Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

Journal of Business Ethics

https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-018-3906-2

ORIGINAL PAPER

An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor


Bruce Barry1 · Mara Olekalns2 · Laura Rees3

Received: 29 November 2016 / Accepted: 2 May 2018


© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Abstract
Our understanding of emotional labor, while conceptually and empirically substantial, is normatively impoverished: very little
has been said or written expressly about its ethical dimensions or ramifications. Emotional labor refers to efforts undertaken
by employees to make their private feelings and/or public emotion displays consistent with job and organizational require-
ments. We formally define emotional labor, briefly summarize research in organizational behavior and social psychology on
the causes and consequences of emotional labor, and present a normative analysis of its moral limits focused on conditional
rights and duties of employers and employees. Our focus is on three points of conflict involving rights and duties as they
apply to the performance of emotional labor: when employees’ and organizations’ rights conflict, when employees’ rights
conflict with their duties, and when organizations’ rights conflict with their duties. We discuss implications for future inquiry
as well as managerial practice.

Keywords Authenticity · Autonomy · Deception · Deontology · Duties · Emotional labor · Emotion management · Rights

Introduction p. 123), Hochschild’s book catalyzed wide scholarly recog-


nition that the emotional life of workers has rising signifi-
Emotional aspects of work life have drawn research attention cance in economies relying increasingly on service-oriented
in management, organizational behavior, industrial/organi- jobs and occupations. In this article we consider the ethical
zational psychology, and the sociology of work for decades. dimensions and moral limits of emotional labor as it relates
A seminal early contribution was Hochschild’s (1983) path- to the relationship between employees and organizations.
breaking ethnography of flight attendants, which shed light In the decades since Hochschild coined the term, con-
both empirically and theoretically on how people at work ceptual and empirical research on emotional labor has flour-
engage in “emotional labor”—the regulation of feelings ished, mainly in the organizational behavior, applied social
and emotion displays in order to comport with employer psychology, and human resource management literatures
expectations, rules, and job requirements. Considered with (for recent reviews see Grandey et al. 2013a; Grandey and
justification to be “the starting point for modern research Gabriel 2015; Wharton 2009). Numerous studies have shed
on emotion in organizations” (Fisher and Ashkanasy 2000, light on variations in forms of emotional labor (e.g., Gabriel
et al. 2015), on individual and contextual antecedents (e.g.,
Diefendorff et al. 2005), on physical (e.g., Chau et al. 2009;
Laura Rees Schaubroeck and Jones 2000), psychological (e.g., Scott and
ReesLa@umkc.edu
Barnes 2011), behavioral (Grant 2013), and organizational
Bruce Barry (e.g., Wang and Groth 2014) consequences, and on modera-
bruce.barry@vanderbilt.edu
tors that amplify (e.g., Biron and van Veldhoven 2012) or
Mara Olekalns suppress (e.g., Grandey et al. 2012) their effects on personal
M.Olekalns@mbs.edu
and organizational outcomes. Sociological work on emo-
1
Owen Graduate School of Management, Vanderbilt tional labor has yielded further insight into the structure of
University, Nashville, TN, USA organizations within which jobs reliant on emotional labor
2
Melbourne Business School, Melbourne, Australia are embedded (Wharton 2009). Emotional labor has been
3
Bloch School of Management, University of Missouri
explored within a number of specific occupational contexts,
- Kansas City, 5110 Cherry Street, Kansas City, MO 64110, including nursing (e.g., Lopez 2006), tourism (e.g.., Guerrier
USA

13
Vol.:(0123456789)
B. Barry et al.

and Adib 2003), sales (e.g., Humphrey and Ashforth 2000), normative analysis. Grandey et al. (2015, p. 770) answered
law (e.g., Lively 2002), media (Hesmondhalgh and Baker that call in part in an essay on what they labeled “the dark
2008), public administration (e.g., Guy et al. 2008), border side of emotional labor.” Although not explicitly refer-
enforcement (Rivera 2015), art (Davidson and Poor 2015), encing frameworks of moral philosophy, Grandey et al.
and even prostitution (e.g., Kong 2006). As a result of this mount a normative case for the proposition that “formal
copious and growing body of work, we know quite a bit emotional display requirements represent an unethical
about who engages in emotional labor, when and why they business practice” (p. 773). They make their case partly
do so, and how it affects them and their organizations. on consequentialist grounds, arguing that the benefits of
However, our understanding of emotional labor, while emotional labor do not outweigh the costs, and partly on
conceptually and empirically substantial, is norma- deontological grounds, arguing that emotional labor vio-
tively impoverished: very little has been said or written lates fair pay practices and compromises dignity.
expressly about its ethical dimensions or ramifications for We answer the call for normative inquiry in a differ-
the employee–employer relationship. Yet anecdotes from ent way, offering a grounded deontological analysis and
the world of practice reveal that ethics are certainly impli- assessment of the moral terms and limits of emotional
cated in how firms manage emotional labor. To cite a recent labor. We will advance normative claims about the rights
example, unfair-labor-practice charges brought against a and duties of both employees and employers that define its
well-known U.S. grocery chain included the allegation that moral boundaries, and develop a series of arguments about
a longtime employee “was repeatedly reprimanded because the ethical conflicts involving employees and employers
managers judged his smile and demeanor to be insufficiently that arise in employment involving significant amounts
‘genuine’” (Schreiber 2016). of emotional labor. Specifically, we will first argue for the
A small number of papers have considered the intersec- importance of the rights to cultivate autonomy and pursue
tion of ethics and emotional labor. Smith and Lorentzon well-being and the duties of fidelity and non-maleficence
(2005), writing on nursing ethics, called into question the for both employees and organizations in the context of
appropriateness of caregivers’ enactments of inauthentic emotional labor. Then, working under the premise that
emotions for patients’ benefit. Analyzing the example of these rights and duties are conditional, we will draw on
Muslim women in Islamic societies, Syed (2008) discussed social contract theory to propose principled arguments for
how workers in emotional roles may find themselves acting establishing relative precedence between rights and duties
in conflict with their religious identities and thus with their when conflicts between them arise. These arguments thus
personal moral values. In the organizational behavior litera- provide a normative basis for discerning appropriate indi-
ture, some analyses of emotional labor contemplate potential vidual and organizational actions with respect to emotional
ethical issues indirectly by attending to the role of various labor. In addition to meeting a need for concerted atten-
attributes of individuals and their emotional behavior that tion to the intersection of ethics and emotional labor, we
may bear implications for their broader moral character; also view this effort as a response to Greenwood’s (2013)
notable examples include questions of autonomy (Grandey call for more scholarly analyses of human resource man-
and Diamond 2010), authenticity (Gardner et al. 2009), agement issues and practices through explicit ethical
deception (Provis 2001), and emotional intelligence (Kilduff perspectives.
et al. 2010) when individuals engage in emotion displays. The paper from here is organized as follows. First, we
A more direct connection between ethics and emotional define emotional labor more formally and present a brief
labor was drawn in an essay by Humphrey (2012, p. 743), synthesis of what extensive research in organizational behav-
who surmised that leaders engaging in emotional labor to ior and social psychology has revealed about its implica-
express emotions not actually felt “may not be demonstrat- tions for individuals and organizations. Second, we develop
ing an ethical character” (a sentiment previously explored our approach to a normative analysis of the moral limits
by Provis 2001). of emotional labor, focusing in particular on conditional
An explicit call for normative inquiry into emotional rights and duties of employees and organizations in relation
labor came from Fulmer and Barry (2009), who noted a to one another. Third, we discuss the moral limits of emo-
dearth of scholarship on the moral duties of employers to tional labor in terms of conflicts between these conditional
workers who engage in emotional labor on the employers’ rights and duties at three points of contact: (a) conflicts
behalf, and on the ethics of employers using employees between employee rights and organization rights; (b) con-
as instruments for exercising influence over customers flicts between employee rights and employee duties; and (c)
in order to fulfill the organization’s objectives. Fulmer conflicts between organizational rights and organizational
and Barry argued that the contours of emotional labor in duties. A fourth and concluding section of the paper con-
particular could be assessed using either consequential- siders some future directions for inquiry and offers a few
ist or deontological lenses, and called for more thorough implications for managerial practice.

13
An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor

Background on Emotional Labor job, above and beyond emotion regulation alone. Emo-
tion regulation, a more basic concept that relates broadly
Defining Terms to social interactions across domains, captures many of
the day-to-day experiences in which individuals generate
Originally defined as “the management of feeling to create socially appropriate emotions and suppress socially unac-
a publicly observable facial and bodily display” (Hochs- ceptable emotions. For example, we use emotion regula-
child 1983, p. 7), emotional labor in early work referred tion when we politely greet co-workers whom we dislike,
to the efforts undertaken by employees to make their pri- when we suppress tears until we are in a private space, or
vate feelings and/or public emotional displays consistent when we remain neutral in the face of attitudes that we
with job and organizational requirements. By emotions we find objectionable.
mean discrete affective events that are typically directed In the decades and hundreds of papers on the subject
at a specific target and are shorter in duration and more that have ensued, our understanding of emotional labor
intense than moods, which are more diffuse affective states has broadened to include a wider set of phenomena than
of lower intensity and without a specific target (Frijda simply the discrete emotional expression of an individual
1994). According to Hochschild’s original formulation, service worker chasing gratuities or sales commissions. For
which arose from a qualitative study of flight attendants instance, as Kilduff et al. (2010, p. 132) observe, emotional
and bill collectors, emotional labor refers specifically to labor can be viewed not just as emotion work explicitly
such efforts undertaken in exchange for wages or other required by the job itself, but also more broadly as encom-
forms of compensation, for example the increased tips that passing conscious efforts by employees to “manage emo-
a restaurant server might earn by smiling and joking with tions in the service of the self” at work. This could be some-
customers. Hochschild uses the terms emotion work and thing as simple as a casual smile or compliment designed to
emotion management to describe similar efforts under- smooth an interaction or maintain workplace cordiality, or
taken for private or personal reasons rather than specifi- something more complex in the domain of conflict manage-
cally for wage compensation. We extend this definition of ment, such as a boss assuming a particular emotional tone
emotional labor to include emotional efforts performed to in order to mediate a disagreement between subordinates,
fulfill perceived or explicit individual work-related moti- or a teacher calibrating emotion to regain control over an
vations or expectations that serve organizational goals. agitated or rambunctious classroom. It can be said, then,
Accordingly, we include in the ambit of emotional labor that emotional labor.
actions motivated by wage incentives (e.g., gratuities or covers a broad swath of emotional actions on the part of
sales commissions) along with efforts that further mon- employees as long as that action is performed in service of
etary and non-monetary individual or organizational goals the job.
(e.g., performance evaluations, customer retention, and To summarize, and following Grandey and colleagues
myriad others). The performance of emotional labor by (Grandey et al. 2013b; Grandey and Gabriel 2015), we treat
an individual is widely understood to take two main forms: emotional labor as an umbrella construct comprised of three
surface acting, in which the individual displays emotions interrelated facets: (a) emotional requirements of the job
he or she is not actually experiencing and is not attempting and/or organization, (b) voluntary intrapsychic efforts to
to feel, while suppressing the display of felt emotions; and manage one’s own emotions at work (basic emotion regula-
deep acting, in which the individual deliberately strives tion), and (c) the performance or behavioral display of emo-
to summon the target emotion and then allows that felt tion (which may or may not be effortful).
emotion to guide outward expression (Hochschild 1983;
Humphrey 2012). A Brief Review of Emotional Labor Research
An important, and related, distinction is between emo-
tion regulation (Gross 1998) and emotional labor. Like Cognizant that this topic and research field may be rela-
emotional labor, emotion regulation refers to the con- tively unfamiliar to many readers of this journal, we speak
trol and expression of emotions. Emotional labor goes briefly to key findings about the impact that emotional
beyond the simple modification of feelings or expressions labor has on employee and organizational well-being.
to highlight the role of emotion performance—the dis- It is not our goal to provide a comprehensive literature
play of expressions—that is in the service of job-based review in this section. Rather, it is our intention to dem-
emotion requirements (Grandey and Gabriel 2015). Thus onstrate that engaging in emotional labor can harm both
emotional labor is both a broader umbrella term and one individuals and organizations. We note, however, that the
more specific to the workplace; emotional labor necessar- extensive literature on emotional labor encompasses both
ily involves the performance of emotions required by one’s a wide variety of occupations and a range of method-
ologies. Following Hochschild’s initial studies of flight

