiding, accounting, and refer- ostensive aspect militates against this mistake.
ring. As practiced objective and subjective dimen- While the ostensive aspect refers to the abstract
sions are mutually constitutive (Bourdieu, 1990). patterns of routines, it is relationally entangled with
Objective and subjective aspects are inseparable performance. This allows Routine Dynamics to
because the objectified summaries of routines (the acknowledge the importance of abstract patterns
artifacts) are constructed from our subjective per- without giving them priority over the actions that
ceptions of them. Thus, ironically, routines exist are integral to them. The notion of ostensive aspects
as objects because of our subjective understand-
that are enacted patterns, produced through action,
ings of them. In a sense, our subjective under-
moves Routine Dynamics away from a focus on
standing and interpretation is the glue that binds
the actions into the patterns we recognize as patterns that are envisioned, intended or mandated.
the routine. (Feldman and Pentland, 2003: 109) As empirical work in Routine Dynamics gave
meaning to the performative and ostensive aspects
The emphasis in Routine Dynamics on both per- of routines by identifying the specific actions taken
formative and ostensive aspects constitutes departures by specific people at specific times and places and

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


What Is Routine Dynamics? 9

the enacted patterns that emerged as a result of 1988) and acquired meaning in Suchman’s distinc-
these specific actions, the processual ontology of tion between ‘plans’ and ‘situated action’.
routines also developed. For instance, in 2014,
That term underscores the view that every course
D’Adderio identified the effortful (Pentland and
of action depends in essential ways on its material
Rueter, 1994) and emergent (Feldman, 2000) and social circumstances. Rather than attempt to
‘“patterning work” that is involved in the con- abstract action away from its circumstances and
stantly challenged and never fully achieved represent it as a rational plan, the approach is to
(Tsoukas and Chia, 2002) pursuit of balance study how people use their circumstances to
between competing goals’ (1346). Danner- achieve intelligent action. Rather than build a
Schröder and Geiger (2016) draw on this idea of theory of action out of a theory of plans, the aim
patterning work to ‘understand the mechanisms is to investigate how people produce and find
that routine participants enact to create and recreate evidence for plans in the course of situated action.
patterns, which they recognize as stable or More generally, rather than subsume the details of
action under the study of plans, plans are sub-
changing’ (656). Goh and Pentland (2019) ‘con-
sumed by the larger problem of situated action.
ceptualize patterning as the formation of new paths
(Suchman, 2007: 70)
and the dissolution of old paths in a narrative
network (Pentland and Feldman, 2007) that One of the ways that the situated nature of action
describes a routine, (1901). There are different has informed Routine Dynamics is through the
ways in which these patterns are created. For idea that practical consciousness (Giddens, 1984)
example, Turner and Rindova (2018) describe or practical sense (Bourdieu, 1990; Boudieu and
how time organizes patterning. Wacquant, 1992) is important to how people enact
Feldman (2016) suggested performing and pat- routines because the actions required are too varied
terning as alternatives to the performative and osten- for rules to be able to determine action (Feldman
sive aspects as a way to make action more focal in and Pentland, 2003; Pentland and Feldman, 2005;
our study of routines, and particularly to emphasize Pentland and Reuter, 1994; Reynaud 2005).
the active nature of creating patterns. Routine Suchman’s (1983) study of filing in triplicate pro-
Dynamics now offers both a weaker process ontol- vided an early example of how an apparently
ogy, based on the idea that routines consist of per- simple routine with a sequence of seven clearly
formative and ostensive aspects, and a stronger defined steps quickly becomes complicated when
process ontology, based on the idea that routines enacted in the real world. The routine participants
are enacted through performing and patterning. The have to draw on their practical sense to ensure that,
difference between the strong and weak process in the end, it will look as if the sequence had been
ontology has been defined by process theorists as followed. The situated nature of action is thus
‘different ontologies of the social world: one a twofold: actions are situated in specific material
world made of things in which processes represent and social circumstances and they are situated in
change in things (grounded in a substantive meta- patterns (here, the pattern of filing in triplicate).
physics) and the other a world of processes, in The development of a hiring routine in a Danish
which things are reifications of processes (Tsoukas research lab provides a more complex example of
and Chia, 2002) (grounded in process metaphysics)’ situated action. The university that was the bureau-
(Langley et al., 2013: 4). Thus, ‘according to a weak cratic home for the research lab articulated rules for
view, processes form part of the world under con- hiring, but the lab directors took action (based on
sideration, according to a strong view the world is their practical sense) to work around the rules so
process’ (Hernes, 2008: 23). that they would be able to hire the kind of people
they needed to realize the goals of the lab. As a
result, actions taken in the hiring routine were
1.4.3 Situated Action
situated in two different patterns: hiring in a uni-
The idea of situated action originated in anthropol- versity bureaucracy and hiring for a research lab.
ogy/information systems (Suchman 2007; Lave, Although research on boundary objects has shown

