Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 11

CHAPTER

Pragmatism and Routine Dynamics


5
DIONYSIOS D. DIONYSIOU

. . . an attitude of orientation is what the pragmatic Lorino, 2018). The founders of classical pragma-
method means. The attitude of looking away from tism drew on a variety of intellectual orientations
first things, principles, ‘categories’, supposed (British empiricism, Kant, Hegel and Darwin) and
necessities; and of looking towards last things, there were sharp differences in their intellectual
fruits, consequences, facts. (James, 1907: 54–55
backgrounds, training and interests. Despite these
emphasis added)
differences, here I focus on the common themes
that tied these thinkers together. For a more
5.1 Introduction detailed exposition to classical pragmatism there
are sources that interested readers may find useful
In this chapter, I explore the relevance of classical (e.g., Bernstein, 2010; Lorino, 2018; Menand,
pragmatism to the study of Routine Dynamics. 2002; Misak, 2013).
The two perspectives share a processual-relational The chapter unfolds as follows. I discuss briefly
view of the world, an emphasis on agency and the emergence of classical pragmatism and the
situated action and reject all forms of dualism in common themes in the ideas of the four major
the theorizing of social phenomena, suggesting figures. I also explore the commonalities between
that a rich common ground exists to allow cross- the key pragmatist ideas and the theoretical
fertilization. While the influence of pragmatist assumptions that underpin Routine Dynamics the-
ideas to the study of routines has so far been orizing and trace their influence in the study of
limited, pragmatism as a ‘problem solving’ phil- Routine Dynamics. Concluding, I suggest that a
osophy holds great promise in advancing further pragmatist perspective has much to offer to the
our understanding of routine enactment in the face study of routines as dynamic, processual phenom-
of increased novelty, contingency and potential- ena, and discuss its implications and potential for
ity, characteristics inherent to the nature of rou- research in Routine Dynamics.
tines as processes.
Pragmatism, the ‘most distinctive philosoph-
ical movement to emerge in the United States’, 5.2 Classical Pragmatism as a
emerged in the last quarter of the nineteenth Philosophical Perspective: Key
century as a radical critique of Cartesianism Figures and Common Themes
and its principle of the self-certainty of the
doubting ego as foundational for philosophy William James, ‘the father of modern psychology
(e.g., Bernstein, 1992: 833; Lorino, 2018). This and the face of American pragmatism’ (Misak,
principle was responsible for a number of 2013: 53), was the first to publicly introduce the
inescapable dualisms (e.g., mind/body, mental/ term ‘pragmatism’ as a new philosophical pos-
physical, fact/value) that haunted modern phil- ition in 1898, in his address before the
osophy and which pragmatists were determined Philosophical Union of the University of
to put aside, along with the traditional California in Berkeley (Bernstein, 2010). James
philosophical quest for absolute certainty. said that he heard the term some twenty years
The four major figures in the development of earlier from Peirce during the meetings of the
Classical Pragmatism were Charles Sanders Metaphysical Club, an informal discussion group
Peirce, William James, John Dewey and George who met in Cambridge, Massachusetts. Peirce, in
Herbert Mead (Bernstein, 2010; Joas 1996; his now famous 1878 paper ‘How to make our

62

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


Pragmatism and Routine Dynamics 63

ideas clear’, formulated what subsequently was thought, in its general sense, has a creative and
referred to as the ‘pragmatic principle’ or ‘maxim’ constructive function (Mead, 1932). James
(James, 1907: 47), namely, that our beliefs or believed that we play a role in creating our future,
ideas are rules for action and their meaning lies
in their conceivable practical effects, the different I, for my part, cannot escape the consideration,
modes of action to which they give rise. Peirce, forced upon me at every turn, that the knower is
not simply a mirror floating with no foot-hold
therefore, called for a shift in our attention from
anywhere, and passively reflecting an order that
the origins of ideas and beliefs to their conse-
he comes upon and finds simply existing. The
quences for conduct, from theoretical abstraction knower is an actor, and co-efficient of the truth
to lived experience and concrete practice on one side, whilst on the other he registers the
(Emirbayer and Maynard, 2011). In this way, he truth which he helps to create (1878: 17, italics
established the inseparability of meaning and added).
action in pragmatist thinking and of concrete
experience (experienced practical consequences) This processual view of the world was shared by
as the ultimate test of our beliefs and ideas. His all classical pragmatists, including John Dewey
concept of ‘inquiry’ through which ‘doubt’ is and George H. Mead, who carried forward the
resolved and new beliefs and habits of conduct pragmatic movement. The idea that permeates their
are developed, and the key role he attributed to thinking is that the social world consists of pro-
the community of inquirers in developing, testing cesses that ‘connect all sorts of entities in relational
and validating our hypotheses and theories, and recursive ways’ (Farjoun et al., 2015: 1789)
became central themes in pragmatist thinking (see also Tsoukas [Chapter 3], this volume). For
(Peirce, 1992). However, the word ‘pragmatism’, Dewey, the distinction between the organism and
‘caught on and spread like wildfire’ when James its environment is a distinction between different
published his Berkeley address (Bernstein, phases of the same process of living; ‘the organism
2010: 3), and it is through his exposition that the is in and of the world’ (Dewey, 1917: 15). He
world perceived and understood pragmatism rejected the knower/known duality and viewed
(Misak, 2013). the problem of knowing as a problem of living
James took Peirce’s pragmatic principle and and that thought and its object lie within the same
turned it to a philosophical orientation or ‘atti- experience. Individuals, society and environment
tude’ (see James’ opening statement), extending are implicated in mutually constitutive relation-
it to the problem of the nature of truth. He sought ships or ‘transactions’; ‘[w]hat has been com-
to help the public realize that philosophical pletely divided in philosophical discourse into
debates are important because the beliefs they man and the world, inner and outer, self and
support lead to different ways of conduct not-self, subject and object, individual and social,
(Dewey, 1981: 46). The insistence of both Peirce private and public, etc., are in actuality parties in
and James on the consequences and possibilities life-transactions’. (Dewey and Bentley, 1949:
of action was ‘almost revolutionary in its conse- 187). In other words, classical pragmatism is
quences’ (Thayer 1982: 33); it suggested bringing underpinned by a processual/relational ontology
the future into consideration and with it an evolu- that is fundamentally anti-dualistic.
tionary, processual view of the world filled with In his classic Human Nature and Conduct
emergence, chance and contingency. Classical (1922), Dewey offered a comprehensive account
pragmatists abandoned the quest for certainty of human nature and conduct and of intelligence
and embraced indeterminacy wholeheartedly; all as a process involving the creative solution of
our knowledge claims are fallible and open to everyday problems and improving human life.
potential criticism (Bernstein, 1992). Such a view Dewey’s model of human conduct is characteristic
leaves space for human agency, choice and cre- of the ‘pragmatist schema that anchors doubt in
ativity to shape the environment and the action’ (Joas, 1996: 128). According to this
unfolding of events (Joas, 1993); reason, or model, we typically follow our well-exercised

