Retrieve PDF

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

Evangelical Toleration

Teresa M. Bejan, University of Oxford

This article recovers “evangelical toleration” as a neglected tradition in early modern political thought with important
consequences for contemporary political theory and practice. Many political theorists dismiss the prudential arguments
made by “proto-liberal” thinkers like Roger Williams or John Locke in favor of toleration as a necessary precondition for
evangelism and conversion as intolerant, unacceptably instrumental, and inessential to their deeper theories. By contrast,
critics of liberalism treat them as smoking gun evidence for an imperial and civilizing mission underlying liberal toler-
ation. I argue that both sides underestimate evangelical toleration’s genealogical and theoretical importance. Not only
were evangelical considerations essential in shaping the particular institutions associated with toleration in England and
America, the varieties of evangelical toleration represented by Williams and Locke shed significant light on the very
different institutions—and intuitions—governing the expression of religious difference in liberal democracies today.

I n 1655, an embassy of Dutch Jews led by Rabbi Menas-


sah ben Israel traveled to London to meet with the Com-
monwealth’s new Lord Protector, Oliver Cromwell. The
informal “Readmission” of Jews—who had been expelled from
England by royal edict in 1290—resulting from the Whitehall
as a yes-or-no proposition of principled pluralism. Rather, the
heterogeneous “horizontal” social practices and “vertical” in-
stitutional arrangements that developed for the peaceful ac-
commodation of religious diversity were more often defended
as prudential, second-best or halfway measures for the sake
conference was once hailed as a high point in the history of greater goods (Williams and Waldron 2008). In the case of
of toleration. Yet in recent years, scholars have increasingly Readmission, these goods were not only politic and economic
challenged the progressive nature of this event, both in its but explicitly evangelical: the apocalyptic expectations of En-
substance and its motivation (Kaplan 2007; Katznelson 2010; glish Protestants dictated that the time for the Jews’ conversion
Walsham 2006). “Toleration” in this case, as in many others, was nigh and carefully circumscribed toleration a necessary
did not entail religious freedom or civic equality; Jews in means to that end.
England were granted legal residency and permitted to worship Such arguments in favor of Jewish Readmission offer a
privately, but citizenship, public worship, and the printing of prime example of what I call “evangelical toleration.” By this,
anything that “opposeth the Christian religion” remained off I do not mean simply theological (particularly Protestant) ar-
the cards. As for its motivation, Edward Whalley’s twofold guments about the voluntary nature of faith or the irratio-
argument was fairly representative: the Jews “will bring in much nality of coercion in the cause of conversion. Mark Goldie,
wealth into this Commonwealth: and where wee both pray for from whom I take the phrase, uses it in this more general way
theyre conversion and beleeve it shal be, I knowe not why wee to describe a constellation of theological arguments for tol-
shold deny the means” (Marshall 2006, 381–82). eration in the seventeenth century.1 Rather, I mean the ar-
In challenging traditional Whig narratives about the “rise of gument that toleration is a necessary precondition for in-
toleration” in early modern England as the inexorable progress dividuals to preach and propagate the Gospel and so convert
of liberal enlightenment, political theorists and historians have others to it. This is a very old Christian argument, although it
rightly stressed that toleration did not emerge in this period is not unique to Christianity, and it achieved new power and

Teresa M. Bejan (teresa.bejan@oriel.ox.ac.uk) is an associate professor of political theory in the Department of Politics and International Relations, Uni-
versity of Oxford, Oxford OX1 3UQ, UK.
1. Goldie outlines this more expansive “evangelical toleration” and its importance for early modern tolerationism in the latter half of his coauthored
essay with Richard Popkin (Goldie and Popkin 2006).

The Journal of Politics, volume 77, number 4. Published online August 13, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/682568
q 2015 by the Southern Political Science Association. All rights reserved. 0022-3816/2015/7704-0016$10.00 1103
1104 / Evangelical Toleration Teresa M. Bejan

prominence in the early modern toleration debates to which of civil society in the wilderness, one committed to protect-
political theorists—despite the best efforts of revisionist his- ing its members’ evangelical liberty, as well as the heated and
torians—continue to trace the origins of liberal political often highly uncivil wars of words it inspired. In contrast with
thought and institutions (e.g., Rawls 1996). Williams’s polemical approach to evangelism, Locke’s was
Given this, theorists’ relative disinterest in these evangeli- irenic—that is, oriented toward peace, conciliation, and con-
cal arguments is striking, if not particularly surprising.2 No sensus.3 His life-long concerns about the dangers of “ill us-
doubt to many readers, “evangelical toleration” will sound age” and “unreasonable” zeal in evangelical competition left a
like a contradiction in terms. For those on the receiving end, lasting impression on his theory of toleration. Specifically,
evangelism can often feel like an inherently intolerant activ- they informed his positive vision of a tolerant society as one
ity and, as a justification for toleration, singularly unper- characterized by “reasonable” evangelism that would encour-
suasive—more like a veiled threat. On this view, evangelical age citizens to cultivate indifference toward their differences,
toleration reflects, at best, a conditional commitment to di- affirm an underlying agreement on the “fundamentals” of faith,
versity for the sake of future uniformity; at worst, it relies and so put an end to religious wars of words entirely.
upon and perpetuates a form of verbal persecution that is Given the importance of evangelical toleration for both
itself a violation of the negative religious freedom of others. thinkers, one might wonder why it has not received more
Still, other readers will likely have an equally strong reaction scholarly attention. Where these arguments have been ac-
in the opposite direction. For them, evangelism will repre- knowledged, political theorists often draw attention to them
sent a straightforward case of free expression and evangelical as part and parcel of a historicizing maneuver meant to
competition an example of the sort of robust disagreement consign these early “liberals” to the antiquarian dustbin by
and contestation that is the lifeblood of liberal democracy. distancing them from the ostensibly secular argumentation
The strong and conflicting intuitions that many readers, of a more enlightened age (e.g., Dunn 1969). On the other
including many self-professed liberals, have about the place of hand, for critics of liberal toleration they represent a smok-
evangelism in a tolerant society is itself strong evidence that ing gun—undeniable evidence of a fundamental, disqualifying
evangelical toleration deserves much closer attention than it intolerance and civilizational imperialism at the heart of the
has hitherto received. Accordingly, this article will explore liberal project (Brown 2008; Mahmood 2009; Scherer 2013).
this tradition and the importance of evangelical arguments The favored alternative among commentators concerned to
and expectations for two seventeenth-century thinkers in defend liberal toleration and the continued salience of figures
particular. Roger Williams and John Locke are commonly like Locke and Williams seems to be to hold their noses and
cited as foundational figures in a distinctive, Anglo-American dismiss these arguments as inessential to the deeper theories,
tradition of liberalism with the principle of religious tolera- as so much lip service to Christian principles when the real
tion at its core. Although scholars often gesture toward the motivating principles or interests (of state, self, etc.) lay
vaguely “protestant” assumptions underlying liberal tolera- elsewhere (Forst 2013; Nussbaum 2008a).
tion and the separation of church and state and individual Underlying all of these responses seems to be an unspo-
rights with which these thinkers are associated (Mahmood ken agreement with Rousseau, that “it is impossible to live
2009; Waldron 2012), I will demonstrate that Williams’s and in peace with people one believes to be damned” ([1762] 1997,
Locke’s projects were shaped specifically by evangelical con- 151). Yet this article will challenge this assumption and dem-
siderations and, moreover, that these considerations also led onstrate that the differences between the theories of evan-
their projects to diverge in important but neglected ways. gelical toleration covered here have unappreciated historical
Williams developed his doggedly controversial and often and normative significance. Far from being antiquarian, when
combative approach to evangelism in the course of his in- it comes to understanding the often very different institu-
teractions with the American Indians and other Protestant tions and intuitions governing the expression of religious
sectarians in New England and Old. In founding Rhode Is- difference in modern liberal democracies—including press-
land, he faced the concrete challenge of creating a new kind ing questions about the place of blasphemy and religious
insult in tolerant societies—the rival traditions of evangelical
toleration developed by Locke and Williams speak volumes.