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


10 Martha S. Feldman et al.

that it is possible to have action that is situated in D’Adderio, 2014; D’Adderio and Pollock, 2020;
different contexts and has different meanings in Glaser, 2017; Kiwan and Lazaric, 2019; Sele and
each of these contexts (Carlile, 2002; Star and Grand, 2016).
Griesemer, 1989), in this particular case the effort This work shows how, for instance, routines
to produce actions that were acceptable in both ‘change dynamically as they are enacted through
contexts ultimately provoked change in how the specific configurations of artifacts and commu-
lab directors envisioned the work of the lab (Rerup nities which shape ostensive and action patterns
and Feldman, 2011). leading to varying outcomes (i.e., alignment or
When Routine Dynamics scholars studied the improvement, replication or innovation)’
situated nature of actions, they also noticed how (D’Adderio, 2014: 1347). The heterogeneous con-
the patterns of routines are themselves situated in a figurations shaping routines are referred to as
context. Howard-Grenville (2005) theorized the socio-technical agencements (Callon, 1998;
situatedness of routines as ‘embeddedness’ in a D’Adderio, 2008) or socio-material assemblages
variety of structures (e.g., technology, coordination (D’Adderio, 2008; Orlikowski and Scott, 2008;
and culture). Embeddedness originally assumed Suchman, 2007). These are agentic arrangements
that the context is separable from, though import- which include a plethora of socio-material features
ant to, the routine. An alternative way of theorizing (texts, bodies, objects, values, etc.) whose proper-
the relation between situation and routine is to see ties are always emergent. Assemblages are
them as inseparable and entangled. In this view, ‘arrangements endowed with the capacity to act
routines are ‘enacted through’ their situated socio- in different ways, depending on their configur-
material context (D’Adderio 2014; Feldman et al., ation’ (Callon and Çalışkan, 2010: 9), and different
2016; see also D’Adderio [Chapter 7], this assemblage configurations bear different effects
volume). The latter definition highlights the con- over routines. Thus for an SOP or rule to have an
stant entanglement and mutual shaping of routines effect on performances, it has to generate an
and their context (see also Howard-Grenville and assemblage (including actors’ intentions, emotions
Lodge [Chapter 16], this volume). and actions, digital and physical artifacts, etc.),
which together supports the assumptions, views
and goals embedded in the SOP at design and/or
1.4.4 Artifacts and Materiality
usage stage. This suggests that the effect of a rule
In reaction to a long-standing and persistent confu- or SOP can only theoretically be ‘fully descriptive
sion in the study of routines that identified routines (a passive, fixed representation of the actual [rou-
with artifacts, i.e., the written procedures or standard tine]) or fully prescriptive (univocally ordering and
operating procedures (SOPs) describing routines, structuring the [routine], mostly they are per-
Pentland and Feldman initially described artifacts formed’ (D’Adderio, 2008: 786), meaning that
as important but exogenous to the generative system they configure routines to various extents (e.g.,
(Pentland and Feldman, 2005). This move allowed weak vs. strong performativity). The notion of
the focus to shift to actions and patterns (performa- assemblage helps us move beyond the unhelpful
tive and ostensive aspects of routines). It, unfortu- ontological separation between actors and artifacts,
nately, also gave some the impression that actions physical and material, objects and subjects, solid
could be enacted and patterns could emerge without and fluid, while also helping us theorize how emer-
artifacts. This impression was rectified through later gent, heterogeneous socio-material configurations
work. D’Adderio (2011) moved artifacts into the shape routines as they are performed within and
generative system, where they have remained. across organizational locations, and over time
D’Adderio and other scholars have continued to (Blanche and Cohendet, 2019; D’Adderio, 2014;
develop our understanding of the centrality of arti- D’Adderio and Pollock, 2020).
facts, and materiality in general, through numerous This novel approach afforded by combining
empirical studies (Aroles and McLean, 2016; Boe- Routine Dynamics with ANT/STS (Science-and-
Lillegraven, 2019; Cohendet and Simon, 2016; Technology Studies)/Performativity Theory-related

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


What Is Routine Dynamics? 11

sensitivities has allowed us to shed new light on a thing rather than an unfolding process, we pretend
long-standing debates, including innovation, repli- that a routine could exist without being enacted.
cation, truces and dynamic capabilities. As a result While descriptions of routines or formalized proced-
of its substantial potential to provide new insights ures (aka SOPs) can exist without being enacted,
into routines and organizations, the concept of Routine Dynamics asserts that routines are onto-
materiality has been and continues to be central to logically processes rather than entities. Routines
the study of routine dynamics (see D’Adderio come into being (and continue coming into being)
[Chapter 7], this volume). Detailed discussion of as people and artifacts enact them. As a result of this
materiality, including the related concepts of arti- ontology, dynamism is intrinsic to routines.
facts, assemblage, performativity, affordance and Analytically, relationality refers to the insepar-
inscription, is included in the Handbook chapters ability of the analytical constructs that we use in
by D’Adderio on materiality (Chapter 7), by Sele on Routine Dynamics. This relationality is fundamen-
actor-network theory (Chapter 6), by Wegener and tal to practice theory, which is an important theor-
Glaser (Chapter 22) on design and by Glaser et al. etical base for Routine Dynamics (Feldman
on algorithms (Chapter 23). [Chapter 2], this volume).