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


64 Dionysios D. Dionysiou

habits in a relatively thoughtless manner; never- 5.3 Classical Pragmatism and


theless, our habits are frequently met with resist- Routine Dynamics
ance from the world or conflict with each other, so
that ongoing conduct is blocked (Dewey 1922: 5.3.1 RD and Classical Pragmatism:
173). This is when ‘thought is excited by the Shared Assumptions
irritation of doubt’ (Peirce, 1992: 127), that is,
Pragmatism has never been completely absent
we engage in deliberation, during which we
from organizational studies (e.g., Selznick,
thoughtfully experiment to find out ‘what the vari-
1957; Weick, 1979, 1995), but its influence has
ous lines of possible action are really’ (Dewey,
only recently reached research on organizational
1922: 190). The outcome of this reconstruction of
routines (e.g., Dionysiou and Tsoukas, 2013;
activity, if successful in dealing with the problem
Dittrich and Seidl, 2018). As Cohen (2007a)
of action, is a creative accomplishment (Joas,
notes, due to its deep roots in modern organiza-
1996: 129). Following Peirce’s work on inquiry,
tional theory (Cyert and March, 1963; March and
Dewey sought to develop a ‘unified theory of
Simon, 1958), work on routines had traditionally
inquiry’ that would help us resolve problematic
promoted a rigid, static view of routines that
situations in everyday life (Dewey, 1938).
emphasizes choice and considers ‘action as less
Dewey’s lifelong friend and colleague at the
problematic, following more or less automatic-
University of Chicago, Mead, is recognized as the
ally from choice’. (Cohen, 2007b: 505). In this
thinker who, next to Dewey, contributed most to
way, the so-called Carnegie School moved the
the development of pragmatism (Reck, 1963).
pragmatists’ emphasis on experience, action,
Mead, more than any other pragmatist thinker,
habit and emotions to the background and
developed a comprehensive and detailed social
brought back a number of dualisms that pragma-
theory of action and language (Bernstein, 2010)
tists abhorred (e.g., thought/action, fact/value,
and it is through his work that the relevance of
and means/ends).
pragmatism to sociology and social psychology
Things started changing during the past decade,
became apparent (Joas and Knobl, 2009). Mead’s
when Feldman (2000) and Feldman and Pentland
work exemplifies pragmatist thinking, as, for
(2003) challenged the traditional view by promot-
instance, in developing his theory of the genesis
ing a processual view of routines as emergent,
of the self (Mead, 1934), he transcended many of
ongoing accomplishments. Their work has been
the dualisms that still prevail in contemporary phil-
highly influential and gave rise to a new branch
osophy and science (Dionysiou, 2017). For Mead,
of research, ‘Routine Dynamics’, which is based
the individual ‘constitutes society as genuinely
on the idea that routines are practices with internal
society constitutes the individual’ (Mead 1935:
dynamics (Feldman et al., 2016). This radical shift
70). He maintained that ‘the behavior of an indi-
in our understanding of the nature of routines
vidual can be understood only in terms of the
brought the concept of routines much closer to
behavior of the whole social group of which he is
key pragmatist ideas. How much closer becomes
a member’ (Mead, 1938: 6) and in this way he laid
apparent when considering the key principles of
the foundation of a process theory of identity for-
practice theorizing (see also Feldman [Chapter 2],
mation (Joas and Knobl, 2009). Mead, above all
this volume) summarized by Feldman and
others, established the symbolic character of inter-
Orlikowski (2011: 1241) – the consequentiality of
action (Stryker, 1980) and his work was founda-
situated actions in the production of social life; the
tional to Symbolic Interactionism as a distinct
rejection of dualisms as a way of theorizing; and
perspective in sociology (Blumer, 1969). Finally,
the mutually constitutive nature of relationships,
his seminal theorization of temporality in The
all consistent with pragmatist thinking. Table 5.1
Philosophy of the Present (1932) has informed
summarizes the shared assumptions that underpin
contemporary accounts of agency that capture
Routine Dynamics theorizing and classical prag-
more fully the complexity of agentic processes
matism and suggests that there is sufficient
(Emirbayer and Miche, 1998).