13
B. Barry et al.

Table 1 Methodologies in emotional labor research


Design Method Examples

Cross-sectional design Survey Bhave and Glomb (2009), Brotheridge and Grandey (2002), Dieffendorf and
Richard (2003), Grandey (2003), Judge et al. (2009), Näring et al. (2006),
Pugh et al. (2011), Schaubroeck and Jones (2000), Yanchus et al. (2010),
Zapf et al. (2001)
Longitudinal design Survey, diary study, experience sampling Beal et al. (2006), Bechtoldt et al. (2011), Nguyen et al. (2016), Scott and
Barnes (2011), Scott et al. (2012)
Time-lagged design Diary study, experience sampling, survey Biron and van Veldhoven (2012), Chau et al. (2009), Goodwin et al. (2011),
Trougakos et al. (2008)
Other Interview, observational, experimental Cohen (2010), Hennig-Thurau et al. (2006), Lively (2002), Lopez (2006)

Table 2 Comparative effect Emotional exhaustion Depersonalization Personal accom-


sizes (ρ) for predictors of plishment
burnout and organizational
outcomes Alarcon (2011)
 Role conflict 0.32 0.31 − 0.31
 Role ambiguity 0.53 0.40 − 0.18
Hühlsheger and Shewe (2011)
 Surface acting 0.34 0.48 − 0.95
 Deep acting 0.09 0.05 0.27
Job satisfaction Organizational attachment Task performance

Surface acting − 0.23 − 0.31 − 0.15


Deep acting 0.54 0.09 − 0.01

attendants and bill collectors, researchers have investi- Consequences of Emotional Labor
gated the consequences of emotional labor in occupations
as diverse as call center workers, bus drivers, cheerleading Both employees and organizations experience significant
coaches, nurses, hospitality workers, sex workers, casino negative consequences when employees engage in surface
employees, and paralegals, among others. In addition to acting. The most consistently demonstrated effect of sur-
field studies using cross-sectional surveys, time-lagged face acting is on employees’ levels of burnout, a form of
surveys and event sampling methodologies, researchers work stress characterized by emotional exhaustion, deper-
have tested the impact of emotional labor in laboratory sonalization, and perceived lack of personal accomplish-
settings. As summarized in Table 1, our selective review ment (Maslach and Jackson 1986). Specifically, research
draws on research across these methodologies. With the shows that when employees suppress displays of nega-
exception of cross-sectional surveys, these methodolo- tive emotions, emotional exhaustion and depersonaliza-
gies allow researchers to demonstrate causal relationships tion increase, and feelings of personal accomplishment
between emotional labor and its consequences, which we decrease (Biron and van Veldhoven 2012; Goodwin et al.
summarize below. 2011; Judge et al. 2009; Pugh et al. 2011). Further, two
We note in particular that emotional labor makes a meta-analyses establish that surface acting is associated
unique contribution to at least one outcome, the experience with higher emotional exhaustion and depersonalization
of work stress (burnout; e.g. Brotheridge and Grandey than deep acting (Hülsheger and Schewe 2011; Kammeyer-
2002; Näring et al. 2006; Zapf et al. 2001), with com- Mueller et al. 2013). Surface acting also harms organiza-
parable effect sizes to the impact of other predictors of tions. For example, high levels of surface acting increase
work stress. Specifically, in terms of effect sizes, we pro- absenteeism, particularly for individuals who are not con-
vide a comparison of the average corrected correlations fident in their surface acting ability (Nguyen et al. 2016).
for emotional labor and other predictors of burnout and Surface acting also increases work withdrawal, especially
other organizational outcomes based on two meta-analyses when surface acting demands are not consistent over
(Alarcon 2011; Hülsheger and Schewe 2011) in Table 2. a work day (Scott and Barnes 2011; Scott et al. 2012).

13
An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor

Finally, surface acting decreases employees’ levels of work 2012; Brotheridge and Grandey 2002; Goodwin et al. 2011;
engagement (Bechtoldt et al. 2011; Chau et al. 2009; Good- Pugh et al. 2011).
win et al. 2011). Overall, surface acting results in nega- Organizational and job characteristics also moderate
tive physical and mental health outcomes for individuals the effects of emotional labor on laborers. For example, an
(Maslach et al. 2001), and—by reducing job satisfaction organizational culture that enables employees to talk openly
and organizational commitment (Hülsheger and Schewe about the demands of emotional labor or that supports the
2011; Kammeyer-Mueller et al. 2013; see Table 2)—also expression of authentic emotions can mitigate the negative
leads to negative organizational outcomes. consequences of surface acting on employees, as can work
In contrast, employees and organizations benefit from schedules that allow regular breaks for recuperation (Dief-
deep acting. For employees, engaging in deep acting fendorf and Richard 2003; Grandey et al. 2012; Lively 2002;
increases the sense of personal accomplishment (Hülsheger Lopez 2006; Trougakos et al. 2008).
and Schewe 2011; Kammeyer-Mueller et al. 2013). Organi- There is some evidence that compensation decreases as
zations benefit from increased work engagement, increased the emotional labor associated with a job increases (Bhave
job satisfaction and job performance, and lower turnover and Glomb 2009; Glomb et al. 2004). On the other hand,
intentions and actual turnover when employees engage in employees who benefit financially from emotional labor are
deep acting (Bechtoldt et al. 2011; Chau et al. 2009; Good- more willing to express positive emotions (e.g., black jack
win et al. 2011; Hülsheger and Schewe 2011; Kammeyer- dealers; Sallaz 2002) and to engage in deep acting (e.g.,
Mueller et al. 2013; Scott and Barnes 2011). self-employed hairdressers; Cohen 2010). Thus, similar
In general, the harm associated with surface acting and to rewarding employees for completing other types of job
the benefits of deep acting suggest that organizations should demands, linking compensation positively to emotional
require deep acting and that employees should engage in labor performance may be one way to encourage emotional
deep acting. However, as we will discuss below in when we labor that benefits the organization.
take up conflicts between rights and duties, organizations
may require or employees may choose to engage in sur- Summary
face acting for a variety of reasons. Moreover, despite role
requirements to engage in emotional labor, employees may On balance, although all types of labor, including emo-
find ways to achieve organizational goals such as customer tional labor, involve both costs and benefits, research sug-
satisfaction through means other than emotional labor. Con- gests that surface acting is more harmful than deep acting
sequently, our ethical analysis considers the moral dilemmas to both employees and their organizations. These costs
associated with requiring or performing both deep and sur- cannot be ignored in an ethical examination of emotional
face acting, as well as opting not to perform emotional labor. labor. Grandey (2015, p. 56), in her overview of emotional
labor research, suggests that “…management cannot simply
Moderating Factors demand ‘service with a smile’ as the effort to put on the
smile may, ironically, have costs to the person and their per-
The negative consequences of surface acting can be miti- formance.” On the other hand, although deep acting may not
gated by certain individual characteristics. Surface acting always deliver direct benefits to employees, it does deliver
is less likely to result in emotional exhaustion for extraverts, benefits to employers and customers, and it appears be less
who report less negative affect than introverts when they harmful than surface acting for employees. The identification
engage in surface acting, and more positive affect than intro- of moderators also suggests specific strategies—recruitment
verts when they engage in deep acting (Judge et al. 2009). and selection, training, compensation, work structure, and
Individuals’ ability to monitor and adapt to the socio-emo- rethinking organizational culture—that can be implemented
tional context can also help buffer them against the nega- to reduce the relatively higher negative impact of surface
tive consequences of emotional labor: individuals who are versus deep acting (e.g., Grandey 2015). With these findings
readily able to adapt to the social context or who have high in mind, we turn next to a discussion of the rights and duties
emotional intelligence report fewer negative effects of sur- of employees and employers that underlie the performance
face acting compared to less adaptable or emotionally intel- of and regulation of emotional labor, and, subsequently, to
ligent individuals (Beal et al. 2006; Bechtoldt et al. 2011; our analysis of how the ethical dilemma of emotional labor
Schaubroeck and Jones 2000; Scott et al. 2012; Yanchus may be located in conflicts between these rights and duties.
et al. 2010). Finally, the negative effects of surface acting (Although much as been written about ways that the terms
can be mitigated if employees are confident in their ability duty and obligation overlap yet can be distinguished [e.g.,
to surface act, but are heightened if employees value the Brandt 1964], for simplicity here we follow Zimmerman
authentic expression of emotion (Biron and van Veldhoven [2013] and use the term duty.)