Relationality is central to the way practice theor-


1.4.5 Relationality ists understand individuals and systems or struc-
tures. Separating individuals and structures lies at
The concept of relationality goes beyond simply
the heart of two dominant and competing explan-
attention to relationships (whether relationships of
ations of social order. Reckwitz (2002) refers to
people or things or people and things) and is in these as homo economicus and homo sociologi-
contrast to an orientation to substances or entities. cus: ‘The model of the homo economicus explains
In a relational framework, the ‘dynamic, unfolding action by having recourse to individual purposes,
process, becomes the primary unit of analysis rather intentions and interests; social order is then a
than the constituent elements themselves. Things product of the combination of single interests’
are not assumed as independent existences present (p. 245). Homo economicus is the foundation for
anterior to any relation, but . . . gain their whole theories of rational action and ‘great man’ theor-
being . . . first in and with the relations which are ies. On the other hand, ‘[t]he model of the homo
predicated of them’ (Emirbayer, 1997: 287). In his sociologicus explains action by pointing to col-
lective norms and values, i.e. to rules which
Manifesto for a Relational Sociology, Emirbayer
express a social “ought”; social order is then guar-
quoted Somers and Gibson (1994) to make a dis-
anteed by a normative consensus’ (Reckwitz,
tinction between ‘a social identity or categorical 2002: 245). [. . .] As different as homo economicus
approach’ that ‘presumes internally stable concepts’ and homo sociologicus theories are, they nonethe-
versus a [relational, transactional] approach’ that less share the fundamental assumptions that (1)
‘embeds the actor within relationships and stories individuals and structures are ontologically inde-
that shift over time and space and thus precludes pendent of one another and (2) either individual
categorical stability in action’ (1997: 286). economic rational interests or social norms are the
Routine Dynamics is fundamentally about going primary basis for social action. Breaking with
‘beyond routines as things’ to understanding that these assumptions, the relationality of practice
routines are ongoing, unfolding processes. An ana- theory provides a third way to view social reality:
that individual interests and social norms can only
logy may be useful. We have tended to turn routines
be separated analytically; in practice, they are
into things in much the same way that we speak of
always in relation to one another, a mutually
the wind as a thing. ‘We say, “The wind is blowing,” constituted duality (Bourdieu, 1977; 1990;
as if the wind were actually a thing at rest which, at a Giddens, 1979; 1984). (Feldman and Worline,
given point in time, begins to move and blow. We 2016: 309)
speak as if a wind could exist which did not blow’
(Elias, 1978: 111–112, cited in Emirbayer, 1997: Because dualities, such as stability and change,
283). Similarly, when we imagine that a routine is individual and institution, subjective and objective,

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


12 Martha S. Feldman et al.

are central to practice theory and, thus, to Routine interdependence of their actions’ (Feldman and
Dynamics, discussions of the relationality of Pentland, 2003: 96). The new conceptualization
mutual constitution often concern dyadic relations. of routines, however, did not stop with this core
Mutuality, however, does not necessarily mean definition, and multiplicity in Routine Dynamics
dyadic but does mean that the relationality cannot does not stop with actors and actions but also
be one-sided. In Routine Dynamics, the initial includes patterns (ostensive aspects) and artifacts
focus was on a dyadic relationship – the performa- (materiality). While at times referring to both the
tive and the ostensive aspects of routines – but performative aspect and the ostensive aspect in the
before long, D’Adderio’s (2011) work brought singular, Feldman and Pentland specifically
artifacts fully into this relationship and the dyad addressed the temptation to think of the ostensive
became a triad. In strengthening the process ontol- aspect as a singular thing.
ogy of Routine Dynamics this triad becomes per-
It is tempting to conceptualize the ostensive aspect
forming, patterning and materializing. Within of the routine as a single, unified object, like a
Routine Dynamics theorizing, it has always been standard operating procedure. This would be a
clear that these aspects of routines are not separ- mistake, because the ostensive incorporates the
able. The language of mutual constitution can, subjective understandings of diverse participants.
however, give the impression of things that are Like any socially distributed stock of knowledge,
separable and that influence one another the ostensive aspect of a routine is usually not
(Orlikowski, 2007). Thus, in further support of monolithic; it is likely to be distributed unevenly
the stronger process ontology, it is also useful to (Berger and Luckmann, 1966; Schutz, 1967).
discuss the relationality of aspects of routines as Each participant’s understanding of a routine
depends on his or her role and point of view.
entangled.
(2003: 101)
The multiplicity of artifacts in relation to routines
1.4.6 Multiplicity
was also important as this reconceptualization
Multiplicity is another important concept for sought to distinguish routines from a unified rule or
studying the dynamics of routines. Without multi- Standard Operating Procedure as noted in the previ-
plicity, there are no dynamics. Multiplicity makes ous quote. Indeed, Pentland and Feldman (2005:
possible the dynamics that produce stability and 797) note that, ‘the range of artifacts that can con-
change. Initially, multiplicity meant simply that strain and enable routines is practically endless’.
there are many – many people, many actions, Over time and through many empirical studies
many patterns, many artifacts, many routines. In the focus of Routine Dynamics has expanded to
more recent work (Pentland, Mahringer, Dittrich, include the multiplicity of routines and the dynam-
Feldman and Ryan Wolf, 2020), the idea of multi- ics that occur as multiple routines affect one
plicity has expanded from a quantitative to a another. As important as it is to see what happens
qualitative multiplicity (see Bergson, 1950) based within a routine, routines are enacted in relation to
on a relational rather than a substantive ontology other routines. Thus, Routine Dynamics articles
(Emirbayer, 1997). have explored ecologies of routines (Birnholtz
Multiplicity of the quantitative sort (numbers of et al., 2007; Sele and Grand, 2016), clusters of
things) is fundamental to the initial reconceptuali- routines (Kremser and Schreyögg, 2016), intersect-
zation of routines that underlies the field of ing routines (Spee, Jarzabkowski and Smets, 2016)
Routine Dynamics. Feldman and Pentland (2003: and interdependent routines (Yi, Knudsen and
95) distilled a core definition of organizational Becker, 2016) to see how these multiplicities affect
routine as ‘a repetitive, recognizable pattern of stability and change in organizations.
interdependent actions, involving multiple actors’. Recently, routine scholars have expanded the
Consistent with the work of previous organiza- notion of multiplicity. to better understand stability
tional scholars, this definition ‘emphasized the and change. Both D’Adderio and Pollock (2020)
involvement of multiple individuals and the and Pentland et al. (2020) theorize the multiplicity

