Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 4

Book Review:

Feminism &Bioethics:
Beyond Repvooduction

Leslie Bender

Susan M. Wolf, ed., Feminism & Bioethiw: Beyond Repro- Feminist scholars have been applying their insights to
duction (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996): 398 bioethical analyses in books, articles, and symposia for al-
pp., ISBN 0-19-508568-x (cloth), $50.00. To order call 1- most two decades. For those new to this burgeoning litera-
800-451-7556. ture, Feminism and Bioethiw is as fine a place as any to
start, because leading feminist scholars have synthesized

D rawing on work from top feminist bioethicists,


philosophers, and law professors, Susan Wolf’s
anthology Feminism and Bioethics reinforces the
vibrancy of feminist theoretical contributions to bioethical
thinking. The twelve articles, accompanied by Wolf’s ex-
their earlier works into easily readable articles. For nonfemi-
nists or unschooled feminists teaching “traditional” bioet-
hics courses, inclusion of this anthology could greatly im-
prove course curriculum. For researchers and practitio-
ners, insights from these articles will alter protocols and
tensive introduction, suggest how feminism’s insights and regular procedures. For feministteachers and scholars, these
critiques refine our thinking on a wide range of bioethical critiques will be very familiar and are available elsewhere,
issues, from health care policies and allocation issues to but Wolf has made them easily accessible in one volume.
biomedical research, from the HIV epidemic t o death and Reproductive and procreation issues most obviously
dying issues, from genetics and disabilities issues to recon- implicate women’s health concerns and deservedly have
structing concepts of the “patient” or “health,” to recon- been a dominant focus of feminist analyses in medical eth-
ceiving the physician-patient relationship through commu- ics or bioethics.’ But feminist bioethics is not just about
nicative ethics. Each essay ultimately asks “the woman reproduction anymore, as Wolf’s anthology attests. Her
question”: What would bioethics look like if women’s ex- volume complements a growing body of feminist bioethi-
periences were central to or, at least, included in the analy- cal books,2 not to mention the geometrically expanding
sis? Not surprisingly, the answers are profoundly different plethora of articles in academic and professional journals
from how traditional bioethics proceeds. But I have a great that apply feminist analyses to a wider body of bioethical
deal of faith in the integrity of bioethicists, so I do not inquiry? Wolf mined the vein of leading feminist bioethi-
doubt that bioethicists, who of all scholars have been espe- cists in creating this collection-many “mothers” of the
cially attentive to issues of fairness, justice, and people’s field. In addition to Wolf’s introduction and own article
needs, will transform their work when confronted head- on death and dying issues, authors indude Susan Sherwin,
on with these clearly articulated arguments about the un- Rosemarie Tong, Mary Mahowald, Dorothy Roberts,
just consequences of excluding women from their analyses. Rebecca Dresser, Laura Purdy, Janet Farrell Smith, Vanessa
Wolf’s book confirms that feminist approaches are no longer Merton, Ruth Faden, Nancy Kass, Deven McGraw,
marginal or to be dismissed by “mainstream” bioethics: Adrienne Asch, Gail Geller, and Hilde and James Linde-
one fails to engage these contributions at hisher own peril mann Nelson.
as a legitimatescholar, teacher, or practitioner in this field. The book is divided in two: the first part consists of
five articles discussing the relationship between feminism
Journalof Law, Medicine &Ethics, 25 (1997): 58-61. and bioethics; the second contains seven articles incorpo-
0 1997 by the American Society of Law, Medicine & Ethics. rating feminist perspectives on specific problems in bioet-