13
B. Barry et al.

Rights and Obligations in Relation In moral philosophy values form a “normative basis for
to Emotional Labor action” (Audi 1997, p. 136) through delineation of goals
or objectives toward which action is directed (Ellis 2008).
The substantial body of extant empirical research on emo- In social psychology their function is similar: values per-
tional labor—represented only in small part by the fore- tain to desired end states that cross situations and guide
going synopsis of findings regarding its impact—demon- behavioral choices (Schwartz and Bilsky 1987). In this
strates that the influence of emotional labor on the health sense, living autonomously and experiencing well-being
and success of individuals and organizations is complex are prudential values that pertain to making “life good
and variable, subject to a stew of contingencies related simply for the person living it” (Griffin 1996, p. 19). How-
to the type of emotional work involved, workplace and ever, for simplicity, we refer to autonomy and well-being
job-related arrangements, and attributes of both those who as “rights” in this and the following sections.
perform and those who are on the receiving end of emo-
tional labor. With this complexity in mind, we explore the Autonomy
moral implications of emotional labor, and the circum-
stances under which its regulation (by firms) or its perfor- In contemporary ethics, autonomy encompasses the capac-
mance (by employees) may cross ethical lines, through an ity “to make reasoned choices about how to live one’s life”
analysis of particular rights inhering in workers and firms (McCall 2001, p. 203) without undue interference from
connected through an employment relationship, as well others (Hill 2015, p. 24). Joanne Ciulla puts autonomy at
as fundamental moral duties they owe to one another. In the center of an understanding of the nature of work that is
this section we identify rights and duties that come into meaningful:
play (and perhaps into conflict) when emotional labor is Employees throughout the ages have struggled to
performed and regulated. We focus our attention on two maintain their autonomy and dignity at work. The prin-
particular rights and two particular duties, outlining for ciple of freedom is at the heart of this relationship and
each its relevance to workplace contexts featuring emo- fundamental to how we think about work—freedom to
tional labor. We regard these rights and duties as condi- work, freedom at work, and I will add freedom from
tional or pro tanto rather than absolute (Frederick 2014); work (Ciulla 2012, p. 118, emphasis in original).
we will have more to say about this below. Then in the next
major section of the paper we discuss prospective conflicts In Kantian terms, autonomy means the ability to act in
among these rights and duties; that is, situations in which concert with one’s ends and principles as a rational agent
rights and duties are incongruous or misaligned and thus (Kant [4:440] 1785/1997, p. 47), but also to act freely in a
lead to ambiguity in terms of the best course of action for negative sense, that is, “independently of alien causes deter-
employees, organizations, or both. mining it” ([4:445], p. 52). It is important to state here that
we do not limit our analysis to a strictly Kantian treatment
of positive autonomy in that we do not limit its application
Rights to the manifestation of universal law (“the property of the
will by which it is a law to itself”; Kant [4:440] 1785/1997,
By rights we do not mean legal or contractual rights, but p. 47). With respect to the negative sense of autonomy, so-
rather moral rights in the sense discussed by Green (Har- called alien causes might include not just the dictates or
ris and Morrow 1986) and Ross (1930/1988)—rights that preferences of external forces or authorities (Timmermann
arise from and through the presence of moral agents as a 2007), but also the individual’s own heteronomous desires.
way to shape their own preferences and define the duties In addition to providing decisional control over one’s
they have to one another. In the analysis to come we have actions, the pursuit of autonomy can also be thought of as
in mind rights carried into an employment arrangement affording individuals decisional privacy regarding their own
yet that have the quality of being limited by duties that fortunes and futures (Wilson 2007).
the employment relationship imposes. The two specific A right to cultivate autonomy comes into play both for
rights that we focus on are the right to cultivate auton- the individual who performs emotional labor (e.g., in the
omy and the right to pursue well-being. It is important form of discretion about how to comport oneself at work)
to say here that autonomy and well-being are not them- and for the employing organization (e.g., in the form of dis-
selves rights: autonomy and well-being are not states that cretion about how to arrange the conditions of work). For
individuals can claim a right to experience. They exist, an individual, this means retaining substantial discretion to
rather, in the domain of values—conditions that a per- choose whether to regulate and/or display certain emotions
son regards as intrinsically desirable (Harsanyi 1997). in any given interaction. This discretion is underpinned by
the right to make an informed choice about whether or not to

13
An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor

regulate emotions based on knowledge and rational analysis with being a moral agent and acting virtuously “is a con-
of likely costs and benefits, independently of alien causes. dition for happiness and so links happiness and morality”
For instance, as we know from empirical research, regulating (Wike 1994, p. 16). Pursuing one’s individual conception of
felt and/or displayed emotions depletes employee resources happiness or fulfillment is what we mean by well-being here.
(i.e., mental energy) and can lead to burnout and a sense of We grant, though, that it can be challenging to disentangle
depersonalization (e.g., Brotheridge and Lee 2002). Feel- well-being from autonomy given that well-being as we dis-
ing these effects from past emotional labor efforts may, in cuss it here (i.e., from an individual’s own point of view)
turn, diminish the employee’s ability to make an autonomous also implies a present or future freely chosen.
and informed choice to engage in emotion regulation and For an employee, a right to well-being stands in relation
display going forward (e.g., if burnout leads to increased to the firm’s ability to inhibit it through the choices it makes
temporal discounting bias, Critchfield and Kollins 2001, about the nature of work. Bowie argues that work should
or other detrimental heteronomous desires), particularly if afford employees “the ability to pursue happiness in accord-
emotional labor is explicitly required by the organization and ance with their own desires” (1998, p. 1087). One manifesta-
the employee encounters external pressure to engage in it. tion of the right to well-being in relation to emotional labor
This example is meant merely to illustrate the influence of is the individual’s right to a safe (harm-free) workplace that,
external and heteronomous alien causes; we will have much for instance, minimizes psychological harms such as the
more to say below about factors of work involving emotional burnout associated with surface acting (e.g., Biron and van
labor that are in tension with and constrain (arguably, via Veldhoven 2012; Brotheridge and Grandey 2002; Goodwin
due interference) the right to autonomy. et al. 2011; Judge et al. 2009; Pugh et al. 2011). Harm-avoid-
For the employer, a right to enhance or maintain auton- ance aside, the right to well-being also implies prerogatives
omy implies that the organization is deserving of substantial to gain benefit, for example by performing emotion displays
(though not unlimited, owing to legal and regulatory impera- with customers in such a way as to further one’s own psy-
tives) deference to preferences for particular practices and chological (e.g., job satisfaction) or economic (e.g., pecuni-
policies of employment—including emotion regulation and ary rewards) outcomes. For example, an individual may wish
displays as a condition of work. Organizations thus have the to maximize remunerative commissions in customer interac-
prerogative to structure work in a way that elicits desired tion through surface acting, as even perfunctory emotional
outcomes (e.g., generating profits) by providing levels of displays can have positive effects on customers (as long as
service desired by customers, or that directs employee labor they are not detected and interpreted as such; see Groth et al.
(including emotional labor) to pursue whatever other stake- 2009) and are less effortful than deep acting. On the other
holder interests or objectives those who govern the organiza- hand, employees may also elicit appreciation from customers
tion may freely wish to prioritize. In making choices about through deep acting (Zhan et al. 2016), which may, in turn,
display rules specifically or the need for emotional labor reciprocally increase employees’ own felt positive emotions
generally, that autonomy right confers on employers some even further. Thus, an interesting tradeoff emerges for the
latitude to encourage (and perhaps even require, as due inter- employee with respect to surface acting: the risk of harm
ference) deep versus surface acting on the part of employees weighed against the potential payoff. The right to well-being
in roles where emotional labor serves organizational goals. grants the employee the discretion to make that choice.
On the employer side of the ledger, a firm is entitled to
Well-being pursue and preserve forms of what can be considered institu-
tional well-being (the ends) that are instantiated by the par-
Raz (1986) provides a cogent and succinct definition of well- ticular goals that define its mission and strategy. This might
being as a prudential value: well-being is the presence of involve, for instance, the goal of generating growth or profit
happiness or good or success in one’s own life from one’s or other outcomes (e.g., customer and stakeholder loyalty)
own point of view, possibly achieved through the deliber- that facilitate the organization’s long-term success via the
ate fulfillment of chosen goals, but also perhaps realized good-faith efforts of its employees—including employees’
through serendipitous pursuits. Relatedly, the source of a efforts to engage in task- and role-appropriate emotion regu-
right to pursue one’s own well-being in Kantian thought lation and displays. That is, organizations have the latitude
is found in the treatment of happiness—an amalgam of to identify and pursue economic and social objectives in part
well-being, health, wealth, and satisfaction (Kant [4:393] on the basis of good-faith efforts by employees to fulfill job
1785/1997, p. 7)—as an end endemic to rational beings, a roles which may include required performance of certain
desire for which “that they not merely could have but that emotion regulation strategies and displays to fulfill those
we can safely presuppose they all actually do have” (Kant objectives. Further, to the extent that organizational goals
[4:415] 1785/1997, p. 26). While happiness cannot itself be are better served by deep rather than surface acting, a well-
regarded as a moral imperative, the satisfaction that comes being right entitles the firm not only to exercise discretion