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


Pragmatism and Routine Dynamics 65

Table 5.1 Shared assumptions between Routine Dynamics and classical pragmatism

RD – Routines as practices (e.g., Feldman, 2000; Feldman


and Pentland, 2003; Feldman and Orlikowski, 2011;
Feldman et al., 2016) Classical Pragmatism

Routines as processes, action transcends dualisms: Rejects all dualisms as arbitrary conceptual ‘cuts’ made in
(agency/structure, mind/body, etc.) the continuum of the life process to facilitate linguistic
representation (e.g., Dewey, 1922; James, 1909: 285;
Mead, 1934)
Action in routines is situated Emphasis on concrete reality, facts, outcomes and their
meaningful experience. Reality ‘can be known adequately
only by following its singularities from moment to moment
as our experience grows’ (James, 1911: 99).
Relationality of mutual constitution (e.g., the mutually The two parts of a dualism (e.g., subject/object, individual/
constitutive relationship of performative and ostensive society, mind/body) are ‘in actuality parties in life-
aspects) transactions’ (Dewey and Bentley, 1949:187). For instance,
individuals, society and nature are mutually constituted
(Dewey, 1922; Mead, 1934, 1938)
Stability is an accomplishment For the pragmatists, what ‘really exists is not things made but
things in the making’ (James, 1909: 263).
Individuals and their agency matter – actors are Individuals have an active role in creating the ‘reality’ they
knowledgeable and often reflective face (James, 1878).
‘[C]ognition, and thought as a part of the cognitive process,
is reconstructive, because reconstruction is essential to the
conduct of an intelligent being in the universe’ (Mead,
1932: 37).

common ground for cross-fertilization between the emotions, has great promise to illuminate the pro-
two perspectives. cesses involved in routine adaptation to novel cir-
In the following, I examine how pragmatism has cumstances and the paradoxical nature of routines
informed recent work in Routine Dynamics. As a as ‘(n)ever changing’ patterns of interaction.
number of routine scholars realized the affinity of Dewey’s model has also been suggested recently
Routine Dynamics theorizing with key pragmatist by Winter (2013: 121), albeit, this time as a useful
ideas, they sought to explore pragmatism’s poten- orientation to ‘strengthen the foundations and
tial to advance our understanding of the dynamic enhance the fruitfulness of theories of organiza-
nature of routines as processes. tional routines and capabilities’. Both Cohen and
Winter highlight the central role of habit in
Dewey’s work. Dewey suggested that habit should
5.3.2 The Influence of Classical
not be reduced to mindless automaticity and repe-
Pragmatism in RD Research
tition, characteristics that pertain to a specific kind
The view of routines as flexible, emergent accom- of habit that he called a ‘routine’ or ‘dead’ habit
plishments (Feldman 2000; Feldman and Pentland (1922: 71, 208). Instead, he emphasized the pri-
2003) gained rapid currency in the study of rou- macy of ‘intelligent’ habit, which is ‘infused with
tines, so that when Cohen (2007a) argued first for thought and feeling’ (1922: 71) and ‘grows more
the relevance of classical pragmatism to the study varied, more adaptable by practice and use’ (1922:
of routines, the field had already become more 72). Our habits filter ‘all the material that reaches
receptive to pragmatist ideas. In particular, Cohen our perception and thought’. (1922: 32). Dewey’s
(2007a) argued that Dewey’s (1922) model of (1922) theorizing by seeing habit as fundamental
human nature and conduct, by accounting for the to human action, along with its interplay with
interactions between habits, cognitions and cognition and emotions, enables the ‘unpacking’

