Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

VID SIMONITI

Assessing Socially Engaged Art

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


abstract
The last twenty-five years have seen a radical shift in the work of politically committed artists. No longer content to merely
represent social reality, a new generation of artists has sought to change it, blending art with activism, social regeneration
projects, and even violent political action. I assess how this form of contemporary art should lead us to rethink theories of
artistic value and argue that these works make a convincing case for an often-dismissed position, namely, the pragmatic view
of artistic value. However, the pragmatic view, when properly applied, sets the bar high indeed—art that tries to change
society should be considered good art only when it succeeds in making a tangible difference.

i. socially useful artworks best-known pioneer of such project-based art.


In one of her earlier works, The Crystal Quilt
Theaster Gates’s artwork Dorchester Projects (1985–1987), Lacy brought together over 400
(2009–) began with a house. In 2009, Gates bought older women in Minnesota for a mass perfor-
a rundown bungalow in Chicago’s impoverished mance, but the real purpose of the project was
South Side and re-created it using repurposed ma- in the reactivation of this socially marginalized
terials, including timbers from defunct Chicago group, through the two-year period of research
factories and wood from disused barns. By 2009, it and workshops, which led up to the event. Today,
would not have been unusual to make an artwork a socially engaged artist might work with a group
out of a house. Robert Smithson partially buried of miners to reenact a strike action that had
a woodshed in 1970 (Partially Buried Woodshed, been brutally suppressed by the police (Jeremy
1970); in 1993, Rachel Whiteread created a neg- Deller, The Battle of Orgreave, 2001); she might
ative concrete imprint of a condemned house mount a wind turbine on top of a railway bridge
(House, 1993); and Christo wrapped the German to demonstrate its benefits to an eco-reluctant
Reichstag in fabric in 1995 (Wrapped Reichstag, community (Marjetica Potrč, The Wind Lift,
1995). Gates’s modification of his house, however, 2014); or she might collaborate with a group of
was significant in that the work centered not on garbage collectors to create self-portraits, financ-
physical but social change. The rebuilt Dorchester ing local community projects with the proceeds
Projects host a community center, a library, and a (Vik Muniz’s Pictures of Garbage series of works,
kitchen, all designed to enliven the neighborhood 2008). An artwork might be a new sun-powered
and affirm its self-image. It is this living, socially reading light intended for off-grid areas of the
transformative aspect that marks out the identity world (Olafur Eliasson’s Little Sun, 2012), a piece
of Gates’s house as a work of art (Wei 2011; Gates of software designed to elude online censorship in
2012; Adams 2015). Iran and China (Jud and Wachter’s picidae, 2007),
Insisting that the social impact is the defining or even a violent political action, such as the
feature of his artworks, Gates’s artistic practice is destruction of a police vehicle (the Voina collec-
typical of contemporary socially engaged artists. tive’s Cop’s Auto-da-fé, or Fucking Prometheus,
The feminist artist Suzanne Lacy is perhaps the 2011).
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76:1 Winter 2018
C 2018 The American Society for Aesthetics
72 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Works like these have been the subject of much ii. how we got to socially engaged art
discussion in recent art theory and have been
theorized under several designations, such as In the opening chapter of One Place After An-
“the social turn,” “relational aesthetics,” “project- other, Miwon Kwon offers a short genealogy of the
based art,” “community-based art,” “new public project-based, socially engaged art (Kwon 2002,
art,” “site-specific art,” “social practice,” “use- 11–33). This trajectory covers the period between
ful art,” and “participatory art” (Lacy 1995; the 1960s and the 1990s and charts the way in
Bourriaud 2002; Kwon 2002; Kester 2004; Jackson which artists responded to the Western (and espe-
2011; Bishop 2012; Doherty 2015). The present cially New York-based) conception of advanced
investigation will focus on a certain cross section art as modernist abstraction. Certainly, this story

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


of these practices, which share two characteristics: only partially accounts for the social turn. In to-
(1) the intended value of the art project is coexten- day’s globalized artworld one should also take
sive with its social and political impact, and (2) the stock of the histories of socially engaged art in
methods utilized to produce that impact bear close the former Eastern bloc and in the global South
resemblance to nonartistic forms of political and (see Bishop 2012 for a more comprehensive his-
social activism. For convenience’s sake, I use the tory). However, since New York has undeniably
term “socially engaged art” to refer to this group dominated the Western art production during the
of artworks. Cold War, this is one relevant story to tell here.
Socially engaged art, I argue, poses a problem to Western socially engaged art in this period, there-
philosophical accounts of artistic value, a problem fore, did not merely have the task of commenting
at least as challenging as that posed by the ready- on pertinent social problems but also had to justify
mades to philosophers of art in the 1960s (Danto its status as art in relation to the New York mod-
1964; Dickie 1969). One among several difficulties ernist paradigm: in relation to the idea that the
posed by the ready-mades was that they were not truly progressive art constantly interrogates the
beautiful, or, at least, they were no more beau- conventions of artistic practice itself. For Kwon,
tiful than their nonart counterparts. Therefore, the crucial notion linking socially engaged art to
old theories conflating artistic value with aesthetic preceding advanced art movements is the artists’
value could not accommodate such works (com- interrogation of the artwork’s physical location
pare Stecker 2012, 355–356). Socially engaged art and its manner of display: its ‘site.’
presents a new challenge. Unlike ready-mades, The first stage of the investigation of the work’s
these works worryingly disregard the confines of site was, as Kwon puts it, “phenomenological,”
the artworld and aim to be judged for their so- and she identifies it with post-object art such as
cial usefulness. As I argue, this upsets the broadly Minimalist, land art, and Conceptual art prac-
held assumption that artistic value is something tices of the 1960s (Kwon 2002, 12–13). Artists
we assess from within the sphere of art. such as Carl Andre, Sol LeWitt, Robert Smithson,
First, I offer a brief history of socially en- Donald Judd, Robert Morris, and Eva Hesse
gaged art within the context of recent ad- challenged the modernist, white cube gallery
vanced art practices. I argue for a synthesis of model of art display of the 1950s, according to
two historical narratives—Miwon Kwon’s and which aesthetic experience was supposed to occur
Jason Gaiger’s—that I think crucial for under- in an uninterrupted interaction between the
standing the appeal of this kind of art and its link- viewer and the colossal, self-contained abstract
age to art of previous eras. I then consider two canvasses and sculptures. Instead, these artists em-
broad accounts of artistic value in Anglophone phasized dynamic ways in which the work can in-
philosophy—aestheticism and pluralism—and ar- teract with its environment. Smithson’s Partially
gue that socially engaged art presents a challenge Buried Woodshed, mentioned above, is typical.
to both accounts. Instead, I offer an account of Unlike a sculpture on a pedestal, no viewer can
artistic value usually dismissed as untenable—the experience Smithson’s shed in isolation from its
pragmatic view—as a way of accounting for this challenging and changing environment.
kind of art. After considering objections that so- The next generation of artists, now known un-
cially engaged art is not art, or is bad art, I conclude der the label “institutional critique,” took the
that such art indeed suggests we should expand engagement with the work’s site a step further.
our conception of what artistic value can be. They came to query the social and political, rather
Simoniti Assessing Socially Engaged Art 73