2. Despite theorists’ growing interest in the plural practices and prudential


justifications of early modern toleration over the past two decades, evangeli-
cal toleration has been consistently ignored. See, e.g., Forst (2013), Men-
dus (1988), Murphy (1997), Sabl (2008), Williams and Waldron (2008), and 3. Both terms derive from ancient Greek: “irenic” from the Greek for
Walzer (1997). peace and “polemic” for war.
Volume 77 Number 4 October 2015 / 1105

Indeed, the conclusion will argue that, beyond its genealogical Word of God, was a sin of pride through which one sacrificed
significance, Williams’s “paradoxical” form of polemical yet another, body and soul, to one’s own self-love.
inclusive evangelical toleration presents an attractive alter- This distinction is often lost today, but for these early
native to Locke’s irenic but exclusionary reasonableness as an modern “evangelicals”—as for many modern believers—it was
approach to difference and disagreement today—not only for paramount (Fisher forthcoming). Nevertheless, as their critics
religious citizens, but for everyone. pointed out, the words they employed in propagating the
Word could be forceful, and these would-be evangelists often
approached the line of verbal violence. Martin Luther had
EVANGELISM AND TOLERATION
instructed his followers that the Greek evangel could also mean
Before turning to the varieties of evangelical toleration found
“a shout” (Szabari 2006, 127), and many of the enthusiastic
in Williams and Locke and their potential for the present, it is
sects that later emerged followed his example. Still, for them,
necessary to say a bit more about the origins of this tradition
the noncoerciveness of evangelism in its reliance on words not
in early modern political thought, as well as its two key terms—
swords was essential. True conversion was linked inextri-
evangelism and toleration—both of which may give modern
cably with “Christian liberty” or the liberty of conscience,
readers pause.
which meant not the modern notion of a blanket freedom
Political theorists often treat evangelism as synonymous
even for erroneous opinions but rather the liberty of an in-
with proselytism, a term that carries pronounced pejorative
dividual, through evangelism and the gift of God’s grace, to
connotations (Robeck 1996). Both words derive from Greek
assent voluntarily to religious truth and convert—literally,
and describe practices forged in the early days of Chris-
“turn”—toward God. Thus, in the sixteenth and seventeenth
tianity. Evangelism—from euangelion meaning “good mes-
centuries neither principle—persuasive conversion or liberty
sage”—describes the act of preaching or promulgating the
of conscience—entailed toleration. Defenders of persecution
good news of the Gospel, while proselytism—from the Greek
followed Augustine in arguing that “benevolent harshness”
for “come toward”—describes the practice of making or at-
could be an essential pastoral support by ensuring evangelists
tempting to make converts, that is “newcomers” to God.4 To-
an audience and making errant consciences shut up and
day, the latter often implies coercion, whether through threats,
listen (Goldie 1991). Although force could not compel belief,
force, or material rewards, but for early Christians, an embat-
it could pressure heretics and apostates to come to church,
tled minority lacking access to the levers of state power, there
hear the sermon, and take communion in the hope that this
was no meaningful distinction. The Apostles, the original
feigned conformity might, in time, become sincere faith.5
evangelists, spread the “good news” of the Gospel throughout
For figures like Sebastian Castellio, however, one of the
the Hellenic world and beyond by preaching alone. With the
earliest protestant defenders of toleration, such arguments
conversion of Constantine, however, Christians gained ac-
for pastoral persecution seemed clearly counterproductive
cess to institutional sources of coercion previously unavail-
and self-defeating. Castellio is often heralded as a harbinger of
able and began to deploy them for pastoral ends.
enlightened humanism and skeptical modernity, but he was
Saint Augustine pioneered and perfected the rationale for
also a pioneer in the tradition of evangelical toleration. In his
applying nonlethal coercion in the “correction” of heretics
most famous work, Concerning Heretics ([1554] 1965), he la-
and apostates as part of the duty of religious and political
mented that Christians were not more “mindful of our office,”
elites to ensure the social conditions most conducive to salus
that is, their evangelical duty of charity to save the souls of their
populi, including their salvation (Goldie 1991). Yet while this
fellow men. A truly mindful evangelist would not dedicate
Augustinian defense of pastoral persecution was highly influ-
himself to condemning others as “heretics” and “infidels” but
ential for more than a millennium, it was also controversial. For
to convincing them of the superior moral truth of Christianity:
its critics—especially early modern protestant dissenters who
saw themselves as the inheritors of primitive Christianity—
Let not the Jews or Turks condemn the Christians,
evangelism was an essential duty belonging to all Christians, as
nor let the Christians condemn the Jews or Turks, but
a demonstration of one’s love for one’s neighbor in seeking his
rather teach and win them by true religion, and let us,
salvation. But proselytism, the practice of making of converts
who are Christians, not condemn one another. . . .
with the aid of coercion beyond the persuasive power of the

5. The extent to which pastoral punishments—and what kind—could


4. OED, “Evangelism, N.”; “Proselytism, N.” (2015). I am grateful to be used would become a sticking point in Locke’s debates with Proast in
the anonymous reviewers for helping me to clarify this distinction. the later Letters on Toleration.
1106 / Evangelical Toleration Teresa M. Bejan

