Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

Richard Boyd (1988) “How to be a moral realist” • Moral intuitions seem to play an analogous role in ethics, but they

to play an analogous role in ethics, but they are far


more variable between individuals.
• Formulates moral realism as the following doctrine: • What, in ethics, plays the role of observation in science?
o Moral statements are the sorts of statements which express • We need to establish this to reject the epistemological contrast.
propositions which are true or false.
o The truth or falsity of moral statements is largely independent of 2.2 reflective equilibrium in moral reasoning
our moral opinions, theories, etc. • Rawls' description of reflective equilibrium describes how we essentially
o Ordinary canons of moral reasoning - together with other canons balance between moral intuitions, general moral principles and moral
of reasoning - constitute, under many circumstances at least, a theories to reach a coherent position.
reliable method for obtaining and improving moral knowledge. • Moral reasoning begins with presuppositions and negotiates between
• Argues developments in realist philosophy of science, philosophy of conflicting ones.
language and epistemology support moral realism. • How could such a 'constructive' procedure involve the discovery of moral
• Also argues Marxists ought to be moral realists (against a trend around facts?
the time of writing).
2.3 moral progress and cultural variability
• If moral judgements = factual judgement, why do we not have moral
1.2 scientific knowledge and moral skepticism progress?
• Contrast between epistemology of ethics and science is a common • Scientists from different cultural backgrounds also agree on assessment
antirealist position. of scientific evidence.
• Properties of science like objectivity, value-neutrality, empirical testability • If moral reasoning = reasoning about objective moral facts, what explains
etc. absent/modified in ethics. lack of progress and agreement?
• Boyd notes two common strategies for conceiving a 'unified knowledge'
between the fields that minimises an epistemological contrast. 2.4 hard cases
o Showing scientific beliefs/methods possess qualities of moral • If goodness, fairness etc. are real objective properties, what should we
beliefs/methods (e.g. Kuhn). say about unsolvable hard cases in ethics?
o Showing moral beliefs/methods possess qualities of scientific • In science these hard questions are only temporarily unanswerable.
beliefs/methods (what Boyd chooses). • The permanent unanswerability of some hard ethical cases + moral
realism = possibility that there are permanently inaccessible moral facts.
• This would be a significant epistemological difference between ethics and
science.
2 some challenges to moral realism
(based on contrast between epistemology of ethics & science) 2.5 naturalism & naturalistic definitions
• If goodness is a real property, then wouldn't it be a natural property? (ie,
definable in terms of facts about the natural world)
2.1 moral intuitions and empirical observations
• In science, observations provide a degree of objectivity.
• Moral realism is committed to the claim that moral terms like 'good'
possess naturalistic definitions. 3 Realist philosophy of science
• Remember Moore on the naturalistic fallacy here.