than merely aesthetic, conditions for the work’s site that is delineated as a field of knowl-
display (Kwon 2002, 14–24). In this way, Mierle edge, intellectual exchange, or cultural debate”
Laderman Ukeles’s pieces often drew attention (Kwon 2002, 26). These works, for Kwon, no
to the (gendered) labor relations that allowed longer react only to the specific site of the gallery
the display of art in the first place. For example, but contribute to broader political efforts and de-
in her “Maintenance Art” performances (1973), bates. However, Gaiger complains, to characterize
Ukeles presented the cleaning of the museum the site of such art as ‘discourse’ is to provide
as an artwork in itself. Hans Haacke, Andrea too imprecise a criterion. As he persuasively
Fraser, Marcel Broodthaers, Christo, and oth- argues, even premodernist figurative art could be
ers associated with institutional critique—which plausibly construed as engaging the work’s site in

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


flourished in the more politically activated art- Kwon’s terms, since much of that art was engaged
world of the 1970s—often attempted similar artis- in a wider field of discourse. Think of Hogarth,
tic exposés of the political conditions of the Goya, Courbet, or Manet: their work undoubt-
work’s site. edly participated in some broader political and
This leads Kwon to explain how socially cultural debate. So, by Kwon’s characterization,
engaged art, taking off in the early 1990s, came to they too should count as engaging their ‘site’ in the
become so readily accepted in the contemporary discursive sense.
art world. One of her case studies is the 1993 Gaiger is therefore led to unstitch Kwon’s tra-
“Culture in Action” program by the Sculpture jectory from Minimalism to socially engaged art
Chicago organization, for which curator Mary along different seams. The useful concept for de-
Jane Jacob, instead of displaying conventional scribing this shift, he claims, is not according to
sculptures, commissioned artists to team up the work’s site but rather as a shift away from the
with communities to tackle local issues, organize demands of artistic autonomy (Gaiger 2009, 52).
workshops, and put on political marches (Kwon Artistic autonomy (self-governance) is a norma-
2002, 28–29, 101–137). Works included the HaHa tive doctrine about artistic value. One way of stat-
Collective growing food for AIDS patients ing the doctrine would be to say that art is intrin-
(Flood, 1993); Simon Grennan and Christopher sically valuable and should therefore not be held
Sperandio collaborating with a candy factory accountable to some external standard, such as the
workers’ union to create and market a chocolate demands of a political movement, state, religion,
bar (The Workforce Makes the Candy of Their or field of knowledge.1 Gaiger suggests that this
Dreams, 1993); and Iñigo Manglano-Ovalle’s doctrine has, over the past fifty years, been gradu-
Tele-Vecindario (1992–1993), a project teaching ally revised in the world of Western advanced art
teenagers how to make videos. For Kwon, such and that this can be seen in the trajectory leading
works again engage their site. The difference up to the social turn.
is that permissible sites for contemporary work The post-object Minimalists and Conceptual
now include not just the gallery but its nonartistic artists of the 1960s reacted specifically against
context as well, whether this be the local commu- the dogma of artistic autonomy as theorized by
nity or a broader political effort. Though Kwon Clement Greenberg in his account of modernism.
does not specifically use the term “social engage- For Greenberg and the critics he influenced, artis-
ment,” but prefers to discuss this art under the tic value was based on the viewer’s absorption in
label “site-specificity,” her third paradigm—the the formal, medium-specific features of the work
primary focus of her book—clearly extends to itself. Greenberg’s analysis of New York school
socially engaged art mentioned above. abstract painters like Jackson Pollock is typical
Jason Gaiger offers an alternative narrative to in this regard: what Greenberg appreciated was
Kwon’s three stages. He agrees that there is an the sense of dynamism and energy created purely
interesting trajectory uniting the successive move- by consideration of the relations between the
ments of post-object art, institutional critique, shapes on the flat canvas (Greenberg 1986–1993,
and the project-based socially engaged artworks 72–74, 200–202, vol. 2; 106–107, 217–235, vol. 3).
but applies critical pressure on Kwon’s usage of Post-object artists, such as Minimalists and
the term ‘site’ (Gaiger 2009, 49–54). Gaiger takes Conceptualists, and Robert Smithson in the
issue with Kwon describing socially engaged example above, are crucial because they chip
art as active within a “discursively determined away at this scheme by canceling the importance
74 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

of the work’s intrinsic features. While the main and everyday life,” in a way that treats “aesthetic
concern of their work was still broadly speaking and art historical concerns as secondary issues”
with the aesthetic experience, post-object art (Kwon 2002, 24). The project-based works by
facilitated the experience through means external Theaster Gates, Marjetica Potrč, Vik Muniz, and
to the work: the location, the viewer’s body, others do not (merely) comment on politics
the relations between the two. Once this step is through an artistic medium, as realist painters
taken, however, artistic autonomy can be further have done. And while they may be following in the
enervated. The next assumption under pressure footsteps of the historical avant-gardes, like the
is the thought that artistic value is chiefly based Dadaists who attempted to “merge” art and life
on the work’s aesthetic interest. In the 1960s (compare Bürger 1984, 49–50), socially engaged