Even though in some matters we disagree, yet should not be tolerated but either persecuted or fully included in civil
we consent together and forebear one another in love, and spiritual life.7
which is the bond of peace, until we arrive at the unity Here one might be tempted to conclude that “evangelical
of faith. But now, when we strive with hate and per- toleration” is not an oxymoron at all but a naked declara-
secutions we go from bad to worse . . . since we are tion of religious hatred, exclusion, and destruction deferred.
wholly taken up with condemnation, and the Gospel In keeping with its medieval origins, to “tolerate” something—
because of us is made a reproach unto the heathen. or someone—still carries an unmistakable whiff of contempt
(Castellio [1554] 1965, 132–33) and exclusion at odds with the respect and “atmosphere of
inclusiveness” that many view as the sine qua non of tolerant
His disappointment with his fellow Christians was palpable: society (Waldron 2012). Should the prudential calculus ever
“We rather degenerate into Turks and Jews than convert them shift, the tolerated can never be certain that the tolerator
into Christians” (133). would not prefer to eliminate the tolerated evil entirely. The
Modern readers inclined to view evangelical toleration as discomfort palpable in recent historical treatments of Jewish
an oxymoron will note that the instrumental justification for Readmission reflects a similar intuition. As for political theo-
toleration as a precondition for persuasive conversion offered rists, many share Stephen Carter’s anxiety that, if the idea that
by Castellio and later taken up by evangelical Protestants in “Christians should tolerate Jews developed hand-in-glove with
the case of Readmission is a far cry from the positive affir- the notion that [they] should try to persuade them to come to
mation of diversity with which tolerance is often linked today. Christ” and so “wipe them off the face of the earth through
Yet as a form of forbearance in the face of an acknowledged conversion,” it would be better to dispense with the concept
evil, this evangelical toleration is “tolerant” in a more tradi- entirely (1993, 93–94).
tional sense. In the Middle Ages, Catholic casuists defended Evangelical toleration would thus seem only to exacerbate
tolerantia as a policy of limited permission appropriate to the problems of instrumentalism and implicit intolerance
lesser evils, including non-Christian minorities, for the sake identified by Rousseau and which political theorists attribute
of avoiding greater ones (Bejczy 1997). The differential treat- to other “merely” prudential arguments for toleration (Men-
ment of religious “outsiders” like Muslims and Jews, who dus et al. 1988). Like them, it seems too unstable and ethically
could be tolerated, and deviant “insiders”—Christian heretics minimal to meet the challenges of cooperation and coexistence
and schismatics—who could not, was key.6 The former were under conditions of deep diversity while at the same time in-
few and were more likely to be brought to Christianity with troducing a source of creeping intolerance (evangelism) de-
honey than gall. But the latter, as corrupt members of the termined to undermine that diversity from within. Given this,
body of Christ, carried with them a more intimate threat of the fact that evangelical toleration has been routinely ignored
spiritual pollution and hence must be “cut off ” or reformed. by theorists, even those determined to push back against the
Being tolerated was thus fundamentally an outsider “moralizing tendency” of recent work on toleration and recover
status, and one can see this medieval dynamic of inclu- its plural practices and motivations, is not at all surprising
sion and exclusion at work in Castellio’s argument. His was (Zuolo 2013, 219). From the standpoint of modern political
an evangelical toleration in which evangelism went one way philosophy, the traditional evangelical arguments developed
only—from the true Christian to the false—while denying by Castellio and deployed by other protestant authors in the
the tolerated any reciprocal liberty. Similarly, in the debates sixteenth and seventeenth centuries are not only unsavory and
about Jewish Readmission at Whitehall, this condition of non- unedifying but philosophically uninteresting and, when it
evangelism was made explicit in the caveat that Jews not print comes to how we should think about toleration today, entirely
anything that “opposeth” Christianity. Proponents argued that beside the point.
the evil of religious diversity in the Commonwealth should be
endured for the sake of the greatest good, the salvation of both
tolerator and tolerated. Yet toleration remained a provisional,
inferior status granted to Jews as dependents and outsiders and
distinguishing them from the recalcitrant religious insiders— 7. Of course, the distinction between insiders and outsiders was often
in this case, Catholics and Protestant sectarians—who would subject to careful negotiation. For instance, the 1689 Act of Toleration
excluded Catholics and Unitarians while affording Trinitarian Protestants
a limited degree of “insider” status by suspending the penalties for non-
attendance at an Anglican church. However, they were still excluded from
holding office and enrolling at the Universities. I thank one of the anony-
6. For a good example of this distinction, see Aquinas (2002, 267–78). mous reviewers for suggesting this example.
Volume 77 Number 4 October 2015 / 1107

Underlying this rejection one can detect, once again, Indeed, in his many toleration writings Williams adopted
an unspoken agreement with Rousseau. Had the tradition of the same prudential reasoning employed by Castellio and
evangelical toleration been limited to the prudential justifi- later at Whitehall by arguing that all heretics and infidels
cations and asymmetrical conditions offered at Whitehall, should be tolerated because all were potential converts. As he
these suspicions might be well founded. Yet in drawing on put it in his most famous toleration tract, The Bloudy Tenent
the evangelical arguments pioneered by Castellio, seventeenth- of Persecution ([1644] 1963b), “he that is a briar, that is, a Jew, a
century thinkers like Williams and Locke also radically trans- Turke, a Pagan, [or] an anti-christian today, may be when the
formed them, from something “mere” into something more: word of the Lord runs freely a member of Jesus Christ tomor-
an evangelical liberty that was not the exclusive privilege of row” (95). Whereas an earlier generation of scholars implicated
true Christians to make converts but a universal right of all. Williams in the “missionary conquest” of America, those con-
The following sections will recover their sophisticated and cerned to celebrate him today as a multiculturalist avant la
competing conceptions of evangelical toleration as a con- lettre ignore these arguments altogether. Nussbaum dismisses
stellation of ethical and institutional arrangements by which this “instrumental” reason as “a common Protestant argument
those convinced of one another’s damnation might never- in the period, one that Locke made central to his own case
theless live together, compete for converts, and flourish. for toleration” but insists that unlike Locke, “one cannot read
Williams’s text . . . and doubt that [he] also thinks damage to
ROGER WILLIAMS AND EVANGELICAL LIBERTY conscience an intrinsic wrong” (2008a, 54). The further im-
Roger Williams (ca. 1603–1683), the founder of Rhode Island, plication that evangelism as such is disrespectful and an un-
has been enjoying something of a renaissance of late among acceptable reason for toleration is clear from her insistence
political theorists who see him as a promising alternative to that his only motivation in conversing with the American
Locke as a “proto-liberal” theorist of toleration (Bejan 2011; Indians must have been “a respectful curiosity” about their
Nussbaum 2008a, 2008b). After all, the 1663 “Charter of customs (46–47). “Despite his fervent Christian beliefs, there
Rhode Island and Providence Plantations” enshrined two is no record that he ever tried to convert any of them” (54).
unprecedented policy innovations closely associated with Given Williams’s own detailed accounts of evangelizing
liberal toleration—complete religious disestablishment and the Americans, both in his published works and correspon-
equal protection for all citizens in the “free exercise and en- dence, this claim simply cannot be sustained. The Rhode Is-
joyment of all their civil and religious rights.” And while land Charter commended him and other colonists by name for
contemporaries like Milton and Locke balked at the idea of diligently attending to the “conversion of the poor ignorant
tolerating Catholics and atheists, Williams argued that Jews, Indian natives” to “holy Christian faith and worship, as they
“Turkes” (Muslims), “pagans” (American Indians), and even were persuaded” (Charter 1663). Yet Nussbaum’s concerted
“anti-Christians”—that is, followers of the papal anti-Christ— efforts to downplay the evangelical core of Williams’s tolera-
were equally entitled to toleration, as well as all protestant sects. tion project reflect the same subterranean discomfort evident
Yet it is Williams’s close relationship with the Narra- in recent histories of Readmission. It seems that in order to
gansett Indians, who sheltered him after his banishment from make Williams palatable to modern audiences, one must deny
Massachusetts Bay, and his impassioned calls for toleration on against all evidence that his evangelical arguments reflected
their behalf that have caught scholars’ attention above all as any interest in actually converting anyone. Yet this funda-
evidence of an open-minded, even multicultural approach to mentally misrepresents his toleration project. For Williams,
toleration attractive today. Foremost is Martha Nussbaum, the suggestion that toleration and evangelism went hand in
who presents Williams as an exemplar of ideals of fairness and hand was more than just an opportunistic, instrumental aside
respect that “continue to be central to the best work in recent that can be written out. Williams’s participation in and re-
political philosophy” from Kant to Rawls (Nussbaum 2008a, imagination of the evangelical tradition inaugurated by Castellio
57). But in making Williams’s relationship with the Narra- had important consequences for his theory of toleration—both
gansett central, she and others have deliberately downplayed ethically, in the everyday practices and interactions of indi-
the extent to which Williams justified the radical scope of his viduals, and institutionally, in the political and legal arrange-
toleration—including American “pagans”—on explicitly evan- ments he believed liberty of conscience required.
gelical grounds.8 To see this, it is necessary to look at how Williams himself
practiced toleration toward American “pagans” and English
8. For a detailed historical treatment of this issue and the salience of
protestants alike. His approach in both cases was unapolo-
concerns about “evangelical liberty” to Williams’s toleration, see Bejan getically evangelistic, but unlike most of his contemporaries,
(2015). Williams saw evangelism as an essentially critical and con-
1108 / Evangelical Toleration Teresa M. Bejan

