Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5

Beyond Good and Evil

Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future


(German: Jenseits von Gut und Böse: Vorspiel einer Philosophie der Beyond Good and Evil
Zukunft) is a book by philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche that expands
the ideas of his previous work Thus Spoke Zarathustra with a more
critical and polemical approach. It was first published in 1886.

In Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche accuses past philosophers of


lacking critical sense and blindly accepting dogmatic premises in their
consideration of morality. Specifically, he accuses them of founding
grand metaphysical systems upon the faith that the good man is the
opposite of the evil man, rather than just a different expression of the
same basic impulses that find more direct expression in the evil man.
The work moves into the realm "beyond good and evil" in the sense
of leaving behind the traditional morality which Nietzsche subjects to
a destructive critique in favour of what he regards as an affirmative
approach that fearlessly confronts the perspectival nature of
knowledge and the perilous condition of the modern individual.

Contents
Title page of the first edition.
Background and themes
Author Friedrich Nietzsche
Structure of the work
Original title Jenseits von Gut
On philosophers, free spirits, and scholars und Böse. Vorspiel
On morality and religion einer Philosophie
On nations, peoples and cultures der Zukunft

Aphorisms and poetry Country Germany

Editions Language German

Commentary Subject Morality,


metaphysics
Notes
Published 1886
External links
Media type Print
Preceded by Thus Spoke
Background and themes Zarathustra (1883–
1885)
Of the four "late-period" writings of Nietzsche, Beyond Good and
Followed by On the Genealogy of
Evil most closely resembles the aphoristic style of his middle period.
In it he exposes the deficiencies of those usually called "philosophers" Morality (1887)
and identifies the qualities of the "new philosophers": imagination, Text Beyond Good and
self-assertion, danger, originality, and the "creation of values". He Evil at Wikisource
then contests some of the key presuppositions of the old philosophic
tradition like "self-consciousness", "knowledge", "truth", and "free will", explaining them as inventions of the
moral consciousness. In their place, he offers the "will to power" as an explanation of all behavior; this ties
into his "perspective of life", which he regards as "beyond good and evil", denying a universal morality for all
human beings. Religion and the master and slave moralities feature prominently as Nietzsche re-evaluates
deeply held humanistic beliefs, portraying even domination, appropriation and injury to the weak as not
universally objectionable.

In several places of the book, Nietzsche drops hints, and even explicit statements as to what the philosophies
of the future must deal with.

Structure of the work


The work consists of a short preface dated to 1885, 296 numbered sections, and an "epode" (or "aftersong")
entitled "From High Mountains". Not counting the preface or epode, the main sections are organized into nine
parts:

Part One: On the Prejudices of Philosophers


Part Two: The Free Spirit
Part Three: The Religious Essence
Part Four: Maxims and Interludes
Part Five: On the Natural History of Morals
Part Six: We Scholars
Part Seven: Our Virtues
Part Eight: Peoples and Fatherlands
Part Nine: What is Noble?

On philosophers, free spirits, and scholars


In the opening two parts of the book, Nietzsche discusses, in turn, the philosophers of the past, who he accuses
of a blind dogmatism plagued by moral prejudice masquerading as a search for objective truth; and the "free
spirits", like himself, who are to replace them.

He casts doubt on the project of past philosophy by asking why we should want the "truth" rather than
recognizing untruth "as a condition of life." He offers an entirely psychological explanation of every past
philosophy: each has been an "involuntary and unconscious memoir" on the part of its author (§6) and exists
to justify his moral prejudices, which he solemnly baptizes as "truths".

In one passage (§34), Nietzsche writes that "from every point of view the erroneousness of the world in which
we believe we live is the surest and firmest thing we can get our eyes on." Philosophers are wrong to rail
violently against the risk of being deceived. "It is no more than a moral prejudice that truth is worth more than
appearance." Life is nothing without appearances; it appears to Nietzsche that it follows from this that the
abolition of appearances would imply the abolition of "truth" as well. Nietzsche asks the question, "what
compels us to assume there exists any essential antithesis between 'true' and 'false'?"