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


and later, Western advanced artists opened art artists do not do so through anti-rational, experi-
to institutional critique and to broader political mental performances. Instead, these artists dedi-
commentary, and, as Gaiger argues, this devel- cate themselves pragmatically to measurable im-
opment further depreciates artistic autonomy. By pact, aligning their art with social work, activism,
the 1990s, advanced art practices are clearly no or technology development.
longer evaluated merely on aesthetic terms but I would therefore like to suggest a synthesis
in terms of their contribution to live political and of Kwon’s and Gaiger’s accounts. Gaiger adds
cultural debates. As Gaiger puts it: to Kwon’s account by plausibly mapping it onto
a shift in critical evaluation of art. This is a shift
In short, it is opposition to the modernist conception from artistic autonomy—the principle of art being
of aesthetic autonomy—rather than the increasingly evaluated by its own standards—to what we might
tenuous conception of a ‘site’—that links the differ- call artistic heteronomy, or the principle that art
ent parts of Kwon’s account together and which estab- should be evaluated by standards of other fields,
lishes a line of continuity between the minimalist and such as politics, religion, ethics, and knowledge.
post-minimalist practices of the 1960s and contempo- What Kwon’s analysis shows, however, is that the
rary project-based art. (Gaiger 2009, 53–54) result has been more radical than Gaiger allows
for. Attempting to directly engage its political
Kwon and Gaiger, then, both offer narratives context, socially engaged art aligns artistic activity
that show how the recent social turn is continuous with political action to a level virtually without
with central concerns in the history of Western ad- precedent. I now turn to the challenge that this
vanced art after World War II. I do not so much presents to the philosophical definition of artistic
wish to assess who of the two provides a better the- value.
oretical framework as to suggest that they should
be combined.
Gaiger usefully inscribes Kwon’s trajectory iii. socially engaged art and artistic value
within the broader theme of artistic autonomy,
which has been more central to art historical nar- The majority of philosophical positions on what
ratives of the twentieth century than the category artistic value is can be classified as belonging to
of site.2 However, there is a danger, in Gaiger’s two broad camps. Aestheticism is united on the
account, in bringing recent history of art full cir- view that only aesthetic values can contribute to a
cle. Gaiger considers contemporary project-based work’s artistic value (for example, Beardsley 1958;
art to be a “partial restitution” of previous po- Lamarque and Olsen 1994; Budd 1996; Zangwill
litically committed art movements, such as natu- 2007; Scruton 2009). Pluralism, by contrast,
ralism and realism at the end of the nineteenth allows artistic value to comprise a wider variety
century and Russian Constructivism and Dada at of values, including aesthetic, epistemic, ethical,
the beginning of the twentieth (Gaiger 2009, 51, political, and more (for example, Nussbaum
55). This suggestion overlooks an important point 1990; Stecker 1997; Kieran 2005a; Robinson 2005;
about the recent social turn, implicit in Kwon’s Gaut 2007). It should be noted these two camps
claim that the site of these works is broader polit- do not exhaust the logical space of possible views.
ical discourse and action. The “dominant drive,” Outside of the present scope, we find nihilism
as she puts it, of these works is “a pursuit of a about artistic value (artistic value is never re-
more intense engagement with the outside world alized) or nonaesthetic monism (the view that
Simoniti Assessing Socially Engaged Art 75

only one nonaesthetic kind of value contributes emphasis). Sometimes such restrictions on artistic
to artistic value). However, aestheticism and value are described as the value something has
pluralism do draw the lines of most of the recent as art. Malcolm Budd, an aestheticist, discusses
debates. the “value as art” as the value of the experience,
Louise Hanson recently offered what I think is which is arrived at through an appropriate
the clearest neutral definition of artistic value, one understanding of the work. Here, “proper”
that should be agreed by all the above positions. understanding seems to rely on appreciation of
Artistic value, Hanson says, is “the thing that by features such as a painting’s tonality, symbolism,
definition, artworks have just to the extent that and formal arrangement (Budd 1996, 1–8, 14–16,
they are good art” (2013, 502). What this captures 41–43). Berys Gaut, a pluralist who discusses