troversial affair. He believed that the true form of Christ’s men were created of stone, then wood (217). Moreover, when
worship had eluded Christians since the conversion of Con- Williams talked Hellfire, the Narragansett talked back. To his
stantine had tempted them with the powers of proselytism assertion that “English-men, Dutch men, and you [Amer-
and persecution. Nevertheless, the “saints” could fulfill their icans] and all the world, when they die . . . that know not
charitable duty to evangelize by witnessing against that which this God . . . goe to Hell or the Deepe [and] shall ever la-
was false in Christendom. In this commitment to a polem- ment,” they responded, “Who told you so?”, and he noted
ical form of evangelism Williams’s controversial religious their critical questioning about whether to accept his an-
and political pamphlets and the conversations described in swer—“Gods Booke or Writing”—approvingly (218–19).
his handbook of Narragansett language, A Key into the Lan- Here the distinctive character of Williams’s universal
guage of America ([1643] 1963a), were of a piece. The Key evangelical toleration as a departure from the tradition in-
reported many dialogues with the Americans about “How augurated by Castellio comes more clearly into view. Ethi-
Man fell from God, and his present Enmity against God, and cally, toleration was clearly compatible with viewing others as
the wrath of God against him until Repentance” (Williams potential converts and with expressing one’s negative judg-
[1643] 1963a, 86–87). The helpful dialogue about damnation ments about them and their religion as well. As far as Williams
included in the chapter “Of Their Religion” expanded on this was concerned, the Americans were “Divell”-worshippers and
theme: “Friend, when you die you perish everlastingly. You Catholics deserved the name of “anti-Christians.” And yet he
are everlastingly undone. God is angry with you. He will believed that American pagans, Catholic anti-Christians, Jews,
destroy you. For your many Gods. The whole world ere long and “Turkes” should not only be grudgingly forborne but ac-
be burnt” ([1643] 1963a, 134). In response to the profitable tively engaged in civil, yet unmistakably evangelical, conver-
question, “What then will become of us?” Williams replied: sation. This mutual and occasionally antagonistic evangelism
“God commandeth. That all men now repent” (138–39). was a messy, unconstrained, and altogether uncertain affair in
Pace Nussbaum then, Williams evidently took his duty to stark contrast with the organized efforts undertaken by his
preach—forcefully—against errors and spread news of the chief competitor in Indian affairs, John Eliot. Williams sus-
“written word of God” quite seriously. Still, one might won- pected that Eliot’s system of “civilizing” Indian proselytes in
der whether in deploying the violent imagery of hellfire and English-style “praying towns” before “Christianizing” them
eternal damnation he risked losing the evangelical high ground introduced inappropriate forms of material and physical co-
and lapsing into proselytism himself. Williams’s fellow Puri- ercion more evident of proselytizing zeal than a truly evan-
tans in Massachusetts accused him of as much, and he was gelical care for their souls. Upon his second return to Lon-
sensitive to the charge. He insisted that the words, not swords, don in 1651, Williams carried a petition from the Narragansett
of civil dialogue were the only legitimate means available to to Parliament “that they might not be forced from their
would-be evangelists—and in this, they might profit from Religion.” This plea for toleration was necessitated, he ex-
the Americans’ example. Although Nussbaum and others cite plained, by the “dayly visit[ations]” and “Threatenings” they
Williams’s praise for the Americans as paragons of “Berean received “by Indians that came from Massachusetts, that if
Civilitie” as further evidence of his disinterested appreciation they would not pray they should be destroyed by war” (1988,
for their culture, even this had evangelical significance. For 2:409–10).
Williams, the Americans resembled the “noble” and “gentle” Williams’s implication was clear: toleration was essential
Bereans, who sheltered Saint Paul after he fled persecution in to true conversion in creating the social and political con-
Thessalonica, not only in their hospitality toward an exiled ditions under which evangelism, rather than proselytism,
evangelist but in their willingness to listen critically and par- could proceed. Here, one can see that his distinctive ethical
ticipate actively in evangelical conversation. The Bereans “re- conception of toleration had profound institutional conse-
ceived the Word with all readiness of mind, and searched the quences as well. For a sufficiently evangelical conversation
Scriptures daily, whether those things were so. Therefore many to take place, the informal freedom to worship privately as
of them believed” (Acts 17:10–12 KJV). second-class citizens, as was the case for Jews in England after
Williams insisted that like the Bereans before them, the Readmission, was insufficient. Rather, toleration required that
Americans must be left at liberty to engage with Scripture and believers and nonbelievers alike be fully included in political
judge for themselves, “according to their Indian or American and social life, and hence that the evangelical liberty to preach
consciences, for other consciences it cannot be supposed they and propagate their own doctrine be extended to all. He il-
should have” ([1644] 1963b, 354). A Key reported how, after lustrated this point with the familiar metaphor of the ship of
telling them about the creation of Adam and Eve, they re- state. In a tolerant society, “both Papists and Protestants, Jews
sponded with their own creation story in which the first and Turks, may be embarqued into one Ship.” But as on a
Volume 77 Number 4 October 2015 / 1109