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


What Is Routine Dynamics? 13

of processes, albeit in different ways. D’Adderio Thus we can ask how does the space of possible
and Pollock (2020) refer to ‘ontological multipli- paths change when organizational members
city’, while Pentland et al. (2020) theorize a spe- change the idealized model? And what are the
cific notion of ‘process multiplicity’. mechanisms that drive this change? (Pentland
D’Adderio and Pollock (2020) draw on the idea et al., 2020)
of ontological multiplicity developed by Mol
(2002) that processes such as routines are not uni- 1.5 Conclusion: Where to Go from Here?
fied, singular ‘objects’ but are themselves multipli-
cities. Specifically, D’Adderio and Pollock (2020: Routine Dynamics involves de-centring and dis-
14) ‘characterize routines as ontologically fluid and solving conventional points of view. ‘Routine’ is
only coming together as “one routine” with great a noun, but a routine is not a thing. Routines are
effort and as a temporary, challenged achieve- repetitive, but not necessarily ‘routine’ (the adjec-
ment’. Through a study of routines replication, tive). Routines are dynamic. Each of the theoretical
they found that ‘routines similarity and singularity underpinnings of Routine Dynamics has this qual-
did not consist in the complete absence of, but ity: ethnomethodology, pragmatism, practice
instead productively encompassed, difference and theory, actor-network theory and socio-materiality
multiplicity’ (D’Adderio and Pollock, 2020: 11). have all been disruptive and decentring, each in its
Similarity and singularity here emerge from the own way. Together, this latticework of theoretical
coordination of multiple versions of the routine perspectives has been generative.
across sites and over time (D’Adderio and In a way, decentring is a natural product of
Pollock, 2020). looking closely at the patterns of doings and
Ontological multiplicity opens up new ways of sayings, along with the actors and artifacts that enact
studying routines and new questions for Routine them. Rather than talking about routines in general,
Dynamics. As D’Adderio and Pollock note, we have looked at routines in particular, but with a
fresh lens. Dittrich (Chapter 8, this volume) counts
studying routines as fluid patterns implies going a 40+ ethnographies, plus many other works that have
fundamental step further in unpacking routines
drawn on computational procedures, simulations
dynamics. Now we can ask new questions such
and experiments. Through this work, we have
as: when is a routine the same routine? How much
can a routine change before it becomes another developed a lively and continuously evolving
routine? And if it does change that far, how can it vocabulary to describe the dynamics of routines.
be re-stabilized, or brought back into being the same So, the way forward is to begin addressing the
routine? And through which agential devices or implications of this way of seeing for important
mechanisms? (D’Adderio and Pollock, 2020: 14) organizational and societal issues, including the
grand challenges of society (George et al., 2016)
The notion of process multiplicity in Pentland and the little challenges of management. Each of
et al. (2020) defines processes as a duality of the chapters contained in this volume charts several
one and many in which the ‘one’ process or new areas for Routine Dynamics to explore.
pattern or routine is always constituted of mul- A common theme among these is that Routine
tiple paths (i.e., possible ways of performing a Dynamics can do more to help solve real world
routine) that emerge from sequential relations problems. So far, Routine Dynamics research has
among actions. The authors state that, been focused on theoretical development (which
[w]hile routine dynamics research has been very has been necessary and generative), but now is the
useful in showing how processes are generative time to put these new theoretical tools to work to
systems in the interplay between the ‘one’ and better understand contemporary phenomena of
actual performances, our conceptualization of pro- societal concern, such as the rise of algorithms
cess multiplicity takes this view one step further: it and automation and the gig economy; and ways
allows us to consider not only change in actual to address inequality and racism, epidemics, nat-
performances, but also changes in possible paths. ural disasters and climate change.