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


is that when we talk about artworks, we talk about ethical and cognitive value, aligns “value qua art”
them as good or bad art, and often compare their with those properties we attend to in art-critical
merits as better or worse. The dispute between discourse (Gaut 2007, 34–37, 95ff, 166f). In
available substantive positions is, then, a dispute Gaut’s analysis of two treatments of the Bath
about what kinds of value contribute to artis- of Bathsheba from Rembrandt’s workshop, this
tic value, and under what conditions (compare includes attending to the theme of the sitter’s
Hanson 2013, 504, 507–508). I will accept inner life as achieved through features such as
Hanson’s claim, and I will additionally take it that tonal harmony and expressive brushwork (Gaut
any substantive position on artistic value should 2007, 87–89). Similarly, pluralists who defend the
therefore follow some form like this: cognitive value of literature customarily specify
that their arguments must show how such value is
(Artistic value) Value V, possessed by artwork X, is an arrived at in virtue of specifically literary features
artistic value ←→ V is a value of the kind Y, and V is of the work: those that distinguish literature
realized under conditions Z. from prosaic modes of description (compare
John 2013, 384–385).
While aestheticism insists that Y be aesthetic All these writers, then, despite significant differ-
value narrowly construed, pluralism is more lib- ences in their theories, tend to agree that a value
eral as to what kinds of value can count as V. I realized by a work of art counts toward its artis-
now wish to suggest that proponents of aestheti- tic value under such limited conditions. This point
cism and pluralism have tended to agree on a fur- is also often expressed by distinguishing between
ther interesting point. the work’s artistic and pragmatic value (Lamarque
This point pertains to the conditions Z under 2013, 56; compare Lopes 2011, 521). For example,
which artistic values must be realized. Namely, a novel may be ethically and cognitively valuable
for pluralists and aestheticists alike, artistic values because it happens to contain a folk recipe for a
are not the values that artworks have simpliciter, medicine, or a painting may be aesthetically valu-
but only the values that are realized through able because it conceals a hideous scene previ-
characteristically artistic features, specific to the ously painted on the canvas. Such values do not
work’s medium, genre, theme, technique, mode of make the work good art, since they are not real-
display, or art kind. For example, among aestheti- ized in virtue of such artistic features as we saw
cists, Monroe Beardsley’s analysis shows how enumerated above.
aesthetic values in painting are achieved through, In short, I would like to describe the view shared
inter alia, the use of color, representation of by pluralists and aestheticists as the demand for
depth, rules of composition, and the relationship the following condition: that only the values that a
between depicted objects and the shape of the work realizes as art—that is, through recognizably
canvas (Beardsley 1958, 168–173, 92–96, 205–209). artistic features—count toward artistic value. Un-
Among pluralists, Robert Stecker considers as til recently, such a contention would have perhaps
characteristically artistic “[the] sort of exploration seemed unremarkable. However, not long ago,
of its subject matter [the work] provides”; “what Dominic Lopes challenged the view that artistic
it requires its audience to imagine and to feel,” value is value “as art” (Lopes 2014, Chapter 5,
and—in the case of literature—how it succeeds especially 90–100).3 Lopes argues that “as art” is
in doing so “in virtue of its literary properties such too broad a category to be useful and that only in-
as vivid description” (Stecker 2012, 358; original dividual arts, on the basis of their specific medium
76 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

profiles, are restrictive enough to allow us to and deep-going philosophical challenge. By as-
measure achievement (Lopes 2014, 103). For similating themselves to the “site” of political ac-
Lopes, there is therefore only musical, painterly, tion and discourse and by radically departing from
literary (and so on) value, and “artistic value” claims of artistic autonomy (to combine Kwon’s
is merely a disjunctive term encompassing all of and Gaiger’s terms), these works have controver-
these. sially dispensed with the idea that what makes
Personally, I am not sure whether Lopes’s is something good art should be realized through
a new position or rather a more explicit state- any features specific to the sphere of art. Instead,
ment of something that has already been accepted it seems, these works embrace a pragmatic view
by pluralists and aestheticists alike. It seems that about art, a position that we might describe as

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


most writers acknowledge that what we count follows:4
among the work’s artistic features is going to de-
pend considerably—though not exclusively—on (Pragmatic view) Value V, possessed by artwork X, is an
the medium-specific art kind in question (for ex- artistic value ←→ V is the positive political, cognitive,
ample, Gaut 2007, 88). Therefore, the disagree- or ethical impact of X.
ment seems to be one of emphasis. Lopes seems
to think, somewhat like Clement Greenberg used Where the pragmatic view differs from aes-
to, that the relevant artistic features gather around theticism is in the kind of value it takes artis-
the medium profile of one of the arts (Lopes tic value to be. Where the pragmatic view dif-
2014, 159–162); other philosophers might allow fers from both aestheticism and pluralism is in
that some artistic features, such as themes and omitting the demand that artistic values should
genre-specific features, may be shared between be realized through characteristically artistic fea-
various arts. tures. In Suzanne Lacy’s, Theaster Gates’s, Iñigo
My point for now, then, is that all these philo- Manglano-Ovalle’s, or Vik Muniz’s project-based
sophically diverse accounts of artistic value place works discussed above, their claim to being good
some “as art” restriction on the realization of artis- artworks is based on the social strengthening of
tic value. One might describe this “value as art” the communities they engage with. In the tech-
consensus, adhered to by both aestheticism and nological artworks of Olafur Eliasson, Marjetica
pluralism, as filling in the conditions Z in (Artistic Potrč, or Jud and Wachter, their claim to being
value), above, as follows: good artworks is based on the impact their art-
works have for the people who use them. Can
(Value as art) Value V, possessed by artwork X, is an such a position, and thereby the status of socially
artistic value ←→ V is a value of the kind Y, and V is engaged artworks as good art, be made philosoph-
realized through features specific to the work’s medium, ically respectable?
genre, theme, technique, modes of display, art kind, or
other artistic features.
iv. socially engaged art defended
What follows from Lopes’s discussion is that it
is certainly difficult to point out which features Above, I stated that socially engaged art “em-
count as properly “artistic” and that one might braces” the pragmatic view. To put this point more
debate as to whether the work’s medium should clearly, I now argue that the existence of good
hold some privileged position among them. In- socially engaged artworks favors the pragmatic
deed, as the arts evolve and the borders between view, since only this view can explain their artis-
them change, these issues have been much dis- tic value. Similarly, the existence of artistically
puted. A case in point is ready-mades, which re- good but nonaesthetic works of art favors plu-
tain little that is recognizably artistic other than ralism over aestheticism, since aestheticism can-
the mode of display in the gallery and the “at- not explain the value of such works. Here I do
mosphere” of art interpretation that goes with it not mean to argue that the pragmatic view is
(compare Danto 1964, 579–581). the correct position to take with regard to the
This formulation of the consensus, however, en- artistic value of all artworks (nor do I think
ables us to see clearly the extent to which so- that would be a sensible position). However, I
cially engaged artworks present us with a new want to show that it can be sensibly applied to
Simoniti Assessing Socially Engaged Art 77

socially engaged art. The structure of my argu- or Russian Constructivism in the early twentieth.
ment is simple: Other genealogies of socially engaged art empha-
size the collaborative and participatory element
1. Socially engaged artworks are works of art. of these works, which can be traced to the Situ-
2. Some socially engaged artworks are good art. ationist International in the 1950s, happenings in
3. Aestheticism and pluralism cannot explain the 1960s, and feminist participatory practices in
how socially engaged artworks can be good art. the 1970s (Kester 2004; Bishop 2012). Therefore,
4. The pragmatic view of artistic value can explain to the extent that the historical definitions of art
how socially engaged artworks can be good art. aim to accommodate continuity as well as innova-
5. Therefore, the pragmatic view is a valid ac- tion, these are precisely the criteria that socially