transatlantic crossing, all must be “suffered to breathe and law banning religious insult of the kind adopted in Mary-
walke upon the Deckes, in the ayre of civill liberty and con- land, Carolina, and Pennsylvania.9
versation in the Ship of the commonwealth”—not “choaked Forst (2013) calls the connection between Williams’s “re-
and smothered” below (Williams [1644] 1963b, 204). Although ligious argumentative framework” and the radicalism of his
the passengers might hate each other, they should make the toleration “paradoxical” (183), but this is wrong. This section
most of their suffering: “in the lamentable shipwreck of has shown that its ethical and institutional character and
mankind . . . next to the saving of your own souls . . . your evangelical outlook were intimately and logically connected.10
task as Christians is to save the souls . . . of others” (87). The success of Williams’s “livelie experiment” of radical in-
Although his most famous institutional innovation re- clusion and unconstrained evangelical liberty in Rhode Is-
mains the “wall of separation” realized in the Rhode Island’s land thus presents a direct challenge to Rousseau’s suggestion
unprecedented disestablishment of religion, the radicalism of that religious intolerance leads always to civil persecution. As
Williams’s position—enshrined in the Rhode Island charter as a practice of individuals and of states, his evangelical tolera-
the “free exercise and enjoyment of [citizens’] civil and reli- tion capitalized on the ethical minimalism of tolerantia while
gious rights”—in contrast with restrictions routinely placed turning it inside out. Whereas early evangelical tolerationists
on tolerated minorities like the Jews at Whitehall cannot be had argued that religious outsiders should be tolerated so as
overestimated. But Williams’s further emphasis on evange- one day to be brought inside the fold and embraced fully as
lism as an essential element of free exercise had equally radical fellow members of the body of Christ, Williams’s polemical
implications. Evangelical liberty—as a freedom to witness and approach erased the distinction by turning everyone into out-
admonish others for their spiritual errors—was crucial for the siders and “briars,” Christians and non-Christians alike. In the
free flowing of the Word among the “briars” of the wilder- end, it was this brilliant but counterintuitive strategy that en-
ness. Toleration thus had two distinct requirements: first, the abled him to create a new kind of community in the New En-
“permission of the most Paganish, Jewish, Turkish, or Anti- gland wilderness from altogether unlikely materials.
christian consciences and worships” and second, “that they . . .
be fought against with that Sword which is only (in Soule JOHN LOCKE AND REASONABLE EVANGELISM
matters) able to conquer: to wit, the Sword of God’s Spirit, the Williams’s views on toleration are often lumped together with
Word of God” (Williams [1644] 1963b, 3). Williams’s crucial those of his younger and more famous contemporary, John
innovation here—and where he departs further from earlier Locke (1632–1704). Yet as scholars have been increasingly
evangelical tolerationists—was in seeing evangelism itself not willing to acknowledge—particularly critics of the liberal tol-
only as an inducement to, but an object of toleration. More eration with which he is synonymous—Locke’s toleration,
radical still, he insisted that this evangelical liberty belonged both as a private practice and a public policy, was also evan-
to all Christians and not just ordained and beneficed clergy. gelical in important ways (De Roover and Balagangadhara
Through the idea of equal protection enshrined in the Rhode 2008; Matar 1993; Scherer 2013; Turner 2011).
Island Charter, this evangelical liberty became a universal Locke argued consistently in A Letter Concerning Tolera-
right belonging to non-Christians, too. tion that to embrace toleration was to follow Christ’s exam-
Nevertheless, Williams’s determination to put this unre- ple and acknowledge words, not swords, as the only divinely
stricted evangelical liberty into practice in Rhode Island— sanctioned methods of spreading the Gospel, for “no man can
which became a “receptacle for all sorts of riff-raff ” and reli- be a Christian without Charity” and “that Faith which works,
gious refugees from New England—severely tested the limits not by Force, but by Love.” Thus, in employing inapt methods,
of his toleration. Particularly obnoxious were the Quakers, persecutors were guilty, among other things, of failing to
who among the many enthusiastic Protestant sects had taken “sincerely and heartily apply themselves to make other people
Luther’s reinterpretation of evangelism as a holy war of words Christians” (Locke [1689] 2010, 8). This evangelical instru-
most closely to heart. Williams complained that “their Tongues mentalism became even stronger in the later Letters. While his
are the most cutting and bitter of any that I can hear of inveterate Anglican critic Jonas Proast expressed shock at the
professing the Protestant Reformation, and it is certain, where “largeness of the toleration,” Locke gave an apt summation of
the Tongue is so . . . they will be as bitter and cutting in Hand
also, where God pleaseth to permit a Sword to fall into it”
([1676 ] 1963c, 207). But in a classic example of trying to 9. The 1649 Maryland Toleration Act, the 1682 Great Law of Penn-
sylvania, as well as the 1669 Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina all
combat uncivil speech with more speech, Williams chal- included religious insult provisions.
lenged several leading Quakers to a public debate and pub- 10. Nussbaum goes further, claiming that Williams “nowhere alludes
lished the results. Moreover, Rhode Island never enacted a to [his religious] beliefs in arguing for liberty of conscience” (2008a, 43).
1110 / Evangelical Toleration Teresa M. Bejan

the evangelical toleration tradition since Castellio: “we pray Here, Locke’s evangelical toleration was closer to that of
every day for their conversion [as is] our duty,” but it will Castellio, or even Augustine, in being motivated by a spirit
“hardly be believed that we pray in earnest if we exclude them of genuine inclusiveness in wanting to bring as many outsiders
from the other ordinary and probably means of conversion; in—to the Commonwealth or to the Church of England—as
either by driving them from, or persecuting them when they possible. Locke had little patience for the separatist scruples
are amongst us” (1690, 62). of “fanatics” like Williams. Any Christian who would deny
Although Locke is sometimes accused of smuggling in that name to others was “truly the author and promoter of
Christian assumptions under the auspices of neutrality, he was schism and division . . . and tears in pieces the church of
evidently not a very able smuggler. Still, many scholars have Christ” (1692, 289). Despite his own considerable heterodoxy,
been tempted to dismiss these evangelical arguments as rhe- Locke remained a communicating member of the Church of
torical moves meant to embarrass the orthodox while doing England throughout his life. This was not just a curious ac-
very little work. In focusing exclusively on the rationalist, in- cident of his biography; it reflects a deeper outlook and un-
differentist or skeptical aspect of his thought however, one derstanding of what toleration as a practice of individuals
fails to appreciate the importance of Christian love in sup- coexisting under conditions of deep diversity requires.
plying the moral core of his toleration project, not to men- Accordingly, while Williams and Locke both justified tol-
tion Locke’s personal interest—and participation—in prac- eration evangelically, they understood its horizontal dimen-
tical efforts in this direction.11 Loving one’s neighbor meant sion as a first-person practice in vastly different ways. Al-
one could not simply content oneself by allowing him to go though he described himself as an “evangelical Christian,”
to Hell in his own fashion. “The care of each man’s Salvation Locke had rejected the bombastic, polemical excesses of “pa-
belongs only to himself,” but “affectionate Endeavours to pists” or “fanatics.”12 He complained that many people who
reduce Men from Errors . . . are indeed the greatest Duty of might easily have been brought into the Church “by friendly
a Christian.” Indeed, “anyone may employ as many Exhor- and Christian debates” and the “gentle methods of the Gospel
tations and Arguments as he pleases, toward the promoting made use of in private conversation” had nevertheless been
of another man’s Salvation” ([1689] 2010, 46). kept out by such “ill and unfriendly treatment” and “railing
Locke’s extension of evangelical conversation from a duty from the pulpit” (1690, 86–87). People would be more likely
of Christians to a universal right of “anyone” is in stark con- to listen if complimented rather than insulted. Hence, to reap
trast with the one-sidedness of traditional evangelical tolera- fully the benefits of “charitable admonition” and the “opposite
tion. In this, he sounds a lot like Roger Williams, and yet closer arguings of men of parts,” one must not only listen to others
examination reveals that his approach to “charitable Admo- and refrain from interruption but should reflect a sincere
nition” was quite different. Whereas Williams’s evangelism “indifferency” to one’s own opinions and a willingness to re-
was polemic, Locke’s was irenic and oriented toward peace vise one’s views (1996, 185–86). His lasting latitudinarian in-
and conciliation, not controversy. This difference can be ex- terest in emphasizing points of agreement as “fundamental”
plained in part by the different projects in which they were and deemphasizing disagreements as adiaphora or matters of
engaged. While Williams saw toleration as a means of creating indifference reflected the same reasonable, consensus-oriented,
community out of unlikely and uncooperative materials in and persuasive approach.13
the New World, writing from exile in the Netherlands Locke As with Williams, Locke’s more robust understanding of
saw it as a way to maintain unity in the face of diversity in ethical toleration had institutional consequences as well. Here
the Old. As he declared in a letter to his friend Philipp van we can see that the familiar picture of “Lockean” toleration as
Limborch commenting on his hopes for the Act of Toleration: the separation of church and state and a particular slate of
“Men will always differ on religious questions and rival parties
will continue to quarrel and wage war on each other” until “the
establishment of equal liberty for all provides a bond of mutual 12. By this he meant: “[Those who] declare war on no one on account of
difference of opinions . . . seeking truth alone, desire themselves and others
charity by which all may be brought together into one body”
to be convinced of it only by proofs and reasons; they are gentle to the errors
(1976, 3:689). of others, being not unmindful of their own weakness; forgiving human
frailty and ignorance, and seeking forgiveness in turn” (1976, 6:495).
13. Locke’s late work The Reasonableness of Christianity (1695) was an
11. As Turner (2011) has shown, during his tenure as Secretary to the exercise in latitudinarian theology in which he attempted to show that the
Lord Proprietors of Carolina (1669–76) and later as a member of the fundamentals necessary to salvation were sufficiently minimal so that
Board of Trade (1696–1700), Locke approved and facilitated the kind of anyone who acknowledged Christ deserved the name of “Christian”—the
state-sponsored missionary efforts among the Americans decried by similarity to Hobbes’s own minimalist creed in Leviathan critics gleefully
Williams. pointed out.
Volume 77 Number 4 October 2015 / 1111