Nietzsche singles out the Stoic precept of "living according to nature" (§9) as showing how philosophy
"creates the world in its own image" by trying to regiment nature "according to the Stoa." But nature, as
something uncontrollable and "prodigal beyond measure," cannot be tyrannized over in the way Stoics
tyrannize over themselves. Further, there are forceful attacks on several individual philosophers. Descartes'
cogito presupposes that there is an I, that there is such an activity as thinking, and that I know what thinking is
(§16). Spinoza masks his "personal timidity and vulnerability" by hiding behind his geometrical method (§5),
and inconsistently makes self-preservation a fundamental drive while rejecting teleology (§13). Kant, "the
great Chinaman of Königsberg" (§210), reverts to the prejudice of an old moralist with his categorical
imperative, the dialectical grounding of which is a mere smokescreen (§5). His "faculty" to explain the
possibility of synthetic a priori judgements is pejoratively compared to a passage from Molière's comedy Le
Malade imaginaire in which the narcotic quality of opium is described in terms of a "sleepy faculty" –
according to Nietzsche, both Kant's explanation of synthetic a priori judgments and Moliére's comedic
description of opium are examples of redundant self-referring statements which do not explain anything.
Schopenhauer is mistaken in thinking that the nature of the will is self-evident (§19), which is, in fact, a highly
complex instrument of control over those who must obey, not transparent to those who command.

"Free spirits", by contrast to the philosophers of the past, are "investigators to the point of cruelty, with rash
fingers for the ungraspable, with teeth and stomach for the most indigestible" (§44). Nietzsche warns against
those who would suffer for the sake of truth and exhorts his readers to shun these indignant sufferers for truth
and lend their ears instead to "cynics"—those who "speak 'badly' of man—but do not speak ill of him" (§26).

There are kinds of fearless scholars who are truly independent of prejudice (§6), but these "philosophical
labourers and men of science in general" should not be confused with philosophers, who are "commanders
and law-givers" (§211).

Nietzsche also subjects physics to critique. "Nature's conformity to law" is merely one interpretation of the
phenomena which natural science observes; Nietzsche suggests that the same phenomena could equally be
interpreted as demonstrating "the tyrannically ruthless and inexorable enforcement of power-demands" (§22).
Nietzsche appears to espouse a strong brand of scientific anti-realism when he asserts that "It is we alone who
have fabricated causes, succession, reciprocity, relativity, compulsion, number, law, freedom, motive, purpose"
(§21).

On morality and religion


In the "pre-moral" period of mankind, actions were judged by their consequences. Over the past 10,000 years,
however, a morality has developed where actions are judged by their origins (their motivations) not their
consequences. This morality of intentions is, according to Nietzsche, a "prejudice" and "something provisional
[...] that must be overcome" (§32).

Nietzsche criticizes "unegoistic morality" and demands that "Moralities must first of all be forced to bow
before order of rank" (§221). Every "high culture" begins by recognizing "the pathos of distance"[1] (§257).

Nietzsche contrasts southern (Catholic) and northern (Protestant) Christianity; northern Europeans have much
less "talent for religion" (§48) and lack "southern delicatezza" (§50). As elsewhere, Nietzsche praises the Old
Testament while disparaging the New Testament (§52).

Religion has always been connected to "three dangerous dietary prescriptions: solitude, fasting and sexual
abstinence" (§47), and has exerted cruelty through demanding sacrifice according to a "ladder" with different
rungs of cruelty, which has ultimately caused God himself to be sacrificed (§55). Christianity, "the most fatal
kind of self-presumption ever", has beaten everything joyful, assertive and autocratic out of man and turned
him into a "sublime abortion" (§62). If, unlike past philosophers such as Schopenhauer, we really want to
tackle the problems of morality, we must "compare many moralities" and "prepare a typology of morals"
(§186). In a discussion that anticipates On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche claims that "Morality is in
Europe today herd-animal morality" (§202)—i.e., it emanates from the ressentiment of the slave for the master
(see also §260, which leads into the discussion in Genealogy, I).

Nietzsche argues that more than what they value as "good" distinguishes noble and base. Even where
agreement exists over what is good, what men consider a sufficient sign of possessing what is good differs
(§194). Nietzsche describes love as the desire to possess a woman. The most unrefined form of the desire is
also the most readily identifiable as a desire to possess another: control over the woman's body. A subtler
desire to possess her also wants her soul, and thus wants her to be willing to sacrifice herself for her lover.
Nietzsche describes this as a more complete possession. A still more refined desire to possess her prompts a
concern that she might be willing to sacrifice what she desires for a mistaken image of her lover. This leads
some lovers to want their women to know them deep down so that their sacrifice really is a sacrifice for them.
A similar rank-ordering applies to statesmen, the less refined not caring whether they attain power by fraud,
the more refined not taking pleasure in the people's love unless they love the statesman for who he really is. In
both cases, the more spiritualized form of the desire to possess also demands one possess what is good more
completely.