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


count of artistic value. engaged works fulfill.
On the other hand, the institutional definitions
I now defend premises (1)–(4) and then offer of art—of which George Dickie is a well-known
some qualifications on what has been achieved. exponent—claim that something is art if it is
First, one might object to premise (1). Socially accepted as such by members of art institutions
engaged artworks, the objection goes, no longer (Dickie 1969). Though the early socially engaged
appear to be art in any meaningful sense. In- works were experimental and marginal, this kind
stead, they have fully assimilated themselves into of work has been since thoroughly embraced
nonart fields of activity. Therefore, philosophical by the art establishment: Theaster Gates is
accounts of artistic value need not take notice of represented by high-profile commercial galleries;
them. international exhibitions like documenta rou-
This objection points to the definitional issue tinely feature socially engaged work; projects
of what it is for something to be a work of art. like Eliasson’s Little Sun are enthusiastically em-
It should be noted that aestheticist definitions of braced by museums like Tate Modern. True, these
art, which define art as human artifacts intended to project-based works do exit the artworld in the
realize aesthetic value, would likely reject socially sense that they take place in the broader political
engaged art altogether (compare Beardsley 1982, sphere rather than in the gallery. Nevertheless,
299). However, this point is dialectically moot. they are validated as art by artworld participants
One cannot espouse a value-based definition of both through art discourse and by showing docu-
art to argue against a rival, pragmatic theory of mentation of social projects in traditional gallery
artistic value without begging the question. We spaces.
must therefore look to value-neutral definitions One might reply to both lines of defense that
of art, such as historical and institutional defini- we resist categorizing socially engaged works
tions, to adjudicate on this issue. as art not because of their novelty but because
For example, according to Jerrold Levinson’s of their success as members of another, nonart
historical definition of art, something is an art- category. Imagine a cook experimenting with
work if it is intended to be regarded in some way sweet appetizers. Her cocoa-coated spicy carrots
in which artworks of the past were standardly may still just about qualify as an appetizer,
regarded (Levinson 1979). Here, Kwon’s analy- but if she ends up making a full-blown carrot
sis is pertinent, since it explains that socially en- cake, it seems she has failed in producing an
gaged art is regarded as engaging with its site. appetizer because she produced a dessert. Simi-
In this respect, these works are continuous with larly, we might resist accepting socially engaged
post-object works such as Minimalist sculpture, artworks as art because they are something
which dominated the production of advanced art else: social projects or works of activism. These
in the 1960s. Gaiger’s analysis places socially en- works migrated into another, nonart sphere
gaged art within an even longer trajectory of het- entirely.
eronomous art. Even though I argued that the On reflection, however, I do not think this ob-
most recent social turn represents a radical out- jection works. Things can belong to multiple cate-
come of that lineage, it would be correct to say gories: something might be a religious object and
that these works are intended to be regarded as art, a piece of erotica and art, or a piece of plumb-
contributing to political outcomes, much as French ing and art (as with Duchamp’s Fountain). What
realist works did in the mid-nineteenth century is wrong with carrot cake as an appetizer, among
78 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

other things, is that it is both institutionally and his- thousand and one wooden chairs, which signified
torically an aberration among appetizers, not that the ‘invisible’ presence of Chinese migrants who
it is a lovely dessert. Just think of sliced melon, anonymously intermingled with the visitors. Ai
which can be both. What matters for categoriz- also showed a companion piece: a large structure
ing socially engaged artworks as art, then, is that made of Qing and Ming dynasty doors, taken
they are historically and institutionally enmeshed from buildings that had to be destroyed to make
with the artworld, not whether they also succeed way for new constructions (Template, 2007). It
as social projects. would certainly be possible to appreciate Fairytale
On at least some respectable definitions of art, as a complex piece of participatory performance
then, socially engaged artworks are art, and should and installation. However, for all these nods