2.6 moral motivation 3.1 the primacy of reality


• Factual judgements constrain rational choice because of antecedent • This is just the doctrine that an external world exists independently of our
interests/desires. perception & conceptualisation of it.
• Moral realism holds moral judgements are factual judgements. • Scientific realism in philosophy
• How could this account for the commendatory force of moral judgements? o methods of science are capable of providing knowledge of
unobservable entities, e.g. atoms
2.7 the semantics of moral terms o also provide knowledge about the behaviour of observable
• Semantic meaning of moral concepts differs substantially between phenomenon.
individuals. o The properties of these & other entities are largely theory
• How can we argue there is one concept of the good? independent.
• Differences suggest noncognitivist or constructivist approach to • Non-realist positions fail to account for the way theory-dependent
understanding semantics of ethical terms. revisions make a positive methodological contribution to science.
• By this Boyd means improving the precision of our measurement and
2.8 verificationism and anti-realism in ethics detection of unobservable entities.
• Verificationists would reject the existence of theoretical entities because • If there was no objective reality, it is unclear why science is able to
they are unobservable and therefore unverifiable in principle. progress through making refinements to measurement and detection.
• Moral statements are meaningless because they are objectively • (Note Boyd's idea of progress = improving instrumental reliability of
unverifiable (mechanisms like intuition or reflective equilibrium don't science. This is its reliability for producing knowledge that is applicable for
provide enough/right sort of verification). practical goals and purposes.)
2.9* comments on the above 3.2 objective knowledge from theory-dependent methods
• Boyd notes 2.1-2.7 are indirect arguments against moral realism. • Two general features of scientific methodology on realist account:
• They point to features of moral beliefs/reasoning that would be best o Conception of scientific research as cumulative by successive
explained by rejecting moral realism. approximations to the truth.
• These arguments are not necessarily verificationist in nature. o Cumulative development possible because of dialectical
• Boyd argues these arguments are closely analogous to Kuhn's objection relationship between current theory and methodology for
to scientific realism, which essentially argues there are features about improvement.
scientific progress that would be best explained by rejecting scientific • So, all aspects of scientific methodology are theory-dependent.
realism. • This theory-dependence reliably produces further knowledge because our
• Boyd aims to reject verificationism and logical positivism (as Kuhn does), currently accepted theories are relevantly approximately true.
but also rebut constructivist/neo-Kantian considerations in Kuhn.
• The approximate truth of current theories is merely a matter of o Understanding the role of these factors is relevant for the
contingent empirical fact. sociology, history & epistemology of science.
• This means epistemology of science is dependent on empirical
knowledge (presumably about these social, psychological factors).
3.3 naturalism and radical contingency in epistemology
3.3.3 radical contingency of scientific epistemology
3.3.1 naturalism in epistemology • Methodological principles in science are theory-dependent.
• Modern epistemology dominated by foundationalism • They are only a reliable guide to the truth because and to the extent that
o Premise foundationalism = all knowledge justifiable from an a the background theories determining their application are approximately
priori specifiable core of foundational beliefs (possessing true.
qualities like 'self-warranting,' 'incorrigible,' etc.) • This is a matter of contingent historical fact.
o Inference foundationalism = principles of justifiable inference are • The rationality of (current) scientific principles of inference rests on this
ultimately reducible to inferential principles which are a priori contingent empirical fact.
rational. • "we must think of [corpuscular theory of matter] as the beginning of
• Naturalistic considerations suggest no beliefs are epistemically privileged rational methodology… not as a consequence of it" (by chance basically).
in the ways required by foundationalism. • Scientific training (absorption/exposure to paradigmatic theory) can
• Naturalism in epistemology + cumulative scientific knowledge + sharpen scientific intuition, which is reliable insofar as it's grounded in
evaluation of theories as an ongoing social process = crucial causal theoretical tradition that is relevantly approximately true.
notion in epistemology to be regulation of belief rather than production.
o I take this to mean epistemology is more involved in prescribing
what we should believe rather than describing what we do 3.5 non-Humean causation
actually know. • Rejects Humean causation by rejecting verificationism.
• Unreduced causal notions are relevant for naturalistic epistemology.
3.3.2 radical contingency in epistemology • I found this confusing but I think this section is arguing that from a
• Because epistemology is prescriptive, the relevant conception of belief- naturalistic perspective it's appropriate to talk about unreducible
regulation must reflect the social & dialectical character of the growth of epistemological causation.
scientific knowledge.
o I think this means the relevant concept of belief-regulation to 3.6 natural definitions
science must also include/account for social + dialectical • I think natural definitions here means definitions that happen to accord
character? accurately to hidden essences of things.
• Social + psychological factors are thus relevant to causal mechanisms of • Sound scientific explanation only possible when we use natural not
knowledge. conventional definitions.
o Criticism, testing, acceptance, modification & transmission of • A wide variety of scientific terms are defined in useful, applicable ways
scientific theories & knowledge include these factors. rather than analytically/stipulatively.
3.7 reference & epistemic access 4 how to be a moral realist
• Naturalistic conception of reference provided by causal connection
between term and referent.
4.1 moral intuitions etc.