13
B. Barry et al.

in how much emotional labor is expected, but also to harbor consent give rise to norms “that become prima facie obliga-
(and perhaps enforce) expectations about the form that this tory” (Dunfee and Donaldson 1995, p. 178).
labor takes. With respect to emotional labor, on the employee side
of the equation, whereas the formal contract specifies role-
Duties related tasks such as delivering a service, the informal con-
tract is more likely the source of expectations about extra-
We frame our discussion of duties in terms of W.D. Ross’s role behaviors such as “service with a smile” and other forms
well-known formulation of prima facie duties—he also calls of emotional performance. Fidelity implies that employees
them “conditional duties”—acts that “in virtue of being of have a duty to perform both in- and extra-role behaviors to
a certain kind...would be a duty proper if it were not at the the best of their ability; a duty that employees themselves
same time of another kind which is morally significant” also acknowledge (Robinson et al. 1994). And to the extent
(Ross 1930/1988, p. 19). A prima facie duty, accordingly, is that deep rather than surface acting may better serve legiti-
provisional rather than absolute, perhaps compelling moral mate organizational purposes, a duty of fidelity could also
action but perhaps not, depending on its juxtaposition with prescribe for employees a duty to agree to choose forms of
other rights and duties in play. Ross himself understood the emotional labor that might otherwise be more demanding
term prima facie to be problematic, suggesting as it does to master, or otherwise potentially compromise employee
that the duty might be illusory rather than merely subordi- autonomy with respect to affective experience. (This is the
nated to other principles. The better label, which we prefer, sort of conflict between rights and duties that we will explore
is pro tanto: whereas a prima facie duty may only appear further in the next section of the paper.)
to be obligatory but “actually not be a reason at all,” a pro On the employer side, fidelity reflects the precept
tanto duty “has genuine weight, but nonetheless may be out- advanced by social contract theorists who focus on busi-
weighed by other considerations” (Kagan 1989, p. 17). Our ness ethics that through consent-based arrangements man-
analysis of duties focuses on two that are featured in Ross’s agement incurs moral duties to its employees (Donaldson
formulation with relevance for employment contexts gener- 1982; Dunfee and Donaldson 1995). To the extent that
ally and emotional labor specifically: a duty of fidelity and a deep acting yields desirable organizational results (such as
duty of non-maleficence. enhanced customer satisfaction and employee work engage-
ment coupled with decreasing absenteeism and turnover;
Fidelity see, e.g., Chau et al. 2009; Goodwin et al. 2011; Groth
et al. 2009; Scott and Barnes 2011), the duty of fidelity in a
Ross’s duty of fidelity refers to the duty “to fulfill prom- performance-based pay context might trigger a duty to give
ises and implicit promises because we have made them” greater compensation to employees who engage productively
(Ross 1930/1988, p. 22, emphasis in original). Employment in emotion regulation via deep acting. Further, performance-
arrangements in developed economies being by nature a based pay can increase job satisfaction and may therefore
form of contracting (see, e.g., Keeley 1988), the relevance amplify employees’ willingness to engage in beneficial regu-
of the duty of fidelity as an operating moral principle in the lation via deep acting (Cohen 2010; Grandey et al. 2013b),
performance of labor (emotional and otherwise) is inescap- which may well, in turn, benefit the organization. Overall,
able. Incorporating as Ross does both explicit and implicit this suggests the existence of a positive feedback loop link-
forms of contractual duty is also apt. On one hand the essen- ing higher emotional-labor-related compensation with more
tial exchange of labor for value is an explicit bargain that beneficial emotional labor behaviors, meaning that compen-
carries mutual basic obligations for employee and employer sation-related actions of fidelity also may contribute to the
to provide effort and remuneration, respectively (Robin- organization’s own well-being interests.
son et al. 1994). At the same time, work arrangements and
workplaces are shaped by psychological contracts—“beliefs, Non-maleficence
based upon promises expressed or implied, regarding an
exchange agreement between and individual and, in organi- The duty not to harm others can be labeled, as Ross does,
zations, the employing firm and its agents” (Rousseau 2004, a duty of non-maleficence, and in his formulation operates
p. 120). Researchers who study these beliefs observe that independently of motivation, “this being a duty whether
commitment to upholding duties that comprise psychologi- or not we have an inclination that if followed would lead
cal contacts are important to “maintaining a relationship of to our harming them; and that when we have such an
consistency and good faith” (Robinson et al. 1994, p. 149). inclination the primary duty not to harm others gives rise
Social contracts theory thus accounts for the fundamen- to a consequential duty to resist the inclination” (Ross
tal notion that formal and informal agreements rooted in 1930/1988, p. 22). Although harm and its avoidance can
seem to imply consequentialist reasoning as the basis for

13
An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor

moral evaluation, we view non-maleficence as deontologi- and beyond emotional labor—that contribute to the organi-
cal in the sense meant by Kagan: a normative principle zation’s goals.
that constrains action by virtue of the “intrinsic signifi-
cance of harm-doing” which invests in that principle “a Further Observations
force sufficient to outweigh good results” (1998, p. 72).
A complication in the realm of non-maleficence concerns We close this section with two observations about our
agency: the difference between doing harm versus merely approach to rights and duties in the context of employment
allowing harm (such as in the original trolley problem; see, generally and emotional labor specifically.
e.g., Thomson 2008). While in some settings this distinc- First, in describing rights to pursue autonomy and well-
tion between “doing” and “allowing” might be dispositive being as attaching to both employees and their employers,
in judging right from wrong, in an employment context the we are compelled to wrestle with the distinction between
two approach moral equivalence to the extent that the one rights of an individual (employee) and those of a collective
whose actions will elicit harm is generally aware of both (the firm or employer), and, more fundamentally, with the
that likelihood and the measures available to forestall it. somewhat controversial notion that both individuals and col-
Similar to the duty of fidelity, the duty of non-malefi- lectives can lay claim to moral rights. This is, of course, a
cence could be taken to suggest a duty for employees to controvertible position. French (1979) famously argued that
engage in deep acting. That is, surface acting may often by virtue of their having a requisite level of collective inten-
fulfill a minimal explicitly labor-for-value contractual tionality that does not necessarily reduce to individual intent,
understanding, but to meet a duty of non-maleficence—in firms possess a metaphysical status and level of agency that
this case to foster and not impede organizational aims— qualifies them as “full-fledged moral persons” (215). Skep-
employees may incur a duty to engage in deep acting. tics argue that to regard the firm as having moral identity of
Doing so may avert the negative organizational outcomes its own as “an agent because it is composed of agents is...to
associated with surface acting and deliver the benefits commit the fallacy of composition.” (Altman 2007, p. 262;
associated with deep acting. see also; Velasquez 2003). Hewing toward French but going
One way that organizations meet a duty to do no harm not quite as far, we choose to accommodate Bowie’s well-
is by providing training to employees that anticipates and known Kantian view of the firm as itself a moral community
buffers against risks of harm. Although doing so may in part with moral agency, one that stands over and apart from the
fulfill a duty of fidelity by equipping employees with rele- individual as moral agent. Just as Kant regarded the state as
vant professional development as part of an overt or psycho- a “moral and collective body...capable of moral valuation,”
logical contract, in the case of emotional labor, training also so too can corporate policies be subject to a Kantian evalu-
addresses the duty of non-maleficence. Employees proficient ation (Bowie 2017, p. 121). And although we do not go as
in emotion management report fewer physical symptoms and far as Hess (2014) in ascribing to corporations “beliefs and
less negative affect, as well as greater job satisfaction and desires,” we do accept her position that to the extent that a
work engagement, and proficiency in expressing emotions collective such as a firm acts on “commitments about fact
is associated with lower absenteeism and reduced emo- and value” arrived at through deliberative processes involv-
tional exhaustion (e.g., Bechtoldt et al. 2011; Biron and van ing the individuals who comprise it, the firm is “morally
Veldhoven 2012; Nguyen et al. 2016; Yanchus et al. 2010). responsible for both the action and the consequences that
Appropriate training thus may serve non-maleficence by follow” (p. 259). However, we also agree with List and Pettit
attenuating harms associated with emotional labor. (2011, p. 181) that, although business organizations can lay
Lastly, organizations can meet a non-maleficence duty in claim to rights and responsibilities (depending on the juris-
broader ways, for instance, by restructuring the nature of the diction), they nonetheless lack “equal rights and responsi-
work itself. For example, organizations can afford employees bilities with individual persons” (emphasis added) because
“time out” to recuperate from their emotional labor efforts, of inherent differences in power (McCall 2001), an issue to
a strategy that demonstrably increases positive emotions which we return in the next section.
(Dieffendorf and Richard 2003; Trougakos et al. 2008). And, Second, as mentioned above, we view these rights and
they can buffer the consequences of surface acting by foster- duties as moral values that are pro tanto in nature, not abso-
ing a supportive culture that allows employees to express lute or inviolable. In a pro tanto theory of moral reason-
genuine emotions either during interactions with clients ing, “one cannot infer anything about the permissibility of
and co-workers (Lopez 2006) or in the aftermath of service a course of action simply by invoking the right, because
encounters (Grandey et al. 2012; Lively 2002). In turn, such the right may or may not conflict with other moral consid-
support policies are likely to have beneficial downstream erations that prevent it from being overriding in the cir-
effects for the organization’s well-being as rejuvenated cumstances” (Frederick 2014, p. 386). As a result, Ross
employees are better able to engage in actions—including observes, conditional duties “[leave] us with no principle

13
B. Barry et al.

upon which to discern what is our actual duty in particular deontological approach as described above provides lim-
circumstances” (Ross 1930/1988, p. 23). Frederick (2014) ited guidance, we now turn more explicitly to social con-
goes as far as to suggest that all rights are pro tanto because tract theory. A contract-based perspective is especially
there is no right for which there is an absence of imagina- relevant to the conflicts that arise in relation to emotional
ble circumstances in which the right might be conditional. labor because, as noted earlier, explicit and implicit con-
Pro tanto rights and duties are well suited to our analysis tracts between employees and organizations are driving
here because one cannot account realistically for the ethics forces behind both parties’ actions and expectations. While
of emotional labor by simply resorting to inviolable duties the formal, explicit contract sets out the objective terms of
like a blanket prohibition on all forms of deception, which employment, the implicit (psychological) contract refers
would rule out many if not most forms of emotional labor to a broader and more subjective set of expectations that
at the outset. More pragmatically, the rights and duties we characterize employment relationships (Rousseau and
have been discussing in this section overlap in various ways, Parks 1993). Psychological contracts can include expec-
sometimes compatibly but often in conflict with one another. tations about organizational commitment, willingness to
We turn next to those conflicts. engage in extra-role behaviors, and minimum duration
of employment on the part of the employer, as well as
expectations about fair treatment, training and professional
Conflicts Between Rights and Duties development, and support on the part of the employee
(Rousseau 1990).
Although both employees and organizations have clearly We assume that psychological contracts, which are less
defined rights and duties, these rights and duties do not explicit than formal contracts, establish a social contract
specify an unambiguous course of action for either party. between organizations and their employees. Drawing on
Our fundamental position is that the ethics of emotional both contractarian and contractualist perspectives within
labor—the question of when either its performance or its social contract theory, we identify two principles that
regulation crosses ethical lines—arise because the condi- can elucidate conflicts between the rights of both parties,
tional rights and duties that employees and organizations and between the rights and duties of one party (either the
bring to the table are not aligned, creating an ambiguous employee or the organization). The first principle, consent,
situation for both employees and organizations. Whether is based on the assumption that contracts have a fair and
these touchpoints of ambiguity are best considered incom- impartial starting point. The second principle, mutual self-
plete specifications of rights and duties or a true conflict still interest, proposes that “morality consists in those forms
leaves open the normative question of how individuals and of cooperative behaviour that it is mutually advantageous
organizations should resolve these touchpoints in everyday for self-interested agents to engage in” (Ashford and Mul-
practice. For simplicity, we refer to the occasions in which gan 2012). We have chosen these principles because they
either the two parties’ rights or their rights and duties are capture two critical features of psychological contracts—
misaligned as “conflicts.” voluntary choice and mutuality (Rousseau 2004)—as well
This ambiguity is unsurprising given tensions between as formal contracts. The parallels between these features
Kant and Ross. Kantian duties may be duties of right (perfect of psychological contracts and the principles of consent
duties) or duties of virtue (imperfect duties; Mansell 2013). and mutual self-interest described in social contract theory
While the former obligate individuals to act in particular make these principles especially relevant to our discussion
way, the latter are conditional and provide justification to of these conflicts.
act only when they do not conflict with duties of right (Tim- In the next sections, we first discuss conflicts between
merman 2013). By definition, conflicts cannot arise between rights and/or duties, the relevance of the principles of
duties of rights (Timmerman 2013). Apparent conflicts arise, consent and mutual self-interest to each of these types of
however, between duties of virtue because such duties are constraints, and the suggested precedence between rights
complex and therefore may not be fully specified. For our and/or duties based on these principles. Although empiri-
analysis, an important consequence of Kant’s perspective is cal evidence demonstrates the clear benefits of engaging in
the implication that duties should not be pursued to the point deep acting and the risks of surface acting for both organi-
where individuals are harmed by their pursuit, for exam- zations and employee, we undertake an ethical analysis of
ple, by violating their own rights (Timmerman 2013). This both deep and surface acting. We do so because as noted
suggests that rights and duties may constrain each other, earlier, despite the benefits of deep acting, employees may
but that faced with a conflict between rights and duties, an choose to engage in surface acting and organizations may
individual’s rights prevail. choose to require no more than surface acting.
Nonetheless, in their daily lives individuals faced with
apparent conflicts must and do resolve them. Because a