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


be included in discussions about artistic value. to artistic autonomy, the documenta catalogue
Another way to defuse the motivation for the also described the work as simply facilitating
pragmatic view would be to maintain that these a cultural exchange program, enabling one
works—while art—are simply not good art: these thousand and one people to experience Europe’s
works are marginal and eye-rollingly awful at- culture and political system (documenta 12
tempts at social do-goodery created by deeply con- catalogue, 208).
fused individuals. If one feels this way, then aes- Thus, if one wants to dismiss socially engaged
theticism and pluralism, and any view subscribing artworks as marginal and claim they are there-
to the “as art” consensus, can conveniently ex- fore not candidates for good art, one will still find
plain why that is. These works are bad because that a kindred desire for direct social relevance
they fail to realize any value by distinctly artistic underpins even the more mainstream contempo-
means. rary works, such as Ai’s. Socially engaged art can,
Dialectically, this objection leads to a stalemate. then, be thought of as a limiting case that most
Different accounts of artistic value are supposed clearly outlines a new, pragmatic view of artistic
to account for good works of art; a contest be- value. However, such a view also underlies other
tween them presupposes that we agree on which contemporary artists’ thinking about what makes
works are good. To move beyond the stalemate, a work of art good or worthwhile.
one could motivate the case for socially engaged Finally, one could deny the third premise: so-
art in two ways. cially engaged art is capable of being good art,
First, one can point to the growing popular- but either aestheticism or pluralism can explain
ity of such works. Though several of the cases its value. Here we should first note that there
discussed in the literature have indeed appeared are some works of participatory art, which also
in relatively marginal festivals with little broad include interaction with audience members or lo-
popularity, other cases of socially engaged art cal communities, but the primary goal of which
have been more widely appreciated. Theaster is to create a remarkable aesthetic experience
Gates’s housing projects have, for example, re- for the participants; some works by Tino Sehgal,
ceived broad exposure in the media, and Vik Kateřina Šedá, Marina Abramović, and Rirkrit
Muniz’s Pictures of Garbage series was the subject Tiravanija are like this. Some version of aestheti-
of an acclaimed documentary, Waste Land (2010). cism or pluralism may well be appropriate for
Second, one could point to the fact that considering this important genre (see Hegenbart
enthusiasm for direct political efficacy has in fact 2016). However, even though such participatory
spread from socially engaged art to many corners practices do overlap with socially engaged art in
of contemporary art. Consider Ai Weiwei’s terms of how they are displayed and curated, we
Fairytale (2007) performance for Documenta should at least in principle distinguish between
12: the work consisted of the artist bringing one aesthetically minded participatory works and the
thousand and one Chinese citizens, selected from socially activist works that have been my focus
over three thousand applicants, to Kassel. This here. The goal of the latter is not necessarily to in-
performance was rich with symbolic resonances. tensify the participants’ aesthetic experience but
The documentation of the journeys referenced to generate measurable social change.
the magical journeys found in the fairy tales of the Turning now to the socially activist works un-
brothers Grimm, who spent their formative years der discussion, it therefore seems clear that aes-
in Kassel; the exhibition included a display of a theticism cannot account for their value. However,
Simoniti Assessing Socially Engaged Art 79

perhaps pluralism can, and the art historian Claire likeable that would raise as much money as
Bishop seems to suggests the beginnings of a plu- possible. Theaster Gates’s attitude toward his
ralist approach. Though Bishop is sympathetic to sculptural output is even more pragmatic, in-
socially engaged art, she criticizes curators Charles deed cynical: the sale of his art objects to afflu-
Esche and Maria Lind for assessing artistic com- ent collectors simply finances his social projects
munity projects only according to their political (Adams 2015). Deller’s project might indeed be
efficacy, but not also “as art.” Rather than sim- appreciated as a kind of tableau vivant by an on-
ply assessing socially engaged art as politics, “[it] looker in the art context, for example, when the
is also crucial,” Bishop suggests, “to discuss, anal- video documentation of the work is presented in
yse and compare this work critically as art, since galleries. However, pace Bishop, Deller’s primary

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


this is the institutional field in which it is endorsed goal appears to have been to make a difference to
and disseminated.” Accordingly, Bishop praises the original participants, who were possibly quite
the “artistic work” in the case of Jeremy Deller’s unconcerned with the work’s artworld status. That
Battle of Orgreave (2012, 13, 17, 22, 33; origi- is even more obviously the case with the “Culture
nal emphases). Deller’s project involved gather- in Action” works discussed by Kwon.
ing oral accounts of police brutality to create a To map this discussion onto my argument,
historical archive told from the miners’ perspec- recall that pluralism is the view that artistic value
tive, but its central piece was a large-scale reen- encompasses a variety of values, realized through
actment of the confrontation between the strik- recognizably artistic features. Now, pluralism is a
ing miners and the police, using some of those broad church of views, so I am willing to concede
originally affected by the strike as performers. that some pluralists might find resources to
As well as socially relevant, Bishop suggests that accommodate socially engaged art. However, the
Deller’s work can therefore be considered as a discussion shows at least three reasons why this
sort of hybrid between a piece of performance is difficult; it is important to note these, because
art and a history painting (30–37). To give an- it is important to understand just how radical
other example, Vik Muniz’s collaboration with a break these works represent. First, in socially
the garbage pickers of Rio de Janeiro, Pictures engaged art traditional artistic features (such as
of Garbage, incorporated traditional artistic tools the production of portraits by Vik Muniz) may be
even more explicitly and so perhaps provides an present, but they are used as an interchangeable
even stronger case in point. Muniz assembled rub- means to an end (they fund social projects or bring
bish into portraits that recalled art historical ref- a community together), rather than as a means
erences; for example, Marat (Sebastião) is a por- through which a value is realized. It is as if we used
trait of a garbage picker that recalls Jacques-Louis a heavy statue to hit an opponent on the head,
David’s The Death of Marat (1793). Photographs rather than expressed dissent through the medium
of these assemblages were then sold, as high- of sculpture. The procedure here is therefore
end gallery art, and the money was distributed to quite different from the way in which pluralists
the garbage pickers to finance various community usually discuss artistic value as arising through
projects. artistic work. Second, any such traditional artistic
Even, though it is possible to detect elements features are always accompanied by features that
of performance, installation, or even portraiture are commonly found outside the sphere of art,
in socially engaged work (works of Suzanne Lacy, such as organizing a protest, creating an archive,
Tania Bruguera, and Thomas Hirschhorn could or rebuilding a neighborhood. It is the values re-
furnish us with further examples), it is impor- alized through such means that pluralist accounts
tant to discern the manner in which these fea- will have trouble accommodating. Third, the fea-
tures are exploited. The portraits made by Muniz tures that allow us to classify socially engaged art
are ingenious, but as is made clear in the Waste as art—such as their institutional acceptance as
Land documentary, Muniz’s main goal was to art—are, interestingly, not the features essential to
lend his skills, fame, and whatever else was re- the realization of their value. Socially engaged art-
quired to improve the lot of the people he worked works are certainly discussed in art magazines and
with. The success of these works as portraits appreciated when documented in museums, and
appeared to be a secondary concern; Muniz’s these venues may be used to publicize the political
primary goal appeared to be to create anything message. However, the bulk of these works’
80 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

achievement is based on the difference they make In this respect, I want to now illustrate the
to constituencies outside of these contexts: to consequences of this philosophical discussion
the former mining community (Deller) or to the for art criticism. When properly taken on board,
garbage pickers (Muniz). Note that the challenge the pragmatic view is in fact a highly demanding
here is different to ready-mades. With Duchamp’s system for assessing artistic value. If socially
Fountain, the institutional context was essential engaged artists intend to bring about a certain
to realizing its humor and message; that gallery positive sociopolitical change, then we should
context is mostly irrelevant to the difference judge their work not only in comparison to other
socially engaged works made to their users. artworks but within a broader context of political
This is precisely what their democratic appeal activity. Here we may detect a certain malpractice,