individual conscience rights is misleading in key respects. than atheists, as Nussbaum assumes (2008b), his principled
While the Letter preached a theory of the “essential distinc- opposition to civil oaths meant that they, along with the
tion” between civil and spiritual goods, laws, and government, Catholics of dual allegiances so feared by Locke, were tolerable
in practice Locke was amenable to a national church and a as well.14 And although Williams was evidently mistaken in his
state-supported ministry actively engaged in missionizing at suspicions of Quaker intolerance, he was more than comfort-
home and abroad (Turner 2011). In contrast with Williams’s able tolerating other theologically intolerant Protestants like
system of the free and vigorous exercise of universal evan- himself, even making nice with the persecutorial denizens of
gelical liberty leading to often highly uncivil wars of words, Massachusetts when the exigencies of the moment demanded
Locke’s tolerant society would be one wherein members uni- (1988, 2:464–70). For Locke, however, for whom oaths were
versally gave up their “implacable enmities” and “ill use” to- essential, cohabiting on terms of equal liberty required a degree
ward one another and recognized their indifferent differences of social trust impossible beyond a fixed range of permissible
as “several paths that are in the same road” while “diligently difference in behavior and belief.15
endeavor[ing] to allay and temper all that Heat and unrea- Thus, while Locke’s toleration became more liberal over
sonable averseness of Mind . . . [and] fiery Zeal for his own time, it also became more limited. The Letter’s infamous ex-
Sect” ([1689] 2010, 27–28). This hope for concord led Locke clusionsreflectedthisinsistenceonfundamentalagreementand
to view the mutual anathemas characteristic of evangelical a reasonable, refined approach to evangelism as conditions of
competition as violations of mutual charity and social unity. toleration that necessarily excluded some people and positions.
Although in his mature toleration writings, he advocated a By tempering their “unreasonable averseness of mind,” he
system of individual freedoms of (public) worship and asso- hoped that evangelical disagreements might themselves be-
ciation, one searches in vain for the principled commitment to come sources of solidarity through which citizens recognized
evangelical liberty one finds in Williams. the fundamental commitments they shared, as well as the rea-
Still, Locke’s reasonable evangelism will likely sound more sonableness and respectability of their disagreements. Locke’s
appealing to a modern audience than does Williams’s enthu- growing emphasis on the evangelical importance of tolera-
siastic, polemical approach. But here again, his evangelical tion and Christian mission, both in theory and in practice, in
toleration was actually closer to traditional arguments in mak- his later works thus reflected his belief in the importance of
ing the toleration of diversity conditional on the recognition of cultivating as well as expanding this consensus by making
a deeper, underlying unity—in this case an agreement on cer- converts, and so reenforcing these affective bonds.16
tain “fundamental” beliefs, including the existence of a deity,
the principle of toleration, and the golden rule. As a policy EVANGELICAL TOLERATION TODAY
matter, then, Locke’s evangelical toleration also had clear Far from being theological window-dressing, then, or an un-
limits, which brought it closer to the traditional vision as well. fortunate “blind spot” in otherwise attractive theories, evan-
While Williams’s toleration turned neighbors into strangers, gelical hopes and endeavors were deeply imbricated in
Locke’s preserved a strong distinction between those inside Williams’s and Locke’s toleration projects and strongly influ-
and those outside the pale. The relative difference, however, enced the institutional and ethical forms they took.17 Never-
was no longer between fully included insiders (Christians) theless, the few scholars who take note of these arguments
and tolerated outsiders (Jews and Turks), as it had been continue to dismiss them as merely prudential, anachro-
for Castellio and the evangelical defenders of Jewish Read- nistic holdovers from a theocratic age, “transitional” theories
mission. Rather, for Locke, the relevant distinction was be-
tween “reasonable” insiders who received all the rights and
privileges he associated with toleration and “unreasonable” 14. Oaths were a serious business in the seventeenth century; their ne-
outsiders who did not (see Fish 1997). cessity to a stable social order was often adduced—including by Locke—as an
Locke’s transformation of medieval tolerantia from an argument against the toleration of Catholics and atheists, and they were used
to ferret out radical protestant sectarians like the Quakers as well.
outsider into an insider status was thus more exclusionary and
15. Forst (2013) characterizes Locke’s insistence on a shared belief in
yet no less radical than Williams’s had been. In extending the a deity as the sine qua non of social life as “Locke’s Fear” and the main obstacle
pale of this more robust toleration as a system of full inclusion keeping his theory from meeting the bar of “mutual respect” (244).
and affective belonging, Locke also sharpened the edge— 16. In addition to his interest—and occasional participation in—the
leaving Catholics, atheists, and the intolerant, out in the cold. ongoing missionary efforts of his countrymen in the New World, the Fun-
damental Constitutions of Carolina justified its grant of religious liberty on
Williams, by contrast, included all of these groups. Although explicitly evangelical grounds (1997, 178).
in calling for the toleration of “anti-Christians” Williams was 17. For the concept of “blind spots” in the history of toleration, see
deploying a common Protestant epithet for Catholics, rather Laursen (2011).
1112 / Evangelical Toleration Teresa M. Bejan