On nations, peoples and cultures


Nietzsche discusses the complexities of the German soul (§244), praises the Jews and heavily criticizes the
trend of German antisemitism (§251). He praises France as "the seat of Europe's most spiritual and refined
culture and the leading school of taste" (§254). He finds the English coarse, gloomy, more brutal than the
Germans, and declares that "they are no philosophical race", singling out Bacon, Hobbes, Hume and Locke as
representing a "debasement and devaluation of the concept 'philosopher' for more than a century" (§252).
Nietzsche also touches on problems of translation and the leaden quality of the German language (§28).

In a prophetic statement, Nietzsche proclaims that "The time for petty politics is past: the very next century will
bring with it the struggle for mastery over the whole earth" (§208).

Aphorisms and poetry


Between §62 and §186 Nietzsche inserts a collection of mostly single-sentence aphorisms, modelled on
French aphorists such as La Rochefoucauld. Twelve of these (§§ 84, 85, 86, 114, 115, 127, 131, 139, 144,
145, 147, 148) concern women or the distinction between men and women. Other subjects touched on include
his doctrine of the eternal recurrence (§70), music (§106) and utilitarianism (§174), among more general
attempts at trenchant observations about human nature.

The work concludes with a short ode to friendship in verse form (continuing Nietzsche's use of poetry in The
Gay Science and Thus Spoke Zarathustra).

Editions
Jenseits von Gut und Böse. Zur Genealogie der Moral, edited by Giorgio Colli and Mazzino
Montinari, Munich: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 2002 (study edition of the standard German
Nietzsche edition)
Beyond Good and Evil, translated by Walter Kaufmann, New York: Random House, 1966;
reprinted in Vintage Books, and as part of Basic Writings of Nietzsche, New York: Modern
Library, 2000
Beyond Good and Evil, translated by R. J. Hollingdale, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1973;
revised reprint 1990 with introduction by Michael Tanner
Beyond Good and Evil, translated by Helen Zimmern, 1906, reprinted in Courier Dover
Publications, New York, 1997, ISBN 0-486-29868-X
Beyond Good and Evil, translated by Marion Faber, Oxford: Oxford World's Classics, 1998
Beyond Good and Evil, translated by Judith Norman and edited by Rolf-Peter Horstmann,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002

Commentary
Andreas Urs Sommer: Kommentar zu Nietzsches Jenseits von Gut und Böse (= Heidelberger
Akademie der Wissenschaften (Hg.): Historischer und kritischer Kommentar zu Friedrich
Nietzsches Werken, Bd. 5/1). XVII + 939 pages. Berlin / Boston: Walter de Gruyter 2016,
ISBN 978-3-11-029307-4 (the comprehensive standard commentary on Beyond Good and Evil
– only available in German).

Notes
1. Nietzsche: On the Genealogy of Morals (https://web.archive.org/web/20120221055547/http://w
ww.unc.edu/~megw/Nietzsche.html), summary by Meg Wallace

External links
Beyond Good and Evil (https://gutenberg.org/ebooks/4363) at Project Gutenberg — English-
language edition.

Beyond Good and Evil (https://gutenberg.org/ebooks/7204) at Project Gutenberg — German-


language edition.
Beyond Good and Evil (https://librivox.org/search?title=Beyond+Good+and+Evil&author=Ni
etzsche&reader=&keywords=&genre_id=0&status=all&project_type=either&recorded_languag
e=&sort_order=catalog_date&search_page=1&search_form=advanced) public domain
audiobook at LibriVox
A searchable, self-referential edition with concordance (https://web.archive.org/web/200602251
45702/http://www.doc.ic.ac.uk/~rac101/concord/texts/bge/)
Beyond Good and Evil – Full PDF Version (https://web.archive.org/web/20190213000832/htt
p://azinelibrary.org/other/Beyond_Good_and_Evil.pdf)
Beyond Good and Evil – Large Print Edition (https://www.amazon.com/dp/1494800934)
"On the Significance of Genealogy in Nietzsche's Critique of Morality" (https://web.archive.org/
web/20071218220154/http://www.carsten-korfmacher.com/PHILOSOPHY/Papers/fngenealogy.
html), by Carsten Korfmacher

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Beyond_Good_and_Evil&oldid=1015702327"

This page was last edited on 3 April 2021, at 00:48 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using this
site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia
Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

You might also like