58
TheJournal of Law, Medicine & Ethics

hics. All articles are linked by a common critique challeng- color, who are constantly subjected to the interlocking,
ing traditional bioethical analyses (whether principlism, ca- mutually reinforcing systems of racial, class-based, and
suistry, Kantian-based theories, or utilitarian approaches) sexual oppressions, offer bioethicists the best perspective
as inadequate, because they fail to confront the politically to evaluate doctor-patient relationships and to critique bio-
and socially oppressivecontexts of racism, sexism, and class- ethical principles such as confidentiality, truth-telling, and
based domination that infuse medical care practices and patient autonomy. Her poignant examples of the impact
ethicists’ understandings and because they fail to examine on poor black women of physicians’ roles in the prosecu-
the specific ways in which women’s lives and experiences tion of drug-addicted, pregnant women, of congressional
are affected. and Supreme Court actions prohibiting doctors from in-
Articles in Part I explain what feminist critiques of forming women at federally funded clinics about abortion
bioethics are and how these critiques alter our approaches options, and of forced cesareans on women who want to
to patient care, physician-patient relationships,research de- proceed with natural childbirth confirm her thesis that black
sign, institutional practices, and scholarly thinking. Sher- women’s experiences reflect a unique perspective on bio-
win’s, Tong’s, and Mahowald’s chapters generally repeat ethics informed by the combination of their being domi-
analyses each has made in her own impressive book? Each nated by these intersecting oppressions, their reliance on
article alone would be a sufficient introduction, but to- systems of publicly financed health care, and their con-
gether they reinforce the others in offering a sufficient comitant distrust of physician benevolence from years of
grounding in feminist theories to enable a beginner to discriminatory treatment. Roberts concludes by suggest-
contextualize the remainder of the volume. An important ing a multi-step approach to reconstruction of the patient
insight from these foundational articles is that feminism is on whom the physician-patient relationship is based.
multifarious and does not lend itself to a single analysis or Dresser’s tight article challenges bioethicists to learn
conclusion. Although these preliminary essays make that from the Women’s Health Movement and in particular from
clear, the volume as a whole does not tease out this thesis the work of the Boston Women’s Health Book Collective,
by presenting complementary or competing feminist ap- which has published several editions of Our Bodies, Our-
proaches on the same issue. Wolf may have chosen this selves.I3 Dresser identifies three themes from that move-
strategy, however, because of page limitations and the ment-discontentment with contemporary health care,
breadtli of topics she included. including the social degradation and neglect that pervade
Articles in Part I1 apply feminist analyses to concrete women’s encounters with the health care system; political
problems. Each article is fact-ladenand carefully researched and cultural barriers to women’s full and fair participation
in its bioethid area, These works draw from extensive, in the health care system; and transformative efforts to
familiar literatures to present critiques of HIV and drug- reduce women’s dependence on medical “experts”-that
related research protocols that ignore “pregnable omen";^ ought to guide bioethicists as well. Her detailed analysis
”information-transfer” models (as opposed to “mutual offers concrete suggestions for improving the medical care
understanding” models) of communication in physician- system that she urges bioethicists to include in their prac-
patient relationships;6narrow constructionsof “the patient” tices and scholarly works.
that exclude actual life experiences of poor women of color In ‘A Feminist View of Health,” Purdy argues for a
and women’s differently socialized perspectivesand physi- definition of health that moves from the dominant view of
cal bodies;’ prenatal and prediction-based genetic screen- health as the absence of infirmities to a richer definition of
ing (which again makes “biology = destiny” in contradis- health as a state of positive well-being. Health involves
tinction to decades of feminist struggle against that very physical and mental infirmities, but positive well-being is a
notion);*health care resource allocation proposals that rec- much broader notion. Purdy makes clear, however, that
ommend age limits on health care access without consider- her definition does not include social infirmities, because
ing that most elderly are women;9 death and dying issues their inclusion in a definition of health medicalizestoo much
that ignore gender ramifications;10and definitions of health of life and makes physicians experts in matters that are
that emphasize the absence of infirmities rather than the better dealt with through public debates that tap the knowl-
state of positive weIl-being.’l It does a disservice to the edge and experiences of a wide range of people. Purdy
richness of each of these works to summarize them in a postulates about some aspects of positive well-being, but
phrase or paragraph, yet space constraintshere limit me to concludes that “[d]iscovering what positive well-being
only whetting a reader’s appetite for more. might mean for women in a world without sexism is a
Roberts’s article “Reconstructing the Patient: Starting project to which we all must now turn.”14
with Women of Color” reflects the compelling work she Communicative ethics are compared to an informa-
has been doing for years in examining bioethics, mother- tion-transfer model of communication in Farrell Smith’s
hood, and social policy issues from the perspectives of black article “CommunicativeEthics in Medicine: The Physician-
women.12 Roberts argues that poverty-stricken women of Patient Relati~nship.”~~ Relying primarily on the work of