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


66 Dionysios D. Dionysiou

of human agency and action, thereby offering a embedded and practically inseparable dynamics
richer and more realistic model of human conduct of habit, inquiry and conversational trans-action’,
than that assumed by modern organization theory which highlights the processual nature of routines.
and economics (Cohen 2007b; Farjoun et al., 2015; Howard-Grenville’s (2005) study of the road
Winter, 2013). mapping routine in a high-tech manufacturing
Simpson and Lorino (2016) focus on Dewey’s company contributes to the unpacking of agency
concept of habit along with two interrelated prag- in routines by showing that participants’ temporal
matist concepts, namely, inquiry and conversa- orientations – to the past, present or future – shape
tional transaction, suggesting that they may help specific performances of the routine. To do so, she
strengthen the processual theorization of routines. draws on Emirbayer and Miche’s (1998) account
They note that habits must be understood as social, of agency, who, in turn, relied heavily on Mead’s
acquired and continuously modified through (1932) theorizing of temporality. Her findings
experience (Dewey, 1922) and that they are mobil- show that participants may choose to iterate on
ized and continuously adapted through the process earlier performances (primary orientation to the
of inquiry, which involves the transformation of an past); apply elements of earlier performances prag-
indeterminate or doubtful situation into one that is matically as they simultaneously pursue multiple
sufficiently unified so that a coherent course of ends (primary orientation to the present); or project
action can be anticipated (Dewey, 1938). The elements of earlier performances to plan for or
mobilization of habits and inquiries is situated imagine future enactments of the routine (primary
within social and temporal contexts, where agency orientation to the future) (Howard-Grenville, 2005:
plays a key role in the adjustment of conduct. 629), thereby influencing the stable or flexible
Situating routine enactment into the temporal and performance of routines.
relational contexts of the ongoing experience Tsoukas and I (Dionysiou and Tsoukas, 2013),
reveals that at every moment, ‘the possibilities for in a theoretical paper, rely on Mead (1934, 1938),
action are manifold, the future is open, and even to propose a process model of routine (re)creation
when uncertainty seems very low, options for ‘from within’ and develop endogenous explan-
action are still contingent’ (Simpson and Lorino, ations of routine (re)creation grounded on the
2016: 59). In particular, these authors emphasize actions and understandings of mutually susceptible
the pragmatists’ conception of agency as inher- participants. In this article, we focus in particular
ently relational and temporal (Emirbayer and on the process of the creation of the ostensive
Miche, 1998; Mead, 1932, 1934) and argue that aspect from the situated interactions of participants
agency arises within the conversational flow, (Feldman and Pentland, 2003). Mead’s (1934)
which is ‘a mutually constituting dynamic that account of the process of emergence of the self is
engages the meanings of conversants’ situations central to our work, as it helped us theorize the
and conversants’ selves’. (Simpson and Lorino, process through which routines emerge as collect-
2016: 62). This process is not a mere interaction ive, effortful phenomena, taking Mead’s (1934)
among distinct entities, but a transaction (Dewey concept of ‘role-taking’ (i.e., taking fellow routine
and Bentley, 1949), in which ‘all entities partici- participants’ roles into account to inform one’s
pating in an inquiry are involved on an equal own actions) as the underlying mechanism. In par-
footing and that their very definition and delinea- ticular, we propose that as participants in routines
tion is completely contingent on the progress of the interact with reference to a common activity, they
inquiry’ (Simpson and Lorino, 2016: 62). develop individual (routine-specific) selves and
Moreover, agency engages the past and the future shared understandings and habits that become
as resources that provide actors with meaning and incorporated in the ostensive aspect of routines,
direction in the present moment. In this way, which in turn facilitates the alignment of their
Simpson and Lorino (2016: 65) propose a framing actions to achieve coordination. The inherently
of ‘the social and temporal dimensions of ordinary social, relational nature of the self, advanced by
everyday practice in terms of the mutually Mead, helped us to clarify the construct of the

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


Pragmatism and Routine Dynamics 67

ostensive aspect, in an effort to account for both its before action, but are ‘ends-in-view’ that ‘arise and
multiplicity and its capacity to introduce a level of function within action’. As he remarked, an end-in-
stability or ‘sameness’ in routine performances view, ‘is the means by which an activity becomes
over time. In particular, we argue that through adapted when otherwise it would be blind and
repeated performances over time, individual under- disorderly, or by which it gets meaning when
standings (schemata) and habits incorporated in the otherwise it would be mechanical. In a strict sense
ostensive aspect of routines become ‘shared’ in the an end-in-view is a means in present action.’
sense of becoming at minimum compatible or con- (1922: 226). By using this idea to interpret their
gruent (and therefore, not necessarily identical or findings, Dittrich and Seidl (2018) challenge the
overlapping). This minimum compatibility or con- assumption, typically implicit in many routine
gruence among individual cognitions and habits studies, that participants pursue ends determined
enables the ‘patterning’ (Feldman, 2016) of inter- in advance of performing the routine. In particular,
actions by supplying participants with ‘mutually they show how routine participants, when faced
consistent interpretations and evaluations of infor- with unfamiliar situations, develop new, emerging
mation, as well as with reciprocal expectations ends-in-view by ‘foregrounding means within the
concerning what actions are appropriate for the concrete situation at hand’. (2018: 129). This
situation they face’ (Dionysiou and Tsoukas, emerging form of intentionality, in turn, can result
2013: 193), while it gives space for agentic inter- in updating routines’ goals. These findings suggest
vention and the creative resolution of problems of that we should understand intentionality in routines
action (Joas, 1996). as a ‘spectrum’, ‘ranging from ends-in-view that
In a more recent work, Sutcliffe and are primarily informed and aligned to any pre-
I (Dionysiou and Sutcliffe, 2019) draw from both established goals (purposeful action) to ends-in-
Dewey (1922) and Mead (1932) to propose a view that are unrelated to any pre-established goals
revised conceptualization of ostensive patterns or (purposive action)’ (131, italics in the original).
‘patterning’ (Feldman, 2016), according to which As this brief review of extant work suggests, the
‘patterning’ refers to the process of enacting pat- influence of classical pragmatism in the study of
terns of relations between participants’ cognitions, Routine Dynamics is gaining momentum and
habits and emotions to resolve emergent situations scholars in the field have demonstrated the fertility
(unexpected events, breakdowns, opportunities, of several key pragmatist ideas to the study of
etc.). We suggest that as participants engage in routines. In the following section, I suggest that
ongoing repetitive interactions in the context of there is still much that classical pragmatism could
performing a routine, not only do their interactions contribute to our understanding of Routine
become patterned or organized in a particular way Dynamics.
but, as part of the same process of activity, so do
their individual understandings, habits and emo-
5.3.3 Pragmatism and Routines Dynamics:
tions that relate to the enactment of a routine.
Future Directions and Implications
This theorizing exemplifies pragmatist thinking
for Research
by considering the individual and the collective
levels as continuous – performing and patterning One of the most promising areas in which prag-
are implicated in a mutually constitutive process matism may help advance our understanding of
or ‘transaction’. the nature of routines as processes is the role
Another important contribution in the field of of participants’ experience during the enactment
Routine Dynamics is Dittrich and Seidl’s (2018) of routines in time (Langley and Tsoukas 2017;
empirical study of a start-up pharmaceutical com- Tsoukas [Chapter 3], this volume). Early research
pany, who applied Dewey’s (1922) notion of the in Routine Dynamics promoted a rich conception
means-ends relationship to explore the full spec- of agency, according to which ‘routines are per-
trum of intentionality in routines. Dewey (1922: formed by people who think and feel and care’
223) argued that ends or goals are not fixed and set (Feldman, 2000: 614) and agency ‘involves the