“typical of [their] time” but of blessedly little contemporary gelical activity than not.18 The liberal connection between re-
significance (Forst 2013, 185; Nussbaum 2008b). Evangelical ligious freedom and free speech—and the priority of these
toleration may have been persuasive in a context where tol- freedoms in America in particular—is thus a curiosity to be
eration was a matter of reconciling doctrinal disputes between explained. The contrasting emphases placed on the protection
European Christians, they suggest, but in our globalized world of evangelical controversy by Williams and Locke suggest that
of multicultural—and secular—liberal democracies, this is no Americans’ peculiar form of “free speech fundamentalism”
longer the case. owes something to the relative density of competing strands
This article has sought to challenge such arguments and of sectarian Protestantism in the American colonies, and to
the reductive, secularizing assumptions on which they rest evangelicals like Williams who were unwilling—or in con-
by recovering evangelical toleration as an important albeit science, unable—to bite their tongues or hold their peace.
forgotten tradition in early modern political thought. Still, one This genealogical observation arguably has contemporary
might wonder whether placing high-profile “proto-liberals” normative significance. The different theories of evangelical
like Locke and Williams at the center of this tradition simply toleration developed by Williams and Locke thus provide
confirms critics’ suspicions of a disqualifying missionary in- examples of religious reasons that can be offered to believing
tolerance at the core of liberal toleration. If these patron saints Christians not simply for tolerating others but for endorsing
of liberalism were evangelical tolerationists, what are we? the specific slate of conscience rights—not only of speech but
Rather than writing off the entire tradition of liberal tol- also exercise and assembly—associated with religious free-
eration as an imperial endeavor on the basis of its evangelical dom in liberal democracies besides.19 An evangelical toler-
origins, the preceding sections demonstrate the importance of ation that affirms liberal institutions must rest on a partic-
being attentive to the varieties of evangelical toleration in play. ular theology of conversion, true, but it is one that can
Here we might see Williams and Locke as representing two perhaps be argued for from within many religious tradi-
competing strands of evangelical tolerationism—one sectarian tions, including proselytizing faiths other than Christianity.20
and polemical, the other ecumenical and irenic—with lasting While these comments are necessarily speculative, ruling out
legacies for liberalism. Something of this legacy can be seen in such questions on the grounds that evangelical arguments are
the tension that continues to characterize liberal political theory invariably “protestant” or “protestantizing” will not do. Such
and practice when it comes to how to address the various forms arguments are not exclusive to Protestant Christianity, nor is
of verbal violence that trouble us today. Whether they come in “Protestantism” a homogeneous monolith. Whether protes-
the form of proposals to prohibit blasphemy and religious in- tants in early modern England espoused evangelical tolera-
sult by law or to establish speech codes, trigger warnings, or safe tion—and what kind—depended on their particular theolo-
spaces on college campuses, attempts to eradicate the wars of gies of mission and conversion. This suggests that toleration,
words characteristic of tolerant societies inspire vastly different in the early modern period or today, never rests on uncon-
reactions among self-proclaimed liberals. Those in favor argue, troversial secular assumptions; it requires theological work as
like Locke, that the members of tolerant societies should be well. The salience of evangelical arguments to a citizenry alto-
committed to reasonable and civil modes of public discourse gether less tolerant and secular than political theorists might
that emphasize points of commonality and downplay divisions hope should not be underestimated.
so as to foster a deeper culture of inclusion and mutual respect. Still, one might grant the genealogical significance of evan-
Others, like Williams, see these forms of uncivil speech as the gelical toleration and its power in explaining certain diver-
inevitable and tolerable by-products of the rowdy, agonistic gences within contemporary liberalism without accepting the
evangelical competition at the heart of liberal democracy in further claim that theorists should approach these early mod-
which the freedom to condemn—and offend—others is sac- ern arguments as alive and possibly attractive for the present.
rosanct. Valuing one’s co-citizens primarily as “briars”—that is, as po-
Genealogically speaking, the kind of evangelical toleration tential converts—as Williams did, seems to show a striking lack
associated with radical sectarians like Roger Williams sheds
light on a strong conceptual and institutional connection be- 18. Consider also the treatment of Jehovah’s Witnesses in Europe or
tween religious freedom and free speech intuitive to many headscarves as “ostentatious” religious signs in France, Turkey, and Quebec.
liberals—especially in America, where it constitutes the first 19. The arguments made by Sala (2013) from a contemporary theo-
“fundamental” of our “First Amendment Faith” (Waldron retical perspective in favor of the liberal commitments of “unreasonable”
evangelistic Christians are supported by empirical work as well (e.g.,
2012, 29). Yet this connection is hardly obvious or universal. Woodberry 2012).
Historically, as in the case of Jewish Readmission, toleration 20. For an attempt to do something along these lines on the basis of
has more often been accompanied by restrictions on evan- the Islamic idea of da’wa, see March (2009).
Volume 77 Number 4 October 2015 / 1113

of respect for their conscientious strivings and moral person- ethic it inspired—is deserving of attention as a potentially
hood, to say the least. And indeed, despite a growing consensus attractive approach to difference and disagreement not only
in favor of including religious arguments in democratic delib- for religious citizens, but for everyone. Unlike Locke, who
eration, even those theorists most open to them balk when it theorized toleration from a safe distance, Williams confronted
comes to evangelism, which they associate with an imperialistic the challenge of constructing and governing a tolerant so-
exclusivism incompatible with mutual respect (Nedelsky 2006, ciety first-hand. In the process, he was forced to acknowledge a
112). The tendency to recast all evangelism as proselytism harsh reality with which many theorists remain uncomfort-
noted above thus undermines its pretensions to persuasiveness able: namely, that familiarity with those from whom we differ
and insinuates that evangelical toleration—even more so than on the “fundamentals,” in politics as in religion, is more likely
the similarly instrumental secular arguments from peace and to breed contempt than its opposite.
public order—falls afoul of the principle of reciprocity essential Williams’s and Locke’s respective “blind spots”—Quakers,
to deliberation, both in not being universally shareable and in on the one hand, and the “unreasonable” on the other—like
relying on an asymmetry in openness to persuasion (Forst their divergent approaches to evangelism, owe much to these
2013, 185; Urbinati 2014).21 different perspectives. It is little wonder, then, that Locke’s is
Yet this distinction between unacceptably “instrumental” so widely shared among political theorists, who approach tol-
evangelism and acceptably “principled” persuasion seems eration in a similarly aspirational and irenic way. But Wil-
clearly overdrawn. Both proceed by reasoning on the basis of liams knew well from experience that a tolerant society can-
core moral commitments or first principles, which are not not pick and choose its materials and remain “tolerant” for
themselves open to negotiation and which one believes to be long. He was under no illusion that constant contact with those
true and hopes, one day, will be universally shared. Here, we believe to be culpably in error on the fundamentals would
would-be evangelists appear to have the edge on consistency bring us to respect them more. Nevertheless, he saw that con-
in actually practicing what they preach. Instead of insu- stant evangelical engagement with the damned could perhaps
lating themselves among the like-minded, they act on their keep us from demonizing them in the way that cloaking one-
commitments by talking to those with whom they funda- self in the righteous certainty of the like-minded certainly will.
mentally disagree on a regular basis and doing the unglamorous While Locke’s irenic ideal of inclusiveness and of embrac-
and unpleasant work of trying to convince them that they are ing the Other as a friend and brother is no doubt attractive, the
wrong. The same cannot usually be said of scholars who alternative to holding those whom we believe to be culpably in
reproach evangelicals for being “unreasonable” and closed- error at arm’s length is more often pushing them overboard.
minded and congratulate themselves on their own willingness If we can appreciate Williams’s alternative vision, as I think
to revise their views while conversing exclusively with those we should, we should also be prepared to take its evangelical
who already agree with them. Then again, if open-mindedness sources seriously, especially insofar as they challenge our as-
were a genuine prerequisite of dialogue, who would bother? sumptions about what it means to be “tolerant” today.
Evangelism—more so than deliberation or persuasion—more
aptly describes much of what the citizens of modern liberal
democracies actually do in the public sphere. When political ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
disagreements begin to look more like proselytizing than pub- Earlier versions of this article were presented at the Centre for
lic reasoning, one wonders whether a truly evangelical com- Ethics at the University of Toronto and the “Toleration of
mitment to competing for converts, rather than preaching Tolerations” workshop hosted by the Columbia University So-
to the converted, might well be a good thing. ciety of Fellows. I am grateful to Bryan Garsten, Andrew Sabl,
Here, Williams’s “paradoxical” and polemical evangelical Andrew Murphy, Stephen Holmes, Ira Katznelson, Jennifer
toleration—and the engaged, inclusive, and contestatory Nedelsky, Simone Chambers, Linford Fisher, Murad Idris,
Rebecca Woods, Claire Sabel, and Alan Johnson as well as the
journal’s anonymous reviewers, for their comments and con-
21. For a compelling rejoinder to the reciprocity argument when it
comes to the role of religious arguments and citizens in democratic de-
structive criticisms at various stages during its development.
liberation in general through an appeal to a “systemic” rather than a
“dyadic” model of persuasion, see Hertzberg (2015, in this issue). Inter-
estingly, this critique of evangelism as a violation of reciprocity is itself REFERENCES
evidence of the salience of early modern evangelical toleration—and its Aquinas, Thomas, and R. W. Dyson. 2002. Aquinas: Political Writings.
critics. Hobbes criticized evangelism as “unwanted counsel” and described Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
all missionary activity in Leviathan as a violation of the golden rule (2012, Bejan, Teresa. 2011. “ ‘The Bond of Civility’: Roger Williams on Toleration
2:456). and Its Limits.” History of European Ideas 37:409–20.
1114 / Evangelical Toleration Teresa M. Bejan