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


14 Martha S. Feldman et al.

Moreover, more work could focus on exploring Bertels, S., Howard-Grenville, J. and Pek, S. (2016).
the role of routines in more thorny contexts, such Cultural molding, shielding, and shoring at
as social injustice, fraud and organized crime. Only Oilco: The role of culture in the integration of
very recently, Routine Dynamics scholars have routines. Organization Science, 27(3), 573–593.
started to look at the dark sides of routines (e.g., Birnholtz, J. P., Cohen, M. D. and Hoch, S. V.
(2007). Organizational character: On the regen-
Eberhard et al., 2019; den Nieuwenboer et al.,
eration of Camp Poplar Grove. Organization
2017). A better understanding of the negative sides Science, 18(2), 315–332.
of the dynamics of routines will be useful in con- Blanche, C. and Cohendet, P. (2019). Remounting a
tributing to discussions and ideas about how to ballet in a different context: A complementary
solve these problems. understanding of routines transfer theories. In M.
We also very much welcome work that connects Feldman, L. D’Adderio, P. Jarzabkowski and K.
Routine Dynamics to other related fields of Dittrich, eds., Routine Dynamics in Action:
research, such as Strategy-as-Practice, institutional Replication and Transformation. Research in
theory or dynamic capabilities. Moreover, Routine the Sociology of Organizations, 61. Bingley:
Dynamics can provide the basis for fields such as Emerald Publishing Limited, pp. 11–30.
behavioural strategy (Levinthal, 2011) and Boe-Lillegraven, S. (2019). Transferring routines
across multiple boundaries: A flexible approach.
practice-driven institutionalism (Smets, Aristidou
In M. Feldman, L. D’Adderio, P. Jarzabkowski,
and Whittington, 2017) that are looking for ‘micro and K. Dittrich, eds., Routine Dynamics in
foundations’. Here, Routine Dynamics can provide Action: Replication and Transformation.
micro-foundations that are grounded in the doings Research in the Sociology of Organizations, 61.
and sayings of people working in organizations Bingley: Emerald Publishing Limited,
(Powell and Rerup, 2017: 313–315; 329–331). pp. 31–53.
Lastly, we welcome enriching both our theoret- Bourdieu, P. (1977). Outline of a Theory of Practice.
ical and methodological repertoire to explore rou- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
tines. Routine Dynamics has started by using new Bourdieu, P. (1984). Distinction: A Social Critique of
methods and drawing on new theories and this the Judgement of Taste. Boston: Harvard
development has been very generative. We hope University Press.
Bourdieu, P. (1990). The Logic of Practice. Stanford,
that in future research new methods and theories
CA: Stanford University Press.
will provide new ways of ‘seeing’ and overcoming Bourdieu, P. and Wacquant, L. J. (1992). An
conventional ways of thinking. Invitation to Reflexive Sociology. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Bucher, S. and Langley, A. (2016). The interplay of
References
reflective and experimental spaces in interrupt-
Aroles, J. and McLean, C. (2016). Rethinking stabil- ing and reorienting routine dynamics.
ity and change in the study of organizational Organization Science, 27(3), 594–613.
routines: Difference and repetition in a Callon, M. (1998). An essay on framing and over-
newspaper-printing factory. Organization flowing: Economic externalities revisited by
Science, 27(3), 535–550. sociology. In M. Callon, ed., The Laws of the
Benner, M. J. and Tushman, M. L. (2003). Exploitation, Markets. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 244–269.
exploration, and process management: The prod- Callon, M. and Caliskan, C. (2010). Economization,
uctivity dilemma revisited. Academy of Part 2: A research programme on the Study Of
Management Review, 28(2), 238–256. Marketization. Economy and Society, 39(1), 1–32.
Berger, P. L. and Luckmann, T. (1966). The Social Carlile, P. R. (2002). A pragmatic view of knowledge
Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the and boundaries: Boundary objects in new prod-
Sociology of Knowledge. Garden City, NY: uct development. Organization Science, 13(4),
Anchor Books. 442–455.
Bergson, H. (1950). Time and Free Will: An Essay on Cohen, M. D. (2007). Reading Dewey: Reflections on
the Immediate Data of Consciousness. London: the study of routine. Organization Studies,
George Allen & Unwin. 28(5), 773–786.