59
Volume 25:I, Spring 1997

Jiirgen Habermas and Seyla Benhabib, Smith critiques the flated because the definition of AIDS does not include gy-
presently accepted model of physician-patient communi- necological conditions due to HIV infection.
cation for failing to focus on the concrete, rather than gen- Wolf’s own article investigates how gender dynamics
eralized, patient. She contends that the current proposal affect physician-assisted~uicide.’~ Her critique is especially
stresses one-way information transfer rather than mutual poignant in light of the recent Supreme Court cases on this
understanding through conversation; and it fails to attend subject.20Asch and Geller’s disability-basedfeminist analysis
to gender, race, and class-based differences in power and of genetics cautions that although genetic testing can be
authority between the parties, in addition to differences in viewed as enhancing choices and informed decision mak-
medical knowledge and experience, that lead to unequal ing, it also risks surrendering “social meaning to biological
exchanges. Smith argues that communicative ethics, which fact,” by allowing scientists to shape the ethical and social
understand communication as action and a source of val- consequences of genetic predispositionswithout the voices
ues rather than as a transparent information-transferring of gene carriers, persons with disabilities, and persons from
event, better serves the interests of equality, justice, and other disciplines.2’The Lindemann Nelsons illustrate how
compassion in physician-patient relations. recent proposals about the just allocation of health care
Merton’s article on biomedical researchI6 and Faden, resources fail to account for the disproportionate effects of
Kass, and McGraw’s article on women and the HIV epi- those plans on women.u They suggest that an adequate
demic” both challenge medical research protocols for their allocation of resources requires the just structuringof power
exclusion of women. Both articles are full of information (with attention to voices of disempowered groups, more
about how women have been excluded from research and participatory democracy, and a demedicalization of aspects
the harmful effects of that exclusion. Merton artfully ar- of health like childbirth), a shift toward remedying prob-
gues against the scientificcommunity’s exclusion of women lems of poverty that impact health resource allocations
from drug testing because they are “pregnable,” carefully (from nonemployment-relatedsources for health benefits
dismantling the biases, fallacious premises, and disuimi- to safe, affordable housing and enhanced education), and a
nation used to justify the exclusion. For example, the re- noncompartmentalized interest in outcomes, not services.
productive capacities of men are never considered to jus- In conclusion, this powerful anthology of bioethical
tify their exclusion in drug research, even though many writings brings together feminist critiques of a wide range
factors affect the health of men’s reproductive materials. of areas sorely in need of power-based and inclusionary