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


68 Dionysios D. Dionysiou

ability to remember the past, imagine the future, of routines as processes. Although the role of
and respond to present circumstances’ (Feldman clock time and event time in the triggering and
and Pentland, 2003: 95). Routine Dynamics sequencing of actions in routines has received
researchers, by relying mainly on ethnographic some attention from Routine Dynamics research-
methods, have developed rich descriptions of rou- ers (e.g., Turner and Fern, 2012; Turner and
tine performances in diverse settings; however, Rindova, 2012, 2018; see Turner and Rindova
the lived experiences of participants, such as tem- [Chapter 19], this volume), this has not been the
porality and emotions, with few exceptions (e.g., case with participants’ experience of temporality.
Grodal et al., 2015; Howard-Grenville, 2005), Howard-Grenville’s (2005) study discussed
have not been woven into theoretical accounts of earlier makes a first step in this direction by
Routine Dynamics. A pragmatist perspective showing that participants’ temporal orientations
prompts scholars of routines to ground their (i.e., a primary focus on the past, present or
explanations to participants’ experience, so that future) influence the persistent or flexible enact-
resulting theories will help us return to the field ment of specific routine performances. This con-
and shed more light on how these experiences tribution can be further extended by examining
shape the unfolding of routines – following how participants experience the flow of time as
James’ (1908: 17) suggestion that theorizing they encounter unique circumstances and how
‘begins with concreteness, and returns and ends this experience shapes the unfolding of routines,
with it’. both of which are important to our understanding
Dewey’s (1922) model of human nature and of the nature of routines as processes (Hernes,
conduct helps in disaggregating the concept of 2014; Langley and Tsoukas, 2017; Tsoukas
agency to focus researchers on how the interplay [Chapter 3], this volume). Mead’s (1932) theoriz-
of habit, cognition and emotion shapes the agentic ing of temporality is highly relevant here. As
micro-processes involved in routine adaptation actors try to make sense of emergent situations,
and flexibility, and has the promise to capture they integrate ‘what has happened before’ (i.e.,
more fully participants’ experiences of the the past) and what ‘might happen next’ (i.e., the
unfolding of routines as processes. For example, future) (Feldman, 2016: 31) to create a meaning-
emotions, such as doubt or worry, alert us that the ful experience of the present and decide what to
situation demands our attention and motivate the do next. Participants select particular elements of
process of inquiry (Dewey, 1922; Locke et al., the past to create new continuities between the
2008; Peirce, 1992;). As Dewey (1938: 70) noted, past and the present, which in turn open up for
‘a problem must be felt before it can be stated’. them new possibilities for action. By attending to
Similarly, an intense emotional reaction to novel, participants’ evolving experience in time we are
unexpected events during routine enactment (e.g., likely to develop a nuanced understanding of
intense surprise, anger or panic) may overwhelm ‘how things become the way they are in view of
routine participants’ capacity to respond adap- the multiple possibilities of becoming’ (Hernes
tively (Loewenstein and Lerner, 2003) and result 2014: 3).
in the breakdown of a routine or its re-direction in Dewey’s and Mead’s theorizing may also help
unpredictable paths (for a review of the role of illuminate the processes through which routine
emotions on routines, see Baldessarelli participants problem-solve in the face of dynamic,
[Chapter 26], this volume). indeterminate situations. In particular, problem-
Moreover, because human experience is inher- solving from a pragmatist perspective highlights
ently temporal (e.g., George and Jones, 2000; the continuously evolving, transactional relation-
Langley and Tsoukas, 2017), capturing partici- ship between habits and inquiry, means and ends,
pants’ experience of the relationship between problems and solutions, as well as situations and
past, present and future helps in revealing the actors, all of which become co-constituted
nuances of the balancing between stability and throughout the process of inquiry (Dewey, 1922,
change in routines and the indeterminate nature 1938; Simpson and Lorino, 2016). Such a view