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


What Is Routine Dynamics? 15

Cohendet, P. S. and Simon, L. O. (2016). Always Dosi, G. Nelson R. R. and Winter S. G., eds. (2000).
playable: Recombining routines for creative effi- Nature & Dynamics of Organizational
ciency at Ubisoft Montreal’s video game studio. Capabilities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Organization Science, 27(3), 614–632. Eberhard, J., Frost, A. and Rerup, C. (2019). The dark
Cyert, R. M. and March, J. G. (1963). A Behavioral side of routine dynamics: Deceit and the work
Theory of the Firm. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: of Romeo Pimps. In M. Feldman, L. D’Adderio,
Prentice-Hall. P. Jarzabkowski and K. Dittrich, eds., Routine
D’Adderio, L. (2008). The performativity of routines: Dynamics in Action: Replication and
Theorising the influence of artefacts and distrib- Transformation. Research in the Sociology of
uted agencies on routines dynamics. Research Organizations, 61. Bingley: Emerald Publishing
Policy, 37(5), 769–789. Limited, pp. 99–121.
D’Adderio, L. (2011). Artifacts at the centre of rou- Elias, N. (1978). What Is Sociology? Translated by
tines: Performing the material. Journal of Stephen Mennell and Grace Morrissey. New
Institutional Economics, 7(2), 197–230. York: Columbia University Press.
D’Adderio, L. (2014). The replication dilemma Emirbayer, M. (1997). Manifesto for a relational soci-
unraveled: How organizations balance multiple ology. American Journal of Sociology, 103(2),
goals in routines transfer. Organization Science, 281–317.
25(5), 1325–1350. Farjoun, M. (2010). Beyond dualism: Stability and
D’Adderio, L. and Pollock, N. (2020). Making rou- change as a duality. Academy of Management
tines the same: Crafting similarity and singular- Review, 35(2), 202–225.
ity in routines transfer. Research Policy, 49(8), Feldman, M. S. (2000). Organizational routines as a
104029. source of continuous change. Organization
Danner-Schröder, A. and Geiger, D. (2016). Science, 11(6), 611–629.
Unravelling the motor of patterning work: Feldman, M. S. (2015). Theory of Routine Dynamics
Toward an understanding of the microlevel and connections to strategy as practice. In D.
dynamics of standardization and flexibility. Golsorkhi, L. Rouleau, D. Seidl and E. Vaara,
Organization Science, 27(3), 633–658. eds., Cambridge Handbook of Strategy as
Deken, F., Carlile, P. R., Berends, H. and Lauche, K. Practice, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge
(2016). Generating novelty through interdepend- University Press, pp. 320–333.
ent routines: A process model of routine work. Feldman, M. S. (2016). Routines as process: Past,
Organization Science, 27(3), 659–677. present, and future. In J. A. Howard-Grenville,
den Nieuwenboer, N. A., Cunha, J. V. d. and Treviño, C. Rerup, A. Langley and H. Tsoukas, eds.,
L. K. (2017). Middle managers and corruptive Organizational Routines: A Process Perspective.
routine translation: The social production of Perspectives on Process Organization Studies.
deceptive performance. Organization Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 23–46.
28(5), 781–803. Feldman, M. and Orlikowski, W. J. (2011).
Dewey, J. (1922). Human Nature and Conduct: An Theorizing practice and practicing theory.
Introduction to Social Psychology. New York: Organization Science, 22(5), 1240–1253.
H. Holt & Company. Feldman, M. S. and Pentland, B. T. (2003).
Dittrich, K., Guérard, S. and Seidl, D. (2016). Talking Reconceptualizing organizational routines as a
about routines: The role of reflective talk in source of flexibility and change. Administrative
routine change. Organization Science, 27(3), Science Quarterly, 48(1), 94–118.
678–697. Feldman, M. S., Pentland, B. T., D’Adderio, L. and
Dittrich, K. and Seidl, D. (2018). Emerging intention- Lazaric, N. (2016). Beyond routines as things:
ality in routine dynamics: A pragmatist view. Introduction to the special issue on routine
Academy of Management Journal, 61(1), dynamics. Organization Science, 27(3), 505–513.
111–138. Feldman, M. S. and Worline, M. (2016). The practi-
Dosi, G., Faillo, M. and Marengo, L. (2008). cality of practice theory. Academy of
Organizational capabilities, patterns of know- Management Learning & Education, 15(2),
ledge accumulation and governance structures 304–324.
in business firms: An introduction. Organization Felin, T. and Foss, N. J. (2009). Organizational rou-
Studies, 29(8–9), 1165–1185. tines and capabilities: Historical drift and a

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


16 Martha S. Feldman et al.

course-correction toward microfoundations. and K. Dittrich, eds., Routine Dynamics in