• Causal connections relevant to reference are those involved in reliable
• Constructs realist reply to 2.1, 2.2, 2.3
regulation of belief.
• Notes to make this reply, needs to be incorporated into broader
• Term T refers to kind K just in case there are casual mechanisms whose
conception of moral knowledge that meets strong constraints.
tendency brings about that what is predicated by T will be approximately
true of K.
4.2 constraints on realist conception of moral knowledge
• Mechanisms include:
o Procedures accurate for recognising instances of K • Must be possible to explain how moral reasoning started out with stock of
o Procedures that govern use of T relevantly approximately true moral beliefs.
o Social transmission of beliefs about K as claims about T. • Answer question of "what plays role analogous to scientific observations
o Deference to experts on K regarding use of T in ethics?"
• Explain why moral properties require natural definitions.
• In these cases, properties of K regulate use of T.
• Show ordinary use of moral terms promotes (imperfect) epistemic access
• What is said using T provides socially coordinated epistemic access to K.
to moral properties (goodness must regulate use of word 'good')
• Portray indeterminacy in extension of moral terms as rationally dictated
3.8 homoestatic property-cluster definitions
by nature of subject matter.
• Type of definition (of natural kinds) that does not provide
necessary/sufficient conditions.
4.3 homeostatic consequentialism
• Definition provided by possession of adequate number of sufficient
• Conception of morals/the 'good' that serves as a sample for argument on
properties.
plausibility of moral realism.
• Relevant properties is a conceptual matter.
• Important human goods are homeostatically clustered - they mutually
• Co-occurrence of properties is a result of a 'homeostatic' mechanism:
support one another, and some psychological & social mechanisms
some favour the presence of others, or there are underlying mechanisms
contribute to this homeostasis.
that tend to maintain presence.
• Moral goodness defined by HPC of goods.
• Relative importance of properties & mechanisms for determining if HPC
• Homeostatic unity & imperative to balance & strengthen homeostasis
term applies to an object is theoretical rather than conceptual issue.
constrains moral choice.
• No refinement of usage which replaces HPC term with less vague term
• Knowledge of goods & homeostasis = knowledge about human
would preserve the naturalness of the kind.
psychological & social potential.
• Can be obtained in way very analogous to scientific knowledge, through
experimental knowledge of political & social experiments (revealed
through psychology, history etc).
4.4 observations, intuitions and reflective equilibrium • If reflective equilibrium is defensible, use of the term good does provide
• Anti-realist objects moral intuitions and reflective equilibrium dictate epistemic access.
constructivist interpretation of morals. o Tendency guaranteed by basic evolutionary & psychological
• Realist can respond as long as we can portray background beliefs an facts.
judgements as: • Serious errors still possible as long as there is epistemically relevant
o Relevantly approximately true causal connection.
o There's an analogue to observation in science • Notes objection that determination of moral beliefs seems to often be
• Argues human sciences like psychology, history, social sciences provide mediated by power (e.g. Class interests).
observation relevant to moral inquiry. o Argues would no the possible to exploit moral terms if there were
• These sciences are subject to just the same theory-dependent influences. no connection to real psychological phenomena.
• Regarding approximate truth of background beliefs - argues we have
good enough beliefs to be able to respond to new evidence & expand & 4.6 hard cases & divergent views
improve knowledge of needs. • Responding to 2.4 and I think also 2.3 - anti-realist explains these
• Therefore reflective equilibrium is possible & doesn't pose epistemological difficulties by denying common subject matter.
problems. • Realist can emphasise failures of bivalence are predicted for HPC
• Also characterises moral intuitions as a species of trained judgement as a properties.
result of being linked to reliable process of reflective equilibrium. • Realist can also emphasise complexity and controversiality of moral
• Anti-realist objections issues.
o Mistaken moral beliefs (e.g. Moral laws are God's laws) - Boyd • All that is needed for homeostatic consequentialism to be defensible is
argues mistaken beliefs about this doesn't mean beliefs about idea that HPC goods epistemically regulate moral discourse to an
HPC of goods were wrong. appreciable extent.
o Disanalogy between foundations of scientific and moral • Notes the similarity in evaluations across ethical schools could support
knowledge - argues it is easier to explain how knowledge is this claim.
possible given evolutionary evidence that recognising
fundamental needs is important. 4.7 morality, motivation & rationality
• Naturalistic moral realism must deny moral judgements necessarily
4.5 moral semantics provide reasons for action and explain close connection another way.
• I think this is responding to 2.5 and 2.7 • Boyd argues motivation to take care of well-being of others & capacity to
• Realist rebuttal possible if: sympathise is evolutionarily programmed.
o Good reasons to think moral terms have natural definitions. • Hence moral judgements, which involve pursuit of human needs 'the
o Good reason to think ordinary use provides epistemic access, good,' typically co-occur with motivation.
goodness regulates use of term 'good.' • Agents who can make moral judgements but do not feel motivation in fact
• If 'good' is defined by HPC, this is a property whose essence is a natural have a deficiency in sympathy on this view.
definition.
4.8 conclusion
• Defence of moral realism depends upon naturalistic & nonfoundational
aspects of realist philosophy of science.
• Support claim that philosophy is an empirical inquiry continuous with the
sciences.
• Arguments presented depend on optimistic empirical claims about unity of
human goods & possibility of reliable knowledge in human sciences.
• Philosophical examination of moral realism should also include
examination into empirical claims about human goods and capacity for
knowledge of ourselves.

You might also like