13
An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor

Conflicts Between Two Parties’ Rights after having entered into an employment contract, employees
still exercise their right to autonomy in a given episode by
We have argued that organizations have the right to deter- choosing to engage in either surface or deep acting (i.e.,
mine how work is structured (autonomy) and to structure recurring acceptance when implementing the contract).
work in a way that furthers organizational goals, including Recognizing the potential harm associated with surface
profit (well-being). Similarly, employees have the right to acting, organizations may choose, at a minimum, to educate
a say in how they complete their tasks (autonomy) and the employees about the costs of surface acting at the point of
right to do so in a way that protects their physical and psy- initial employment and/or on an ongoing basis, or, in a more
chological health (well-being). The rights of the two parties complete exercise of the organization’s rights to autonomy
are not perfectly aligned: the autonomy rights of one party and well-being, require that employees engage in deep act-
delimit the well-being rights of the other, and vice versa. We ing. Employees may, nonetheless, preference autonomy over
briefly review these constraints and then use the principles well-being and choose to engage in surface acting in any
of consent and mutual self-interest to analyze the recipro- given episode. This choice may reflect their inability (for
cal limits that organizational and employee rights place on reasons briefly discussed in our literature review, or others)
each party. to engage in deep acting. It may also reflect temporal dis-
When organizations enact their right to autonomy by counting (Critchfield and Kollins 2001), a decision bias in
requiring emotional labor, they delimit the employee’s which individuals overweight short-term benefits (surface
right to well-being (the right to a safe work environment) acting is less effortful) and underweight long-term costs
by requiring task-related behavior that may harm employ- (impact on well-being).
ees. Although organizations might mitigate this harm to
their employees by specifying the form of emotional labor Principle of Mutual Self-interest
(i.e., deep acting) or through the structure of work (e.g.,
through providing frequent breaks), doing so encroaches on Mutual self-interest, at first glance, removes the constraints
an employee’s right to choose how to do the job (right to that each party’s rights place on the other party. As we
autonomy). On the other hand, employees who enact their argued earlier, employees who deep act do not encounter
right to autonomy by choosing whether to engage in surface as many negative physical and psychological consequences
or deep acting may also infringe upon the organization’s as those who surface act. Reciprocally, organizations that
right to well-being, since this organizational right is best develop and reward employees’ deep acting also reap the
served when employees choose to engage in deep acting. associated benefits: employees’ behavior requires less regu-
However, even when they favor deep acting over surface lation (e.g., Rafaeli and Sutton 1987), turnover and absentee-
acting, arguably employees constrain an organization’s ism are reduced, and customers are happier. Since it is in the
right to autonomy by restricting the ways in which tasks are organization’s interest to mandate deep acting, and it is in
performed. For example, organizations may require only a the employee’s interest to engage in deep acting, a rational
surface-acted “service with a smile” from employees even analysis of the situation should result in a mutually accept-
though it is likely that an organization’s right to well-being able course of action. This analysis assumes that knowing
is not well served by such a narrow specification of task what is in each party’s best interests will not only result in
requirements. Further, specifying the form of emotional the implementation of deep acting, but that the choice to
labor may ultimately harm both employer and employee deep act will be freely made.
by reducing employees’ capacity to respond flexibly in the However, as we have already discussed, employees (and
moment. organizations) may—despite the well-known benefits of
deep acting—prefer surface acting or may lack the resources
Principle of consent to engage in deep acting. In the case of employees, the
choice to surface act may reflect a transactional view of the
This principle underscores that a contract’s starting point organization in which employees exert the minimum neces-
and procedures should be fair and impartial (Ashford and sary effort to meet their task requirements. Organizations
Mulgan 2012). When jobs require emotional labor, a fair may choose to encourage surface acting because it requires
and impartial starting point implies that the specification of less organizational effort in the form of training and work
work tasks by an organization should include the require- structure than deep acting. Both parties may thus choose
ment to perform emotional labor. An explicit statement of to forgo their right to well-being in order to reduce effort;
this requirement acknowledges an employee’s primary right arguably, they are redefining well-being as reflecting short-
to autonomy in accepting the contract: employees may opt term benefits.
out of jobs that require emotional labor (i.e., initial accept- Applying the principle of mutual self-interest empha-
ance of a contract; Rousseau and Parks 1993). Further, even sizes the importance that both parties identify and agree to

13
B. Barry et al.

a particular course of action. Our discussion suggests that in and supporting deep acting, it is again worth noting that
the principle is met when both parties align on deep acting individuals may still choose to engage in surface acting and
or when both parties align on surface acting. It reflects an organizations may elect not to support the practice of deep
alignment of goals that favors neither party, and leaves the acting through training, work structure, or compensation for
rights of both parties intact. Instead, in this case the mutual many reasons (e.g., Gabriel et al. 2015).
adoption of either a long- or short-term perspective leads Overall, we have argued that the principle of informed
both individuals and organizations to favor deep or surface consent favors employees’ rights at least in the opening
acting, respectively. stages of an employment relationship, but that organiza-
tions’ rights gain more equal status with employees’ rights
Resolving Conflicts Between Rights when organizations educate and support employees in the
performance of emotional labor. We have also argued that,
Although organizations can exercise their rights by specify- in the simplest case, if organizations and employees align on
ing the requirement for emotional labor and also the form the form of emotional labor to be delivered, the principle of
of emotional labor, we argue that the principle of consent mutual self-interest removes the need to determine whether
licenses employees to override organizational rights in favor organizational or employee rights take precedence.
of their own because it is unlikely that the prerequisite for
consent—a fair and impartial starting point for contracts— Conflicts Between One Party’s Rights and Duties
will be met. This principle implies that organizations and
employees have equal power. It is, however, unlikely that The conflicts between the rights of one party in an employ-
this will be the case. Drawing on McCall (2001), we argue ment relationship and that party’s duties are more challeng-
that employees inherently cannot start from a position of ing to resolve, in part because the duties of fidelity and non-
equal bargaining power with organization because of asym- maleficence are, in Kantian terms, “wide and imperfect”
metries in dependence and information between the two par- (Denis 2001): although the end can be specified, the means
ties: organizations are less dependent on and better informed by which that end is accomplished remain ambiguous.
about potential risks than employees. Because employees Although fidelity may seem like a duty of right (a perfect
start from a position of disadvantage, we argue that employ- duty), because it relates to a contractual obligation (Mansell
ees’ rights to autonomy and well-being take precedence over 2013), we argue that this obligation is ambiguous in relation
organizational rights, giving employees discretion over how to emotional labor because it arises from a duty to adhere
they implement both the explicit and implied contracts, pro- to the spirit of the contract (i.e., the psychological contract;
vided that their behavior falls within normative ranges. Rousseau and Parks 1993) rather than the letter of the con-
The dynamic and evolving nature of psychological con- tract. The duty of non-maleficence, which serves the goal of
tracts, however, suggests a caveat to this position. Over time, beneficence, is more clearly a duty of virtue (an imperfect
organizational policies and practices may reduce the power duty) in that there is ambiguity about the specific extent to
imbalance: organizations can directly (through training) and which employees or organizations need to go in order to
indirectly (through work structure and compensation) edu- prevent harm to the other party and sufficiently fulfill their
cate employees about the risks associated with performing duty. The assessment of harm is further complicated by the
emotional labor. As employees’ knowledge increases and subtleties of emotional labor. On the one hand, organizations
thus the principle of informed consent is met, the prece- may underappreciate the consequences of emotional toil,
dence of employee rights over organizations’ rights is attenu- obscuring and dampening managers’ ability to comprehend
ated: employees over time are presumed to consent to more and trade off ethical risks in relation to stakeholder interests
explicitly defined and organizationally specific ranges of where the emotional lives of their employees are concerned.
normatively acceptable behaviors. On the other hand, employees may underappreciate the
Both principles (informed consent and mutual self- consequences of neglecting their duties of fidelity and non-
interest) imply that organizations and individuals will act maleficence for the long-term survival of the organization.
as rational decision makers, that is, that each will engage With these ambiguities in mind, we now outline the con-
in a cost-benefit analysis to determine whether and how flicts between one party’s rights and duties and then consider
emotional labor is performed. The decision to require or the how the principles of consent and mutual self-interest
perform deep acting results from the recognition of long- apply to these conflicts. An employee’s duties of fidelity (to
term benefits, and reflects a willingness to incur short-term fulfill both formal and psychological contracts) and non-
costs. As we suggested earlier, however, decision makers maleficence (to avoid harming the organization) give rise
are prone to temporal discounting—a preference to pursue to duties to engage in emotional labor when the job role
short-term benefits while underplaying the long-term costs calls for it, and arguably to perform deep rather than sur-
of such a strategy. Thus, despite the benefits of engaging face acting because of the higher potential benefit to the