And Merton asks why unborn and even unconceived fe- analyses. Because feminist bioethical literature is so diverse
tuses take priority over the health of already living women. and dispersed in the literature, Wolf has served the bioeth-
This article should be required reading for all medical re- ics community well by coIIecting so many ideas in one
searchers. place.
The subordination of the health interests of live women
to unborn fetuses in research protocols for drug testing is
further exposed by Faden, Kass, and McGraw, who show References
that almost all the studies of women and H N were de- 1. See, for example, KH. Rothenberg and E.J. Thomson,
voted to issues of vertical transmission-primarily to fe- eds., Women and Prenatal Testing: Facing the Challenges of Ge-
netic Technology (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1994);
tuses through childbearing and breast-feeding (but also by C. Overall, Ethics and Human Reproduction (Boston: Allen 8c
prostitutes communicatingthe disease to men)-rather than Unwin, 1987); B.K. Rothman, The Tentative Pregnancy: Prena-
to the health of the infected women. This article examines tal Diagnosis and the Future of Motherhood (New York: Viking,
the painful history of the inordinately slow response of 1986); G. Corea, The Mother Machine: Reproductive Technolo-
H N and AIDS researchers to women’s health needs (the gies from Artificial Insemination to Artificial Wombs (New York:
Harper & Row, 1985); M. Stanworth, ed., Reproductive Tech-
first reported case of AIDS in a woman was 1981,but the nologies: Gender, Motherhood and Medicine (Minneapolis: Uni-
first major study by the National Institutes of Health of versity of Minnesota Press, 1987); J. Callahan, ed., Reproduc-
how HIV progresses and manifests in women did not be- tion, Ethics and the Law: Feminist Perspectives (Bloomington:
gin until late 1994)and the absence of women from clini- Indiana University Press, 1995); C.R. Daniels, At Women’s Ex-
cal trials and from the AIDS literature. This narrative is pense: State Power and the Politics of Fetal Rights (Cambridge.
HarvardUniversity Press, 1993); I? Boling, ed., wetting Trouble:
complemented by analysis of the injustice of women’s ex- Surrogacy, Fetal Abuse &New Reproductive Technologies (Boul-
clusion and its impact on women’s health. Though women der: Westview Press, 1995); R. Arditti et al., eds., Test-Tube
represent a smaller percentage of AIDS cases than their Women: What Future for Motherhood (Boston: Pandora, 1984);
proportion of the population, the authors explain that the H.B. Holmes, ed., Issues in Reproductive Technology I: An An-
number of AIDS cases in women have increased faster than thology (New York: Garland, 1992); H.B. Holmes et al., eds.,
The Custom-Made Child?-Women-Centered Perspectives
in men in nearly every year since 1986,and, between 1985 (Clifton: Humana, 1981); R.F. Chadwick, ed., Ethics, Repro-
and 1988, the mortality rate in women quadrupled.’* In duction and Genetic Control (London: Routledge,rev. ed., 1992);
addition, statistics on AIDS in women are inaccurately de- J.G. Raymond, Women as Wombs: Reproductive Technologies