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


consists in. or even a kind of hypocrisy, which appears to
To sum up, given the popularity and acclaim be rife in contemporary art. Curators and critics
achieved by socially engaged art over the last routinely praise socially engaged artworks as if
few decades, I propose that philosophical theo- their commitment to social progress alone already
ries of artistic value cannot dismiss such work as constituted an accomplishment. Elsewhere, they
“not art” or “bad art.” Moreover, if we take se- occupy a kind of halfway position, reverting to
riously the intent of these art practices to make aesthetic criteria when a socially enaged work fails
a difference to the political process, then the politically. Claire Bishop rightly complains when
value of these works ought to be assessed prag- she writes: “The aspiration is always to move
matically: a socially engaged artwork is good art beyond art, but never to the point of comparison
simply to the extent that it realizes a politically with comparable projects in the social domain”
valuable end, regardless of the means the work (Bishop 2012, 19). Bishop’s own solution is to
employs. search for artistic features in socially engaged
artworks, but my alternative (and perhaps more
v. qualifications and the pragmatic view radical) pragmatic proposal is precisely to insist
in practice that for this subset of artistic production we
should evaluate art by means of its impact,
A theory of artistic value can make a claim to that is, by comparing it with “nonart” political
universal validity, or it can limit itself to a sub- initiatives.
section of art. Thus, one and the same person Once such a comparison is made, it can become
might argue for pluralism in relation to litera- clearer to what extent and which socially engaged
ture but aestheticism in relation to absolute music artworks have been effective. For example, though
(compare Kieran 2005b, 298). My goal here has many of the works presented at the Culture in
been to show how one vital strand of contem- Action program were pioneering, most were
porary art legitimizes the pragmatic conception woefully inefficient, with the artists lacking the
of artistic value. My claim is not, of course, that infrastructure and expertise necessary to carry out
this renders the pragmatic view an acceptable the- their ideas in a sustained and impactful way. Only
ory of all art. As I noted, even among contempo- one project, Manglano-Ovalle’s video workshops
rary participatory practices there are some more with local youth gang members, Tele-Vecindario,
aestheticized works (Sehgal, Abramović, Šedá, appears to have made any lasting difference to the
Tiravanija). The value of these is either aesthetic community with which it engaged (Kwon 2002,
or else resides in that hybrid aesthetic–ethical 101–137; Kester 2004, 117; Bishop 2012, 205–206).
realm, traced by some pluralists. That is all per- More recently, when Olafur Eliasson—one of
fectly all right; I merely want to suggest that in a the best-known contemporary installation artists
significant subsection of our artistic production we working with light—presented his Little Sun, a
have also come to think about artistic value prag- handheld torch intended for off-grid areas, this
matically, in terms of the work’s tangible social was met with much fanfare. One reviewer gushed:
impact. These distinctions, I hope, should be illu- “If Olafur Eliasson can enlighten those of us
minative for philosophers of art but also for those who have time and resources to devote to art,
in the contemporary artworld who want to char- well and good; but if he can literally enlighten
acterize more precisely what is at stake in these places of darkness, that must be more valuable”
new art forms. (Flanders 2012). But are we certain that this
Simoniti Assessing Socially Engaged Art 81

work is making a significant difference? Possibly; references


but I was unable to find any reviews that tried
Adams, Tim. 2015. “Chicago Artist Theaster Gates: ‘I’m
to assess the project more systematically. For Hoping Swiss Bankers Will Bail Out My Flooded South
example, Alfredo Moser, a Brazilian mechanic, Side Bank in the Name of Art.’” The Guardian. https://www.
invented an ingenious bleach-based “bottled theguardian.com/artanddesign/2015/may/03/theaster-gates-
artist-chicago-dorchester-projects.
light,” which can be easily installed in corrugated Beardsley, Monroe C. 1958. Aesthetics: Problems in the Philos-
roofs and provides indoor light in off-grid areas ophy of Criticism. New York: Harcourt, Brace.
(Zobel 2013). An NGO called Liter of Light has . 1982. The Aesthetic Point of View. Cornell University
since then been installing these lights worldwide. Press.
Bishop, Claire. 2012. Artificial Hells: Participatory Art and the
Eliasson’s project might very well be worthwhile,