13
An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor

organization. Both duties may impinge on an employee’s may clearly specify such terms as salary, tenure, notice peri-
rights to autonomy by directing them to engage in emotional ods and minimum stays. However, although employees may
labor, and by specifying the form of that labor (deep act- acknowledge their duties to engage in extra-role behavior
ing). They may also impinge on their right to well-being: such as emotional labor and to be loyal to the organization,
although deep acting is less harmful than surface acting, the and organizations may acknowledge their duties to train,
loss of control over how work is performed is known to cre- develop and support employees (Rousseau 1990), the actual
ate stress and harm individual well-being (i.e., via decreased means of implementation of these duties is highly ambigu-
felt responsibility for outcomes, which may lead to lower ous. In turn, because they are ambiguous, when and how
motivation; Karasek 1979). duties are fulfilled is unclear. Employees and organizations
A parallel argument emerges in relation to organiza- may thus give some precedence to their rights by limiting
tional rights and duties. To fulfill contractual duties (fidel- the extent to which they fulfill these duties. While doing so
ity) and avoid doing harm to employees (non-maleficence), may fail to fulfill the implicit contract between employees
an employer is obliged to ensure that employees are not and organizations, it does appear in many cases, particularly
adversely affected by organizational practices in relation to if deep acting is not directly specified, to fulfill the literal
compensation, professional development, or support. How- contract. Thus, when the precise implementation of duties
ever, these duties to fidelity and non-maleficence may, on is ambiguous, and contracts are not perfectly unambiguous,
the surface, exist at cross purposes with the organization’s the principle of consent seems to suggest that rights may
right to autonomy. That is, tailoring organizational practices take precedence over duties.
to meet these duties may—in the view of organizations or
their shareholders—unnecessarily constrain organizations’ Principle of Mutual Self-interest
autonomy in establishing practices and policies that serve
their ends. For example, even though it is arguably in the Mutual self-interest—because it relies on cooperation
organization’s long-term well-being interests to train, sup- between individuals with differing interests—is neces-
port, and reward deep acting, doing so may interfere with an sarily based on the recognition of others’ rights and an
organization’s right to focus instead on near-term profitabil- effort to address those rights. In this sense, the principle
ity—to choose (autonomy) to spend its money and attention of mutual self-interest implies that the duty of non-malef-
on other pursuits at that point in time. icence should override rights to autonomy and well-being
(see Ross 1930/1988 for a similar argument in relation to
Principle of Consent non-maleficence and other duties). Further, to the extent that
both parties upholding the terms of the formal and implied
We argue that if the principle of consent has been upheld, contracts is in the self-interest of both parties, this principle
the duty of fidelity overrides employee and organizational also suggests that the duty of fidelity should override each
rights to autonomy and well-being. A contract freely entered party’s rights.
into implies a duty to fulfill the contract to the best of one’s As we noted earlier, mutual self-interest is served by
ability, even if this fulfillment takes precedence over one’s both parties supporting either deep acting or surface act-
rights. To act in accordance with this principle, organiza- ing. If mutual self-interest translates into the implementa-
tions must disclose the requirement to engage in emotional tion of deep acting, the duty of non-maleficence may be
labor and its associated risks. Disclosing these risks carries interpreted as a further requirement to maximize the ben-
with it the duty to support employees in the performance efits of this kind of emotional labor. On the part of organi-
of emotional labor and to offset the risks through organiza- zations, this implies positive organizational practices that
tional practices such as support, training, and appropriate might include the development of employees’ acting skills,
compensation for employees who engage in emotional labor. or use of remuneration practices that recognize and reward
Based on disclosure by the organization, employees make effective deep acting. On the part of individuals, it implies
an informed choice to about whether and how to engage in genuine effort to foster and convey the required emotions.
emotional labor. Their duties of fidelity and non-maleficence In contrast, if mutual self-interest translates into the imple-
then direct them not only to engage in emotional labor but mentation of surface acting, the duty of non-maleficence
do so in a way that enhances organizational performance. may be interpreted as a requirement to minimize harm. In
However, this discussion overlooks the difficulty in unam- this case, organizations can support employees by imple-
biguously specifying the terms of an employment contract menting workplace programs that counteract the conse-
as well as the particular circumstances in which employee quences of surface acting (e.g., programs targeted at stress
rights may instead override their duties. This is especially management or peer support) and structuring work to pro-
the case when we consider the implicit psychological con- vide frequent breaks from the demands of emotional labor.
tract that characterizes individuals’ working lives. Contracts Further, it may be the case that this translation of mutual

13
B. Barry et al.

self-interest changes according to the type of interaction or organizations, damage to the organization’s reputation as an
customer (e.g., between customers valuing quick service ver- employer, falling profits or stock prices, or excessive com-
sus personalized care; Sutton and Rafaeli 1988), the tenure pensation payouts to employees harmed by emotional labor,
of the employee (such that surface acting may be accept- are examples of circumstances that license organizations to
able for new, untrained employees), or some other criterion. give precedence to rights over duties. In the case of employ-
For example, employers and employees may also choose to ees, substantial physical or psychological strain, high levels
identify and implement alternative work practices to replace of stress, or strain that carries over and affects their personal
emotional labor that nonetheless deliver equivalent levels of lives and relationships, are examples of circumstances that
customer satisfaction. license employees to give precedence to rights over duties.
This argument is reminiscent of threshold deontology, which
Reconciliation of Rights and Duties proposes that “deontological norms govern up to a point
despite adverse consequences; but when the consequences
As we noted above, specifying the extent and degree that become so dire that they cross the stipulated threshold, con-
contracts must be fulfilled and the extent and degree of harm sequentialism takes over” (Alexander and Moore 2016).
that is possible and that must be avoided in order to ful-
fill one’s duties sufficiently protecting one’s rights is chal-
lenging. This conflict could be as straightforward as the Discussion
employee who gives precedence to controlling her emotional
experiences in the moment (right to autonomy) over the We close with three observations about implications and
longer-term organizational harm that arises from her choice possible extensions that follow from the foregoing analysis.
to engage in surface rather than deep acting (duties of fidel-
ity, non-maleficence). The situation grows more complicated The Onus of Disclosure?
if we further imagine the rights–duties conflict in a different
light: the employee giving precedence to his right to auton- Implicit in our argument of a fair starting point for con-
omy by using surface acting (e.g., displaying an insincere tractual agreements between employer and employee is
smile to increase commission-based sales) over his duty of the simple notion that in order to exercise their rights to
non-maleficence (for example, avoiding the organizational autonomy and well-being, employees must understand what
costs of losing dissatisfied customers). they are agreeing to in the labor contract. In this sense,
This ambiguity raises a further issue, that is, the limits to the employer, who will presumably know more about job
self-harm permitted under the guise of fulfilling one’s duties: demands than a not-yet-hired employee, bears the burden
should employees and organizations fulfill their duties at of disclosing the emotional labor expectations of the job,
any cost to themselves, or is there a threshold after which as well the consequences of performing emotional labor.
fulfilling duties imposes unacceptable harms (and thus also Such disclosure is akin to a builder informing potential
violation of one’s rights)? Employees and organizations carpenters about the requirement that carpenters be able to
already receive legislative protection in many countries. measure, lift, and fit wood as part of the job, and that such
Employees are often guaranteed a safe work environment— work may be physically demanding. Not doing so would in
one that is free from incivility, bullying, harassment, and effect be misrepresenting the job, opening the employer to
discrimination—as well as broader protections for whistle- potential legal ramifications (e.g., wrongful hiring claims
blowers. Organizations are often protected against enduring in the U.S.).1 However, as we outlined in the introduction,
inadequate performance by employees and acts of sabotage characteristics of the individual (e.g., extraversion versus
ranging from theft to industrial espionage. These protections introversion [Judge et al. 2009]; confidence in surface acting
limit the harm that each party can inflict on the other. By ability; [Pugh et al. 2011]) moderate the impact of emo-
analogy, we propose that there ought to be limits to the harm tional labor on employees. Given that the firm arguably has
that individuals or organizations inflict on themselves in ser- a better idea than either potential or even current employ-
vice of their duties to the other party. We hasten to restate ees of these moderators, the firm should also bear respon-
here a point we made earlier, however: while both employees sibility for informing employees of these likely moderators
and firms lay claim to rights and incur obligations, the moral and their effects. Providing such information to employees
rights of organizations are generally subordinate to those of further allows employees to make fully informed decisions.
individuals (List and Pettit 2011).
While recognizing that any limit has exceptions (see
also Garrett’s 2004 note on Ross), we argue that the bal- 1
See, for example, Minnesota Statutes 181.64, False Statements as
ance tips in favor of rights at the point that either organi- Inducement to Entering Employment. https://www.revisor.mn.gov/
zational or employee survival is threatened. In the case of statutes/?id=181.64.