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


Pragmatism and Routine Dynamics 69

promotes a more dynamic and exploratory attention to how participants, immersed in the flow
approach to problem-solving and learning com- of activity, experience in a holistic manner (inter-
pared to traditional frameworks, which promote a play of habits, emotions, cognition and temporal-
separation between cognition and action (we think ity) the unfolding of routines, and tracing how
before we act) as well as means and ends (ends participants’ anticipations and retrospections con-
precede action and define the means) (Lorino, tribute to the meaningful resolution of everyday
2018). Instead, for pragmatists, problem-solving problems of action and with what effects in the
starts from a vague sense that ‘there is something stability and change of routines. ‘Zooming out’
wrong’ in a situation while the problem definition helps in exploring the ‘thick texture of intercon-
remains tentative and evolving during the process nections’ (Nicolini, 2009: 128) or ‘transactions’,
of inquiry. Learning is highly situated and provi- within which routines are immersed.
sional, fostered by the exploration of means–ends Moreover, as a ‘problem solving philosophy’
relations during problem-solving, and is subject to (Farjoun et al., 2015), pragmatism places great
verification and revision based on new experi- emphasis on how participants handle emergent
ences. Learning outcomes are not necessarily situations (discrepancies from expectations, real-
explicit in nature but also become embodied in izations of opportunities, surprise, etc.) that chal-
habits, which become revised and renewed through lenge the continuous unfolding of routines
the process of inquiry (Dewey 1938: 104–110; (Dionysiou and Tsoukas, 2013; Dittrich and
Joas, 1996; Lorino, 2018: 106–108). Seidl, 2018). These situations represent ‘turning
The application of pragmatist ideas has several points in activity’ (Dewey, 1922: 223) that provide
methodological implications for the study of researchers with unique opportunities to uncover
Routine Dynamics. Although the classical prag- the ‘logic’ that is internal to routines as practices
matists did not develop an empirical programme (e.g., Feldman and Worline, 2016; Howard-
for research1 (Emirbayer and Maynard, 2011), Grenville and Rerup, 2017) and explore the role
research conducted in the tradition of ethno- of participants’ ‘experimenting intelligence’ in the
methodology (e.g., Garfinkel, 1967; see also creative resolution of problems (Joas, 1993: 248).
López-Cotarelo [Chapter 4], this volume), con- Similarly, Shotter (2010: 273) suggests that it is
versation analysis (e.g., Sacks, Schegloff and within such situations ‘that we can find the
Jefferson, 1974), practice theory (e.g., Nicolini, uniquely new beginnings for genuinely innovative
2009), as well as research employing ethno- changes in organizations’. He proposes a ‘with-
graphic methods of research (particularly partici- ness’ approach (Shotter, 2006), which requires
pant observation) (see also Dittrich [Chapter 8], the researcher to immerse himself or herself in
this volume) are well-suited to put into practice the practices in question and, in ‘dialogic inter-
many pragmatist ideas. action’ with practitioners, contribute to identifying
Pragmatism-inspired scholars of routines may new possibilities for action. Wegener and Lorino
also find Nicolini’s (2009) ethnographic method (2020) operationalize the withness approach by
useful, involving ‘a recursive movement of embedding it within pragmatist inquiry and pro-
zooming in and zooming out on the data and pose ‘pragmatist withness inquiry’ as a method-
between data and theory’ (2009: 120). By ology for capturing the lived experiences of
‘zooming in’, scholars of routines may focus on researchers and practitioners along with the
the situated performances of routines, paying changes in their beliefs and habits throughout the
process of inquiry.
1
Finally, Sandberg and Tsoukas (2011: 348–349)
It must be noted, however, that that research in the
discuss a number of techniques and methods well-
tradition of Symbolic Interaction has had a significant
contribution in the generation of empirical knowledge
suited for studying breakdowns in routine perform-
by field research and is the disciplinary tradition that ance, and how scholars of routines may actively
informed the development of grounded theory (Locke, create a breakdown in a routine to uncover the
2001). ‘relational whole’ into which participants are

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


70 Dionysios D. Dionysiou

absorbed. Overall, scholars of routines have a large References


number of methods, tools and techniques available
in order to pursue a pragmatism-inspired, empirical Bernstein, R. J. (1992). The resurgence of pragma-
programme for research in Routine Dynamics. tism. Social Research, 59(4), 813–840.
Bernstein, R. J. (2010). The Pragmatic Turn.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
5.4 Conclusion Blumer, H. (1969). Symbolic Interactionism:
Perspective and Method. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
As the ideas of the original Pragmatists are being
Cohen M. D. (2007a). Reading Dewey: Reflections
rediscovered, scholars in diverse fields of study find on the study of routine. Organisation Studies, 28
that pragmatism offers useful resources in order to (5), 773–786.
tackle problems in a world that becomes increas- Cohen, M. D. (2007b). Administrative behavior:
ingly more complex, unpredictable and volatile. In Laying the foundations for Cyert and March.
the field of Routine Dynamics, the influence of Organization Science, 18(3), 503–506.
pragmatist ideas has been limited so far but also Cyert, R. M. and March, J. G. (1963/1992).
indicative of the promise of pragmatism as a A Behavioral Theory of the Firm. Malden, MA:
research programme to guide future research. Blackwell Publishers.
Pragmatism provides a rich and coherent con- D’Adderio, L. (2011). Artifacts at the centre of rou-
tines: Performing the material turn in routines
ceptual framework to the study of routines as inde-
theory. Journal of Institutional Economics,
terminate social processes, always ‘in the making’
7(2), 197–230.
(James, 1909: 263). Pragmatism augments the Dewey, J. (1917). The Need for a Recovery of
tools scholars have for focusing on how people Philosophy. In J. Dewey, ed., Creative
go about their everyday activities in a world filled Intelligence: Essays in the Pragmatic Attitude.
with surprise, uncertainty and possibility, and for New York: Holt, pp. 3–69.
developing further our understanding of routines as Dewey, J. (1922). Human Nature and Conduct: An
emergent and effortful accomplishments and the Introduction to Social Psychology. New York:
dynamics of stability and change in routines. In Random House/The Modern Library.
particular, the pragmatist concepts of habit, emo- Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The Theory of Inquiry.
tion and cognition and their interplay in human New York: Henry Holt and Company.
Dewey, J. (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey.
conduct; of inquiry as a method to resolve every-
(J. J. McDermott, ed.). Chicago: University of
day problems; and the role of temporality in the
Chicago Press.
meaningful experience of present activities provide Dewey J. and Bentley, A. (1949). Knowing and the
scholars of routines with a rich conceptual toolkit Known. Boston: Beacon Press.
to theorize about the lived experiences of partici- Dionysiou, D. D. (2017). Symbolic interactionism. In
pants, which shape and are shaped by routine A. Langley and H. Tsoukas, eds., The Sage
enactment (e.g., Hernes, 2014; Langely and Handbook of Process Organization Studies.
Tsoukas, 2017). Pragmatism, therefore, prompts London: Sage Publications, pp. 144–159.
us to pay attention to concreteness and its mean- Dionysiou, D. D. and Sutcliffe, K. M. (2019). Acting
ingful experience, in order to weave into our theor- in a Dynamic World: Pragmatism and Routine
izing what really matters to practitioners; only then Dynamics. Paper presented at the Annual
Meeting of the Academy of Management, 8–12
will our theories lead us successfully ‘back into
August 2019, Boston.
sensible experience again’ (James, 1909: 100).
Dionysiou, D. D. and Tsoukas, H. (2013).
I hope that this short exposition to classical Understanding the (re)creation of routines from
pragmatism and its relevance to the study of rou- within: a symbolic interactionist perspective.
tines will help spread the message that ‘we can Academy of Management Review, 38(2),
continue to draw inspiration from the pragmatic 189–205.
legacy and to develop it in creative ways’. Dittrich, K. and Seidl, D. (2018). Emerging intention-
(Bernstein, 1992: 840). ality in routine dynamics: A pragmatist view.