Bejan, Teresa. 2015. “ ‘When the Word of the Lord Runs Freely’: Roger March, Andrew F. 2009. Islam and Liberal Citizenship: The Search for an
Williams and Evangelical Toleration.” In C. Beneke and C. Grenda, eds., Overlapping Consensus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
The Lively Experiment: Religious Toleration in America from Roger Wil- Marshall, John. 2006. John Locke, Toleration and Early Enlightenment
liams to the Present. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 65–84. Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bejczy, István. 1997. “Tolerantia: A Medieval Concept.” Journal of the History Matar, Nabil I. 1993. “John Locke and the Jews.” Journal of Ecclesiastical
of Ideas 58 (3): 365–84. History 44 (1): 45–62.
Brown, Wendy. 2008. Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity Mendus, Susan, ed. 1988. “Introduction.” In Justifying Toleration: Con-
and Empire. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ceptual and Historical Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Carter, Stephen L. 1993. The Culture of Disbelief: How American Law and Press, 1–19.
Politics Trivialize Religious Devotion. New York: Anchor Books. Murphy, Andrew. 1997. “Tolerance, Toleration, and the Liberal Tradition.”
Castellio, Sebastian. (1554) 1965. Concerning Heretics. New York: Octagon Polity 29 (4): 593–623.
Books. Nedelsky, Jennifer. 2006. The Least Examined Branch: The Role of Leg-
“Charter of Rhode Island and Providence Plantations—July 15, 1663.” islatures in the Constitutional State. Ed. R. Bauman and T. Kahana.
http://avalon.law.yale.edu/17th_century/ri04.asp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
De Roover, Jakob, and S. N. Balagangadhara. 2008. “John Locke, Christian Nussbaum, Martha. 2008a. Liberty of Conscience: In Defense of America’s
Liberty, and the Predicament of Liberal Toleration.” Political Theory 36 Tradition of Religious Equality. New York: Basic Books.
(4): 523–49. Nussbaum, Martha. 2008b. “The First Founder.” New Republic, Septem-
Dunn, John. 1969. The Political Thought of John Locke. Cambridge: Cam- ber 10. http://www.newrepublic.com/article/books/the-first-founder.
bridge University Press. Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Fish, Stanley. 1997. “Mission Impossible: Settling the Just Bounds between Robeck, Cecil M. 1996. “Mission and the Issue of Proselytism.” Interna-
Church and State.” Columbia Law Review 97 (8): 2255–333. tional Bulletin of Missionary Research 20 (1): 2–8.
Fisher, Linford. Forthcoming. “Evangelicals and Unevangelicals: The Con- Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. (1762) 1997. Rousseau: “The Social Contract” and Other
tested History of a Word, 1500–1950.” Religion and American Culture. Later Political Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Forst, Rainer. 2013. Toleration in Conflict: Past and Present. Cambridge: Sabl, Andrew. 2008. “ ‘Virtuous to Himself ’: Pluralistic Democracy and the
Cambridge University Press. Toleration of Tolerations.” In M. Williams and J. Waldron, eds., Toler-
Goldie, Mark. 1991. “The Theory of Religious Intolerance in Restoration ation and Its Limits. New York: New York University Press, 220–42.
England.” In O. P. Grell, J. Israel, and N. Tyacke, eds., From Persecution to Sala, Roberta. 2013. “The Place of Unreasonable People beyond Rawls.”
Toleration. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 331–68. European Journal of Political Theory 12 (3): 253–70.
Goldie, Mark, and Richard Popkin. 2006. “Scepticism, Priestcraft, and Tol- Scherer, Matthew. 2013. Beyond Church and State: Democracy, Secularism,
eration.” In M. Goldie and R. Wokler, eds., The Cambridge History of and Conversion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Eighteenth-Century Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Szabari, Antonia. 2006. “The Scandal of Religion: Luther and Public Speech in
Press, 79–109. the Reformation.” In H. de Vries and L. Sullivan, eds., Political Theologies.
Hertzberg, Benjamin. 2015. “Chains of Persuasion in the Deliberative System: New York: Fordham University Press, 122–36.
Addressing the Pragmatics of Religious Inclusion.” Journal of Politics 77 Turner, Jack. 2011. “John Locke, Christian Mission, and Colonial America.”
(4): (forthcoming). Modern Intellectual History 8 (2): 267–97.
Hobbes, Thomas. 2012. Leviathan. Ed. N. Malcolm. Oxford: Clarendon. Urbinati, Nadia. 2014. “Half-Toleration: Concordia and the Limits of
Kaplan, Benjamin J. 2007. Divided by Faith: Religious Conflict and the Dialogue.” In A. Stepan and C. Taylor, eds., Boundaries of Toleration.
Practice of Toleration in Early Modern Europe. Cambridge: Belknap. New York: Columbia University Press, 130–67.
Katznelson, Ira. 2010. “Regarding Toleration and Liberalism: Considerations Waldron, Jeremy. 2012. The Harm in Hate Speech. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
from the Anglo-Jewish Experience.” In Ira Katznelson and Gareth University Press.
Stedman Jones, eds., Religion and the Political Imagination. Cambridge: Walsham, Alexandra. 2006. Charitable Hatred: Tolerance and Intolerance
Cambridge University Press, 46–68. in England, 1500–1700. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Laursen, John Christian. 2011. “Blind Spots in the Toleration Literature.” Walzer, Michael. 1997. On Toleration. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14 (3): Press.
307–22. Williams, Melissa, and Jeremy Waldron, eds. 2008. Toleration and Its Limits.
Locke, John. (1689) 2010. A Letter Concerning Toleration and Other New York: New York University Press.
Writings. Ed. M. Goldie. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. Williams, Roger. (1643) 1963a. “A Key into the Language of America.” In
Locke, John. 1690. “A Second Letter Concerning Toleration.” In The The Complete Writings of Roger Williams, vol. 1. New York: Russell &
Works of John Locke, vol. 5. London: Rivington. Russell.
Locke, John. 1692. “A Third Letter for Toleration.” In The Works of John Williams, Roger. (1644) 1963b. “The Bloudy Tenent of Persecution.” In The
Locke, vol. 5. London: Rivington. Complete Writings of Roger Williams, vol. 3. New York: Russell & Russell.
Locke, John. 1695. “The Reasonableness of Christianity.” In The Works of Williams, Roger. (1676) 1963c. “George Fox Digg’d Out of His Burrowes.”
John Locke, vol. 6. London: Rivington. In The Complete Writings of Roger Williams, vol. 5. New York: Russell
Locke, John. 1976. The Correspondence of John Locke. Ed. E. S. de Beer. & Russell.
Oxford: Clarendon Press. Williams, Roger. 1988. The Correspondence of Roger Williams, vol. 2. Ed.
Locke, John. 1996. Some Thoughts Concerning Education: And, Of the G. LaFantasie. Providence, RI: Brown University Press.
Conduct of the Understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett. Woodberry, Robert D. 2012. “The Missionary Roots of Liberal Democ-
Locke, John. 1997. Locke: Political Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- racy.” American Political Science Review 106 (2): 244–74.
versity Press. Zuolo, Federico. 2013. “Frontiers of Toleration and Respect: Non-Moral
Mahmood, Saba. 2009. “Religious Reason and Secular Affect: An In- Approaches and Groups’ Relations.” European Journal of Political
commensurable Divide?” Critical Inquiry 35 (4): 836–62. Theory 12 (3): 219–22.
Copyright of Journal of Politics is the property of University of Chicago Press and its content
may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright
holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for
individual use.

You might also like