60
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics

and the Battle Over Women’s Freedom (New York: Harper Vectors: Lessons from the HIV Epidemic,” in Wolf, ed., supra
Collins, 1993); G. Sen and R.C. Snow, eds., Power and Deci- note 3, at 252-81.
sion: The Social Control of Reproduction (Boston: Harvard Uni- 6.J.F. Smith, “Communicative Ethics in Medicine: The
versity Press, 1994); R. Rowland, Living Laboratories: Women Physician-Patient Relationship,” in Wolf, ed., supra note 3, at
and Reproductive Dchnologies (Bloomington: Indiana Univer- 184-215.
sity Press, 1992);and I? Spallone and D.I. Steinberg, eds., Made 7. D.E. Roberts, “Reconstructing the Patient: Starting with
to Order: The Myth of Reproductive and Genetic Progress (New Women of Color,” in Wolf, ed., supra note 3,at 11643;and R.
York: Pergamon, 1987). Dresser, “What Bioethics Can Learn from the Women’s Health
2. R. Tong, Feminist Approaches to Bioethics (Boulder: Movement,” in Wolf, ed., supra note 3, at 144-59. Actually,
Westview Press, 1997); M.B. Mahowald, Women and Childma both articles are in Part I, but they seem to fit better here in my
in Health Care: An Unequal Majority (New York: Oxford Uni- review
versity Press, 1993);H.B. Holmes and L.M. Purdy, eds., Femi- 8. A. Asch and G. Geller, “Feminism, Bioethics, and Ge-
nist Perspectives in Medical Ethics (Bloomington: Indiana Uni- netics,” in Wolf, ed., supra note 3, at 318-50.
versity Press, 1992); S. Sherwin, No Longer Patient: Feminist 9. H.L. Nelson and J.L.Nelson, ‘‘Justice in the Allocation
Ethics and Health Care (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, of Health Care Resources: A Feminist Account,” in Wolf, ed.,
1992);A. Dula and S. Goering, eds., “It lust Ain’t Fair”: The supra note 3, at 351-70.
Ethics of Health Care for AfZcan Americuns (Westport: Praeger, 10. S.M. Wolf, “Gender, Feminism, and Death: Physician-
1994);E.C.White, ed., The Black Women’sHealth Book: Speak- Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia,” in Wolf, ed., supra note 3, at
ing for Ourselves (Seattle: Seal Press, 1990); A.D. Todd,lnti- 282-317.
mate Advemaries: Cultural ConflictBetween Doctors and Women 11. L.M. Purdy, ‘A Feminist View of Health,” in Wolf, ed.,
Patients (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1989); supra note 3, at 163-83.
S. Fisher, In the Patient’s Best Interest: Womenand the Politics of 12. See, for example, D.E. Roberts, “Unshackling Black
Medical Decisions (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, Motherhood,” Michigan Law Review, 95 (1997):938-64;D.E.
1986); and L Darvd, Medicine, Law and Social Change: The Roberts, “Race and the New Reproduction,” Hastings Law]our-
lmpact of Bioethics, Feminism and Rights Movements on Medi- nal,47 (1996):935-94; D.E. Roberts, “Racism and Patriarchy
cal Decision-Making (Brookfield: Dartmouth Press, 1993). in the Meaning of Motherhood,” American University Journal
3. The endnotes to Susan Wolf’s introductory essay pro- ofGenderand theLaw, 1 (1993):1-38; and D.E. Roberts, “Pun-
vide an outstanding source for bioethical scholars and practitio- ishing Drug Addicts Who Have Babies: Women of Color, Equal-
ners. See S.M.Wolf, “Introduction: Gender and Feminism in ity, and the Right of Privacy,” Haward Law Review, 104 (1991):
Bioethics,” in S.M.Wolf, ed., Feminism @. Bioethics: Beyond 1419-82.
Reproduction (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996): at 13. See Dresser, supra note 7;and Boston Women’s Health
3343. Book Collective, The New Our Bodies, Ourselves: A Book By
4. S. Sherwin, “Feminism andBioethics,” in Wolf, ed.,supra and For Women (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1992).
note 3,at 47-66; R. Tong, “FeministApproaches to Bioethics,” 14. Purdy, supra note 11,at 177.
in Wolf, ed., supra note 3, at 67-94; and M.B.Mahowald, “On 15. See Smith, supra note 6.
Treatment of Myopia: Feminist Standpoint Theory and Bioeth- 16. See Merton, supra note 5.
ics,” in Wolf, ed., supra note 3, at 95-115. These three articles 17. See Faden, Kass, and McGraw, supra note 5 .
may seem repetitive to the schooled feminist reader who has 18. See id. at 260.
read their books and/or other writings and has a grounding in 19. See Wolf, supra note 10.
feminist theory and bioethics. 20. Washingtonu. Gl&6qY 117 S. Ct. 37 (1996)(granting
5. Y Merton, “EthicalObstacles to Participation of Women cert.); and Quill u. Vacco, 117 S . Ct. 36 (1996)(granting cert.).
in Biomedical Research,” in Wolf, ed., supra note 3, at 216-51; 21. See Asch and Geller, supra note 8, at 342.
and R. Faden, N. Kass, and D. McGraw, “Women as Vessels and 22. See Nelson and Nelson, supra note 9.

61

You might also like