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


Pragmatism and Routine Dynamics 71

Academy of Management Journal, 61(1), Howard-Grenville, J. A. (2005). The persistence of


111–138. flexible organizational routines: The role of
Emirbayer, M. and Maynard, D. W. (2011). agency and organizational context. Organization
Pragmatism and ethnomethodology. Qualitative Science, 16(6), 618–636.
Sociology, 34, 221–261. Howard-Grenville, J. and Rerup, C. (2017). A process
Emirbayer, M. and Miche, A. (1998). What is perspective on organizational routines. In A.
agency? American Journal of Sociology, Langley and H. Tsoukas, eds., The Sage
103(4), 962–1023. Handbook of Process Organization Studies.
Farjoun, M., Ansell, C. and Boin, A. (2015). London: SAGE Publications, pp. 323–339.
Pragmatism in organization studies: Meeting James, W. (1878). Remarks on Spencer’s definition of
the challenges of a dynamic and complex world. mind as correspondence. The Journal of
Organization Science, 26(6), 1787–1804. Speculative Psychology, 12(1), 1–18.
Feldman, M. S. (2000). Organizational routines as a James, W. (1907). Pragmatism: A New Name for
source of continuous change. Organization Some Old Ways of Thinking. New York:
Science, 11(6), 611–629. Longman, Green and Co.
Feldman, M. S. (2016). Routines as process: Past, James, W. (1908). The pragmatist theory of truth and
present and future. In C. Rerup, J. Howard- its misunderstanders. The Philosophical Review,
Grenville, A. Langley and H. Tsoukas, eds., 17(1), 1–17.
Organizational Routines: How they are Created, James, W. (1909). A Pluralistic Universe. New York,
Maintained, and Changed. Perspectives on Longman, Green and Co.
Process Organization Studies Series. Oxford: James, W. (1911). Some Problems of Philosophy.
Oxford University Press, pp. 23–46. New York, Longman, Green and Co.
Feldman, M. S. and Orlikowski, W. J. (2011). Joas, H. (1993). Pragmatism and Social Theory.
Theorizing practice and practicing theory. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Organization Science, 22(5), 1240–1253. Joas, H. (1996). The Creativity of Action. Chicago:
Feldman, M. S. and Pentland, B. T. (2003). The University of Chicago Press.
Reconceptualizing organizational routines as a Joas, H. and Knobl, W. (2009). Social Theory:
source of flexibility and change. Administrative Twenty Introduction Lectures. New York:
Science Quarterly, 48, 94–118. Cambridge University Press.
Feldman, M. S., Pentland, B., D’Adderio L. and Langley, A. H. and Tsoukas, H. (2017).
Lazaric N. (2016). Beyond routines as things: Introduction: Process thinking, process theoriz-
Introduction to the special issue on routine ing and process researching. In A. Langley and
dynamics. Organization Science, 27(3), 505–513. H. Tsoukas, eds., The Sage Handbook of
Feldman, M. S. and Worline, M. (2016). The practi- Process Organization Studies. London: Sage
cality of practice theory Academy of Publications, pp. 1–25.
Management Learning and Education, 15(2), Locke, K. (2001). Grounded Theory in Management
304–324. Research. London: Sage Publications Ltd.
Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in Ethnomethodology. Locke, K., Golden-Biddle, K. and Feldman, M. S.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. (2008). Making doubt generative: Rethinking
George, J. M. and Jones, G. R. (2000). The role of the role of doubt in the research process.
time in theory and theory building. Journal of Organization Science, 19(6), 907–918.
Management, 26(4), 657–684. Loewenstein, G. and Lerner, J. S. (2003). The role of
Grodal, S., Nelson, A. J. and Siimo, R. M. (2015). affect in decision making. In R. J. Davidson, K.
Help-seeking and help-giving as an organiza- R. Scherer and H. H. Goldsmith, eds., Handbook
tional routine: Continual engagement in innova- of Affective Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University
tive work. Academy of Management Journal, Press, pp. 619–642.
58(1), 136–168. Lorino, P. (2018). Pragmatism and Organization
Hernes, T. (2014). A Process Theory of Organization. Studies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. March, J. H. and Simon, H. A. (1958). Organizations.
Hernes, T., Simpson, B. and Soderland, J. (2013). New York: John Wiley.
Managing and temporality. Scandinavian Mead, G. H. (1932). The Philosophy of the Present.
Journal of Management, 29, 1–6. London: The Open Court Company.