13
An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor

Employees may also benefit from labor unions that may take with or treated as simply analogous to physical and cognitive
some of the onus for protecting employees from the unique labor in analyses of their ethical implications.
effects of emotional labor, and vocational and trade schools We further suggest that the framework used in this analy-
and other programs that may help better prepare employees sis might be applied to other costs of labor not explicitly
to recognize and manage the emotional labor demands of linked to physical labor as it is traditionally defined.2 For
various positions. Yet since employers, unions, and train- example, situations that involve taking physical risks (e.g.,
ing programs cannot fully predict how emotional labor may exposure to dangerous chemicals in the workplace), or
affect any particular worker, employees also ought to under- completing mind-numbing paperwork may implicate simi-
take due diligence and, incorporating this employer-provided lar questions of autonomy, fidelity, well-being, non-malefi-
information on emotional labor consequences and modera- cence, consent, and mutual self-interest.
tors, assess the likely impact on themselves before accept-
ing an employment arrangement. Thus, while the primary A Caution Against Losing Sight of Consequences
onus of disclosing emotional labor costs and benefits rests
with employers, employees also bear some responsibility for Finally, although we discuss and incorporate many of the
assessing the impact of emotional labor given their unique effects of emotional labor on both individuals and organiza-
traits. tions throughout our analysis, perhaps the most significant
question we have left unaddressed concerns the relative role
Emotional Labor as Distinct from Other Forms of a purely consequentialist view of emotional labor (putting
of Labor aside rights and duties) versus considering consequences
in light of how they are implicated by various rights and
It is reasonable to question whether rights and duties related duties, as we have done. Indeed, given our reliance on the
to emotional labor differ from standards for physical or documented (and often negative) effects of emotional labor
cognitive labor. We see two distinct differences. First, the on both employees and employers, particularly in our discus-
physical harm incurred in workplaces is better recognized sion of conflicts between rights and duties and their potential
and documented than the psychological harm. Legislative resolutions, it might be unfairly dismissive to assume that
frameworks document potential physical harms, and require rights and duties would take precedence over a purely con-
organizations to monitor and to take action to eliminate sequentialist argument. To the contrary, we take the posi-
those harms. Absent effective monitoring and corrective tion that consequences merit consideration in conjunction
practices, employees are entitled to redress through worker’s with rights and duties even in an explicitly deontologically
compensation guidelines in many countries. The same is focused analysis in order to accommodate how those rights
not as clearly true for psychological harm, which has only and duties are best enacted and balanced against one another.
in recent decades begun to receive similar, but sometimes Thus, as is evident in our discussion above of conflicts
tenuous, legislative attention (Ivancevich et al. 1985). Given between rights and duties, rather than limiting our analysis
that the daily impact of performing emotional labor may purely to a deontological lens independent of consequences,
be less immediately and outwardly apparent than effects of we have bolstered our arguments wherever possible with
physical labor, it may be more difficult for employees to gain empirical evidence of the consequences of emotional labor
recognition of and compensation for less apparent but still and explicit discussion of the relative harms and benefits
intensive psychological harm. Overall, although a myriad of of it.
physical and other job demands create stressors on employ-
ees, emotional labor has distinct and negative effects (e.g.,
Brotheridge and Grandey 2002; Näring et al. 2006; Zapf Conclusion
et al. 2001) that are sufficient to justify a separate analysis
of its moral contours. Research attention in the social sciences to emotional labor
The second difference is that, unlike jobs that require at work has been conceptually and empirically substantial,
physical labor, those that require emotional labor can incur but normatively deprived: very little has been said or writ-
a wage penalty (often in jobs with low cognitive demands; ten expressly about its ethical dimensions or ramifications.
Bhave and Glomb 2009; Glomb et al. 2004). Accordingly, Working from a perspective focused on the pro tanto recipro-
levels of compensation do not always adequately account cal rights and duties of employees and employers, we have
for harms associated with extensive emotion regulation and/ assessed the moral dimensions of emotional labor, including
or displays. Thus, unless and until compensation packages its component facets of organizational emotion requirements
are adjusted to take fully into account the psychological (as
well as physical) costs and harm to employees engaging in 2
We thank one of the journal’s reviewers for suggesting this line of
these behaviors, emotion requirements should not be equated thought.

13
B. Barry et al.

as well as individual emotion regulation and displays, as Brandt, R. B. (1964). The concepts of duty and duty. Mind, 73,
they arise at a critical point of contact and potential ten- 374–393.
Brotheridge, C. M., & Grandey, A. A. (2002). Emotional labor and
sion in organizational life: the nexus between employer burnout: Comparing two perspectives of “people work. Journal
and employee. We have also proposed several arguments of Vocational Behavior, 60, 17–39.
for resolving conflicts between rights and duties when they Brotheridge, C. M., & Lee, R. T. (2002). Testing a conservation of
arise, both within and between employees and organizations. resources model of the dynamics of emotional labor. Journal
of Occupational Health Psychology, 7(1), 57.
Finally, we have raised several practical implications and Chau, S. L., Dahling, J. J., Levy, P. E., & Diefendorff, J. M. (2009).
potential avenues for further inquiry. A predictive study of emotional labor and turnover. Journal of
Organizational Behavior, 30, 1151–1163.
Acknowledgements The authors contributed equally and are listed in Ciulla, J. B. (2012). Worthy work and Bowie’s Kantian theory of
alphabetical order. We thank the editor and anonymous reviewers for meaningful work. In D. G. Arnold & J. D. Harris (Eds.), Kan-
insightful comments that catalyzed significant improvements in the tian business ethics: Critical perspectives (pp. 115–131). Chel-
article. This research was partially funded through a Melbourne Busi- tenham: Edward Elgar.
ness School Distinguished Visiting Scholar grant and ARC Discovery Cohen, R. L. (2010). When it pays to be friendly: Employment rela-
Grant DP140100630. An earlier version of this paper was presented at tionships and emotional labour in hairstyling. The Sociological
the 2015 Academy of Management Meeting, Vancouver. Review, 58(2), 197–218.
Critchfield, T. S., & Kollins, S. H. (2001). Temporal discounting:
Author Contributions All the authors are contributed equally to this Basic research and the analysis of socially important behavior.
work. Journal of Applied Behavioral Analysis, 34, 101–122.
Davidson, R., & Poor, N. (2015). The barriers facing artists’ use
of crowdfunding platforms: Personality, emotional labor, and
Compliance with Ethical Standards going to the well one too many times. New Media & Society,
17, 289–307.
Conflict of interest The authors declare that they have no conflict of Denis, L. (2001). Moral self-regard: Duties to oneself in Kant’s
interest. moral theory. New York: Garland.
Diefendorff, J. M., Croyle, M. H., & Gosserand, R. H. (2005). The
dimensionality and antecedents of emotional labor strategies.
Journal of Vocational Behavior, 66, 339–357.
References Diefendorff, J. M., & Richard, E. M. (2003). Antecedents and con-
sequences of emotional display rule perceptions. Journal of
Alarcon, G. M. (2011). A meta-analysis of burnout, job demands, Applied Psychology, 88, 284–294.
resources, and attitudes. Journal of Vocational Behaviour, 79, Donaldson, T. (1982). Corporations and morality. Englewood Cliffs,
549–562. NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Alexander, L., & Moore, M. (2016). Deontological ethics. In E. N. Dunfee, T., & Donaldson, T. (1995). Contractarian business ethics:
Salta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter Current status and next steps. Business Ethics Quarterly, 5,
Edition). https ://plato .stanford.edu/archives/win20 16/entri es/ 173–186.
ethics-deontological. Ellis, S. (2008). The main argument for value incommensurability
Altman, M. C. (2007). The decomposition of the corporate body: What (and why it fails). Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46, 27–43.
Kant cannot contribute to business ethics. Journal of Business Fisher, C. D., & Ashkanasy, N. M. (2000). The emerging role of
Ethics, 74, 253–266. emotions in work life: An introduction. Journal of Organiza-
Ashford, E., & Mulgan, T. (2012). Contractualism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), tional Behavior, 21, 123–129.
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (fall 2012 ed.). https Frederick, D. (2014). Pro-tanto versus absolute rights. The Philo-
://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/contractualism/. sophical Forum, 45, 375–394.
Audi, R. (1997). Intrinsic value and moral duty. Southern Journal of French, P. A. (1979). The corporation as a moral person. American
Philosophy, 35, 135–154. Philosophical Quarterly, 16, 207–215.
Beal, D. J., Trougakos, J. P., Weiss, H. M., & Green, S. G. (2006). Frijda, N. H. (1994). Varieties of affect: Emotions and episodes,
Episodic processes in emotional labor: Perceptions of affective moods, and sentiments. In P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson (Eds.),
delivery and regulation strategies. Journal of Applied Psychol- The nature of emotions: Fundamental questions (pp. 197–202).
ogy, 91, 1053–1065. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bechtoldt, M. N., Rohrmann, S., De Pater, I. E., & Beersma, B. (2011). Fulmer, I. S., & Barry, B. (2009). Managed hearts and wallets: Ethi-
The primacy of perceiving: Emotion recognition buffers nega- cal issues in emotional influence by and within organizations.
tive effects of emotional labor. Journal of Applied Psychology, Business Ethics Quarterly, 19, 155–191.
96, 1087–1094. Gabriel, A. S., Daniels, M. A., Diefendorff, J. M., & Greguras, G.
Bhave, D. P., & Glomb, T. M. (2009). Emotional labour demands, J. (2015). Emotional labor actors: A latent profile analysis of
wages and gender: A within-person, between-jobs study. Journal emotional labor strategies. Journal of Applied Psychology,
of Occupational and Organizational Psychology, 82, 683–707. 100, 863–879.
Biron, M., & van Veldhoven, M. (2012). Emotional labour in service Gardner, W. L., Fischer, D., & Hunt, J. G. (2009). Emotional labor
work: Psychological flexibility and emotion regulation. Human and leadership: A threat to authenticity? Leadership Quarterly,
Relations, 65, 1259–1282. 20, 466–482.
Bowie, N. (2017). Business ethics: A Kantian perspective (2nd edn.). Garrett, J. (2004). A simple and usable (although incomplete) ethical
New York: Cambridge University Press. theory based on the ethics of W.D. Ross. http://peopl e.wku.
Bowie, N. E. (1998). A Kantian theory of meaningful work. Journal edu/jan.garrett/ethics/rossethc.htm.
of Business Ethics, 17, 1083–1092.