Scandinavian Journal of Management, 25(2), Action: Replication and Transformation.
157–167. Research in the Sociology of Organizations, 61.
Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in Ethnomethodology. Bingley: Emerald Publishing Limited,
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. pp. 173–192.
Gavetti, G., Greve, H. R., Levinthal, D. A. and Kremser, W. and Schreyögg, G. (2016). The dynam-
Ocasio, W. (2012). The behavioral theory of ics of interrelated routines: Introducing the clus-
the firm: Assessment and prospects. Academy ter level. Organization Science, 27(3), 698–721.
of Management Annals, 6(1), 1–40. Langley, A. and Tsoukas, H, eds. (2017).
George, G., Howard-Grenville, J., Joshi, A. and Perspectives on Process Organization Studies.
Tihanyi, L. (2016). Understanding and tackling Oxford: Oxford University Press.
societal grand challenges through management Langley, A., Smallman, C., Tsoukas, H. and Van de
research. Academy of Management Journal, Ven, A. H. (2013). Process studies of change in
59(6), 1880–1895. organization and management: Unveiling tem-
Giddens, A. (1976). New Rules of Sociological porality, activity, and flow Academy of
Method: A Positive Critique of Interpretative Management Journal, 56(1), 1–13.
Sociologies, 1st ed. Oxford: Polity Press. Latour, B. (1986). The powers of association. In
Giddens, A. (1979). Central Problems in Social J. Law, ed., Power, Action and Belief: A New
Theory: Action, Structure and Contradiction in Sociology of Knowledge? London: Routledge &
Social Analysis. Basingstoke: Macmillan. Kegan Paul, pp. 261–277.
Giddens, A. (1984). The Constitution of Society. Latour, B. (1987). Science in Action. Boston: Harvard
Cambridge: Polity Press. University Press.
Glaser, V. L. (2017). Design performances: How Latour, B. (1992). Where are the missing masses? The
organizations inscribe artifacts to change rou- sociology of a few mundane artifacts. In W. Bijker
tines. Academy of Management Journal, 60(6), and J. Law, eds., Shaping Technology/Building
2126–2154. Society: Studies in Sociotechnical Change.
Goh, J. M., Gao, G. and Agarwal, R. (2011). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 225–258.
Evolving work routines: Adaptive routinization Latour, B. (2005). Reassembling the Social: An
of information technology in healthcare. Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxford:
Information Systems Research, 22(3), 565–585. Oxford University Press.
Goh, K. T. and Pentland, B. T. (2019). From actions Lave, J. (1988). Cognition in Practice: Mind,
to paths to patterning: Toward a dynamic theory Mathematics and Culture in Everyday Life.
of patterning in routines. Academy of Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Management Journal, 62(6), 1901–1929. LeBaron, C., Christianson, M. K., Garrett, L. and
Hernes, T. (2008). Theory for a Tangled World. Ilan, R. (2016). Coordinating flexible perform-
London: Routledge. ance during everyday work: An ethnomethodo-
Howard-Grenville, J. (2005). The persistence of flex- logical study of handoff routines. Organization
ible organizational routines: The role of agency Science, 27(3), 514–534.
and organizational context. Organization Leidner, R. (1993). Fast Food, Fast Talk: Service
Science, 16(6), 618–636. Work and the Routinization of Everyday Life.
Howard-Grenville, J. and Rerup, C. (2017). A process Berkeley: University of California Press.
perspective on organizational routines. In A. Levinthal, D. A. (2011). A behavioral approach to
Langley and H. Tsoukas, eds., Sage Handbook strategy: What’s the alternative? Strategic
of Process Organizational Studies. London: Management Journal, 32(13), 1517–1523.
Sage Publications, pp. 323–339. Mahringer, C. (2019). Exploring Routine Ecologies:
Huntington, S. P. (1968). Political Order in A Characterization and Integration of Different
Changing Societies. New Haven, CT: Yale Perspectives on Routines. PhD, Stuttgart:
University Press. University of Stuttgart.
Kiwan, L. and Lazaric, N. (2019). Learning a new March, J. G. and Simon, H. (1958). Organizations.
ecology of space and looking for new routines: New York: Wiley.
Experimenting robotics in a surgical team. In Mayhew, A. (2008) Institutions, culture and values.
M. Feldman, L. D’Adderio, P. Jarzabkowski In J. B. Davis and W. Dolfsma, eds., The Elgar

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


What Is Routine Dynamics? 17

Companion to Social Economics. Cheltenham: R. Greenwood et al., eds., The SAGE Handbook
Edward Elgar, pp. 28–43. of Organizational Institutionalism, 2nd ed.
Mol, A. M. (2002). The Body Multiple: Ontology in London: Sage Publications, pp. 311–337.
Medical Practice. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Rasche, A. and Chia, R. (2009). Researching strategy
Nelson, P. R. and Winter, S. (1982). An Evolutionary practices: A genealogical social theory perspec-
Theory of Economic Change, Cambridge, MA: tive. Organization Studies, 30(7), 713–734.
Harvard University Press. Reckwitz, A. (2002). Toward a theory of social prac-
Orlikowski, W. J. (2002). Knowing in practice: tices: A development in culturalist theorizing.
Enacting a collective capability in distributed European Journal of Social Theory, 5(2),
organizing. Organization Science, 13(3), 243–263.
249–273. Rerup, C. and Feldman, M. (2011). Routines as a
Orlikowski, W. J. (2007). Sociomaterial practices: source of change in organizational schemata:
Exploring technology at work. Organization The role of trial-and-error learning. Academy of
Studies, 28(9), 1435–1448. Management Journal, 54(3), 577–610.
Orlikowski, W. J. and Scott, S. V. (2008). Reynaud, B. (2005). The void at the heart of rules:
Sociomateriality: Challenging the separation of Routines in the context of rule-following. The
technology, work and organization. Academy of case of the Paris Metro Workshop. Industrial
Management Annals, 2(1), 433–474. and Corporate Change, 14(5), 847–871.
Parmigiani, A. and Howard-Grenville, J. (2011). Salvato, C. (2009). Capabilities unveiled: The role of
Routines revisited: Exploring the capabilities ordinary activities in the evolution of product
and practice perspectives. Academy of development processes. Organization Science,
Management Annals, 5(1), 413–453. 20(2), 384–409.
Peng, D. X., Schroeder, R. G. and Shah, R. (2008). Salvato, C. and Rerup, C. (2018). Routine regulation:
Linking routines to operations capabilities: Balancing conflicting goals in organizational
A new perspective. Journal of Operations routines. Administrative Science Quarterly,
Management, 26(6), 730–748. 63(1), 170–209.
Pentland, B. T. and Feldman, M. S. (2005). Schatzki, T. R. (2002). The Site of the Social:
Organizational routines as a unit of analysis. A Philosophical Account of the Constitution of
Industrial and Corporate Change, 14(5), Social Life and Change. University Park:
793–815. Pennsylvania State University Press.
Pentland, B. T. and Feldman, M. S. (2007). Narrative Schatzki, T. R. (2010). The Timespace of Human
networks: Patterns of technology and organiza- Activity: On Performance, Society, and History
tion. Organization Science, 18(5), 781–795. as Indeterminate Teleological Events. Lexington
Pentland, B. T. and Feldman, M. S. (2008). Designing Books.
routines: On the folly of designing artifacts, Schutz, A. (1967). The Phenomenology of the Social
while hoping for patterns of action. Information World. G. Walsh, F. Lehnert, trans. Evanston,
and Organization, 18(4), 235–250. IL: Northwestern University Press.
Pentland, B. T., Mahringer, C., Dittrich, K., Feldman, Schutz, A. (1970). Reflections on the Problem of
M. S. and Ryan Wolf, J. (2020). Process multi- Relevance, R. M. Zaner, ed., New Haven, CT:
plicity and process dynamics: Weaving the space Yale University Press.
of possible paths. Organization Theory. DOI: Sele, K. and Grand, S. (2016). Unpacking the dynam-
https://doi.org/10.1177/2631787720963138. ics of ecologies of routines: Mediators and their
Pentland, B. T. and Rueter. H. H. (1994). generative effects in routine interactions.
Organizational routines as grammars of action. Organization Science, 27(3), 722–738.
Administrative Science Quarterly, 39(3), Sevon, G. (1996). Organizational imitation in identity
484–510. transformation. In B. Czarniawska and G. Sevon,
Porter, M. and Siggelkow, N. (2008). Contextuality eds., Translating Organizational Change.
within activity systems and sustainability of New York: Walter de Gruyter.
competitive advantage. Academy of Simon, H. A. (1947). Administrative Behavior:
Management Perspectives, 22(2), 34–56. A Study of Decision-Making Processes in
Powell, W. W. and Rerup, C. (2017). Opening the Administrative Organization. Basingstoke:
black box: Microfoundations of institutions. In MacMillan.