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


Politics of Spectatorship. London: Verso.
but a critical assessment of socially engaged art Bourriaud, Nicolas. 2002. Relational Aesthetics. Translated by
should include comparisons with such nonart Simon Pleasance and Fronza Woods. Dijon: Les presses du
réel.
enterprises and an empirical assessment of the Budd, Malcolm. 1996. Values of Art: Pictures, Poetry and Music.
work’s impact. Further, Vik Muniz’s portraits London: Penguin.
of the garbage pickers of Rio are certainly Bürger, Peter. 1984. Theory of the Avant-Garde. Translated by
Michael Shaw. University of Minnesota Press.
heartwarming, as the film critics reviewing the
Danto, Arthur C. 1964. “The Artworld.” Journal of Philosophy
Oscar-nominated documentary about it noted. 61: 571–584.
As a social project, however, one might worry Dickie, George. 1969. “Defining Art.” American Philosophical
that the project amounted to little more than an Quarterly 6: 253–256.
documenta. 2007. Documenta 12 Catalogue. Documenta und
arbitrary, Santa-Claus-style charity event: some Museum Fridericianum. Köln: Taschen.
of the workers Muniz collaborated with received Doherty, Claire, ed. 2015. Public Art (Now): Out of Time, Out
huge amounts of money, but it is not clear what of Place. London: Art Books Publishing.
Flanders, Judith. 2012. “Fiat Lux (review of Olafur Eliasson’s
long-term difference this made to the commu- Little Sun).” The Times Literary Supplement, August 17 &
nity. Before we get too enthusiastic about the 24, no. 5707/8: 19.
“transformative power” of art, as the advertising Foster, Hal. 1996. The Return of the Real: The Avant-Garde at
copy for the film about Muniz’s work suggests, we the End of the Century. MIT Press.
Gaiger, Jason. 2009. “Dismantling the Frame: Site-Specific Art
should think seriously about each social artwork’s and Aesthetic Autonomy.” British Journal of Aesthetics 49:
actual political and ethical impact. 43–58.
One consequence of the pragmatic view, then, . 2013. “Value Conflict and the Autonomy of Art.” In
Aesthetic and Artistic Autonomy, edited by Owen Hulatt, 65–
is to call for a more rigorous practice in art crit- 88. London: Bloomsbury.
icism of socially engaged art. We have entered a Gates, Theaster. 2012. “Dorchester Projects (video),” Vimeo.
paradigm whereby artistic resources can be freely https://vimeo.com/36813608.
Gaut, Berys. 2007. Art, Emotion and Ethics. Oxford University
marshaled in support of political ends, and that is
Press.
good; however, I suspect much socially engaged Greenberg, Clement. 1986–1993. The Collected Essays and Crit-
work currently fêted at biennales would not stand icism, 4 vols., edited by John O’Brian. University of Chicago
up to the kind of scrutiny we subject nonart so- Press.
Hanson, Louise. 2013. “The Reality of (Non-Aesthetic) Artistic
cial projects to. Perhaps works such as those by Value.” Philosophical Quarterly 63: 492–508.
Suzanne Lacy, Theaster Gates, or the Voina col- Hegenbart, Sarah. 2016. “The Participatory Art Museum: Ap-
lective may be looked to as models, given that they proached from a Philosophical Perspective.” Royal Institute
of Philosophy Supplement 79: 319–339.
seem to constitute a genuine political challenge to Jackson, Shannon. 2011. Social Works: Performing Art, Support-
the authorities or a genuine improvement in the ing Publics. London: Routledge.
lives of the communities in which they intervene. John, Eileen. 2013. “Art and Knowledge.” In The Routledge
If socially engaged artworks are to be good art, Companion to Aesthetics, 3rd edition, edited by Berys Gaut
and Dominic McIver Lopes, 384–393. London: Routledge.
they ought to make a real difference. Kester, Grant H. 2004. Conversation Pieces: Community and
Communication in Modern Art. University of California
VID SIMONITI Press.
Kieran, Matthew. 2005a. Revealing Art. London: Routledge.
Department of History of Art and Faculty of . 2005b. “Value of Art.” In The Routledge Companion
Philosophy to Aesthetics, 2nd edition, edited by Berys Gaut and Dominic
Churchill College, University of Cambridge McIver Lopes, 293–305. London: Routledge.
Kwon, Miwon. 2002. One Place after Another: Site-Specific Art
Cambridge, CB3 0DS, United Kingdom
and Locational Identity. MIT Press.
Lacy, Suzanne. 1995. Mapping the Terrain: New Genre Public
internet: vs418@cam.ac.uk
Art. Seattle: Bay Press.
82 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Lamarque, Peter. 2013. “Historical Embeddedness and Artistic Zangwill, Nick. 2007. Aesthetic Creation. Oxford University
Autonomy.” In Aesthetic and Artistic Autonomy, edited by Press.
Owen Hulatt, 51–63. London: Bloomsbury. Zobel, Gibby. 2013. “Alfredo Moser: Bottle Light Inventor
Lamarque, Peter, and Stein Haugom Olsen. 1994. Truth, Fiction, Proud to Be Poor.” BBC News Magazine. http://www.
and Literature: A Philosophical Perspective. Oxford: Claren- bbc.co.uk/news/magazine-23536914.
don Press.
Levinson, Jerrold. 1979. “Defining Art Historically.” British
Journal of Aesthetics 19: 232–250.
1. Gaiger (2009, 52) calls this view aesthetic autonomy.
Lopes, Dominic McIver. 2011. “The Myth of (Non-Aesthetic) Given that I discuss aestheticism below, under a slightly
Artistic Value.” The Philosophical Quarterly 61: 518– different definition, I shall here omit this designation. See
536. also Gaiger (2013).
. 2014. Beyond Art. Oxford University Press. 2. See especially Peter Bürger’s analysis of the avant-

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/76/1/71/5981287 by guest on 23 December 2022


Nussbaum, Martha C. 1990. Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Phi- gardes (1984, 35–37, 46–47, 54) and responses to it (for ex-
losophy and Literature. Oxford University Press. ample, Foster 1996, 1–34).
Robinson, Jenefer. 2005. Deeper than Reason. Oxford University 3. For an earlier paper and debate see Lopes (2011),
Press. Stecker (2012), and Hanson (2013).
Scruton, Roger. 2009. Beauty. Oxford University Press. 4. Note that my usage of ‘pragmatic’ here has nothing
Stecker, Robert. 1997. Artworks: Definition, Meaning, Value. to do with the philosophical tradition of American pragma-
Pennsylvania State University Press. tism. Also note that it might also be possible to formulate a
. 2012. “Artistic Value Defended.” The Journal of Aes- pragmatic position for other kinds of value (prurient? com-
thetics and Art Criticism 70: 355–362. mercial? aesthetic?), but for now I will stay with the for-
Wei, Lilly. 2011. “In the Studio: Theaster Gates.” Art in America mulation that traces political, cognitive, and ethical values
99: 120–126.
central to socially engaged art.

You might also like