13
An Ethical Analysis of Emotional Labor

Glomb, T. M., Kammeyer-Mueller, J. D., & Rotundo, M. (2004). Hesmondhalgh, D., & Baker, S. (2008). Creative Work and Emotional
Emotional labor demands and compensating wage differentials. Labour in the Television Industry. Theory, Culture and Society,
Journal of Applied Psychology, 89, 700–714. 25(7–8), 97–118.
Goodwin, R. E., Groth, M., & Frenkel (2011). Relationships between Hess, K. (2014). The free will of corporations (and other collectives).
emotional labor, job performance, and turnover. Journal of Voca- Philosophical Studies, 168, 241–260.
tional Behavior, 79, 538–548. Hill, T. E. (2015). Kantian autonomy and contemporary ideas of auton-
Grandey, A. A. (2003). When “the show must go on”: Surface acting omy. In O. Sensen (Ed.), Kant on moral autonomy (pp. 15–31).
and deep acting as determinants of emotional exhaustion and Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
peer-rated service delivery. Academy of Management Journal, Hochschild, A. R. (1983). The managed heart: Commercialization of
46(1), 86–96. human feeling. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Grandey, A. A. (2015). Smiling for a wage: What emotional labor Hülsheger, U. R., & Schewe, A. F. (2011). On the costs and benefits of
teaches us about emotion regulation. Psychological Inquiry, 26, emotional labor: A meta-analysis of three decades of research.
54–60. Journal of Occupational Health Psychology, 16, 361–389.
Grandey, A. A., Chi, N., & Diamond, J. A. (2013b). Show me the Humphrey, R. H. (2012). How do leaders use emotional labor? Jour-
money! Do financial rewards for performance enhance or under- nal of Organizational Behavior, 33, 740–744.
mine the satisfaction from emotional labor? Personnel Psychol- Humphrey, R. H., & Ashforth, B. E. (2000). Buyer-supplier alliances
ogy, 66, 569–612. in the automobile industry: How exit-voice strategies influence
Grandey, A. A., & Diamond, J. A. (2010). Interactions with the public: interpersonal relationship. Journal of Organizational Behavior,
Bridging job design and emotional labor perspectives. Journal 21, 713–730.
of Organizational Behavior, 31, 338–350. Ivancevich, J., Matteson, M., & Richards, E. (1985). Who’s liable
Grandey, A. A., Diefendorff, J. M., & Rupp, D. E. (2013a). Bring- for stress on the job? Harvard Business Review, 63(2), 60–72.
ing emotional labor into focus: A review and integration of Judge, T. A., Woolf, E. F., & Hurst, C. (2009). Is emotional labor
three research lenses. In A. A. Grandey, J. M. Diefendorff & D. more difficult for some than for others? A multilevel, expe-
E. Rupp (Eds.), Emotional labor in the 21st century: Diverse rience-sampling study. Personnel Psychology, 62(1), 57–88.
perspectives on the psychology of emotion regulation at work Kagan, S. (1989). The limits of morality. New York: Oxford Uni-
(pp. 3–27). New York: Routledge. versity Press.
Grandey, A. A., Foo, S. C., Groth, M., & Goodwin, R. (2012). Free Kagan, S. (1998). Normative ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
to be you and me: A climate of authenticity alleviates burnout Kammeyer-Mueller, J. D., Rubenstein, A. L., Long, D. M., Odio,
from emotional labor. Journal of Occupational Health Psychol- M. A., Buckman, B. R., Zhang, Y., & Halvorsen-Ganepola,
ogy, 17, 1–14. M. D. K. (2013). A meta-analytic structural model of disposi-
Grandey, A. A., & Gabriel, A. S. (2015). Emotional labor at a cross- tional affectivity and emotional labor. Personnel Psychology,
roads: Where do we go from here? Annual Review of Organi- 66, 47–90.
zational Psychology and Organizational Behavior, 2, 323–349. Kant, I. (1785/1997). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (M.
Grandey, A. A., Rupp, D. E., & Brice, W. N. (2015). Emotional labor Gregor, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
threatens decent work: A proposal to eradicate emotional display Karasek, R. A. (1979). Job demands, job decision latitude, and men-
rules. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 36, 770–785. tal strain: Implications for job redesign. Administrative Science
Grant, A. M. (2013). Rocking the boat but keeping it steady: The role of Quarterly, 24, 285–307.
emotion regulation in employee voice. Academy of Management Keeley, M. (1988). A social contract theory of organizations. Notre
Journal, 56, 1703–1723. Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Greenwood, M. (2013). Ethical analyses of HRM: A review and Kilduff, M., Chiaburu, D. S., & Menges, J. I. (2010). Strategic use of
research agenda. Journal of Business Ethics, 114, 355–366. emotional intelligence in organizational settings: Exploring the
Griffin, J. (1996). Value judgement: Improving our ethical beliefs. dark side. Research in Organizational Behavior, 30, 129–152.
Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kong, T. S. K. (2006). What it feels like for a whore: The body poli-
Gross, J. J. (1998). The emerging field of emotion regulation: An inte- tics of women performing erotic labour in Hong Kong. Gender,
grative review. Review of General Psychology, 2, 271–299. Work and Organization, 13, 409–434.
Groth, M., Hennig-Thurau, T., & Walsh, G. (2009). Customer reactions List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design,
to emotional labor: The roles of employee acting strategies and and status of corporate agents. New York: Oxford University
customer detection accuracy. Academy of Management Journal, Press.
52(5), 958–974. Lively, K. J. (2002). Client contact and emotional labor: Upsetting
Guerrier, Y., & Adib, A. (2003). Work at leisure and leisure at work: the balance and evening the field. Work and Occupations, 29,
A study of the emotional labour of tour reps. Human Relations, 198–225.
56, 1399–1417. Lopez, S. H. (2006). Emotional labor and organized emotional care:
Guy, M. E., Newman, M. A., & Mastracci, S. H. (2008). Emotional Conceptualizing nursing home care work. Work and Occupa-
labor: Putting the service in public service. Armonk, NY: M.E. tions, 33, 133–160.
Sharpe. Mansell, S. (2013). Shareholder theory and Kant’s “Duty of Benefi-
Harris, P., & Morrow, J. (Eds.). (1986). T. H. Green: Lectures on the cence”. Journal of Business Ethics, 117, 583–599.
principles of political duty and other writings. Cambridge: Cam- Maslach, C., & Jackson, S. E. (1986). Maslach Burnout Inventory man-
bridge University Press. ual (2nd edn.). Palo Alto, CA: Consulting Psychologists Press.
Harsanyi, J. C. (1997). Utilities, preferences, and substantive goods. Maslach, C., Schaufeli, W. B., & Leiter, M. P. (2001). Job burnout.
Social Choice and Welfare, 14, 129–145. Annual Review of Psychology, 52, 397–422.
Hennig-Thurau, T., Groth, M., Paul, M., & Gremler, D. (2006). Are all McCall, J. J. (2001). Employee voice in corporate governance: A
smiles created equal? How emotional contagion and emotional defense of strong participation rights. Business Ethics Quarterly,
labor affect service relationships. Journal of Marketing, 70(3), 11, 195–121.
58–73. Näring, G., Briët, M., & Brouwers, A. (2006). Beyond demand-control:
Emotional labour and symptoms of burnout in teachers. Work &
Stress, 20, 303–315.

13
B. Barry et al.

Nguyen, H., Groth, M., & Johnson, A. (2016). When the going gets Scott, B. A., Barnes, C. M., & Wagner, D. T. (2012). Chameleonic or
tough, the tough keep working: Impact of emotional labor on consistent? A multilevel investigation of emotional labor vari-
absenteeism. Journal of Management, 42, 615–643. ability and self-monitoring. Academy of Management Journal,
Provis, C. (2001). The ethics of emotional labour. Australian Journal 55, 905–926.
of Professional and Applied Ethics, 3(2), 1–15. Smith, P., & Lorentzon, M. (2005). Is emotional labour ethical? Nurs-
Pugh, S. D., Groth, M., & Hennig-Thurau, T. (2011). Willing and able ing Ethics, 12, 638–642.
to fake emotions: A closer examination of the link between emo- Sutton, R., & Rafaeli, A. (1988). Untangling the relationship between
tional dissonance and employee well-being. Journal of Applied displayed emotions and organizational sales: The case of conven-
Psychology, 96(2), 377–390. ience stores. Academy of Management Journal, 31(3), 461–487.
Rafaeli, A., & Sutton, R. I. (1987). Expression of emotion as part of Syed, J. (2008). From transgression to suppression: Implications of
the work role. Academy of Management Review, 12(1), 23–37. moral values and societal norms on emotional labour. Gender,
Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. New York: Oxford University Work and Organization, 15, 182–201.
Press. Thomson, J. J. (2008). Turning the trolley. Philosophy and Public
Rivera, K. D. (2015). Emotional taint: Making sense of emotional dirty Affairs, 36, 359–374.
work at the U.S. Border Patrol. Management Communication Timmerman, J. (2013). Kantian dilemmas? Moral conflict in Kant’s
Quarterly, 29, 198–228. ethical theory. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 95, 36–64.
Robinson, S. L., Kraatz, M. S., & Rousseau, D. M. (1994). Chang- Timmermann, J. (2007). Kant’s groundwork of the metaphysics of mor-
ing duties and the psychological contract: A longitudinal study. als. Cambridge: Cambridge Univrsity Press.
Academy of Management Journal, 37, 137–152. Trougakos, J. P., Beal, D. J., Green, G. S., & Weiss, H. M. (2008).
Ross, W. D. (1930/1988). The right and the good. Indianapolis: Making the break count: An episodic examination of recovery
Hackett. activities, emotional experiences, and positive affective displays.
Rousseau, D. M. (1990). New hire perceptions of their own and their Academy of Management Journal, 51, 131–146.
employer’s duties: A study of psychological contracts. Journal Velasquez, M. (2003). Debunking corporate moral responsibility. Busi-
of Organizational Behavior, 11, 389–400. ness Ethics Quarterly, 13, 531–62.
Rousseau, D. M. (2004). Psychological contracts in the workplace: Wang, K. L., & Groth, M. (2014). Buffering the negative effects of
Understanding the ties that motivate. Academy of Management employee surface acting: The moderating role of employee–cus-
Executive, 18, 120–127. tomer relationship strength and personalized services. Journal of
Rousseau, D. M., & Parks, J. (1993). The contracts of individuals and Applied Psychology, 99, 341–350.
organizations. In L. L. Gummings & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research Wharton, A. S. (2009). The sociology of emotional labor. Annual
in organizational behavior (Vol. 15, pp. 1–43). Greenwich, CT: Review of Sociology, 35, 147–165.
JAI Press. Wike, V. S. (1994). Kant on happiness in ethics. Albany, NY: State
Sallaz, J. J. (2002). The house rules: Autonomy and interests among University of New York Press.
service workers in the contemporary casino industry. Work and Wilson, J. (2007). Is respect for autonomy defensible? Journal of Medi-
Occupations, 29, 394–427. cal Ethics, 2007, 33, 353–356.
Schaubroeck, J., & Jones, J. R. (2000). Antecedents of workplace emo- Yanchus, N. J., Eby, L. T., Lance, C. E., & Drollinger, S. (2010). The
tional labor dimensions and moderators of their effects on physi- impact of emotional labor on work–family outcomes. Journal of
cal symptoms. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 21, 163–183. Vocational Behavior, 76, 105–117.
Schreiber, N. (2016). At Trader Joe’s, good cheer may hide com- Zapf, D., Seifert, C., Schmutte, B., Mertini, H., & Holz, M. (2001).
plaints. The New York Times, November 3. http://www.nytim Emotion work and job stressors and their effects on burnout.
es.com/2016/11/04/busin ess/at-trade r-joes-good-cheer-may- Psychology & Health, 16, 527–545.
hide-complaints.html. Zhan, Y., Wang, M., & Shi, J. (2016). Interpersonal process of emo-
Schwartz, S. H., & Bilsky, W. (1987). Toward a psychological structure tional labor: The role of negative and positive customer treat-
of human values. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, ment. Personnel Psychology, 69, 525–557.
53, 550–562. Zimmerman, M. J. (2013). Duty and duty. The International Encyclo-
Scott, B. A., & Barnes, C. M. (2011). A multilevel field investigation of pedia of Ethics. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee
emotional labor, affect, work withdrawal, and gender. Academy 158.
of Management Journal, 54, 116–136.

13

You might also like