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press


72 Dionysios D. Dionysiou

Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, Self, and Society from the organizations. Organizational Research
Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. London: The Methods, 13(2), 268–285.
University of Chicago Press. Simpson, B. and Lorino P. (2016). Re-viewing rou-
Mead, G. H. (1935). The philosophy of John Dewey. tines through a pragmatist lens. In C. Rerup,
International Journal of Ethics, 46(1), 64–81. J. Howard-Grenville, A. Langley and H.
Mead, G. H. (1938). The Philosophy of the Act. Tsoukas, eds., Organizational Routines: How
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. they are Created, Maintained, and Changed.
Menand, L. (2002). The Metaphysical Club. London: Perspectives on Process Organization Studies
Flamingo. Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
Misak, C. (2013). The American Pragmatists. pp. 47–70.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stryker, S. (1980). Symbolic Interactionism. New
Nicolini, D. (2009). Zooming in and zooming out: Jersey: The Blackburn Press.
A package of method and theory to study work Thayer, H. S. (1982). Pragmatism: The Classic
practices. In S. Ybema, D. Yanow, H. Wels and Writings. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.
F. Kamsteeg, eds., Organizational Ethnography: Turner, S. F. and Fern, M. J. (2012). Examining the
Studying the Complexities of Everyday Life. stability and variability of routine performances:
London: SAGE Publications, pp. 120–138. The effects of experience and context change.
Peirce, C. S. (1992). The Essential Peirce, Vol 1 Journal of Management Studies, 49(8),
(1867–1893). Bloomington: Indiana University 1407–1434.
Press. Turner, S. F. and Rindova, V. (2012). A balancing
Peirce, C. S. (1998). The Essential Peirce, Vol 2 act: How organizations pursue consistency in
(1893–1913). Bloomington: Indiana University routine functioning in the face of ongoing
Press. change. Organization Science, 23(1), 24–46.
Pentland, B. T. and Feldman, M. S. (2005). Turner, S. F. and Rindova, V. (2018). Watching the
Organizational routines as unit of analysis. clock: Action timing, patterning, and routine
Industrial and Corporate Change, 14(5), 793–815. performance. Academy of Management
Reck, A. J. (1963). The philosophy of George Herbert Journal, 61(4), 1253–1280.
Mead. In Studies in Recent Philosophy. Tulane Wegener, F. and Lorino, F. (2020). Capturing the
Studies in Philosophy Series, Volume 12. experience of living forward from within the flow:
Netherlands: Springer, pp. 5–51. Fusing ‘withness’ approach & pragmatist inquiry.
Sacks, H., Schegloff, E. A. and Jefferson, G. (1974). In J. Reinecke, R. Suddaby, A. Langley and H.
A simplest systematics for the organization of Tsoukas, eds., Perspectives on Process
turn-taking for conversation. Language, 50, Organization Studies Vol. 7: About Time:
696–735. Temporality and History in Organization Studies.
Sandberg, J. and Tsoukas, H. (2011). Grasping the Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 138–168.
logic of practice: Theorizing through practical Weick, K. E. (1979). The Social Psychology of
rationality. Academy of Management Review, Organizing, 2nd ed. Reading, MA: Addison-
36(2), 338–360. Westley.
Schatzki, T. R. (2001). Introduction: Practice Weick, K. E. (1995). Sensemaking in Organizations.
theory. In T. R. Schatzki, K. Knorr-Cetina and Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
E. V. Savigny, eds., The Practice Turn in Weick, K. E. (2003). Theory and practice in the real
Contemporary Theory. London and New York: world. In H. Tsoukas and C. Knudsen, eds., The
Routledge, pp. 10–23. Oxford Handbook of Organization Theory.
Selznick, P. (1957). Leadership in Administration: A Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 453–475.
Sociological Interpretation. Berkeley: University Weick, K. E., Sutcliffe, K. M. and Obstfeld, D.
of California Press. (2005). Organizing and the process of sensemak-
Shotter, J. (2006). Understanding process from ing. Organization Science, 16(4), 409–421.
within: An argument for ‘withness’-thinking. Winter, S. G. (2013). Habit, deliberation, and action:
Organization Studies , 27 (4), 585–604. Strengthening the microfoundations of routines
Shotter, J. (2010). Situated dialogic action research: and capabilities. Academy of Management
Disclosing ‘beginnings’ for innovative change in Perspectives, 27(2), 120–137.

https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993340.007 Published online by Cambridge University Press

You might also like