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press


18 Martha S. Feldman et al.

Smets, M., Aristidou, A. and Whittington, R. (2017). Journal of Management Studies, 49(8),
Towards a practice-driven institutionalism. In R. 1407–1434.
Greenwood et al., ed., The SAGE Handbook of Turner, S. F. and Rindova, V. P. (2012).
Organizational Institutionalism, 2nd ed. A balancing act: How organizations pursue
London: Sage Publications, pp. 384–411. consistency in routine functioning in the face
Somers, M. R. and Gibson, G. D. (1994). Reclaiming of ongoing change. Organization Science,
the epistemological ‘other’: Narrative and the 23(1), 24–46.
social constitution of identity. In C. Calhoun, Turner, S. F. and Rindova, V. P. (2018). Watching the
(ed.), Social Theory and Political Identity. clock: Action timing, patterning, and routine
Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 37–99. performance. Academy of Management
Spee, P., Jarzabkowski, P. and Smets, M. (2016). The Journal, 61(4), 1253–1280.
influence of routine interdependence and skillful Ventola, E. (1987). The Structure of Social
accomplishment on the coordination of standard- Interaction: A Systematic Approach to the
izing and customizing. Organization Science, 27 Semiotics of Service Encounters. London: Pinter.
(3), 759–781. Weske, M. (2019). Business Process Management.
Star, S. L. and Griesemer, J. R. (1989). Institutional Concepts, Languages, Architectures, 3rd ed.
ecology, ‘translations’ and boundary objects: Berlin; Heidelberg: Springer.
Amateurs and professionals in Berkeley’s Whittington, R. (2007). Strategy practice and strategy
Museum of Vertebrate Zoology, 1907–39. process: Family differences and the sociological
Social Studies of Science, 19(3), 387–420. eye. Organization Studies, 28(10), 1575–1586.
Stene, E. O. (1940). An approach to a science of Winter, S. G. (2003). Understanding dynamic cap-
administration. American Political Science abilities. Strategic Management Journal, 24
Review, 34(6), 1124–1137. (10), 991–995.
Suchman, L. A. (1983). Office procedure as practical Winter, S. G. (2013). Habit, deliberation, and action:
action: Models of work and system design. ACM Strengthening the microfoundations of routines
Transactions on Information Systems (TOIS), 1 and capabilities. Academy of Management
(4), 320–328. Perspectives, 27(2), 120–137.
Suchman, L. A. (2007). Human-Machine Wittgenstein, L. (2001). Philosophical Investigations.
Reconfigurations: Plans and Situated Actions, Translated by G. M. Anscombe. London:
2nd ed. New York: Cambridge University Press. Blackwell. [Orig. pub. 1953.]
Taylor, F. (1911). The Principles of Scientific Yi, S., Knudsen, T. and Becker, M. C. (2016). Inertia
Management. New York: Harper and Brothers. in routines: A hidden source of organizational
Tsoukas, H. and Chia, R. (2002). On organizational variation. Organization Science, 27(3),
becoming: Rethinking organizational change. 782–800.
Organization Science, 13(5), 567–582. Zbaracki, M. J. and Bergen, M. (2010). When truces
Turner, S. F. and Fern, M. J. (2012). Examining the collapse: A longitudinal study of price-
stability and variability of routine performances: adjustment routines. Organization Science,
The effects of experience and context change. 21(5), 955–972.

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.002 Published online by Cambridge University Press

You might also like